Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
The Question of Pure Altruism
Tohme Abounader
PSY342A
April 9, 2018
1
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
2
The Question of Pure Altruism
Suppose a stranger throws himself in front of a car to save the life of a child about to be
run over or a dying wealthy man decides to give all his wealth to charity at no gains to himself.
What motivates that stranger to act, causing absolute harm to himself and death with no reward
received in return? What motivates the dying man who has nothing to gain from charity decide to
give away his fortunes to complete strangers? One answer is pure altruism, the selfless concern
for others’ wellbeing at the cost of one’s own wellbeing, time, or energy. This would be a
satisfactory answer that seems to have been accepted society, that selflessness can truly exist.
However, there are serious concerns about the selfless aspect of altruism with some scholars,
such as evolutionary psychologists and proponents of the social exchange theory, claiming that it
is not simply unlikely for it to exist, but that it is outright impossible, while others counter these
claims be it through innate, biologically, or religious conviction of divinely acquired selflessness
or Batson’s infamous empathy-altruism hypothesis. Regardless of which route one takes, the
means to the end do not require proper identification to notice that humans do participate in
behavior that penalizes them and benefits others, but the question is can and do they do so
independently of self-interest?
Initially we are to ask if such altruistic behavior, or behavior in general, is voluntary.
With the understanding that there is a huge contemporary philosophical division between
determinism and free will, we must note that if behavior is ultimately deterministic then no act is
voluntary and therefore any individuals performing altruistic behavior are acting under
compulsion of biology, physics, or divine guidance. Such behavior would then not truly be
selfless behavior, but rather the result of manipulation by someone or something that poses harm
to or sacrifices this individual to save another. That is, if that is the case then the pure and
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
3
benevolent nature of that prosocial behavior is lost and therefore is not truly altruistic. Therefore,
we must assume that free will must exist for pure altruism to exist. If free will exists, then actions
can indeed be voluntary insomuch as they are not influenced, nudged, or even the direct result of
external or social compulsion. This means that a person should be able to perform prosocial
behavior out of his own choice and conviction rather than because such behavior is expected of
him or bred into him. This is important because if he is acting because of such external
motivations then he cannot be acting without the underlying threat of costs and penalties for
inaction that might be more severe than the consequences of taking an action (even death, if we
are to accept that reputation and judgment proceeds after death or beyond death). For instance, if
external motivations are the motive then the man who jumped in front of the car did so not out of
pure selfless altruism, to help that child, but rather because this course of action was primed into
him, if not also to avert the social consequences of having to live his life shunned, shamed, or
guilt-ridden for inaction in a society that penalizes non-prosocial behavior, especially when it is a
question of saving an innocent child, or dying buried with billions of dollars that could have
saved many lives.
Therefore, for altruism to exist, it would require that individuals possess free will and act
out of their own convictions with little to no external stimuli and threats of sanctions for inaction.
The person jumping in front of the car would have to do so because he alone wants to
independent of society or biological conditioning. The problem here, of course, is that if the
person does so because he wants to, then he is inadvertently benefiting himself. There is
absolutely no way around this. This is what the social exchange theory posits.
Others have disagreed with this assessment by presenting a differing definition of
altruism. They would contend that external rewards (for reputation) detract from the altruistic
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
4
nature of an act while acting to obtain internal rewards (such as good feelings, averting trauma,
etc.) in return for prosocial behavior is actually altruistic. The problem with this line of thought is
that it requires the convolution of semantics and the changing of the definition of “selfless.” That
is, it would require that we not consider seeking internal rewards as an instance of self-interest,
which is evidently erroneous since acting for any form of internal or external reward would
necessitate that the actor be benefiting from the act and therefore is no longer acting selflessly, or
altruistically for that matter. Self-interest is then all-pervasive in human action.
Enter Batson who in his 1991 article in Psychological Inquiry titled “Evidence for
Altruism: Toward a Pluralism of Prosocial Motives” (Batson, 1991). There Batson argues in
favor of an alternative explanation, what he calls the “empathy-altruism hypothesis.” According
to Batson, the negation of rewards is not necessary, that altruism can coexist alongside the
reception of benefits by the altruist but only inasmuch as “these benefits to self are not the
ultimate goal of empathy-induced helping, only unintended consequences” (Batson, 2008).
Therefore Batson would seek to look at the root of the act – the motivation for acting beyond the
fact that it would benefit the actor. To determine whether the motivation is out of egotistical
reasons or altruistic reasons arising from empathy, Batson conducted several studies that
attempted to isolate and control for variables of empathy and social consequences. Apparently,
he created “high empathy” and “low empathy” situations and compared the participants’
willingness to help someone in need named Carol. These situations were created by simply
encouraging the participants to “feel for” Carol or to “remain objective”, respectively. In the
“high empathy” situation, the participants were willing to help Carol regardless of external
rewards/costs or meeting her again while the “low empathy” situation they were willing to help
Carol only when the chance of meeting her was high and when the costs for inaction are high. Of
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
5
course this might seem satisfactory on the surface, but the problem with this is that the
participants were primed to feel or act in a certain way that to the researchers seemed selfless.
However, it needs to be noted that even empathy can be an ultimately self-interested pursuit
where the participants felt empathetic towards Carol because of the artificial situational priming
by the researchers rather than any innate or benefitless sentiments. That is they would feel bad
for not helping Carol and therefore would try to minimize such an undesirable feeling by helping
Carol as a result of cognitive manipulation such as the “framing effect” and the priming and not
because they legitimately cared for Carol and would render aid to her with no benefits for
themselves. The benefits received are subtle. In fact, the participants could even feel ashamed
and pressured by the researchers for not offering aid to Carol after being primed for empathy
whether it lasts after the experiment or if they consciously realize it or not.
Furthermore as Batson along with Ahmad and Tsang noted in their paper “Four Motives
for Community Involvement” (Batson, Ahmad, & Tsand, 2002), they argue that it is not altruism
alone that must be looked at for prosocial behavior, but four motives in total: egoism, altruism,
collectivism, and principlism. They argue that these motives may all be present at the same time
and interplay with a notable addition: “it may not be possible to feel empathy for an abstract
social category like the community, people with AIDS, the elderly, or the homeless” (Batson, et
al., 2002). Continuing, different levels of empathic feelings exist based on four elements, those:
“(a) who are friends, kin, or similar to us, (b) to whom we are emotionally attached, (c) for
whom we feel responsible, or (d) whose perspective we adopt (Batson, 1991; Stotland, 1969).
And, like any emotion, empathic feelings are likely to diminish over time (Batson, 1987, 1991)”
(Batson, et al., 2002). In other words, though they believe that selfless altruism through empathy
can exist between individuals when sufficiently primed, the extension of such a finding to the
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
6
social settings appears to be tenuous at best. After all, emphasizing a focus on caring will spark a
need to fulfill ingrained or nurtured sentiments of virtue and charity, that is not surprising and
harkens back to “name of the game” experiments influencing selfish vs cooperative tendencies
such as the Wall Street Game vs Community Game priming experiment (Liberman, et al., 2004).
Any attempts at arriving at the answer to the question of pure altruism in favor of its existence
would necessitate the dissecting the definition, the identification of several factors in interplay,
and disregarding any small or indirect benefits received.
The danger here is that even after all is said and done, individuals have an incentive to
self-report altruistic behavior in an attempt to engage in virtue signaling either as a result of
intentional deception or belief arising out of self-deception (Mijović-Prelec & Prelect, 2010).
Even preference falsification whereby individuals conceal their true intentions, beliefs, and later
actions can distort true motivations behind actions such as seemingly selfless altruistic behavior
by appearing to want to render aid out of sympathy when the underlying motivations are
ultimately selfish (Kuran, 1987).
Regardless, though arguments in favor of the existence of true altruism would criticize
the circular nature of the selfish altruist claim, they do concede that “There can be no such thing
as an ‘altruistic’ act that does not involve some element of self-interest, no such thing, for
example, as an altruistic act that does not lead to some degree, no matter how small, of pride or
satisfaction” (Burton, 2012) but contend by that same reasoning that the universality of selfbenefit arising from human action does not mean that true altruism must be impossible, but
rather that these “an act should not be written off as selfish or self-motivated simply because it
includes some inevitable element of self-interest. The act can still be counted as altruistic if the
‘selfish’ element is accidental; or, if not accidental, then secondary; or, if neither accidental nor
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
7
secondary, then undetermining” (Burton, 2012). For after all, a rich man satisfied with his
reputation on his deathbed might still give away all his belongings to charity for nothing in
return, because it’s the right thing to do. The point that is then made is that simply because
there’s unintentional or a hint of reward for altruistic actions does not necessarily mean that the
act itself is self-interested. After all, an individual can find benefits even in the worst and most
self-harming situations and actions. It therefore does not follow that the self-harming acts are
therefore self-interested because of the miniscule amount of benefit gained.
On the other hand, evolutionary biologists would contend that altruism could not have
successfully evolved. Robert Trivers in “the Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism” explains that for
altruism to be successful, it would require two basic conditions: memory and high population
viscosity (Trivers, 71). A society would have to be small enough to be able to retain memory as a
reputational accounting mechanism and repeat interactions with the same people over the course
of years, but in large-scale societies this largely fails as memory does not scale properly (though
money can act as somewhat of an imperfect measure of social contribution (Kocherlakota, 1996)
and population viscosity is largely nonexistent beyond the limited interactions within small
social or work groups. Meaning, though scholars like Batson might put forward the notion that
true or pure altruism can be observed through empathy in controlled experiments to some degree
through priming, it would be extremely difficult to observe such altruism in the real world,
especially in a society where direct and indirect interactions between us and millions of
individuals occur on a daily basis. The problems here are many, but mainly it’s that selfdeception and false signalling are major setbacks for the idea of the existence of true or pure
altruism. That is essentially because through the evolutionary process, as best exemplified in by
Robert Axelrod’s 1981 “Evolution of Cooperation”, concludes that if a society of pure altruists
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
8
encounters a single selfish individual then in non-iterative and iterative interactions (or in
Axelrod’s case, prisoner’s dilemma game theory) will lead to a successful invasion by a selfish
individual (represented as “ALL D” in Axelrod’s paper). That is to say, during humanity’s early
development, altruism would have been compromised by a single mutation that leads to a selfish
individual and with evolutionary psychology in the mix, then that individual would have
increased his survival fitness at the expense of everyone else who, being altruists, are also
increasing his survival fitness and sacrificing their own. The selfish individual will be able to
maximize his benefits and pass on his (selfish) genes which would lead to a repeated process of
exploitation and defection against the altruists. Down the road, as in the repeated simulations of
the iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma shows, the society of pure altruists and the pure altruists
themselves will lose out in the end and potentially become extinct as a result without the ability
to successfully pass down their genes. Therefore, the selfish individuals would inadvertently
develop selfish society which would harm everyone as a result (lower overall payouts from
“ALL D” societies compared to all cooperative interactions (Axelrod, 1981)).
However, such an outcome can be averted as with Trivers and Axelrod through the
process of reciprocal altruism or “TIT FOR TAT” strategy where cooperation is the first move
whereafter all other moves by the opponent are mirrored in subsequent moves by the participant.
This is very important because if a society of “TIT FOR TAT” individuals encounters a selfish
individual then they will reciprocate his behavior. Say he refuses to help build the communal
storage, then the individuals in that society will refuse to aid him in his own building projects or
even deny him access to the communal storage as a result. Even though the people in that society
would be acting selfishly they would only be doing so as a response to the other individual’s
action or inaction only to ensure further cooperation which nets higher rewards. This would
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
9
penalize the selfish individual’s inaction and it would force him to cooperate for his own selfinterest, thus turning the selfish individual into a cooperative self-interested altruist. But this
poses a new strategy for the selfish altruist: deception and false signalling. In cases where
monitoring is simple, such strategies would prove to be very difficult since people can observe to
see if that person’s words are being put to action. However where obfuscation results due to
large societies and increasing numbers of people, then Dunbar’s number dictates that past an
approximate number of 200 people will cease treating each other as friends and humans and treat
them more as numbers or even objects. That is to say, the ability to monitor others’ behaviors
becomes very limited and attempts to rely purely on trust take hold. Individuals would find it
necessary to rely on trusting that others are doing what they are saying unless proven otherwise.
In other words, the selfish individual in a large scale or modern society can pose as an altruist
with no accurate means of verification. Even in early human societies that began to increase in
size and relationships began to be less consistent, such behavior could have occurred and
benefited the selfish individual greatly to such an extent that successful acts of concealed
defection and exploitation would have led to an increased ability to provide for himself, his kin,
and pass on his deceptive genes through the generations. A skilled deceiver could perform a
charitable act or two then capitalize on those acts by turning the spotlight on them, referencing
them, all the while adeptly not putting in any more notable instances of cooperation or
contribution. The concern thereafter is the realization that if such a process occurred, and it
seems likely that it did, then ideals of altruism might be ingrained in our biological programming
but not pure altruism, but instead that of selfish altruism or even worse: self-deception where
unknowingly to us our acts of alleged pure altruism are the result of our evolutionary biological
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
10
imperative to signal our true or false virtue to others in order to achieve reputational gains, avert
punishment, and ensure survival.
The process does not end there. If the biological argument does not hold water, then the
cultural argument retains the same basic ideas of gene transferral but instead of sexual
reproduction it would be liberated through the means of social interactions, child rearing, and
manipulation. Where evolutionary psychology necessitates the interaction of genes in a
competition for survival, manipulative selfish individuals can still have historically come to
dominate modern society by convincing and appealing for people in their society to act
altruistically and cooperate when they themselves would defect. This can even be seen in the
case of the parent-child relationship where the parent stands gain immensely from teaching the
child their selected values and ensuring that the child can adequately benefit the parent when the
latter becomes unable to provide for themselves. A child, in a sense, would be a parent’s
insurance policy for later years. A selfish individual, if he manages to convince society to act
altruistically, can exploit such a system to his benefit, and if such a society continues down the
road with a culture of selflessness and altruistic behavior then selfish individuals can also
continue down the same road of manipulation and exploitation without the need for any gene
selection. Charity then benefits the selfish individuals who are not ashamed of abusing it. And
this gain does not have to be in the from of money, but in the form of respect, reputation, and
favor that would be much more powerful that money alone. In primitive tribal societies,
popularity would been extremely important in maintaining one’s status and value for the tribe so
as to not be left out for the wolves over someone else. Even in today’s society, reputational gains
and popularity are extraordinarily important that could pave the way for social benefits and
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
11
facilitation that would have otherwise been extremely unlikely to achieve (even for something as
lowly as getting a free entrance to the dining hall because the cashiers like you).
Nevertheless, a 2014 study concludes that given the ability to mitigate suffering, people
would choose, on average, to “sacrifice more money to reduce a stranger’s pain than their own
pain” (Crockett, Kurth-Nelson, et al., 2014). In a 2014 interview with lead author Molly Crockett
noted her expressing the following, “Although I’m fairly confident that the volunteers in our
recent study were not making altruistic choices out of concern for their reputation, we cannot
rule out the possibility that they behaved altruistically in order to avoid feeling guilty, or to feel
good about themselves, rather than because they truly cared about the suffering of others.”
Crockett then goes on to ask whether figuring out if true altruism exists even matters, quoting a
Stanford neuroscientist Jamil Zaki, and then explaining that unlocking the mechanisms behind
altruism and increasing it dwarfs asking if true altruism really exists (Crockett, 2014).
Conversely, in a 2011 meta study of 129 dictator game studies by Christoph Engel where one
participant receives a sum of money and can then voluntarily impart them money to another
participant concludes,“While 63.89% violate the income maximisation hypothesis, 36.11% do
not. Hence more than a third of a typical population does indeed consist of subjects who have no
reticence to leave a recipient with nothing, although this recipient is at their mercy. Clearly,
generosity is not a human universal. Moreover, those who are willing to make a donation do
neither give everything, nor do they split the pie equally. On average, they give 42.64%. Hence
even those who in principle are generous to a degree exploit the opportunity to their advantage.
Even generous subjects thus tend to have a selfish side.” Given what was found by Axelrod
regarding the successful invasion capability of an “ALL D” individual in a cooperative altruistic
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
12
society, this finding is indeed frightening especially as our societies grow ever larger and more
independent with less reliance on cooperation between individuals (Malcolm, 2014).
Regardless of the history, development, and current consequences of altruism, one thing
can be known for sure. In the case of the rich philanthropist on his deathbed giving away all his
wealth to charity, it may seem like an ultimate selfless act, but it too may be as a result of selfinterest and satisfaction. After all, the perseverance of memory is certainly one way through
which a form of immortality can be achieved just as reputation persists in the world after the
person dies, if not in the potential afterlife where worldly actions would be judged by an ethereal
being for goodness. Either way, such an act would still be susceptible to selfish gains, especially
if physical and genetic survival is not the ultimate goal for humans but rather their perseverance
in memory and reputation. That might be why the man jumped in front of the car to save the
child, not because he’s selfless, but because he wanted to do the right thing, die doing something
that he believes is in line with his beliefs, and be remembered as someone who sacrificed
themselves (highest cost) to save a child’s life. Consciously or unconsciously he succumbed to
the spur of the moment and gambled for something of potentially very high value.
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
13
References
Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. science, 211(4489),
1390-1396.
Batson, C., & Shaw, L. (1991). Evidence for Altruism: Toward a Pluralism of Prosocial Motives.
Psychological Inquiry, 2(2), 107-122. Retrieved from www.jstor.org/stable/1449242
Batson, C. D. (2010). Empathy-induced altruistic motivation. Prosocial motives, emotions, and
behavior: The better angels of our nature, 15-34.
http://portal.idc.ac.il/en/symposium/herzliyasymposium/documents/dcbatson.pdf
Batson, C. D., Ahmad, N., & Tsang, J. A. (2002). Four motives for community involvement.
Journal of Social Issues, 58(3), 429-445.
http://www.baylorisr.org/wp-content/uploads/tsang_motives.pdf
Burton, N (2012). Does true altruism exist? Psychology Today. Retrieved from
www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/hide-and-seek/201203/does-true-altruism-exist
Crockett, M. J., Kurth-Nelson, Z., Siegel, J. Z., Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2014). Harm to others
outweighs harm to self in moral decision making. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, 111(48), 17320-17325.
Kocherlakota, N. R. (1998). Money is memory. journal of economic theory, 81(2),
232-251.https://www.minneapolisfed.org/research/sr/sr218.pdf.
Kuran, T. (1987). Preference falsification, policy continuity and collective conservatism. The
Economic Journal, 97(387), 642-665.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/2232928?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Kuran, T. (1997). Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification.
Harvard University Press.
Running head: THE QUESTION OF PURE ALTRUISM
14
Liberman, V., Samuels, S. M., & Ross, L. (2004). The name of the game: Predictive power of
reputations versus situational labels in determining prisoner’s dilemma game moves.
Personality and social psychology bulletin, 30(9), 1175-1185.
http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0146167204264004
Malcolm, L. (2014, August 19). Research says young people today are more narcissistic than
ever. Retrieved April 11, 2018, from
www.abc.net.au/radionational/programs/allinthemind/young-people-today-are-morenarcissistic-than-ever/5457236
Mijović-Prelec, D., & Prelec, D. (2010). Self-deception as self-signalling: a model and
experimental evidence. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
Sciences, 365(1538), 227-240. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2827460/
Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly review of biology,
46(1), 35-57.
http://greatergood.berkeley.edu/images/uploads/Trivers-EvolutionReciprocalAltruism.pdf