The Humanistic Psychologist
Lifespan Human Development and “The Humanistic
Perspective”: A Contribution Toward Inclusion
Eugene M. DeRobertis and Andrew M. Bland
Online First Publication, May 9, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/hum0000141
CITATION
DeRobertis, E. M., & Bland, A. M. (2019, May 9). Lifespan Human Development and “The
Humanistic Perspective”: A Contribution Toward Inclusion. The Humanistic Psychologist.
Advance online publication. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/hum0000141
The Humanistic Psychologist
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
© 2019 American Psychological Association
0887-3267/19/$12.00
2019, Vol. 1, No. 999, 000 – 000
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/hum0000141
Lifespan Human Development and “The
Humanistic Perspective”: A Contribution
Toward Inclusion
Eugene M. DeRobertis
Andrew M. Bland
Brookdale College and Rutgers
University-Newark
Millersville University
Humanistic psychology has a long tradition of developmental thought. Yet, no place has been
reserved for a specifically humanistic perspective in developmental psychology textbooks.
This article presents a humanistic perspective to serve as a convenient guide for the potential
creation of a textbook entry. A highly condensed account of Existential-Humanistic SelfDevelopment Theory (EHSDT) is outlined and compared with the theories that most
frequently garner coverage in developmental textbooks. Suggestions for further research on
the major themes of EHSDT are also provided. These include the role of the imagination in
shaping the trajectories of lifespan development, the intercorporeal and multicultural embeddedness of the narrative imagination, the self-cultivation process, cooperative culture
creation, thriving amid paradox, and the ways in which motivational dynamics operate within
diverse social contexts. Carefully planned rollout of such research should help prevent further
marginalization of explicitly humanistic developmental theory on the basis that it challenges
some of the fundamental assumptions of the established theories and, accordingly, tends to
be met with resistance or, at best, indifference.
Keywords: lifespan development, Existential-Humanistic Self-Development Theory,
imagination, self-cultivation, phenomenology
This article is part of a larger, ongoing effort to ameliorate an unfortunate gap in the
psychological literature left by the near exclusion of explicitly humanistic viewpoints in
the study of lifespan development. In accordance with Lefrancois (2001) and Crain
(2005), we believe that humanistic psychology has made significant developmental
contributions to psychology since its inception, not the least of which are its numerous
explications of the growth process inherent in human health (see Bland & DeRobertis,
Eugene M. DeRobertis, Department of Psychology, Brookdale College, and Department of
Psychology, Rutgers University-Newark; Andrew M. Bland, Department of Clinical Psychology,
Millersville University.
We thank Joseph Cali for his conscientious reading of this article.
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Eugene M. DeRobertis, Department of Psychology, Brookdale College, MAN 126c, Lincroft, NJ 07738. E-mail:
[email protected]
1
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
2
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
2017; DeRobertis, 2000, 2008, 2012, 2015b, 2017; DeRobertis & McIntyre, 2016). In
Crain’s (2005) words, “There is one place where the developmentalists’ concerns are
seriously expressed. This is in humanistic psychology” (p. xvi).
For example, foundational humanistic thinkers including Wilhelm Dilthey (see Teo,
2003), Edmund Husserl (see Allen, 1976), Maurice Merleau-Ponty (Merleau-Ponty,
2010), Abraham Maslow (Maslow, 1987, 1999; also see Bland & DeRobertis, 2017),
Charlotte Bühler (Bühler, 1967; Bühler & Allen, 1972; also see DeRobertis, 2008), Alfred
Adler (see DeRobertis, 2012), and Carl Rogers (see DeRobertis, 2008) all wrote about
child psychology and human development in general. Especially within the existentialphenomenological branch of the humanistic movement, entire volumes have been dedicated to the study of human development involving varied foci, from quantitative and
qualitative research to the establishment of conceptual models for approaching the
lifespan (e.g., Bühler & Massarik, 1968; DeRobertis, 2008, 2012, 2017; Knowles, 1986;
Schachtel, 1959; Simms, 2008; Welsh, 2013). Moreover, a parallel current of phenomenological thought in the domain of pedagogy has been developing for some time (van
Manen, 2014).
Despite all this, humanistic developmental thought continues to be vastly underrepresented in the developmental literature. At least in recent years, this seems attributable to
the general marginalization of the humanistic perspective in a culture that values predictability and technocratic utility (Dewell & Foose, 2017; Van Kaam, 1966). The numerous
parallels between humanistic theorizing and conventional developmental theory and
research (see Bland & DeRobertis, 2017) notwithstanding, to date, the appearance of an
explicitly humanistic perspective in a developmental text remains unusual (DeRobertis,
2008), likely because historically the perspective has been too “outside the box.” Similar
things can be said of the limited coverage of humanistic psychology in educational
psychology textbooks, which tend to give little more than brief mention of Maslow’s
hierarchy of needs in connection with the importance of motivation in teaching and
learning (e.g., Woolfolk, 2016).
To be fair, humanistic psychologists are partly responsible for this estrangement.
Founding humanistic psychologists (e.g., Maslow, 1987; May, 1967; Van Kaam, 1966)
preferred that the existential-humanistic approach not be taken up as a separate school or
subfield of psychology but rather as a basis for psychology itself. Because several aspects
of foundational humanistic theorizing—particularly its developmental focus (e.g., see
Bühler, 1967; Bühler & Allen, 1972)— have become embraced (albeit in narrow-band
empirical form) by conventional psychologists since the final third of the 20th century,
today several of its once-radical propositions have either become commonplace and/or
treated as revolutionary by contemporary psychologists who coopt and repackage them.
Despite this, the humanistic community generally has not adequately sought to accentuate
and advocate for its developmental acumen, and research on developmental theory in
humanistic psychology has been stagnant in the new millennium (as noted by one of the
reviewers of this article) since the rollout of seminal process research in the second half
of the 20th century (e.g., Belenky, Clinchy, Goldberger, & Tarule, 1986; Kegan, 1982;
Levinson, Darrow, Klein, Levinson, & McKee, 1978; White, 1966). All the while, many
broader-band humanistic principles that are typically taken for granted within the humanistic community remain obscure to most mainstream psychologists.
Accordingly, in this article we provide an introduction to humanistic developmental
thought by using an approach that is long overdue. Specifically, we outline a highly
condensed “humanistic perspective”—specifically, Existential-Humanistic SelfDevelopment Theory (EHSDT; see DeRobertis, 2008, 2012, 2015b, 2017)—to serve as a
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
3
convenient guide for the potential creation of a textbook entry. Our aim is to provide
conceptual raw material to act as a stepping-stone for professionals who can use their
expertise to bring humanistic developmental thought to students at varied levels of study.
Conceptually, this article is a follow-up to DeRobertis and McIntyre’s (2016) introduction
to humanistic developmental thought, which was written for an audience of undergraduate
readers in particular and which emphasized that: (a) human beings have teleological goals
that undergird individual development, (b) human awareness and knowledge are experientially graded and ever-expanding, and (c) empathetic, accepting relationships found
children’s abilities to develop into confident, fully functioning social beings. In addition,
we compare and contrast EHSDT with several theories that have become regularly
featured in developmental college textbooks in the interest of familiarizing the reader with
the overall character of a “new” old perspective. By pointing out both connections and
areas of divergence between EHSDT and the traditional models and research with which
most psychologists and students should be familiar, humanistic psychologists’ contributions to and influence upon the mainstream may become better appreciated, and areas of
further exploration better contextualized and understood.
Existential-Humanistic Self-Development Theory (EHSDT)
The strong influence of existential-phenomenology in humanistic developmental
thought in general, as well as our own background in existential-phenomenology, have
prompted us to speak of an existential-humanistic approach to development. The term
existential-humanistic is borrowed from Van Kaam (1966) and is combined with the term
self-development to accentuate the theory’s nonreductive, nondeterministic orientation.
EHSDT is an open-ended, holistic, macrolevel approach to human development that has
interdisciplinary origins in philosophy, anthropology, education, pedagogy, sociology,
and history (see DeRobertis, 2008, 2012, 2015b, 2017). EHSDT values philosophicalanthropological reflection and metapsychological rigor, and it also acknowledges the
importance of being guided by data. For example, we have previously demonstrated the
validity of EHSDT principles—specifically those espoused by Maslow— by connecting
them with both classic and contemporary research findings in developmental psychology
(Bland & DeRobertis, 2017). In addition, Bland and McQueen (2018b) provide empirical
support for the role of intimate relationships in self-development.
Here, EHSDT is presented using six broad metathemes. First, EHSDT is a theory of
the whole developing person-in-context with a focus on the core integrational system of
the developmental process: the self-system. The holism of the theory is undergirded by a
notion of the developing person as a situated network of meaningful relationships and
projects, the relative integration of which is a function of the imagination (Murray, 1986,
2001). Second, the unfolding of human development is viewed in process-oriented terms,
as an ever-diversifying connectivity. Third, healthy human development or thriving in the
process of becoming oneself entails competent negotiation of paradox throughout the
lifespan. Fourth, the dialectical tension between stability or sameness and change throughout the lifespan is understood on the basis of a dynamic motivational complex. Fifth, this
motivational complex originates within a social context that is at once highly tactile and
linguistically structured. On the basis of this social-contextual orientation, EHSDT sees
self-development in terms of self-cultivation. Sixth, EHSDT values pluralism in research,
with an overriding preference for phenomenological data that are sensitive to direct human
involvement in the lifeworld (Lebenswelt).
4
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
An Existential-Phenomenological Systems Orientation
EHSDT’s holistic approach to human development represents a particular kind of
systems orientation in which the organism is regarded as a multifaceted, relatively
organized whole capable of responding “intelligently” and flexibly to varying life circumstances. Human development refers to a dynamic gestalt that is ever in flux— but
more than this, it refers to a certain someone’s development, that is, a specific person in
the perpetual process of becoming more fully human (i.e., tolerant of ambiguity, creative,
spontaneous but not impulsive, or mindful but not compulsive). A person-in-process is an
active participant in a lifestyle marked by intentionality and the coming-to-awareness of
one’s own being. These two features are indicative of EHSDT’s overarching phenomenological and existential characteristics, respectively.
Adopting the holism of this approach means refusing to compartmentalize even those very
broad aspects of psychological life that are normally referred to as “objective behavior” and
“subjective mental processes.” Instead, development is viewed in terms of ever-unfolding
experiaction (von Eckartsberg, 1979)—the functional inseparability of experiencing and
acting—that serves as a concrete touchstone for any exploration of developmental partprocesses. This means that the study of human development by way of its various constituents
(e.g., genetic precursors, sensitive periods, information processing systems, temperamental
predispositions, attachment patterns, and so forth) begins and ends with experiencing, acting
persons in the process of negotiating and/or constructively responding to their discrete
circumstances. Emphasis is given to unfolding, living relations with self, other, and world at
large. The process of development is, thus, held to involve a perpetual holonic (i.e., part-whole
unfolding; see Wilber, 2000) dynamic.
Placing the unique developing person-in-process living in and through his or her life
circumstances at the center of EHSDT’s concerns has two implications. First, it means that
EHSDT must rely on a dialogue between the general and the particular when it comes to
data collection, of which more will be said later. Second, the consideration of isolated
aspects of development fulfills its scientific potential when these aspects are properly
contextualized as part of a meaningful, value-laden human reality. Psychological life is
describable on the basis of many levels of functioning, from the molecular and cellular to
the cultural and historical, all of which play varied roles in the formation of an allencompassing developmental context (Wilber, 2000). However, these formative dimensions of development’s context taken in their pregiven (i.e., “objective”) aspects alone
cannot reveal that context’s full phenomenal reality.
A developmental context is given its decisive shape once it is taken up by a developing
person engaged in the process of co-constituting its continually unfolding meaning. Here,
developmental context denotes an intricately intertwined fabric of meaning evokers,
delimiters, modifiers, and amplifiers. In each case, developmental context refers to the
platform and the occasion for relative change to commence, a setting of the stage for a
unique project of human becoming. Human development is radically situated, implying a
state of being that cannot be captured by the antinomy of merely being subject to an
environment’s many compelling forces versus the intellectual manipulation of that environment like a scientist-in-training. These opposing extremes are projections of a rationalizing scientific consciousness, and neither approaches the issue of developmental
context with an appreciation of its relationship to situated human consciousness as it
realistically operates within the lifeworld. Rather, for EHSDT, living human consciousness is characteristically world-disclosing and world-invested as its default state, viscerally and affectively “caught up” in the day-to-day life of meaningful interchange before
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
5
the developing person is reflectively aware of his or her involvement. From the perspective of this highly “molar” synthetic-relational approach, the developing person-in-process
is a meaningfully structured network of unfolding relationships and projects. He or she is
a situated (nonabsolute) freedom, taking up positions that both structure and are informed
by the world qua referential totality of meanings. Conceptualized in this way, there is no
hard-and-fast distinction to be made between person-in-process and world-in-process;
together they form a figure-ground nexus. With varying degrees of awareness, the
person-in-process is ever co-constituting world meanings and, beyond that, co-creating
culture.
Thus, EHSDT approaches the organizational achievement of a developing person’s
being, as a total being-in-the-world, in terms of the ongoing evolution of the self-system
(sometimes called the proprium; Allport, 1955) in human development, the essence of
which is integrative and imaginative in nature (Frick, 1971; Murray, 2001). Human
development is dependent upon the concurrent and relatively harmonious functioning of
numerous physical, emotional, cognitive, social, and moral subsystems on an ongoing
basis. That is, healthy development entails a workable center of gravity among the
subsystems (see Wilber, 2000). The manners in which humans engage and operationalize
these subsystems at any given time can be portrayed in broad species-typical and
culture-typical terms as a matter of course. However, the overall form of this harmonization is ultimately determined by the developing person’s characteristic world-openness,
which is marked by an irreducible imaginative-integrative impetus and awareness (i.e., the
self—Who am I? Who am I becoming?). Meantime, here the imagination does not refer
primarily to fantasy or to the mere manipulation of mental images, but rather to a
genuinely teleological creative-productive power. Likewise, EHSDT does not restrict its
understanding of the imagination to special instances of creative productivity. Rather, the
imagination is the most fundamental form of cognition— embodied, affectively attuned,
and socially emergent (Bolton, 1982).
Human Development as a Differential-Integrative Process:
Diversifying Connectivity
For EHSDT, the myriad subsystems at work in human development are mutually
interdependent comparable with the transparent pages in an anatomy book that illustrate
the circulatory, digestive, respiratory, nervous, and other systems working in tandem. The
subsystems’ deeply intertwined nature is most evident at the outset of development.
However, there is not an absolute zero point of total indistinction, either. The imagination
is hard at work straightaway, as early experience comes to be populated with primitively
organized figures differentiated from their backgrounds (Koffka, 1931). The global state
of the self-system displays this same quality, manifesting as an evolving figure-ground
nexus in its world-relations fit with prototypical manifestations of operational body
schema and perceptual body image from infancy (Gallagher & Meltzoff, 1996). As Straus
(1975) observed, with the first breath, the child establishes a lived inner-outer relationality
that will persist throughout the lifespan. Development is founded upon an implicit
separation-in-connection or belonging-in-opposition that is mediated by the affectively
experienced undulations of the body across the medium of the flesh. The child is not born
in an autistic state completely shielded by a stimulus barrier. Rather, he or she turns
toward the world with interest (Schachtel, 1959). “Primary creativeness, i.e., when an
individual engages in an activity which results in the discovery of new potentials, is
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
6
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
observable from about the infant’s second week of life” (Bühler & Marschack, 1968, p.
93).
In this turning toward the world, the child does not lapse into a kind of quasi-symbiotic
confusion with the subjectivity of the caregiver. As Bühler (1968) noted, newborns
display a selectivity of perception that is observable within the first 4 to 5 days of life, and
this perceptual selectivity “forces us to assume the existence of a primary individuality,
even a singularity of personality” (pp. 28 –29). Of course, the infant has a way to go before
he or she can grasp the highly abstract conceptual distinction between “inside” and
“outside” that has come to pervade Western adult consciousness (Romanyshyn, 1989). As
implicated by Kegan (1982), experiaction in early infancy has an “adualistic” character,
not in the sense of displaying a total inability to differentiate self from other, but in the
sense that it operates outside the artificial antinomy of the inner and the outer that results
when the connective bonding medium of living flesh is habitually covered over by the
literal dividing boundary of the anatomical epidermis. Beginning with a highly embedded
sense of experiactional organization, part-processes are increasingly differentiated (with
varying degrees of rapidity and salience) and are then sooner or later reintegrated when
conditions are ideal to form a more dynamically responsive world openness (see Bowen,
1978; Firestone, Firestone, & Catlett, 2013). As development unfolds, thus, one witnesses
an evolving pattern wherein personal organization is repeatedly destabilized and then
reorganized to create a more multifaceted style of integration, giving healthy human
development the character of a diversifying connectivity. For empirical support of this
principle, see Bland and McQueen (2018b) and DeRobertis (2017).
To be sure, the assimilation of highly rationalized third-person views of self and world
is part of what it means to develop in a contemporary Western cultural landscape.
However, for EHSDT, such assimilations merely serve the increasing articulation of
unfolding self-development as part of a perpetual dialectic between more embodied and
embedded forms of knowledge and more salient, intellectualized forms of knowledge (i.e.,
diversifying connectivity). There are many subtle gradations of salience in experiactional
world-relatedness as development proceeds. These result from differential-integrative
accomplishments like the gradual realization of upright posture, confronting the world
face-to-face, investigating it with increasingly agile hand-eye coordination, qualitative
refinements in imitative abilities, and improvements in both receptive and expressive
language. With the refinement of each of these abilities comes the potential for a new,
more sophisticated form of personal integration to emerge— but only a relative potential.
That is, notions of “not me” become increasingly integrated as possibilities into the
self-concept and enacted as situations demand (Combs, 1999; Combs, Richards, &
Richards, 1988). Moreover, optimal development depends on improvements in one’s
ability to connect to the object world in a manner that does not result in (inter)subjective
disconnect and a denuding, alienating, stultifying loss of holistic perspective (a threat that
pervades contemporary technologized culture). In the end, the optimization of the growth
process depends on the unity-building power of the imagination (Murray, 1986) and its
potential for adopting a sufficiently vitalizing, ambiguity tolerant, inclusive style of
integration reminiscent of Maslow’s self-actualizing personality (see Bland & DeRobertis,
2017).
Regarding diversifying connectivity as social connectivity, in recent times there has
been a heightened recognition of the fact that humans are born with an integrative capacity
and that certain senses of self are already differentiating soon after birth. This recognition
is due in large part to the efforts of Stern (2000), whose arguments fit in well with the
tradition of humanistic developmental thought because of his characterizations of devel-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
7
opmental differentiation and integration as a perpetual function of the interpersonal. In his
words, “The most important point is that a primary intersubjectivity starts from the
beginning, as does the sense of an emergent self, as does the sense of a core self” (Stern,
2000, p. xxii). Around 9 months, the sense of intersubjective self begins to become salient,
followed by the sense of verbal self around 18 months and the narrative self at approximately 3 years. Stern’s assertions regarding the timing of the narrative self-fall squarely
within the period that the child is beginning to take up a globally integrative, generalized
goal orientation within his or her social world (Adler, 1979; Kohut, 1977). By about
8 years of age, the child can not only engage complex social interactions with the third
person perspective of a generalized other, but he or she can also integrate skill specific
notions of self-efficacy into a global self-concept, resulting in the consolidation of an
overall sense of self-esteem (Harter, 1999; Tischler, 2010). Moving toward adolescence,
the child then begins to develop a more socially reflective form of differential-integrative
awareness with the development of identity. Commitment and fidelity then become the
issues that found the highly self-transcendent differential-integrative opportunities of adult
development, including love, care, and wisdom (Erikson, 1963; Knowles, 1986) that
enable one to be at ease in multiple social roles without assuming an off-balance center
of gravity whereby one life domain (e.g., work) becomes accentuated at the expense of
others (e.g., family, health, and recreation; see Bland & McQueen, 2018a; Erikson,
1959/1994; Frankl, 1983; Sweet, 2014).
Thriving Amid Paradox
Self-development, as the evolution of one’s imaginative-integrative impetus and
awareness, is uniquely suited to the lifelong process of handling those growth opportunities that specifically call out for mediating creative-productive potentials. This implicates the challenges of thriving amid paradox as a significant metatheme. The entire
process of human development is paradoxical from the point of view of EHSDT in two
fundamental senses. First, building upon von Eckartsberg’s (1998) “existentialphenomenological paradox” (p. 15), EHSDT assumes that human development simultaneously exhibits trans-individual (essential) regularities that nonetheless always present as
concretized (existential) particulars (see Friedman, 1964; Natanson, 1970). Human becoming is best described as a situated becoming oneself, marking the insertion of the
unique developing person within the natural world (DeRobertis, 2015a). Second, as
discussed, EHSDT approaches human development as involving both differential and
integrative processes.
Beyond these global characteristics, there are many other manifestations of the
paradoxical throughout human development, each presenting a particular bipolar reality
that must be competently negotiated for growth to commence. Birth introduces the
dynamic tension of stability or sameness and change, with the transition to life outside
the womb being one of the most radical changes in one’s lifetime. Thereafter, throughout
the lifespan, humans are faced with needs for predictability and safety on the one hand,
and normative eustress, age-appropriate progress, and overall growth on the other. The
risks involved in growth implicate the perpetual tension between life and death or being
and nonbeing (see May, 1977), from the highly embedded awareness of vulnerability
experienced during infancy to the articulated fears of death that manifest in old age (see
Erikson, 1959/1994). The comforting presence of others first emerges as a means of
containing the threat of nonbeing, giving rise to the lifelong dynamics of interdependence
and independence.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
8
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
In the calm, opening presence of comforting primary caretakers, self-investigatory bodily
awareness soon gives rise to the discovery of additional paradoxical realities. The child
discovers that he or she not only is a lived bodily presence to the world-with-others, but that
he or she also has a body that is subject to various degrees of objectification. In its various
objectified forms, the body might be that which is deliberately manipulated or experienced as
that which exerts control over one’s functioning. This marks a polarity between being and
having, which has transformed into what is perhaps the major crisis of contemporary American culture: the tension between caring participation (as a way of being) and egoistic
consumption (as a kind of having; see Fromm, 1976). The body itself has not been immune
to the problems associated with a failure to navigate this paradox, as is most evident by the
extent to which the body has come to be objectified (Romanyshyn, 1989) and made the object
of consumption. This is especially pronounced with regard to femininity; thus, implicating the
paradox of human androgyny and the many challenges it has posed (as discussed at length
within the psychoanalytic movement and as recently taken up by Newsom, 2015).
That the body can sometimes enable willing action or prove to be an obstacle introduces
a juxtaposition of freedom and limitation, as well as the tension between activity and passivity
throughout human development. Still other bipolar realities emerge upon the realization that
the body can be used for creation or destruction and, later, for good or evil. Optimally, the child
embarks on a progressive path toward an ever-widening creative expansion wherein destruction plays the facilitating role of helping to undo outmoded forms of integration. This
progression then calls forth the paradox of pursuing an increasing sense of completion in a life
that forever points to an “always more to come,” giving human happiness the character of
incomplete-completion (Strasser, 1977). The pursuit of incomplete-completion itself evokes
the question as to the meaning of human affairs, including their ultimate meaning in the face
of the possibility of their potential meaninglessness. Here, one is confronted with the difficult
issue of contending with the desire for certainty in a world that is full of ambiguity, which
requires a mutual respect for both evidence and mystery (including the pervasive role of faith
in human living).
To reiterate, for growth to occur, these dualities must be faced, engaged, truly encountered,
negotiated, and made productive. Otherwise, they become frustrating, growth-stifling dualisms
(Schneider, 1990, 2013). Opposition must be preserved in dialectical relatedness and in that
way “overcome” (hence, the relative, differential nature of the integrative process). It is in this
dialectical capacity that the imagination actualizes its specialized mediatory role, giving rise to
the proliferation of certain psychological strengths, exemplary characteristics of healthy
self-formation, exhibiting outstanding integrative power. Such strengths include hope, vitalizing bodily awareness, will, social interest and relatedness, purpose, biophilia (the urge to
affiliate with other forms of life; Wilson, 1984), the capacity for wonder and awe, creative
transcendence, competence, identity, fidelity, integrity, love, socioecological rootedness, care,
wisdom, gerotranscendence, discerning prudence of judgment, and the development of an
overarching frame of orientation in life.
Human Becoming: Being-in-Time and Its Dynamic Motivational Complex
As noted, at a broad level of analysis, EHSDT approaches self-development via a
hermeneutic of being in time involving an ongoing dialectic between stability/sameness
and the possibility of being different or changing who one is moving forward into the
future. Selfhood is seen in terms of both the desire to maintain or reestablish a certain
order of being-in-the-world as well as the striving to transcend and become “other than”
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
9
any given order throughout the lifespan. In this regard, human development involves a
dynamic complex of overlapping, interpenetrated motivational tendencies.
Insofar as human beings seek to discharge certain states of tension and return to prior
states of relative calm, they can be said to display homeostatic tendencies. Inasmuch as
they also seek to “self-regulate” by coping with challenges, fitting in with their surroundings, and attaining a sense of security in the world, they can also be said to display reactive
adaptational tendencies. Developmental theory and psychology at large have made much
of these modes of comportment, both of which envision the person as adjusting to change
with the purpose of maintaining sameness. Alone, however, these motivational tendencies
are inadequate to describe healthy development. In contrast, EHSDT and humanistic
psychology at large have insisted that a more complete understanding of motivation
involves accounting for those motivational tendencies that welcome and/or propagate
creative change (Bühler & Allen, 1972; May, 1975).
Human development also involves a tendency toward self-enrichment. The purpose of
the self-enriching motivational tendency is to attain and cultivate a personally agreeable
quality of life and experience as a being-in-the-world. Here, interactions with one’s own
body, oneself, others, and the world at large are pleasing, not merely because tensions are
removed, but because the sustained interaction itself is invigorating. As growth proceeds
and the world takes on its more objective characteristic, the self-enriching tendency will
be joined by a burgeoning self-transcending motivational tendency. Self-transcendence
refers to the desire to be in contact with the world out of a care, concern, or dedication that
is aimed at things and others on their terms. Self-transcendent aims prevent the self from
becoming a system of self-concern, closed in upon itself. The purpose of the selftranscending motivational tendency is to relate to things and others in the most meaningful
and profound manner, overriding (without necessarily eliminating) concern for one’s own
enjoyment or self-interest. Under the galvanizing, streamlining auspices of self-enriching
and self-transcending motivational tendencies, homeostasis recedes in overall significance
and gives ground to something more akin to von Bertalanffy’s (1968) steady state or
Goldstein’s (1995) equalized centering. Likewise, reactive adaptation recedes in overall
significance in comparison to proactive adaptation. The self-system can, thereby, uphold
a vitalized tendency toward enhanced forms of organization with maximum efficiency.
EHSDT emphasizes understanding self-enriching and self-transcending motivational
tendencies, as they are most indicative of world-openness, openness to the future, growth,
and (as their names indicate) evolving selfhood. Historically, terms like self-realization,
self-actualization, and self-fulfillment have been used to highlight this growth-oriented
view of human development. For EHSDT, these terms refer to the dynamically motivated
process of situated becoming oneself in relation to time. To illustrate, EHSDT is more
profoundly appreciative of the present in comparison to developmental viewpoints rooted
in the natural sciences. For the latter, the present is an isolated “point” in time that is the
mere residue of past causes. For EHSDT, the present is not interpreted exclusively in
terms of the mere maintenance of what has been. The present may also be functionally
autonomous of the past. Optimally, the present is a gift, so experienced on the basis of an
affirming presence to self, others, and the world. The present is the paradoxical place
where what has been (one’s past) and what may be (one’s future) as deemed by “me in
my circumstances” comingle and are realized. The meaningful, experiactional dynamics
of the here-and-now are, thus, considered more central to understanding human development in terms of becoming oneself than clock time or “real” time, as it is sometimes
called. In childhood, time is lived primarily in the here-and-now and progressively spirals
outward as growth proceeds (DeRobertis, 2008; McAdams, 2015).
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
10
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
The past, in turn, is brought to life in the present looking forward to what is coming
from the future, whether immediate or distant. Human being is historical being, but not
in the mere sense of historical determinism. The meaningful learning experiences of the
past co-contextualize future growth. At the same time, how the person imaginatively
projects himself or herself toward the possibilities of future becoming provides a frame of
reference for interpreting the nature and significance of the past (i.e., what is deemed
“memorable”). One’s past and one’s future have a reciprocal relationship through the
medium of the present. To paraphrase May (1983), as people creatively construct their
future by shaking off defensive and/or habitual means of dealing with life circumstances,
they also reconstruct their past.
Finally, the future is not the temporal emptiness of quantified, measured time. The
future is pregnant with meanings to be fulfilled and can be motivating. Although it can
incite dread, it can also captivate and call one forward into the process of becoming
oneself. This perspective rests on the notion of a situated freedom engaged in the genuine
pursuit of aims, goals, and purposes throughout the lifespan. It requires the acknowledgment of human of intentionality in the specifically phenomenological sense of that term,
what May (1969) referred to as “the structure which gives meaning to experience . . . our
imaginative participation in the coming day’s possibilities” (pp. 223–224).
Social Context and Situated Becoming Oneself: Self-Cultivation
EHSDT insists on the primacy of the subject-subject relationship (Strasser, 1969) in
light of the fact that the aforementioned motivational tendencies require an adequately
nurturing field within which to emerge and operate. The infant’s vital functioning and
corresponding “functioning intentionality” (Husserl, 1969, p. 157) must be met with
welcoming for growth to ensue. Birth affords but a precursory experiactional organization,
which is only secured and readied for growth by holding and handling that is perceived
to be tender and capable of modulating the proximity of the potentially overwhelming
postnatal world (DeRobertis, 2008, 2012; Jaffe, Beebe, Feldstein, Crown, & Jasnow,
2001; Strasser, 1969; Winnicott, 1965). The caregiver’s comportment co-constitutes and
is ultimately interwoven within the child’s lived, owned body via the invitations of his or
her contact. Through his or her empathically discerning touch, the caregiver creates a field
within which the object world at large and the objective bodily characteristics of self and
others can become integrated within the child’s emerging consciousness in a calm, open,
nonthreatening way. Embodied cobeing emerges from a tactile “point of departure” that
establishes the hope, confidence, self-acceptance, self-respect, and self-worth necessary
for sustained world-openness and the evolution of a cooperative, cocreative disposition
toward being-with-others in the process of becoming throughout life.
Since becoming oneself is situated in a broader, cosmic-ecological setting, human
development is dependent upon culturally constructed meanings and customs that provide
structure and orientation in a world subject to infinite interpretations. These meanings are
co-constituted and co-transmitted via narrative means, attesting to the centrality of the
imagination and its creative power in human development at both the individual and
collective levels. Situated becoming oneself involves the emergence of a unique life story
nested within a multitude of larger stories, the nature and quality of which is subject to
infinite variation (Fancher, 1995/2017). Not all narratives are equal when it comes to
human development, however (see Wilber, 2017). Space constraints do not allow an
extended analysis of the relative quality of life narratives, but a few words may be said
based on what has been covered thus far.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
11
According to EHSDT, the structure and orientation that narratives provide best serve
self-development when they enhance one’s ability to connect to a wider world of meaning
and, thereby, achieve a more multifaceted, ambiguity-tolerant style of personal integration. Optimal narrative form secures a valued place for difference and for otherness while
paradoxically supporting the imaginative-integrative impetus of the self as one opens to
the manifold possibilities of relatedness in the sense of authentic presence, participation,
dialogue, and encounter. This kind of relatedness respects and preserves dialectical
process in the fluid realm of the in-between where the full reality of paradox becomes
manifest and the integrative strengths that allow one to make creative-productive use of
tension and/or conflict are promoted.
Sympathetic to this view, EHSDT has advanced the concept of self-cultivation as
exemplary for designating the unfolding process of human development conceived in
terms of situated becoming oneself (DeRobertis, 2015b, 2017). In doing so, phenomenological data are available to support EHSDT’s notion that self-cultivation thrives where
personal narratives bespeak (i.e., shape and are shaped by) a developmental partnership
between manifold forms of learning and creativity (DeRobertis, 2017). These reflect an
ever-expanding, hierarchically ordered system of values (see Bland & DeRobertis, 2017;
Wilber, 2017).
Research Orientation
As noted earlier, placing the unique developing person-in-process living in and
through his or her life circumstances means that EHSDT values and relies on a dialogue
between the general and the particular in data collection. Given that life circumstances
among individuals will share certain similarities (i.e., “each person’s inner nature is in part
unique to [oneself] and in part species-wide”; Maslow, 1999, p. 5, emphasis added), the
general or nomothetic is important. However, because the uniqueness of one’s life process
is never fully comparable (Strasser, 1977), to complement traditional and nontraditional
(e.g., modeling) quantitative methods that focus on the general level of normative trends,
one cannot ignore the rich potential of case-based, idiographic or morphogenic, and
microgenetic analyses to maintain contact with the variety and nuances of situated
psychological life (Bühler & Allen, 1972; Maslow, 1966).
The importance that EHSDT places on having a proper liaison between the general
and the specific by way of situatedness in the lifeworld has played a major role in its
having prioritized phenomenological data collection and analysis at the psychological
level of meaning. To illustrate, as Giorgi (1975) has developed phenomenology for
psychological application, the research process begins at the idiographic level with
situated findings and then moves on to derive general structural (eidetic) descriptions of
phenomena in a transition to the nomothetic level. His method is systematic, rigorous, and
open to dialogue with quantitative methodologies (Giorgi, 2009). With its phenomenological emphasis, EHSDT insists that developmental research should not remain exclusively tied to impersonal, third person, explanatory approaches to development. Rather,
data collection ought to be sensitive to the dynamics of the whole developing person and
include disciplined descriptive attempts to grasp development as a meaningfully structured individualized process. The striving to articulate anonymous predispositions, laws,
trends, norms, and so forth, are part of science as a matter of course, especially as
conceived as a natural science. For EHSDT, however, a counterbalancing human scientific
strategy is needed so that one may work with data that bring us ever-closer to the living
reality of the whole organism rather than spiraling off in the direction of increasing
12
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
abstraction. As Gurwitsch (1974) put it, “The sciences find the subject matter of their
study in the life-world; their purpose and sense are to provide a theoretical account of the
life-world” (p. 139). Phenomenology gives EHSDT research footing in the lifeworld
rather than the world as construed by the scientist in the abstract, looking on as a
disinterested, uninvolved observer.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
Theoretical Comparisons and Contrasts
Several theoretical perspectives have become standard inclusions in developmental
textbooks. Garnering greater or lesser degrees of coverage, these theories include Freudian
psychosexual theory, Eriksonian psychosocial theory, behavioral learning theory, social
learning or social– cognitive theory, Piagetian theory, and the theories of Vygotsky and
Bronfenbrenner as eco-sensitive alternatives for developmental theory. In this section, we
will briefly outline ways in which EHSDT is similar to and different from each of these
approaches. Before proceeding, it should be noted that we are engaging each theory in
response to what is regularly presented in college texts. It is beyond the scope of this
article to engage the larger debate over whether what is presented in college texts
represents the best, most accurate version of each theory (see Abramson, 2013; Bland &
DeRobertis, 2017; Churchill, 1988; DeRobertis & Bland, 2018; Ferguson, Brown, &
Torres, 2018; Henry, 2017; Weiten & Wight, 1992).
Freudian Psychosexual Theory
The typical developmentally oriented introduction to Freudian thinking in college
textbooks highlights the “instinctual” origins of development along with the tripartite
system of id, ego, and superego. Unconscious motivation is often stressed, including some
mention of defenses like fixation and regression within the context of the five psychosexual stages of development. EHSDT is in agreement with this viewpoint inasmuch as
human development is about desire and affect long before dispassionate, distanced
intellect becomes a potential mode of behavior. Human development is embodied, and this
includes pleasure-seeking or tension-reducing (homeostatic) tendencies, especially as one
faces transitions and setbacks (Bland, 2018b; Bland & DeRobertis, 2017). EHSDT also
sees the mental life of the developing person as graded and dynamic rather than naively
transparent. Moreover, like Freud, EHSDT also conceptualizes adult consciousness as
having a historical context, and that this context (i.e., one’s life history) normally involves
a degree of tension and conflict.
However, while EHSDT concedes that the psychosexual in human development
cannot be outstripped, it does not give overriding priority to the drive character of
development or to homeostatic motivational tendencies. The entire embodied, affective
life of the developing person is an integral part of a triune consciousness involving
affection, cognition, and volition simultaneously (Tallon, 1997, p. 202). In other words,
affective bodying forth operates within an intentional matrix that is nuanced beyond what
can be captured by the rigid bifurcation of mental life into animal impulses set against
rationality (adaptive or defensive).
EHSDT does not ascribe to the historical determinism of psychosexual theory either,
nor does it focus on fixation or regression beyond one’s life circumstances having
precluded the possibility of optimal functioning (Bland & DeRobertis, 2017). The past is
not assumed in advance to have precedence over other temporal modalities. Pathology,
even as Freud’s (1965) psychopathology of everyday life, is not prioritized over health.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
13
Rather, EHSDT holds that conflict can be a productive, progressive force in development.
Further, the conflictual unconscious is not assumed in advance to have precedence over
other unconscious processes, prereflective processes, or conscious processes responsible
for the creation of healthy tensions and integrative syntheses. Finally, EHSDT assigns an
important role to the development of genuine conscience as a self-transcendent process
and is not reducible to the superego’s fear of punishment (Allport, 1955).
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
Eriksonian Psychosocial Theory
Eriksonian psychosocial theory is regularly presented as a modern alternative to
traditional psychosexual theory. The aspect of Erikson’s work that is almost always given
focal attention is the manner that he revisited the psychosexual stages of development and
supplemented them with psychosocial stages revolving around ego needs (i.e., ego crises).
In addition to supplementing the five psychosexual stages, his work identifies and details
three stages of adult development. EHSDT aligns with psychosocial theory in that
embodied being, including the psychosexual, is socioculturally embedded. There is further
agreement concerning the notion that ego functioning in its many forms can contribute
important developmental support for growth and health.
Whereas Erikson approached development by taking the ego in its social adaptability
as his point of departure, EHSDT follows Knowles (1986) in suggesting a broader
approach to development that gives greater emphasis to the self’s “relationship to Being”
whereby “the person is not completely determined by others and the world nor does he or
she have complete control over them” (p. 15). That is, one does not have control over to
whom one is born, when, where, in what social class, and so forth. On the other hand, one
also is responsible for not becoming “lost in the ‘they,’ forgetting [one’s] own views and
conforming to [society’s] views” (p. 16) and/or distracting oneself from “basic issues,
such as . . . death” via mechanical “involvement . . . [in] everyday tasks” and “the ego
aspects of prediction and control” (p. 11).
Finally, although EHSDT is welcoming of stage conceptions of development, it is
important to note that contextually embedded experiaction tends to exceed what can be
captured by such frameworks. As we have noted elsewhere (DeRobertis & Bland, 2018),
Erikson was aware of this. The identification of discontinuous stages has not always been
meant to rigidly carve out certain times of life to deem them dictated by a certain kind of
psychological structure. Freud (1949) likewise rejected “clear-cut” stages (p. 26). EHSDT
holds that formalized developmental stages are socio-culturally emergent heuristic devices
(Bühler, 1968; DeRobertis, 2012). What are normally considered time-specific developmental issues are “worked on in some manner during all of the major periods of
development” (DeRobertis, 2008, p. 199).
Behavioral Learning Theory
The behavioral principles that take center stage in developmental texts are the same as
what one finds in most other introductions to behaviorism. The core concept of association
is presented as a function of classical conditioning and then again as a function of operant
conditioning with its various consequences for behavior. Concepts like extinction, spontaneous recovery, and Premack’s principle may also be presented. The overall gist of this
coverage is that human development is a passive process of being “shaped” by environmental contingencies.
Phenomenologically oriented views like EHSDT have more in common with learning
theory than may be assumed. As Kvale and Grennes (1975) observed, both behavioral and
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
14
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
phenomenological orientations reject the bifurcation of psychological life into an intracranial introspectionist or representationalist realm and a separate public sphere of worldly
interaction. Both have adopted a highly dialectical-relational epistemology of action that
highlights the critical role of learning in human development (DeRobertis, 2017). Finally,
as Skinner maintained throughout his career, radical behaviorism (like phenomenological
human science) places a premium on disciplined, systematic description over hypothesis
testing.
However, EHSDT departs from behavioral learning theory in that it envisions the
developing person-in-process as more than an object of environmental control and manipulation. Human development involves the emergence of intentional, meaning-making, world
co-constituting consciousness. This intentionality is embodied without being reducible to the
anatomical functioning of bodily processes, as humanistic psychologists such as Maslow have
sought to demonstrate (Arons & Richards, 2015). With EHSDT, there is no move to eradicate
the subjective pole of human psychological life. Healthy developmental progress gives rise to
an experiential (reflective, reflexive, contemplative) “inner” quality that endows one’s beingin-the-world with the quality of intimacy (Strasser, 1985, p. 113). Thus, from the perspective
of EHSDT, the study of any given conditioning process remains incomplete without some
form of attention being given to the experiential, meaning-bestowing dimension of the learning
process. Here, conditioning becomes experiactional and, thus, psychophysically neutral rather
than purely behavioral. Thus, the question of conditioning becomes, “What are the meaningfully structured experiences involved where environmental contingencies are felt to be exerting an influence on a developing person’s attempts to take up positions with respect to his or
her total bio-psycho-social-spiritual situation?” To be sure, learning as such in its many
typological variations has a phenomenologically derived experiactional structure that is highly
valued by EHSDT, but remains foreign to behavioral theory (DeRobertis, 2017).
Finally, EHSDT does not stress environmental influences on development to such an
extent that organismic structure is disregarded. Human development is supported by a
plastic, adaptable structural architecture displaying varied and changing needs that give
rise to general motivational tendencies (Bland & DeRobertis, 2017; DeRobertis, 2008,
2012; DeRobertis & Bland, 2018). The unfolding of human becoming does not begin as
behaviorism’s blank slate, nor does it occur by near fiat, as in Sartrean existentialism
(May, 1981; Strasser, 1963).
Social Learning or Social Cognitive Theory
Social– cognitive theory, formerly known as social learning theory, is presented in introductory texts as a contemporary alternative to traditional learning theory. Bandura’s (1971)
work is the standard for coverage, which typically highlights triadic reciprocal causation as
opposed to the strict stimulus-response (S-R) model inherent to conditioning theories. The
environment and behavior are now joined by a “person” (P) variable, which includes various
processes like attention, representation, and motivation, as well as issues related to performance (e.g., optimal arousal and self-efficacy). The observation of others is offered as a means
by which the person internalizes models of potential behavior, which then potentiates latent
learning. Should the person find himself or herself vicariously reinforced by what he or she
witnesses, the modeling effect is more likely to occur than otherwise.
EHSDT and social– cognitive theory concur that the person is important for understanding behavior as it occurs within specific environmental niches. They both assume that
representational activity (e.g., language) is important in mediating person, behavior, and
environment interactions, as well as the learning process in general. They are in further
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
15
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
agreement regarding the critical role of other human beings in codetermining psychic
structure and the development of one’s sense of competence. Proponents of both theories
have argued in favor of the human capacity to create self-regulatory processes from a
continuous flow of social interaction impacting the learner’s motives, values, and goals
(Bandura, 1971; DeRobertis, 2017). As stated by the phenomenologist Plessner (1964):
Imitating and objectifying proceed from one source, namely, [people’s] capacity to detach
[themselves] and to transform [themselves] into something else—in other words, [individuals’] remoteness from [themselves] of which [they are] fully cognizant, this is [their] eccentric
position. (p. 66)
However, whereas social– cognitive theory looks upon language as a mere representational tool, EHSDT considers language to be a formative aspect of both culture and
self-cultivation, operating on many levels of awareness simultaneously. The child is born
into a world that is replete with languages that offer prefigured meanings, which affect
(i.e., structure) experiactional possibilities of different kinds to varying degrees. Language
is more than an instrument of Bandura’s “P” variable (the person) to be used in effecting
causative reciprocation. Language is a living historical force that houses the means by
which a developing person may interpret and integrate the various aspects (physical,
cognitive, emotional, social, moral, and agentic) of his or her being-in-the-world. Human
development is narrative in nature, and the development of every person’s life narrative
takes its lead (though not its final form) from the myths, metaphors, and symbols furnished
by culture. For example, the Hindu namaste, for which there is no immediate English
equivalent, typically requires several English words and sometimes a discussion thereabout to comprehend by a novice whereas it is readily understood in Indian culture. The
person-in-process emerges from within a field where there is already a language-inprocess imbued with tendencies toward revealing some meanings, concealing others, and
influencing the power dynamics of his or her limited, situated freedom. In this sense,
language “has” the developing person long before he or she has language and, thus, is
never reducible to a mere possession, even though the final form of human development
requires the creative participation of the individual embedded within his or her particular
linguistic meaning-making matrix.
In effect, social– cognitive theory has not offered an account of language that is
profound enough to properly account for the creative power inherent to human development. From the perspective of EHSDT, social– cognitive theory is intellectualist leaning,
and by virtue of this intellectualism, it cannot shed light on the dynamics involved in the
embodiment of cultural meaning. Despite its laudable work in the areas of learning and
agency, social– cognitive theory shows little appreciation of depth, life’s paradoxes, or
conflict. The drama of human development goes largely unarticulated. And yet, somewhat
ironically, the intellectual life that plays such an important liberating role in social–
cognitive theory is denigrated by Bandura (1989, 2008), who dismisses the concepts of
freedom and autonomy on the basis of the straw man argument that such notions deny
human embeddedness within worldly conditions. Thus, as Deci and Ryan (2000) observed, social– cognitive theory “is not equipped to deal with a more complex and
meaningful conceptualization of agency” (p. 257):
[Because Bandura’s] theory does not distinguish between autonomous and controlled behaviors, it maintains, at least implicitly, that people who are pawns to reward contingencies or to
other controlling events are agentic so long as they feel able to carry out the activities they feel
coerced or seduced into doing. (p. 257)
16
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
Piagetian Theory
The work of Piaget has long been the exemplar for introducing students to the study
of cognitive development, and this introduction typically begins with an overview of
concepts such as schemas, assimilation, accommodation, and equilibration. What will
inevitably take center stage, however, are his qualitative distinctions among sensorimotor,
preoperational, concrete operational, and formal operational thought along with several
associated developmental achievements (i.e., object permanence, decentration, conservation, and abstract thinking, respectively).
EHSDT shares Piaget’s reliance on and inclination toward the use of qualitative
research, which is rarely highlighted (Giorgi, 2009). As Lourenço and Machado (1996)
observed, “Piaget believed that science begins with description, not explanation” (p. 149).
EHSDT shares Piaget’s conviction that the development of the intellect emerges from
bodily and perceptual engagement. Further, EHSDT and Piagetian theory hold that
intellection and reason can take on more concrete or more abstract forms (i.e., what
EHSDT refers to as relative embeddedness or salience).
EHSDT does not abide by the standard textbook presentation of Piaget, which only allows
for his qualitative distinctions in cognition to be understood as a rigid, stage-like ordering.
Taking a lead from Chapman’s (1989) reading of Piaget, EHSDT looks upon Piaget’s
qualitative distinctions as first and foremost characterizing different forms of engagement
involving varying manners of information gathering rather than positing lockstep phase shifts.
For EHSDT, Piaget provided a language to articulate various cognitive configurations involved in one’s situated, ever-changing world-relations. Given the developing person’s life
situation, he or she may require any one or some combination of sensorimotor, preoperational,
concrete operational, and formal operational thought for intellectual growth to occur. Rather
than seeing sensorimotor knowledge as de facto “primitive” or formal operations as de facto
superior to other forms of cognition, EHSDT first withholds (i.e., phenomenologically “brackets”) value judgments and asks how different kinds of engagement and information gathering
suit or are not suited to the developing person’s given life situation. Following Stern (2010),
no overriding priority is given to the achievement of an abstracting intellect. As psychological
life becomes more differentiated, increasingly withdrawn (i.e., abstract), salient forms of
knowing complement without necessarily “overriding” or negating more embodied and
embedded forms of knowing. As Strasser (1977) put it:
The process of withdrawal is simultaneously positive and negative. Positively, it signifies the
progressive differentiation, stricter articulation, and greater objectivating power of experience;
negatively, it signifies the estrangement and splitting of the natural unity of the person. An
ever increasing withdrawal would endanger the unity of the person. From living experience
[Erleben] “living-asunder” [“Zer-leben”] would develop. The various “withdrawals” must be
reincorporated into the wholeness of personal life. (p. 93)
To state the matter in Schachtel’s (1959) terms, more relatively autocentric forms
of perceiving and knowing are joined by more relatively allocentric forms of perceiving and knowing. However, the value of either of these cognitive modalities is a
matter of goodness-of-fit for the activities at hand. For EHSDT, optimal developmental progress is marked by the capacity to add new nuances to one’s personal
integration without losing touch with the fresh, vital, holistic perspectives that
preceded their arrival. EHSDT’s recoil from stage myopic Piagetianism rejects the
implication that human development involves a global transition from phenomenalism
to Kantian, scheme-based idealism.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
17
The emphasis that EHSDT places on preserving the integrity and value of embedded
cognition increases the relative importance assigned to the socioemotional aspects of cognitive
development. So, for example, Werner’s (1948) term “sensory-motor-affective” (p. 101) is
preferred over the Piagetian term sensorimotor when referring to embedded cognizing.
Further, EHSDT places greater importance on the role of motivation in learning and cognitive
development, particularly regarding the need for belonging (Maslow, 1987, 1999) or relatedness as it is sometimes called (Alderfer, 1972; Ryan & Deci, 2004). To illustrate, Topál et al.
(2008) showed that infants’ A-not-B errors are triggered by the communicative cues given by
the experimenter (e.g., eye contact, gaze shift, and addressing) rather than the age-based
cognitive deficiencies suggested by a Piagetian account of the phenomenon. Thus, the error is
a function of the inherently social character of human learning and the normal bonding
processes inherent to a positively functioning learning environment (DeRobertis, 2017).
Topál’s study touches upon a further point of divergence between EHSDT and Piagetian
theory, which is that EHSDT sees cognition as operating more squarely in light of the language
and communication systems the child has been born into as he or she strives to author a
workable and fulfilling life story. Schiff’s (1983) study of conservation using a classic
Piagetian estimation task can further illuminate the relative importance of language that is at
issue here. Schiff (1983) found that children (ages 3.5 to 5.5 years) who were unable to
conserve length when given verbal instructions but could then conserve length with parallel
nonverbal tasks did not fail to conserve because of centration, misleading perceptual information, or immature cognitive operations. Rather, the children did not yet possess the verbal
skills to understand what exactly was being asked of them in performing the task. In the light
of such data, EHSDT looks upon what Piaget referred to as “preoperational” less in terms of
a more primitive advancement toward logical operations and more in terms of a symbol-driven
transformation of the imagination that must remain accessible through adolescence and into
adulthood in moving toward the integration of postformal cognition (see Arnett, 2016). Here,
the last of EHSDT’s divergences from Piagetian thought is exposed, which is EHSDT’s
greater emphasis on the imagination in cognitive development. In Piaget’s work, the productive power of the imagination (“the opening up of new possibilities”) is not truly appreciated
until “preadolescence” or thereafter (Piaget & Inhelder, 1969, pp. 149 –150). For EHSDT, this
power is a core focus throughout the lifespan. As Bolton (1982) observed:
It may be supposed that in the normal process of conceptual development the child will progress
all the more when the situation captures his imagination. A good example of this is provided by
the literature on the attainment of conservation. As is well known, Piaget and his colleagues (see,
e.g., Piaget & Inhelder, 1969) found that children below the age of six or seven were unable to
solve conservation problems. However, Donaldson (1978) was able to make the test situation more
meaningful to the child by simplifying it or by introducing a “naughty teddy” to carry out the
transformations. Under such conditions children of 4 or 5 years admitted conservation. I would like
to suggest that what made the situation more meaningful for the children in these experiments was
not just the simplifications introduced. What appears to be crucial is that the new settings for the
Piagetian tasks were such as to allow the child to be present to the situation through his
imagination. He could respond with his feelings as well as with his thought. (p. 16)
Two Eco-Sensitive Alternatives: Vygotsky and Bronfenbrenner
The work of Vygotsky is typically presented in developmental texts as an alternative
to what is widely considered classic Piagetian thought. Bronfenbrenner, who was influenced in part by Vygotsky, is typically presented thereafter. The Vygotsky coverage will
offer zones of proximal development as an alternative to stages of development. The
highly influential, mediational nature of cultural tools will be noted, along with ideas
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
18
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
concerning the way in which learning is a function of the languages being utilized in the
student–teacher relationship. This will usually include some information about the pedagogical value of scaffolding. Finally, Vygotsky’s account of language development will
be discussed, consisting of highly social beginnings, eventually transitioning toward inner
speech. Bronfenbrenner is then mentioned with little more than reference to his ecological
systems model, spanning the microsystem through to the chronosystem.
Based on his analysis of cultural tools, Vygotsky (1986) found Piaget to have created
a developmental theory wherein the social is primordially “alien” to the child (p. 44). This
sort of critique has immediate and compelling appeal to humanistic- and phenomenologically oriented thinkers who share a social-contextual emphasis (e.g., DeRobertis, 2012;
Packer & Goicoechea, 2000). Given the important role that language, narrative, and
self-cultivation play in EHSDT, it is sympathetic to the Vygotskian emphasis on cultural
tools, which is stronger relative to Piagetian thought. EHSDT is no less sympathetic to
Bronfenbrenner’s attempt to articulate the intricacies of the developing person’s contextual field as a network of nested systems, the interactions among which serve as protective
and risk factors that enhance and/or preclude the possibility of optimal development
taking place (see Bland & DeRobertis, 2017; Masten, 2014).
Of all the theories mentioned above, it is the most difficult to speak to those of Vygotsky
and Bronfenbrenner because much of their theories are not mentioned in introductory textbooks at all. So, for instance, as the first author has discussed elsewhere (DeRobertis, 2012),
EHSDT shares Vygotsky’s convictions concerning the important role of the imagination in
human development, as well as his Adlerian insight that “a creature that is perfectly adapted
to its environment, would not want anything, would not have anything to strive for, and, of
course, would not be able to create anything” (Vygotsky, 2004, p. 29). Such ideas are nowhere
to be found in textbook coverage. Similarly, Bronfenbrenner (e.g., Bronfenbrenner & Morris,
2006) speaks to the way in which characteristics of the person affect proximal processes (i.e.,
particular forms of interaction between organism and environment) throughout development.
This line of analysis could form the basis of a dialogue with EHSDT, but it is not mentioned
in textbook introductions to Bronfenbrenner’s theory.
The dearth of material on these two theories in introductory texts makes the prospect
of speaking critically about them even more problematic. To engage in a critical dialogue
in a manner that does justice to each theory would require an entire discussion of their
lesser-known aspects, which far exceeds the scope of the current article. The case of
Vygotsky is particularly problematic, as controversies abound concerning the adequacy
of his translation into English (van der Veer & Yasnitsky, 2011). Generally, critiques of
Vygotsky tend to focus on the unfinished nature of his work, which have purportedly
resulted in lingering ambiguities in certain of his concepts (e.g., the zone of proximal
development). When viewed in terms of the concerns of EHSDT, this criticism has
relevance with respect to Vygotsky’s view of the imagination. As Saifer (2010) has noted
regarding Vygotsky’s analysis of play, “rules predominate in Vygotsky’s argument, while
the role of the imagination and the development of higher order thinking is secondary”
(p. 40). This seems to contradict the important role that Vygotsky assigns to the imagination in human development, as previously mentioned. Saifer then goes on:
Vygotsky’s essay on play ends with the enigmatic statement: “Superficially, play bears little
resemblance to what it leads to, and only a profound internal analysis makes it possible to
determine its course of movement and its role in the preschooler’s development.” This implies
that he left more to be uncovered to fully understand play. Vygotsky’s protégé Daniel Elkonin
did pick up the charge in his work, The Psychology of Play (2005), in which he argued at
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
19
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
length that the imaginary situation is the most prominent and vital aspect of play with the
greatest impact on development. However, this view does not appear to be widely accepted
and is not impacting practice. (p. 41)
Thus, in the light of Elkonin’s (2005) work, it appears that what looked to be a
divergence between EHSDT and Vygotskian theory has become a point of convergence.
How Vygotskian theory will handle EHSDT’s concerns with the mediational role of the
imagination in negotiating life’s many paradoxes and motivational growth tendencies
remains to be seen.
EHSDT has similar, perhaps more serious concerns with Bronfenbrenner’s work.
Bronfenbrenner tended to associate both imagination and creativity with fantasy, which is
common among natural scientific psychologies (e.g., Bronfenbrenner & Morris, 2006).
Bronfenbrenner (1979), for example, cited Piaget as rightfully assigning a certain constructive role to the child’s imaginative effort by noting that the child’s imaginings are a
kind of “fantasy” that create frustration and thereby motivate the child to overcome his or
her confusion of “the subjective and objective features of the environment” (p. 10). It has
become commonplace that the imagination is discussed in child psychology with terms
that denote the illusory, such as imaginary friends, imaginary play (i.e., “make believe”),
or imaginary audience. EHSDT deviates from this trend in considering the imagination to
be an ever-present and vital component of the real as socially co-constituted, that is, the
developmentally appropriate means by which children make sense of their world; thus,
deserving of a more robust explication of its significance in the incarnate child’s worldrelatedness.
Concluding Remarks
EHSDT’s future development will depend on further research in at least five general
areas to demonstrate the validity and/or viability of its principles. Particularly, attention
needs to be given to EHSDT’s assumptions that differ from the more conventionally
accepted but typically narrower-band theories reviewed above.
First, more research should be conducted on the role of the imagination in shaping the
trajectories of lifespan development, including emphases on narrative imagination, its
intercorporeal (i.e., interpersonally embodied) and multicultural embeddedness, and the
dynamics of meaning disclosure (i.e., meaning’s evocation, delimitation, modification,
and amplification). Second, this research ought to extend to the area of creativity, a topic
that is almost as neglected as the imagination and all too often studied from a merely
utilitarian point of view (e.g., as a means of “solving problems”). Readers are encouraged
to consult Arons’ writings on humanistic-existential-phenomenological approaches to
creativity as a starting point (see Bland, 2018a). Third, further research efforts ought to
focus on the diversifying connectivity characteristic of healthy human development,
particularly as it relates to the self-cultivation process. This work would necessarily
revolve around the dynamic interrelatedness of learning and creativity (see DeRobertis,
2017), resting on a notion of intentionality as cooperative way-of-life (i.e., culture)
creation (see von Eckartsberg, 1989). Fourth, paradox negotiation deserves systematic
study throughout the lifespan in conjunction with the self-cultivation process. Fifth, all
this work should be adjoined to research on human development’s dynamic motivational
complex operating within diverse social and cultural contexts.
Moving far beyond the reductionistic, homeostatic, and adaptive foci of natural
scientific psychology, such research requires the integration of human scientific, phenom-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
20
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
enologically oriented methods. From there (see Barrell, Aanstoos, Rechards, & Arons,
1987), once operational criteria are established and/or measures developed (as appropriate), quantitative methods are also recommended to present a convincing case to conventional developmental psychologists in a form most of them tend to value or, at least, are
more familiar with. This will help prevent further marginalization of explicitly humanistic
developmental theory on the basis that it challenges some of the fundamental assumptions
of the established theories and, accordingly, is likely to be met with resistance or, at best,
indifference. Thereafter, it seems inevitable that further reflection and subsequent qualitative inquiry will be in order, to further deepen the research base for EHSDT and to
continue its dialogue between the general and the specific.
References
Abramson, C. I. (2013). Problems of teaching the behaviorist perspective in the cognitive revolution.
Behavioral Science, 3, 55–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/bs3010055
Adler, A. (1979). Superiority and social interest. New York, NY: Norton.
Alderfer, C. P. (1972). Existence, relatedness, and growth: Human needs in organizational settings.
New York, NY: The Free Press.
Allen, J. (1976). A Husserlian phenomenology of the child. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 6, 164 –179. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/156916276X00052
Allport, G. (1955). Becoming. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Arnett, J. J. (2016). Human development: A cultural approach (2nd ed.). Boston, MA: Pearson.
Arons, M., & Richards, R. (2015). Two noble insurgencies: Creativity and humanistic psychology.
In K. J. Schneider, J. F. Pierson, & J. F. T. Bugental (Eds.), Handbook of humanistic psychology
(2nd ed., pp. 161–176). Los Angeles, CA: Sage. http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781483387864.n12
Bandura, A. (1971). Social learning theory. Retrieved from http://www.jku.at/org/content/e54521/
e54528/e54529/e178059/Bandura_SocialLearningTheory_ger.pdf
Bandura, A. (1989). Human agency in social cognitive theory. American Psychologist, 44, 1175–
1184. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.44.9.1175
Bandura, A. (2008). Reconstrual of “free will” from the agentic perspective of social cognitive
theory. In J. Baer, J. C. Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free? Psychology and free
will (pp. 86 –127). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:
oso/9780195189636.003.0006
Barrell, J. H., Aanstoos, A., Rechards, A. C., & Arons, M. (1987). Human science research methods.
Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 27, 424 –457. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022167887274004
Belenky, M. F., Clinchy, B. M., Goldberger, N. R., & Tarule, J. M. (1986). Women’s ways of
knowing: The development of self, voice, and mind. New York, NY: Basic.
Bland, A. M. (2018a). Remembering Mike Arons (1929 –2008): An annotated bibliography. The
Humanistic Psychologist. [Advance online publication.] http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/hum0000118
Bland, A. M. (2018b). The lightning bolt: A hope- and compassion-centered symbol of progress.
Samaritan Counseling Center 2017 Annual Report to the Community, 4.
Bland, A. M., & DeRobertis, E. M. (2017). Maslow’s unacknowledged contributions to developmental psychology. Journal of Humanistic Psychology. [Advance online publication.] http://
dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022167817739732
Bland, A. M., & McQueen, K. S. (2018a). The distribution of Chapman’s Love Languages in
couples: An exploratory cluster analysis. Couple and Family Psychology, 7, 103–126. [Advance
online publication.] http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cfp0000102
Bland, A. M., & McQueen, K. S. (2018b). Unemployment and marital quality in Great Recession
America: An exploratory canonical correlation. Journal of Humanistic Psychology. [Advance
online publication.] http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022167818779964
Bolton, N. (1982). The lived world: Imagination and the development of experience. Journal of
Phenomenological Psychology, 13, 1–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/156916282X00082
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
21
Bowen, M. (1978). Family therapy in clinical practice. New York, NY: Aronson.
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The ecology of human development: Experiments by nature and design.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bronfenbrenner, U., & Morris, P. A. (2006). The bioecological model of human development. In
R. M. Lerner & W. Damon (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Theoretical models of human
development (pp. 793–828). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Bühler, C. M. (1967). Human life goals in the humanistic perspective. Journal of Humanistic
Psychology, 7, 36 –52. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/002216786700700105
Bühler, C. M. (1968). The developmental structure of goal setting in group and individual studies.
In C. M. Bühler & F. Massarik (Eds.), The course of human life: A study of goals in the
humanistic perspective (pp. 27–54). New York, NY: Springer.
Bühler, C. M., & Allen, M. (1972). Introduction to humanistic psychology. Monterey, CA:
Brooks/Cole.
Bühler, C. M., & Marschack, F. (1968). Basic tendencies of human life. In C. M. Bühler & F.
Massarik (Eds.), The course of human life: A study of goals in the humanistic perspective (pp.
92–102). New York, NY: Springer.
Bühler, C. M., & Massarik, F. (Eds.). (1968). The course of human life: A study of goals in the
humanistic perspective. New York, NY: Springer.
Chapman, M. (1989). Constructive evolution: Origins and development of Piaget’s thought. New
York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Churchill, S. D. (1988). Humanistic psychology and introductory textbooks. The Humanistic
Psychologist, 16, 341–357. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08873267.1988.9976830
Combs, A. W. (1999). Being and becoming: A field approach to psychology. New York, NY:
Springer.
Combs, A. W., Richards, A. C., & Richards, F. (1988). Perceptual psychology: A humanistic
approach to the study of persons. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Crain, W. (2005). Theories of development: Concepts and applications (5th ed.). Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and the “why” of goal pursuits: Human needs and
the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11, 227–268. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1207/S15327965PLI1104_01
DeRobertis, E. M. (2000). The long-term significance of having been psychologically maltreated by
one’s maternal figure: An empirical-phenomenological investigation (Doctoral Dissertation,
Duquesne University). Available from ProQuest Dissertations and Theses database. (UMI No.
9991680).
DeRobertis, E. M. (2008). Humanizing child developmental theory: A holistic approach. New York,
NY: IUniverse.
DeRobertis, E. M. (2012). The whole child: Selected papers on existential-humanistic child
psychology. Charleston, SC: CreateSpace.
DeRobertis, E. M. (2015a). Philosophical-anthropological considerations for an existentialhumanistic ecopsychology. The Humanistic Psychologist, 43, 323–337. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1080/08873267.2014.961637
DeRobertis, E. M. (2015b). Toward a humanistic-multicultural model of development. In K. J.
Schneider, J. F. Pierson, & J. F. T. Bugental (Eds.), The handbook of humanistic psychology:
Theory research, and practice (2nd ed., pp. 227–242). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
DeRobertis, E. M. (2017). The phenomenology of learning and becoming: Enthusiasm, creativity,
and self-development. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/978-1349-95204-5
DeRobertis, E. M., & Bland, A. M. (2018). Tapping the humanistic potential of self-determination
theory: Awakening to paradox. The Humanistic Psychologist, 46, 105–128. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/hum0000087
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
22
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
DeRobertis, E. M., & McIntyre, S. (2016). Development through a humanistic lens. In R. Bargdill
& R. Broomé (Eds.), Humanistic contributions for psychology 101: Growth, choice, and
responsibility (pp. 117–132). Colorado Springs, CO: University Professors Press.
Dewell, J. A., & Foose, K. (2017). Marginalizing humanism, a preference for the objectifiable, and
moving on. The Journal of Humanistic Counseling, 56, 111–126. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/
johc.12047
Donaldson, M. (1978). Children’s minds. London: Fontana.
Elkonin, D. B. (2005). Psychology of play. Journal of Russian & East European Psychology, 43,
11–21. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10610405.2005.11059245
Erikson, E. H. (1963). Childhood and society. New York, NY: Norton.
Erikson, E. H. (1994). Identity and the life cycle. New York, NY: Norton. (Original work published
1959)
Fancher, R. T. (2017). Health and suffering in America: The context and content of mental health
care. New York, NY: Routledge. (Original work published 1995)
Ferguson, C. J., Brown, J. M., & Torres, A. V. (2018). Education or indoctrination? The accuracy
of introductory psychology textbooks in covering controversial topics and urban legends about
psychology. Current Psychology, 37, 574 –582. [Advance online publication.]
Firestone, R. W., Firestone, L., & Catlett, J. (2013). The self under siege: A therapeutic model for
differentiation. New York, NY: Routledge.
Frankl, V. E. (1983). The doctor and the soul: From psychotherapy to logotherapy (3rd ed.). New
York, NY: Vintage.
Freud, S. (1949). An outline of psycho-analysis. New York, NY: Norton.
Freud, S. (1965). The psychopathology of everyday life. New York, NY: Norton.
Frick, W. B. (1971). Historical perspective on holistic personality theory. In W. B. Frick (Ed.),
Humanistic psychology: Conversations with Maslow, Murphy, and Rogers (pp. 122–140).
Columbus, OH: Merill.
Friedman, M. (1964). The worlds of existentialism: A critical reader. Trenton, NJ: Humanities
Paperback Library.
Fromm, E. (1976). To have or to be? New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Gallagher, S., & Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent
development studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 211–233. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/
09515089608573181
Giorgi, A. (1975). An application of phenomenological method in psychology. In A. Giorgi, C.
Fischer, & E. Murray (Eds.), Duquesne studies in phenomenological psychology (Vol. 2, pp.
82–103). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/dspp197529
Giorgi, A. (2009). The descriptive phenomenological method in psychology. Pittsburgh, PA:
Duquesne University Press.
Goldstein, K. (1995). The organism. New York, NY: Zone.
Gurwitsch, A. (1974). Phenomenology and the theory of science. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Harter, S. (1999). The construction of the self: A developmental perspective. New York, NY:
Guilford Press.
Henry, C. D. (2017). Humanistic psychology and introductory textbooks: A 21st century reassessment. The Humanistic Psychologist, 45, 281–294. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/hum0000056
Husserl, E. (1969). Formal and transcendental logic. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-4900-8
Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., Feldstein, S., Crown, C., & Jasnow, M. (2001). Rhythms of dialogue in infancy:
Monographs for the society for research and child development. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.
Kegan, R. (1982). The evolving self: Problem and process in human development. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Knowles, R. T. (1986). Human development and human possibility: Erikson in the light of
Heidegger. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Koffka, K. (1931). The growth of the mind. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
23
Kohut, H. (1977). The restoration of the self. Madison, CT: International Universities Press.
Kvale, S., & Grennes, C. E. (1975). Skinner and Sartre: Towards a radical phenomenology of
behavior? In A. Giorgi, C. Fischer, & E. Murray (Eds.), Duquesne studies in phenomenological
psychology, Volume II (pp. 38 –59). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Lefrancois, G. R. (2001). Of children: An introduction to child and adolescent development
(9th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Levinson, D. J., Darrow, C. N., Klein, E. B., Levinson, M. H., & McKee, B. (1978). The seasons
of a man’s life. New York, NY: Ballantine Books.
Lourenço, O., & Machado, A. (1996). In defense of Piaget’s theory: A reply to 10 common
criticisms. Psychological Review, 103, 143–164. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.103.1.143
Maslow, A. H. (1966). The psychology of science: A reconnaissance. Chicago, IL: Gateway.
Maslow, A. H. (1987). Motivation and personality (3rd ed.). New York, NY: HarperCollins.
Maslow, A. H. (1999). Toward a psychology of being (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Wiley.
Masten, A. S. (2014). Ordinary magic: Resilience in development. New York, NY: Guilford Press.
May, R. (1967). Psychology and the human dilemma. New York, NY: Van Nostrand.
May, R. (1969). Love and will. New York, NY: Norton.
May, R. (1975). The courage to create. New York, NY: Norton.
May, R. (1977). The meaning of anxiety (rev. ed.). New York, NY: Norton.
May, R. (1981). Introduction. In J. P. Sartre (Ed.), Existential psychoanalysis. New York, NY:
Gateway.
May, R. (1983). The discovery of being: Writings in existential psychology. New York, NY: Norton.
McAdams, D. P. (2015). The art and science of personality development. New York, NY: Guilford
Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Child psychology and pedagogy. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Press.
Murray, E. L. (1986). Imaginative thinking and human existence. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne
University Press.
Murray, E. L. (2001). The quest for personality integration: Reimaginizing our lives. Pittsburgh, PA:
Simon Silverman Phenomenology Center.
Natanson, M. (1970). The journeying self. Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.
Newsom, J. S. (Director). (2015). The mask you live in [DVD]. New York, NY: Virgil Films.
Packer, M. J., & Goicoechea, J. (2000). Sociocultural and constructivist theories of learning:
Ontology, not just epistemology. Educational Psychologist, 35, 227–241. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1207/S15326985EP3504_02
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child. New York, NY: Basic.
Plessner, H. (1964). On human expression. In E. Straus (Ed.), Phenomenology: Pure and applied.
The first Lexington conference (pp. 63–74). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Romanyshyn, R. D. (1989). Technology as symptom and dream. New York, NY: Routledge.
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2004). Overview of self-determination theory: An organismic dialectical
perspective. In E. L. Deci & R. M. Ryan (Eds.), Handbook of self-determination research (pp.
3–33). Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.
Saifer, S. (2010). Higher order play and its role in development and education. Psychological
Science and Education, 3, 38 –50.
Schachtel, E. G. (1959). Metamorphosis: On the development of affect, perception, attention, and
memory. New York, NY: Basic. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/14419-000
Schiff, W. (1983). Conservation of length redux: A perceptual-linguistic phenomenon. Child
Development, 54, 1497–1506. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1129812
Schneider, K. J. (1990). The paradoxical self. New York, NY: Insight.
Schneider, K. J. (2013). The polarized mind: Why it’s killing us and what we can do about it.
Colorado Springs, CO: University Professors Press.
Simms, E. M. (2008). The child in the world: Embodiment, time, and language in early childhood.
Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
24
DEROBERTIS AND BLAND
Stern, D. N. (2000). The interpersonal world of the infant: A view from psychoanalysis and
developmental psychology. New York, NY: Basic.
Stern, W. (2010). Psychology and personalism (James T. Lamiell, Trans.). New Ideas in Psychology,
28, 110 –134.
Strasser, S. (1963). Phenomenology and the human sciences. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne.
Strasser, S. (1969). The idea of dialogal phenomenology. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University
Press.
Strasser, S. (1977). Phenomenology of feeling. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Strasser, S. (1985). Understanding and explanation. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Straus, E. W. (1975). The monads have windows. In P. J. Bossert (Ed.), Phenomenological
perspectives: Historical and systematic essays in honor of Herbert Spiegelberg (pp. 130 –150).
Leiden, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1646-9_8
Sweet, S. (2014). The work-family interface: An introduction. Los Angeles, CA: Sage. http://
dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781483387932
Tallon, A. (1997). Head and heart: Affection, cognition, volition as triune consciousness. New
York, NY: Fordham.
Teo, T. (2003). Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911) and Eduard Spranger (1882–1963) on the developing
person. The Humanistic Psychologist, 31, 74 –94. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08873267.2003.9986920
Tischler, H. L. (2010). Introduction to sociology. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Topál, J., Gergely, Gy, Miklósi, Á., Erdöhegyi, Á., & Csibra, G. (2008). Infants perseverative search
errors are induced by pragmatic misinterpretation. Science, 321, 1831–1834.
van der Veer, R., & Yasnitsky, A. (2011). Vygotsky in English: What still needs to be done.
Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 45, 475–493. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12124011-9172-9
Van Kaam, A. L. (1966). Existential foundations of psychology. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
van Manen, M. (2014). Phenomenology of practice. Walnut Creeek, CA: Left Coast.
von Bertalanffy, L. (1968). Organismic psychology and systems theory. Barre, MA: Clark University Press.
von Eckartsberg, R. (1979). The eco-psychology of personal culture building: An existentialhermeneutic approach. In A. Giorgi, R. Knowles, & D. L. Smith (Eds.), Duquesne studies in
phenomenological psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 227–244). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University
Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/dspp1979320
von Eckartsberg, R. (1989). The unfolding meaning of intentionality and horizon in phenomenology. The
Humanistic Psychologist, 17, 146 –160. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08873267.1989.9976848
von Eckartsberg, R. (1998). Existential-phenomenological research. In R. S. Valle (Ed.), Phenomenological inquiry in psychology: Existential and transpersonal dimensions (pp. 21–61). New
York, NY: Plenum Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-0125-5_2
Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Vygotsky, L. S. (2004). Imagination and creativity in childhood. Journal of Russian & East
European Psychology, 42, 7–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10610405.2004.11059210
Weiten, W., & Wight, R. D. (1992). Portraits of a discipline: An examination of introductory
psychology textbooks in America. In C. L. Brewer, A. Puente, & J. R. Matthews (Eds.),
Teaching of psychology in America: A history (pp. 453–504). Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/10120-020
Welsh, T. (2013). The child as natural phenomenologist: Primal and primary experience in
Merleau-Ponty’s psychology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. http://dx.doi.org/
10.2307/j.ctv47w5kg
Werner, H. (1948). Comparative psychology of mental development. New York, NY: International
Universities Press.
White, R. W. (1966). Lives in progress: Study of the natural growth of personality. New York, NY:
Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
DEVELOPMENT FROM A HUMANISTIC PERSPECTIVE
25
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
Wilber, K. (2000). Integral psychology: Consciousness, spirit, psychology, therapy. Boston, MA:
Shambhala.
Wilber, K. (2017). Trump and the post-truth world. Boulder, CO: Shambhala.
Wilson, E. O. (1984). Biophilia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Winnicott, D. W. (1965). The maturational process and the facilitating environment: Studies in the
theory of emotional development. London: Hogarth.
Woolfolk, A. (2016). Educational psychology (13th ed.). New York, NY: Pearson.
Author Note
Eugene M. DeRobertis is a Professor of Psychology at Brookdale College and a
Lecturer for the Department of Psychology at Rutgers University-Newark. He is the
author of The Phenomenology of Learning and Becoming: Enthusiasm, Creativity, and
Self-Development.
Andrew M. Bland is a member of the graduate clinical psychology faculty at Millersville University in Lancaster County, Pennsylvania. He serves as co-editor of the
newsletter for the Society for Humanistic Psychology.
Received June 12, 2018
Revision received October 5, 2018
Accepted March 11, 2019 䡲
View publication stats