Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2019, Deep Green Resistance News Service
…
6 pages
1 file
PARTY WITH ECOCENTRIC VALUES CHALLENGES THE POLITICAL ORTHODOXY IN TASMANIA. Ecocentrism is an all-encompassing concept that covers geo-diversity and biocentrism but extends the latter. Also, by definition, ecocentrism is the basis of calls for the Rights of Nature and is the fundamental basis of Deep Ecology (including Deep Green Resistance). Eco-centrism is the opposite of anthropocentrism. This creates a divide within the Green/environment/conservation movement – but a largely unacknowledged divide (however, United Tasmania Group [UTG] has experienced clashes with the anthropocentric section of this movement). As Kopnina et al point out (2018), anthropocentrism supports and is based on utilitarianism and human self-interest. They also argue that there is no such thing as ‘good’ anthropocentrism or, for that matter, ‘legitimate’ and ‘illegitimate’ human interests. I have argued elsewhere about the limitations and consequences of utilitarian and bureaucratic attempts to redefine wilderness (Holloway 2018). Anthropocentrism is not just about capitalism (or for that matter, socialism) and economic elites; it is about the ideology that privileges humans above the rest of nature (Kopnina et al, 2017).
Ecological Citizen, 2017
Ecocentrism is the broadest term for worldviews that recognize intrinsic value in all lifeforms and ecosystems themselves, including their abiotic components. Anthropocentrism, in contrast, values other lifeforms and ecosystems insofar as they are valuable for human well-being, preferences and interests. Herein, the authors examine the roots of ecocentrism and discuss its mixed history of international recognition. They argue that non-human nature has intrinsic value irrespective of human preferences or valuation, and they refute the claim that ecocentrism is misanthropic. They then summarize four key examples from the academic literature in which anthropocentrism fails to provide an ethic adequate for respecting and protecting planet Earth and its inhabitants. The authors conclude that ecocentrism is essential for solving our unprecedented environmental crisis, arguing its importance from four perspectives: ethical, evolutionary, spiritual and ecological. They contend that a social transformation towards ecocentrism is not only an ethical but a practical imperative, and they urge support for ecocentric understanding and practices.
By examining several versions of eco-centrism, I argue that environmental eco-centrism fails as a normative principle. Consequentialist versions fail since they cannot generate traditional moral principles and may in fact be inconsistent with traditional morality. Eco-centrism will therefore only make sense as a nonconsequentialist principle, particularly as a prima facie duty-based principle. However, duty-based eco-centrism also fails since the list of environmental duties it recommends will be the same as the list recommended on a purely anthropocentric approach. In short, eco-centrism is irrelevant to the process of both arriving at our environmental duties, and resolving conflicts with human duties.
JAST: Journal of American Studies of Turkey, 2009
World history has seen many manifestos-some political, others artistic. American author Scott Russell Sanders's environmentalist manifesto is uniquely visionary and inviting. Most manifestos are emphatic calls to action. Sanders's does more than that. In addition to offering a compelling formula for living human lives that take the future into account and will help to create "a culture of conservation," Sanders helps readers re-imagine what it means to be human in the context of the natural world, what it means to live in a way that considers the limitations and requirements, the "expectations," of the world beyond ourselves. The forty core declarations of his "Conservationist Manifesto" urge readers not to confuse financial wealth with real wealth, to understand that we must work collectively to protect our "common wealth," not only for our own good, but for the sake of generations to come.
The Anthropocene raises two interrelated problems for the Australian envir- onment movement. The first concerns the movement’s normative and political relationship to non-human nature: climate change in particular is forcing an urgent reconsideration of how nature is to be understood and managed. The second problem concerns the implications of full recognition of the rights of First Peoples for environmental justice. These issues may lead to crises of identity, legitimacy, and effectiveness for the Australian movement. The nor- mative bases upon which Australian environmentalists may draw in order to ‘protect nature’ in the Anthropocene are discussed. Setting aside the simple emancipatory ambition of preservationist environmentalism and the Australian movement’s earlier Romantic protectionism, a new pragmatic, plur- alistic environmental politics – based on precaution, the avoidance of pain and suffering, and protection of the most vulnerable – is suggested.
""In my last annual roundup for YWCCT, I review: 1. Timothy Morton's 'The Ecological Thought', Stacy Alaimo's 'Bodily Natures' and John Parham's 'Green Man Hopkins'. 2. A whole bunch of eco-poco collections and monographs. 3. Ecofeminism and queer ecology, including Greta Gaard, Carol Adams and the Sandilands and Erickson anthology. 4. The Oxford Literary Review selection of deconstructive ecocriticism (including Morton and Timothy Clark). I hope people find it useful.""
In the last 20 years, ecocriticism has developed from its early incarnation as the relatively under-theorised preserve of nature writing enthusiasts to its current vibrant state as a sophisticated array of ‘earth-centred’ approaches to cultural criticism that mobilise and reframe theories drawn from a range of disciplines in- cluding ecology, philosophy, sociology and biology. Ecocriticism’s diversity also extends to engaging with a variety of literary forms as well as, increasingly, film, TV, digital environments and music, and to an interest in representations of the urban. At its heart is the conviction both that we are living in a time of ecological crisis that requires us to reassess with some urgency our modes of being in the world and that our cultural perceptions of ‘nature’ and the ‘human’, and the relationship between the two, have to a large degree been responsible for these damaging modes of being. Its role is to interrogate and critique these perceptions, even within environmentalism itself, with some ecocritics also committed to exploring alternative ways of conceptualising our relationship with the non-human world. This paper briefly traces the history of ecocriticism, discussing its initial development in the USA and Britain, outlining the two strands of social ecology and deep ecology that underpin its ongoing formulation, and tracing the ‘waves’ of its development. It then focuses on contemporary and emergent theorisations, in particular the global inflection of current post-colonial ecocriticism and the environmental justice movement, which introduces the new paradigm of eco-cosmopolitics, and the recent formulation of ecocritical post- humanism. This emphasises the imbrication of the human in earth’s matrix, drawing on the insights of ecofeminism, phenomenology and biosemiotics, and has its most recent incarnation in the currently emerging field of material ecocriticism, which, in its engagement with the complex entanglement of the human and the non-human, the social and the scientific, hints at a more dissonant paradigm.
This paper discusses normative appeals to naturalness in ecocentric environmental ethics. First, it demonstrates the resemblance between these appeals, as they are framed in ecocentric moral thinking and classical naturalistic ethical theories such as stoicism and Aristotelian ethics. It goes on to consider two objections to which this resemblance seemingly renders ecocentrism vulnerable: the naturalistic fallacy objection and the natural evils objection. The paper argues that raising the naturalistic fallacy objection against ecocentrism conflates an issue of normative ethics with a metaethical one. The issue of whether something can be good because it is natural is distinct from the issue of whether value concepts can be reduced to concepts referring to natural properties. The paper then defends ecocentrism from the natural evils objection, which argues that what is natural cannot be good because too many harmful events occur in the natural world. That objection conflates two ways of saying that something is valuable. What it shows is that natural events are sometimes bad for humans, whereas ecocentrism holds that nature is valuable independently of its goodness for human beings. It has been argued that this nonanthropocentric stance gives rise to the further objection that ecocentrism is committed to sacrificing human life and well-being when doing so is required to maintain ecosystems in a healthy state. The paper responds to this concern by emphasizing both the prima facie nature of ecocentric duties as they are understood by prominent ecocentrists, and the convergence between the good of humans and that of ecosystems.
Ecological Citizen, 2017
It has been noted that (early childhood) experiences with Nature enhance environmental values (Wells et al., 2007). These findings suggest that Nature activities in childhood and youth are key pathways that lead people to take an interest in Nature and later work for its protection. Yet, early exposure alone does not explain why some people who grow up next to forests do not try to stop the logging, while others from the same villages do. This question of why some come to ecocentrism and some do not is fascinating. Like others, I have no perfect answer. In the documentary film If A Tree Falls: A Story of The Earth Liberation Front, environmental activist Daniel McGowan reflects that he grew up as a typical ‘city boy’. He came to care about Nature from watching a film about deforestation when he was in his twenties (discussed in Kopnina, 2014). It appears difficult to discern why some individuals choose to stand up for Nature and others do not, this commitment seems to vary individually, independent of culture, as I describe in my articles and books. In reflecting what wilderness means for me, I have three lived experiences to relate.
2011
In 'Respect for Everything', David Schmidt rightfully criticizes species egalitarianism, buts neglects an even more fundamental problem. Ecocentric egalitarianism is not only self defeating, but in fact ultimately entails a morally dubious radical anthropocentrism. Perhaps the morally most troubling aspect of anthropocentrism is not its assumption that humans are superior to non-humans, but that what matters to human beings is true in an absolute sense. Taylor's argument that there are no valid moral reasons to consider humans superior, assumes that it is in principle possible to compare the value of both humans and non-humans, and that it would make sense to use normative expressions such as ‘superior’ and ‘inferior’ objectively, e.g. outside the particular context of a human ethical outlook. Yet, evaluative concepts only have meaning within that context. To suggest that ethical concepts have meaning in an absolute sense, implies that the human moral perspective has absolute validity, and thus entails a radical form of anthropocentrism..
Methods in Molecular Biology, 2018
Karaman Dil-Kültür ve Sanat Dergisi, 2005
Epilepsy & Behavior, 2014
Penerbit BRIN eBooks, 2023
Makedonsko farmacevtski bilten, 2022
Psychotherapy: Theory, Research, …, 1997
Discorso alla Catholic Fraternity of Charismatic Covenenat Communities and Fellowships
International Journal of Cardiology, 2013
Applied Radiation and Isotopes, 2000
Aging & Mental Health, 2017
The Annals of the …, 2009
Environmental Engineering and Management Journal
Kajian Moral dan Kewarganegaraan, 2020
Inverse Problems & Imaging, 2013
Applied Mathematical Sciences
The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery, 2014