1
Wrongful Convictions and the State Risk Harm Paradigm
Dr. Myles Frederick McLellan*
* LL.B. (J.D.); LL.M. (Osgoode); Ph.D (Anglia Ruskin). The author is a Professor of Law and Justice in
the Department of Law and Politics at Algoma University; a member of the Policy Review Committee for
the Canadian Criminal Justice Association and the Founder and Director of the Innocence Compensation
Project.
1.0 Introduction
It is a fundamental organizing principle of risk reduction and avoidance in western criminal
justice systems that the rate of false positives society is prepared to accept is low and the rate of
false negatives or acquittals of the guilty is correspondingly high. This principle is often
epitomized in what is referred to as Blackstone’s ratio “It is better that ten guilty persons escape
than that one innocent suffer.”1
The risk of error during modern liberalism fell to the State to protect the factually innocent
from being wrongly convicted. The 1960’s ushered in an era of protection for due process rights
that continued for a quarter of a century in the United States and certainly for the first decade
following the enactment of The Charter of Rights and Freedoms2 in Canada after 1982.
Thereafter however, the importance of considerations of the antithetical principles of crime
control and public safety in a neo-liberal society engendered a shift in the risk of error to fall on
the person who is thought to pose a risk of harm. The movement away from the protection of
rights to the efficiency of crime control in the criminal justice system as aptly defined by Packer3
will be demonstrated. This paper will firstly show how the Supreme Court of Canada4 has raised
the risk of error for false positives by constitutionally advancing “societal interests” over Charter
due process rights that would otherwise guard against the recognized systemic factors that lead to
wrongful convictions.5
1
Blackstone, William, (1765-1769) Commentaries On the Laws of England.
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the
Canada Act 1982 (UK), 1982, c.11
3
Herbert Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction. (Stanford, Stanford Univ. Press, 1968)
4
Hereinafter referred to as the “Court” unless indicated otherwise
5
These rights include the presumption of innocence, the burden of the prosecution to prove the elements of an
offence beyond a reasonable doubt, the prosecution’s obligation for disclosure, the right to silence, the right to
counsel, protection against unreasonable search and seizure, bail and the right to speedy trial. Most of these rights
will be discussed with a view as to how their exercise has an effect on the factors leading to wrongful convictions,
including their implications for tainted eyewitness identification, problematic police interrogation procedures, false
confessions, and perjured jailhouse informant testimony. The right against unreasonable search and seizure, the
2
2
2.0 Risk Theory
Michel Foucault introduced the term governmentality in the 1970s as a function of his
writings on political power.6 Foucault argued that a certain way of thinking that he called
governmentality had become the common ground of all modern forms of political thought and
action. In part Foucault was making sense of the transformations in the art of governance that
was underway in the western world. These transformations took the form of substantial criticism
to the welfare state, universal insurance, and virtually all aspects of the social state that had taken
place in the first three quarters of the twentieth century. Modern liberalism was replaced by
neoliberalism which created a revised rationality for government in the name of freedom and
utilized a range of techniques that enabled the state to divest itself of many of its obligations by
responsibilizing non-state entities.
In 1991 papers were written by Francois Ewald and Robert Castel that examined risk
within the context of this analytic framework.7 These “landmark papers in the development of
governmental approaches to risk…are worth special attention”8 Risk for governmentality is a
political rationality that provides a framework for envisaging and dealing with problems. The
distinguishing characteristic of risk is that it is a particular way in which problems can be viewed
or imagined. What is specific to risk is that large numbers of events can be sorted into a
distribution and that distribution in turn can be used as a means of making probabilistic
predictions. According to Pat O’Malley, for governmentality “attention therefore is paid to the
ways in which the increasingly prevalent adoption of risk as a framework of government creates
new subjectivities and redefined relationships”9 Simply put “to govern something as a risk is to
identify a future condition as being more or less probable, and to set in train ways of responding
that will affect this probability in some way.”10
For Ewald insurance was seen as a method that could spread risks over a population for
future specified but uncertain harms. Insurance is not interested in creating detailed case records
of every insured party or object; rather it focuses on relevant “risk factors” that act as predictors
of insured events. In this way “risk pools” are created wherein a group of identified interests
right to bail and the right to be tried within a reasonable time will not be dealt with in this paper as these rights are
not endemic to wrongful convictions.
6
Michel Foucault (1978) “Governmentality” in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Graham Burchell,
Colin Gordon, Peter Miller, eds. (Chicago, The Univ. of Chicago Press, 1991) pp.87-104.
7
Francois Ewald “Insurance and Risk” (Chp.10) and Robert Castel “From Dangerousness to Risk” (Chp.14) in The
Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, Peter Miller, eds. (Chicago, The
Univ. of Chicago Press, 1991)
8
Pat O’Malley, Governmentality and Risk: Social Theories of Risk and Uncertainty, J. Zinn ed. (Oxford, Sydney
Law School Research Paper, 2008) at p.4.
9
Ibid at p.10.
10
Ibid at p.3.
3
have a similar probability of experiencing some uncertain condition in the future for which
insurance will deal with in an agreed upon way. Castel on the other hand outlined the
engagement of risk technologies in relation to the practice of psychiatry. While Ewald and his
reflections on insurance dealt with spreading of risks, the fundamental feature for Castel
psychiatric model was risk reduction. Indeed Castel identified risk reduction as the central
theme of the new preventative policies.11 The rise of risk as a way of thinking transformed
decision making for mental health issues and gave way for actuarial management over clinical
intervention. As with insurance, the presence of a risk factor for the purposes of a psychiatric
diagnosis consigned prospective patients to a risk pool. In this way suggested preventative
strategies working on whole categories of people removed the notion of the subject or concrete
individual and put in its place a combination of factors of risk for the purposes of such diagnosis.
At the same time as the release of this governmentality literature in the early 1990s,
Ulrich Beck provided an alternate strategy on the importance of risk in relation to governance
which he called “risk society”.12 For Beck it was “uncertainty” as the primary non-probabilistic
way in which government based expectations on how the future was likely to unfold that was
central. While Beck recognized that risks involved statistical predictions of the future,
“uncertainty” consisted rather of other organized forms of prediction which included
professional judgment and rules of thumb. He saw that “modernization risks” such as global
warming, ozone layer depletion and nuclear accident were threats to human existence and could
not be the subject of statistical analysis. These were “one-off” events. However, O’Malley
argues that “uncertainty” should not be regarded simply as the “incalculable” alternate to risk,
but as a distinct way of governing that includes the broader category of “foresight”. This also
does not mean that with the ubiquitous focus on the government of risks that one should
necessarily assume that risks have become greater than was once the case. What has changed is
the “increased propensity to govern in terms of risk”13
The difference in approach between the governmentalists and the risk society theorists is
that the former see risk as a probabilistic prediction based on the distribution of events and the
latter center upon uncertainty as an estimation of future harm based upon judgment. For the
purposes of this paper and the implications of risk theory as applied to criminal justice it is
probabilistic risk based governance that is of primary importance as a means of risk reduction,
particularly in light of the observation that since the 1970’s “no risk has preoccupied Americans
more than that of crime.”14 This was a function of what David Garland saw as three social
11
Castel, supra at note 7, pp. 281,288.
Ulrich Beck, Risk Society: Toward a New Modernity (London, SAGE Publishers, 1992).
13
O’Malley, supra at note 8, p.5.
14
Jonathan Simon, (2005). "Risk and Reflexivity: What Socio-Legal Studies Add to the Study of Risk and the Law
Meador Lecture Series 2004-2005: Risk and the Law." Ala. L. Rev. 57: 119 at p.129.
12
4
developments in the last quarter of the twentieth century that formed the basis of a change in
sociological and criminological discourse as a result of an emerging culture of control. 15
It was in the light of changing middle-class attitudes to crime and control that this
transformation took place. The first change took hold as a function of the organizational
adjustments to middle class lifestyles. The transportation of children to school and child care,
long commutes to work, and significant dissassociative realities to the familial environment all
led to “the new element of precariousness and insecurity…into the fabric of everyday life.”16
Garland rationalized this to the creation of an enhanced need in society to establish control over
risks and uncertainties. This, in turn, resulted in a need to know about the exposure of risks from
the criminal justice system and heightened awareness of “dangerous” others.
The second development was the defining of deviance down resulting from the lessening
ability of the sovereign state in crime control. The relaxation of law enforcement at the lower
end of the crime pool produced increasing public anxiety about the security being provided for
all those perceived criminal activities pervasive in modern society. In turn, the third change
further exacerbated the “crime consciousness” with the impact of mass media and the popular
depictions of crime that led the audience to fear crime as an everyday event that potentially
victimized an exaggerated number of individuals on a regular basis. Garland summed up these
historical circumstances emphasizing high crime rates and increased insecurity in the
institutional form of the “crime complex”17 In this regard, he examined the changes to the
criminal justice systems in the two “late-modern” societies of the United Kingdom and the
United States at the macro-level to view the structural patterns and to identify the changes in
criminological theory and crime prevention.
In the last thirty years in Canada and other western liberal democracies, there has been a
growing concern that:
… “justice” is very much under threat in the “risk society”. In contemporary western
societies adherence to long held principles of justice is endangered by excessive concern
with safety: fear of crime and fear of terrorism are rational fears, but are heightened to the
point where they overwhelm our care for liberty and justice.18
15
David Garland, The Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in Contemporary Society (Chicago, The
University of Chicago Press, 2001).
16
Ibid at p.155.
17
Ibid at p.163.
18
Barbara Hudson, Justice in the Risk Society: Challenging and Re-Affirming Justice in Late Modernity. (London,
Sage Publications, 2003) at p. x (Introduction).
5
In this regard, the widespread application of risk theories as they have evolved over the
past three decades has dominated the way governments, private enterprise and individuals organize
their everyday activities.19
Before this dramatic shift in criminological discourse, for more than a century there was a
penal welfarism that was underscored with the liberal ideals of “due process and proportionate
punishment with a correctionist commitment to rehabilitation, welfare and criminological
expertise”.20 As part of the progressive movement in the 1960’s to address discrimination, calls
were made to protect minority rights by enhancing prisoner’s rights, restrict state power and
promote decarceration. With respect to punishment, this movement supported replacing
indeterminate sentencing with more fixed and certain penalties within the framework of
sentencing guidelines. What ending up happening over the course of the next two decades
however was the opposite. What occurred was the unforeseen utility of greater incarceration
primarily as a function of a litany of offences that attracted mandatory minimum sentences and
pervasive hard line policies of deterrence.
Starting in the 1970’s, crime came to be seen not as a problem centred upon individual
deviance needing correction through rehabilitation, but rather a matter that required severe
controls, disincentives and segregation of offenders. To a great degree this shift was the
realization that “the threat of crime has become a routine part of modern consciousness, a
standing possibility that is constantly to be ‘kept in mind’. Crime has become an everyday risk
that must be routinely assessed and managed.”21
This changing outlook on crime control and prevention was heralded with the recognition
that governments as sovereign states were incapable of being the sole providers of law and order.
In turn, this engendered a focus on the effects of crime rather than the causes. Garland described
the two strategies that developed in this environment as firstly the creation of the preventative
partnership between the government and the private sector, and secondly punitive segregation.
19
In 1985, Stan Cohen wrote that the individual had ceased to be the concern of an emerging generation of
criminology, criminal justice and social control and said “…what is being monitored is behavior…No one is
interested in inner thoughts…the game is up for all policies directed to the criminal as an individual, either in terms
of detecting (blaming and punishing) or causation (finding motivational or causal chains)..The technological
paraphernalia directed at the individual will now be invested in cybernetics, management, systems analysis,
surveillance, information gathering and opportunity reduction. This might turn out to be the most radical form of
behaviourism imaginable – prevention of the act of crime by the direct control of whole populations, categories and
spaces.” Stanley Cohen, Visions of Social Control: Crime, Punishment and Classification (Cambridge, Polity Press,
1985) pp. 146-147. In 2001, David Garland stated that “This desire for security, orderliness, and control, for the
management of risk and the taming of chance is, to be sure, an underlying theme in any culture. But in Britain and
America in recent decades that theme has become a more dominate one, with immediate consequences for those
caught up in its repressive demands, and more diffuse, corrosive effects for the rest of us.” David Garland, The
Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in Contemporary Society (Chicago, The University of Chicago Press,
2001) at p.194.
20
Ibid at p.27.
21
Ibid at p.105.
6
The latter approach endorsed the turn to harsher sentences and the increasing use of
imprisonment. At the same time, the engagement of professional expertise diminished
significantly in the arena of policy making in the face of highly politicized decision making.
All of these transitions as described by Garland were the result of what he termed the
“increased salience of crime”22 This shift away from the rehabilitative approach to the welfare
state resulted into what was termed “actuarial justice”.23 Whereas the primary concern of “penal
modernism” was directed to the rehabilitation of individual offenders, the “new penology”
adopted a risk model of governance based upon probabilities and statistical distributions. This
was not unlike Castel’s position relative to changes in the treatment of mental illness where risk
factors and actuarial management of risk populations replaced clinical assessment. Indeed:
…the new penology is markedly less concerned with responsibility, fault, moral
sensibility, diagnosis, or intervention and treatment of the individual offender. Rather, it
is concerned with techniques to identify, classify, and manage groupings sorted by
dangerousness. The task is managerial, not transformative. It seeks to regulate levels of
deviance, not intervene or respond to individual deviants or social malformations.24
As such, the new penology’s goal was not to eliminate crime but to make it tolerable
through systemic coordination. The emerging risk techniques in crime control tended to use
statistical methods to correlate pre-existing conditions and criminal actions and to treat these
conditions as “risk factors”. These factors were used to identify individuals as part of a category
of potential offenders and thereby assign them to a certain “risk pool”.25 It was “risk
categorization” rather than the uniqueness of individuals that became of interest.
2.1: Risk, the Law and Wrongful Convictions
For the purpose of risk reduction, the law is a risk technique which is used to shape the
conduct of individuals in relation to things identified as risks. With particular regard to what has
become a safety-dominated forward looking approach, the law may restrict the rights and
liberties of individuals not because of what they have done in the past but solely to protect
society against a perceived risk of causing harm in the future. In this way, law can be used to
manage, control and sometimes incapacitate members of groups that are seen to pose a risk.
22
Ibid at p.152.
23
Martin Feeley and Jonathan Simon, (1992). The new penology: Notes on the emerging strategy of corrections and
its implications. Criminology, 30, 449; Martin Feeley and Jonathan Simon, (1994). Actuarial justice: The emerging
new criminal law. In D. Nelken (ed.) The Futures of Criminology (pp. 173-201). London: Sage Publications.
24
25
Ibid, at p.452.
Pat O’Malley, Crime and Risk (London, Sage Publishing, 2010) at p.2.
7
It is hard to deny that there are some circumstances in which the State has the right to
restrict liberty in order to protect the public. However, this inevitably leads to considerations of
just who should belong to the “risk pool” where liberty is to be curtailed as a probalistic
prediction rather than a materialization of harm. This raises the problem of over-inclusiveness
and the prospect of false positives in the criminal justice process resulting in wrongful
convictions.
2.2: Risk Reduction
Potential offenders have become a risk to the public which “inevitably permeate[s]
through the courts into thinking about rights.”26
Liz Campbell relying upon Garland contextualizes these propositions by seeing that
“throughout the pre-trial stage of the criminal process, the court-hearing and sentencing, a shift
in focus from the due process rights of the accused towards the result-oriented aims of the State
is apparent.”27 Barbara Hudson, as well, believes that justice has become now very much less
important than risk as a preoccupation of criminal justice conceptualized by neo-liberalism.28
The law and order agenda of western governments has emboldened a significant shift from doing
justice to managing risk as its goal. This leads one inexorably to consider to whom are rights
owed and under what circumstances can they be derogated.
The rights and freedoms enshrined in the Charter that are most often engaged in the
criminal justice process are the fundamental freedoms found in s.2; legal rights in ss.7 to 14; and
equality rights as set out in s.15. It has been suggested that such rights and freedoms exist in a
hierarchy that are differentiated according to the permissibility of their derogation. 29 At the top
of the hierarchy are rights which are non-derogable, rights which must be upheld in all
circumstances and must never be suspended for public interest reasons. These are the “right to
life; the right not to be subjected to torture or to inhuman or degrading treatment; the right not to
be subjected to forced labour, and the right not to be subjected to retrospective criminal law or
penalties.”30 These protections are most broadly contained in Canada under s.7 of the Charter.
The second level of rights is often referred to as the fair trial rights which most importantly
26
Ibid, at p.467.
Campbell, L. “Decline of Due Process in the Irish Justice System: Beyond the Culture of Control” (2006)
Hibernian Law Journal, 125 at p.129.
27
Barbara Hudson, “Punishment, rights and difference: defending justice in the risk society” Chapter 8, at p.144
in K. Stenson and R. Sullivan, (eds.), Risk, Crime and Prudentialism Revisited. Crime, Risk and Justice: The
Politics of Crime Control in Liberal Democracies, (London, Willan 2012).
28
29
See: Emmerson, Ben, Ashworth, Andrew, Macdonald, Alison (Eds.), Human Rights and Criminal Justice (2 nd)
(London, Sweet & Maxwell, 2007).
30
Hudson, supra at note18, p.69.
8
contain the rights to due process. In the Charter, these rights are most particularly found in ss.7
to 14.31 These rights are not absolute and may be rescinded on occasion, but it is argued that
they should be limited only under the most pressing circumstances and that their suspension
requires very powerful justification32. Third-level rights may be suspended or curtailed when
necessary for national security, or when they interfere with the rights of other persons or groups.
These third level rights include the right to freedom of expression, the right to freedom of
thought and religion, the right to freedom of assembly and association, and the right to respect
for private life. In Canada, these rights are referred to as fundamental freedoms as found under
s.2 of the Charter. These third-tier rights are best regarded by some scholars as civil rights
rather than human rights33. This is the case because these rights or freedoms can vary over time
with a change in the cultural context.
Hudson believes that the evolving systems of risk control “violate some of the
fundamental tenets of due process”34 and by doing so appear to allow derogation of second tier
rights. As such, the risk pool of those accused of criminality is subject to the exposure of a
higher risk of harm due to a diminishment of rights that are intended to provide constitutional
constraints on the investigative and prosecutorial powers of the State.
3.0 Risk of Wrongful Conviction
"In the end, a good lawyer is the best defense against wrongful convictions"35
At no time in the criminal justice process is the risk of error more acute than at the
investigatory stage of a case, both pre- and post-charge where the police are gathering evidence
in their pursuit to establish both the existence of criminality and their case against the accused.
An error made by the police which points their investigation to an accused who is in fact,
innocent, is not easily undone and may well lead to a wrongful conviction. Due process rights
and the rules of evidence are existing safeguards for all accused defendants.
31
More particularly, these rights include the right to be secure against unreasonable search and seizure; the right not
to be arbitrarily detained or imprisoned; the right upon arrest or detention to be informed of the reasons therefor and
to retain counsel without delay; the right to be informed of the predicate offence without delay; to be tried in a
reasonable time; to be presumed innocent until proven guilty; not to be denied reasonable bail; the right against double
jeopardy and the right not to give self-incriminating evidence.
32
Hudson, supra at note 28 p.27.
33
Ibid at p.69.
34
Ibid.
35
Janet Reno, Remarks at the American 2000 National Symposium of Indigent Defence, as noted in A.P.D. Worden
Andrew Lucas, Elizabeth Blaize Brown "Patchwork of Policies: Justice, Due Process, and Public Defense across
American States, A." (2010) Alb. L. Rev. 74: 1423 at p.1423.
9
The Charter’s legal rights provisions in sections 7 through 14 impose constitutional
restraints on the investigative powers of police, protections that are supplemented by guarantees
that are directed at ensuring fair treatment for individuals once they are detained or charged with
a crime. These guarantees, combined with the remedial provision of section 24(1) and the
discretion to exclude unconstitutionally-obtained evidence under section 24(2) exist to strike a
proper balance between the interests of the individual and societal interests as determined by
State decisions to restrict those rights. It is the job of defence counsel to energetically and
vigorously defend the constitutional rights of her client so that the existence of factual innocence
translates to a dismissal or withdrawal of proceedings before trial, or a finding of not guilty at
trial.
The Charter’s promotion of due process started out in earnest with three early judgments
by the Court36 giving clear recognition that the Charter's role is to control legislative
abridgments of rights. The Court held that if the police undertook an activity that allegedly
breached a right that afforded an accused protection under the Charter, it was the court’s role to
uphold that right against the actions of the state. Nevertheless, and over time the Court has
narrowed the opportunity for defence counsel to successfully argue that evidence gathered by the
police should be excluded at trial on the basis that the defendant’s rights have been infringed.
Firstly the analysis of the Court’s scrutiny of constitutional rights as it was conducted within the
parameters of section 1 will be discussed, followed by a review as to how the Court has moved
that review from section 1 to an examination of an alleged breach of rights as found in a specific
section.37 This is particularly important for the protection of Charter rights in the face of police
activity that has not been authorized by either statute or the common law. Such activity is
particularly relevant when the right to counsel, the right to remain silent and how confessions are
admitted into evidence are at play, together with otherwise tainted evidence such as mistaken
eyewitness identifications and jailhouse informant testimony. Lastly it will be seen that the
Court has dramatically restricted the exclusion of evidence, even when it is constitutionally
tainted because there now exists a presumption of good faith on the part of police conduct.
As a precursor to reviewing the protections to an accused as provided by the due
process provisions of the Charter, it is important to state that underscoring these rights is the
presumption of innocence. The presumption of innocence has a significant historical pedigree
and is the backbone of the common law approach to administering the criminal law. The House
of Lords' timeless statement in Woolmington v D.P.P.38 remains relevant today:
36
R v Big M Drug Mart [1985] 1 SCR 295; Hunter et al v Southam Inc. [1984] 2 SCR 145; Andrews v Law Society
of British Columbia [1989] 1 SCR 143.
37
The evolution on this approach to challenging the abridgment of Charter rights is described as the Court’s
movement from utilizing “external” limits on rights to “internal” limits on rights. See Kent Roach, “Unreliable
Evidence and Wrongful Convictions: The Case for Excluding Tainted Identification Evidence and Jailhouse and
Coerced Confessions” (2007) Crim.L. Q 210.
38
[1935] A.C. 462.
10
Throughout the web of the English Criminal Law one golden thread is always to be seen,
that is the duty of the prosecution to prove the prisoner's guilt [...] and no attempt to
whittle it down can be entertained.39
The point of the presumption of innocence is a liberal one: the state must justify any
interference with the freedom of the individual and be put to the strict proof of any allegations
against her. The presumption of innocence is constitutionally protected under the Charter s.11
(d). This provision provides procedural and evidentiary protection to an accused once a charge
has been laid.
An integral part of the presumption of innocence is the reasonable doubt standard of
proof. Justice Cory in R v Lifchus40 succinctly situates this burden within the presumption and
within the context of wrongful convictions:
The onus resting upon the Crown to prove the guilt of the accused beyond a reasonable
doubt is inextricably linked to the presumption of innocence. That jurors clearly
understand the meaning of the term is of fundamental importance to our criminal justice
system. It is one of the principal safeguards which seek to ensure that no innocent person
is convicted. The Marshall, Morin and Milgaard cases serve as a constant reminder that
our system, with all its protections for the accused, can still make tragic errors. A fair trial
must be the goal of criminal justice. There cannot be a fair trial if jurors do not clearly
understand the basic and fundamentally important concept of the standard of proof that
the Crown must meet in order to obtain a conviction.41
Charter analysis on the extent a right protects an accused against State activity, including
actions by the police and by Crown attorneys, has followed a relatively standard form since the
Court's ruling in R v Oakes 42 a fundamental decision that outlines when and how rights can be
overridden in certain, limited circumstances.
3.1 Section 1- the Oakes test
In the course of a criminal trial, when defence counsel believes that evidence to be
tendered by the Crown has been obtained by virtue of a Charter breach, a motion will be made
under s.24(2) of the Charter to exclude that evidence before its admission.43
39
Ibid, at pa.7.
[1997] 3 SCR 320.
41
Ibid, at pa.13.
42
[1986] 1 SCR 103.
43
In the event that the trier of fact is a jury, the motion will be by way of a voir dire to be heard in the absence of the
jury, so that the jury does not know what the nature of the impugned evidence might be. The phrase “voir dire” is
not used in the Code, per se. The provision that deals with this process is found in s.645 of the Code. The test is
40
11
At the first stage of the analysis, a court determines the scope of the substantive
Charter guarantee and determines whether an infringement has been made out. If a Charter
breach is established, the court then moves on to consider whether the infringement can be
"saved" under section 1. Section 1 states:
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set
out in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society
The court begins by asking whether the Charter violation is "prescribed by law".44 This
stage of the analysis requires the state to show that the infringement is legally authorized, by
either statute or by the common law.
If the limit is “prescribed by law”, the court moves on to consider whether the
legislation or government action furthers a pressing and substantial objective, whether it is
minimally impairing, and whether it is proportional, in that its benefits exceed its costs. Since the
government's objective is often to further "society's interest" in some way, interest balancing
occurs as a matter of course under section 1. In other words, if government action that infringes
Charter rights is to be upheld under this section, the benefits to society must exceed the costs to
an individual's rights.
However, in some cases police take action that has no basis in statute or common law, in
such cases, police may be acting “outside the law”. In this regard, police might obtain evidence
that is not authorized by virtue of a statute such as the Code, or otherwise requires a warrant
before its collection, for example. If there is no such basis and there is an infringement of a
Charter right, then the action is not “prescribed by law” and therefore cannot be "saved" by s.1.
The analysis then proceeds directly to the question of whether the evidence should be excluded
under section 24(2) of the Charter. The "prescribed by law" requirement therefore limits the
function of the court. It is interesting to note that internationally “Proportionality analysis – the
Oakes test to Canadians – is the dominant approach globally for adjudicating human rights
claims today.”45
3.2 Section 7 – Fundamental Justice
The Court has also looked to s.7 in recognition of the risk of wrongful conviction. The
section reads:
whether the admission of the evidence will bring the “administration of justice into disrepute” as set out in the
wording of s.24 (2).
44
Oakes, supra at note 42, p.135.
45
Mathews, Jud “Rights in the Balance” (2018) 23 Review of Constitutional Studies 225 at p.225.
12
Everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of the person and the right not to be
deprived thereof except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice
In United States of America v. Burns,46 the Court took notice of the reality of wrongful
convictions and reinforced the principle that the innocent not be punished as one of the unifying
principles of section 7 as it relates to the administration of justice. The principle that the innocent
not be punished stands for an accepted commitment that our justice system will take all
reasonable precautions to prevent wrongful convictions. The Court stated:
Legal systems have to live with the possibility of error. The unique feature of capital
punishment is that it puts beyond recall the possibility of correction. In recent years,
aided by advances in the forensic sciences, including DNA testing, the courts and
governments in this country and elsewhere have come to acknowledge a number of
instances of wrongful convictions for murder despite all of the careful safeguards put in
place for the protection of the innocent. The instances in Canada are few, but if capital
punishment had been carried out, the result could have been the killing by the
government of innocent individuals. The names of Marshall, Milgaard, Morin, Sophonow
and Parsons signal prudence and caution in a murder case…47
Courts have established that a number of rights exist under section 7, including the right
to silence and the confessions rule, the right to counsel48 the right to a full answer and defence
which includes Crown disclosure, as well as the general right to exclude otherwise tainted
evidence due to its propensity to cause wrongful convictions. It is interesting to note however
that case law has illustrated that it is by reference to section 7 where courts have engaged in the
balancing of rights and “societal interests” rather than through the traditional exercise undertaken
by virtue of applying the s.1 analysis in Oakes to Charter infringements.
In R v Sinclair,49 the Court's seminal decision on the right to counsel, the majority set out
that:
…in defining the contours of the s. 7 right to silence and related Charter rights,
consideration must be given not only to the protection of the rights of the accused but
also to the societal interest in the investigation and solving of crimes50
46
[2001] 1 SCR 283. In this case two Canadian citizens were under threat of extradition to the United States, where
they would face the death penalty if found guilty of the crimes of which they were accused. The Canadian
government did not want to extradite them to the United States without assurances that the death penalty would not
be sought.
47
Ibid at pa.1. While this case dealt with an application to extradite the accused to the United States on a charge of
first degree murder where the death penalty was available, the sentiment of the Court to the prospect of wrongful
convictions is emphasized.
48
As distinguished from the right under s.10 (b) to retain and instruct counsel.
49
[2010] 2 SCR 310.
50
Ibid, at pa.63.
13
This approach to Charter interpretation gives constitutional weight to considerations of
societal interests when delineating the scope of the legal rights of the accused, rather than at the
later stage of determining whether a violation of those rights is justified under s.1. The Court
made it clear that an accused does not have the right to counsel present while being interrogated
by the police but does have the right to remain silent. The difference is pointed out by way of
noting:
I do not believe that many clients detained by the police and placed in an
interview room appreciate the subtle difference between the fact that they
have a right to refuse to talk to the police unless a lawyer is present and the
fact that they have no right to have a lawyer present while being interrogated by the
police.51
Kent Roach proposes that section 7 provides a right to the exclusion of unreliable
evidence by virtue of the principle laid down in Burns52 that the innocent should not be punished
and the courts should be proactive in avoiding wrongful convictions.53 As such section 7 is
significant in its utility as a right to address the systemic factors that lead to wrongful
convictions, including, inter alia, mistaken eyewitness identification, false confessions and
perjured testimony from jailhouse informants.54
3.3 The Charter and Mistaken Eyewitness Identification
Eyewitness identification is a critical tool for investigating and prosecuting criminals.
This type of evidence is among the most persuasive testimony that can be used in a
courtroom. A positive identification of an accused in court is an essential element for any
successful prosecution. It is powerful and compelling evidence often given by a
confident and positive witness…However, we know that mistakes have happened. Wellmeaning, honest and credible people can and have been wrong…55
Orris, Glen “Section 10(b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Legal Advice” (2017) The Advocate
355 at p.361.
52
Burns, supra at note 46.
53
Kent Roach, “Unreliable Evidence and Wrongful Convictions: The Case for Excluding Tainted Identification
Evidence and Jailhouse and Coerced Confessions” (2007) Crim.L. Q 210.
54
The other sections of the Charter, such as s.8: right against unreasonable search and seizure; section 9: right
against arbitrary detention; s.10(b) right to counsel; s.10(c) right of habeas corpus; s.11(b) right against undue delay;
s.11(e) right to bail may well in individual cases play a contributing part in a wrongful conviction. However, the
infringement of these rights is not necessarily systemic to wrongful convictions and as such, will not be examined at
length in this paper.
55
Federal Provincial Territorial Heads of Prosecutions Committee, (2011) The Path to Justice: Preventing Wrongful
Convictions, at p.55.
51
14
Mistaken eyewitness identifications have been identified as the leading cause of wrongful
convictions.56 The Innocence Project states that research shows that the human mind is not like a
tape recorder. People do not record events exactly as they see them, nor recall them like a tape
that has been rewound. Eye witness memory “must be preserved carefully and retrieved
methodically, or it can be contaminated”.57
False identifications are exceptionally difficult for defence counsel to refute in crossexamination because mistaken witnesses often believe they are telling the truth. Defence counsel
in many American courts rely on expert testimony to discredit questionable eyewitness
testimony, as experts can bolster their testimony by referring to the large body of psychological
research in this area. Unfortunately, there is authority that restricts the admissibility of expert
evidence on the frailties of eyewitness identification in Canadian courts. In R v MacIntosh and
McCarthy58 counsel for the defence proposed to adduce evidence from a psychologist as to the
inherent frailty of such evidence. The trial judge refused to accept this evidence as an expert
opinion. Justice Finlayson of the Court of Appeal for Ontario made it very clear that evidence
from the behavioural sciences was to be treated quite differently than that from the natural
sciences. He unequivocally held that this type of evidence was not outside the experience of
triers of fact.
In R v Henderson,59 the Manitoba Court of Appeal dealt with a trial record that contained
both a caution by the judge and an expert opinion as to the frailty of eyewitness identification.
The appeal court restated its earlier decision that cautioned trial judges against letting expert
witnesses appropriate the function and role of the trier of fact. The court made clear that “while
the concerns over the frailties of eyewitness identification are real, they are generally best
addressed through strong jury instructions as opposed to thorough expert testimony”60 At the
end of the day and having regard to the fact that the witness personally knew the accused, the
eyewitness testimony was allowed to stand on the appeal.
The strength of the judge’s caution to a jury regarding the reliability of eyewitness
testimony was also at issue in the Court’s earlier decision in R v Hibbert61 where a real estate
agent was a victim of a brutal attack while she was holding an open house. When the victim
took her assailant to look at the garage, she was struck from behind, beaten and strangled her
until she was unconscious. The Crown’s case against the accused was based largely on
Bruce MacFarlane “Convicting the Innocent: A Triple Failure of Justice (2006) 31 Man.L. J 403
Innocence Project, Affiliated with the Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law at Yeshiva University, New York.
58
(1997) 35 OR (3d) 97.
59
2012 MBCA 93.
60
Ibid at pa. 109. This decision relied upon the Court’s decision in R. v. D.D. [2000] 2 S.C.R. 275 that stated “[t]he
primary danger arising from the admission of any opinion evidence is that the province of the jury might be usurped
by that of the witness” (at pa.53).
61
[2002] 2 SCR 445.
56
57
15
circumstantial evidence and fundamentally rested upon the victim making an in-court
identification of the accused.
The accused was convicted, and on appeal argued the inherent weakness of eyewitness
identification evidence and in particular the need for forceful instructions by the trial judge to the
jury emphasizing such weakness. The Court held that the judge’s directions to the jury on
identification evidence were not so deficient as to constitute an error of law. However, the Court
held that the trial judge should have cautioned the jury more strongly that the identification of the
accused in court was highly problematic as direct reliable identification of the perpetrator of the
offence. Justice Arbour for the majority of the Court stated:
It is important to remember that the danger associated with eyewitness in-court
identification is that it is deceptively credible, largely because it is honest and
sincere. The dramatic impact of the identification taking place in court, before the jury,
can aggravate the distorted value that the jury may place on it. The instruction to the
effect that such identification should be accorded “little weight” does not go far enough
to displace the danger that the jury could still give it weight that it does not deserve. 62
Justice Arbour also said:
The danger of wrongful conviction arising from faulty but apparently persuasive
eyewitness identification has been well documented. Most recently the Honourable Peter
deC. Cory, acting as Commissioner in the Inquiry regarding Thomas Sophonow, made
recommendations regarding the conduct of live and photo line-ups, and called for
stronger warnings to the jury than were issued in the present case (Peter de C. Cory, The
Inquiry Regarding Thomas Sophonow: The Investigation, Prosecution and Consideration
of Entitlement to Compensation (2001) ("Sophonow Inquiry"), at pp. 31-34).63
The Court overturned the conviction and ordered a new trial.64
3.4 The Charter and False Confessions
As counterintuitive as it may seem, factually innocent people confess to crimes they have
not committed. Within the context of wrongful convictions, these confessions are more often
than not the result of an abusive police interrogation. The Innocence Project 65 has indicated that a
62
Ibid at pa.50.
Ibid at pa.49.
64
For a discussion on the inaccuracy of eyewitness testimony and possible reforms see: See Sandra Thompson,
“Beyond a Reasonable Doubt? Reconsidering Uncorroborated Eyewitness Identification Testimony, (2008) 41 U.C.
Davis L.Rev. 1487 and Kent Roach “Wrongful Convictions: Adversarial and Inquisitorial Themes” (2010) N.C.
Int’l. & Com. Reg. 387.
65
Supra at note 57.
63
16
variety of factors can contribute to a false confession during a police interrogation. Many cases
have included a combination of several of these causes, including “duress, coercion, intoxication,
diminished capacity, mental impairment, ignorance of the law, fear of violence, the actual
infliction of harm, the threat of a harsh sentence and the misunderstanding the situation”66
The Court has as well identified the danger of this systemic factor leading to wrongful
convictions. In R. v. Oickle 67the Court recognized:
A large body of literature has developed documenting hundreds of cases where
confessions have been proven false by DNA evidence, subsequent confessions by the true
perpetrator, and other such independent sources of evidence... One of the overriding
concerns of the criminal justice system is that the innocent must not be convicted: see,
e.g., R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668, at para. 71; R. v. Leipert, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 281, at
para. 4. Given the important role of false confessions in convicting the innocent, the
confessions rule must understand why false confessions occur.68
In this case, the Court established the confessions rule – which ascertains that
confessions can only be admitted if they are voluntary and not the result of coercive police
tactics, which included threats or promises,69 oppression,70 and other police trickery71 and must
be obtained from individuals who show evidence of an “operating mind”.72 The Court however
went onto to say that “false confessions are rarely the product of proper police techniques.”73
Christopher Sherrin takes issue with this conclusion and urges greater consideration of risk
factors that make some accused susceptible to false confessions “including sleep deprivation,
intoxication and withdrawal from drugs, intellectual disabilities and youth.”74
The Court in defining the confessions rule kept in mind the twin goals of protecting the
rights of the accused without unduly limiting society’s need to investigate and solve crimes. The
confessions rule deals most particularly with false confessions and the dangers of improper
interrogation techniques. Within the context of a police interrogation, where the detainee knows
she is speaking to a person in authority, the finding that the confession was voluntary is
“determinative of the s.7 issue.75 Further the Court made clear:
66
Ibid.
[2000] 2 SCR 3.
68
Ibid at pa.35-36.
69
Ibid at pa.48-57.
70
Ibid at pa.58-62.
71
Ibid at pa.65-67.
72
Ibid at pa.63-64.
73
Ibid at pa.45.
74
Roach, Kent “Wrongful Convictions in Canada” (2012) 80(4) U. of Cinn. L.R. 1465 at p.1506 referencing
Christopher Sherrin “False Confessions and Admissions in Canadian Law (2005) 30 Queens L.J.602.
75
Oickle, supra at note 67, pa.33.
67
17
The common law confessions rule is well-suited to protect against false confessions.
While its overriding concern is with voluntariness, this concept overlaps with reliability.
A confession that is not voluntary will often (though not always) be unreliable.76
The confessions rule is also applicable to the accused’s common law right to remain
silent which can be contrasted with a s.7 right to remain silent. The question turns on whether
inculpatory evidence, including prospectively false confessions should be allowed into the record
when police act concertedly to circumvent an accused’s right to remain silent to persons in
authority. If the accused chooses voluntarily to make incriminating admissions, should the law
nevertheless sanction the police behaviour by excluding the evidence?
This was the question before the Court in R. v. Singh.77 Jagrup Singh, a 28-year-old
truck driver, was detained and questioned by the police after a fatal shooting outside a strip club
in Surrey, B.C. During the interrogation Singh asserted his right to remain silent eighteen times.
The police nevertheless persisted in what the trial judge described as an "effort to get him to
confess, no matter what".78 Eventually, Singh made an incriminating admission that resulted in
his conviction. On appeal, Singh conceded that his admission had been "voluntary" for the
purposes of the common law confessions rule, but that the persistent interrogation had
nevertheless violated his s. 7 Charter right to silence. Thus, the question before the Court was
whether the Charter provided residual protection to an accused in such circumstances, even
where the common law would have allowed the admission into evidence. The Court ruled that,
in the context of a detained person knowingly speaking to authorities, the confessions rule and
right to silence are "functionally equivalent" - both turn on whether the confession meets a
"voluntariness" test.
Nevertheless, s. 7 enshrines, as a principle of fundamental justice, a stand-alone right to
silence. Chief Justice McLachlin in R v. Hebert79 saw the s. 7 right to silence as providing
protection where the confessions rule could not since, as she explained:
[T]his suggests that the drafters of the Charter viewed the ambit of the right to silence
embodied in s. 7 as extending beyond the narrow formulation of the confessions rule,
comprehending not only the negative right to be free of coercion induced by threats,
promises or violence, but a positive right to make a free choice as to whether to remain
silent or speak to the authorities.80
76
Ibid, at pa.47.
[2007] 3 SCR 405.
78
Ibid, at pa.15.
79
[1990] 2 SCR 151.
80
Ibid, at pa.54.
77
18
In that case, the suspect was induced to speak to someone he thought was another
prisoner, who was in fact someone in authority and therefore his right to silence was infringed.
It can also be noted that in Sinclair81 the justices, in dissent, argued that the majority judgment
appeared to be part of a broader trend of balancing individual rights against societal interests
outside of section 1. The dissent in Sinclair believed that the majority's conception of the right to
silence and the right to counsel "effectively recognizes a new police power of virtually unfettered
access, for the purposes of endless interrogation, to custodial detainees who have chosen to
remain silent".82
Most recently and importantly the police tactic characterized as the “Mr. Big” sting has
reached the Court.83 This undercover RCMP interrogation technique is aimed at inducing a
confession from a suspect where there is no evidence and involves enticing the individual
through rewarding involvement in illegal activity and finally culminating in a meeting with the
big boss whereby the individual must confess to all previous criminality. It is at this point that
the confession is recorded and the suspect arrested. On August 7th, 2014 the Court ruled that
confessions generated from the RCMP’s “Mr. Big” investigation technique are to be presumed
inadmissible at trial. The Crown is allowed however to convince the judge that the reliability of
a confession outweighs its prejudicial effects. In this particular case, the Court ruled that Nelson
Hart’s confession to an undercover officer about drowning his twin daughters should not be
admitted as there were significant social and financial inducements to confess. There was also no
other evidence leading to Hart’s culpability. Comparatively “the Mr. Big operation is not used in
the United States, perhaps raising doubt as to it’s efficiency and reliability.”84
3.5 The Charter and Jailhouse Informants
Jailhouse informers are notorious as a class of self-serving and unreliable witnesses.
Widespread recognition of their inherent unreliability has grown in the aftermath of
public inquiries into wrongful convictions where jailhouse informers figured
prominently.85
In the inquiry into the wrongful conviction of Thomas Sophonow86 Justice Cory
recommended that jailhouse informants as a rule should not be allowed to testify. However,
81
Sinclair, supra at note 49.
Ibid at pa.128.
83
R v Hart (2014) SCC 52. This particular technique was used in the widely publicized wrongful conviction
involving the false confession of Kyle Unger. See R v Unger (1993) 85 Man. R.(2d) 284.
84
Selwyn A Pieters and Rick E Frank, “Police Interrogations and The Psychology of False Confessions”,
2016 CanLII Docs 388 at p.17 with reference to R. v. Osmar, 2007 ONCA 50 at pa. 54.
85
FPT, supra at note 55. The public inquiries referenced were The Morin Inquiry (Kaufman Commission): Guy
Paul Morin (Ontario, 1998) and The Sophonow Inquiry (Cory Commission): Thomas Sophonow (Manitoba, 2001).
86
Ibid.
82
19
Justice Fred Kaufman in the inquiry into the wrongful conviction of Guy Paul Morin found
otherwise.87 This was notwithstanding the abundant evidence that two jailhouse informants were
clearly providing perjured testimony on numerous occasions and in the face of Kaufman finding
the informants evidence as “wholly unreliable”.88 Indeed, he found that “[t]heir evidence was
motivated by self-interest. They were predisposed, by character and psychological make-up to
lie.”89
The Court’s decision in R v Brooks90 raises serious problems for the prospect of
wrongful convictions and the test for admissibility of unreliable evidence. In that case, a one and
one-half year old girl was beaten to death in her crib. Only the accused and the infant’s mother
had access to the child on the night of the murder. There was a good deal of forensic evidence
but much of it was contaminated and did not inculpate or exculpate the accused. There was no
direct evidence that the accused had struck the fatal blows to the infant. The Crown led evidence
from two jailhouse informants who testified that the accused, while incarcerated, had admitted
that he had killed the child to stop her crying. Both informants had lengthy criminal records
including crimes of dishonesty and both had histories of testifying as jailhouse informants in
previous trials.
A Vetrovec91 warning may serve as a protection to a defendant when an unreliable
witness testifies against them. This warning entails a judge admonishing a jury through a “clear
and sharp warning” with respect to the testimony of disreputable or unsavoury witnesses. This
evidence requires that:
1. the evidence of certain witnesses is identified as requiring special scrutiny;
2. the characteristics of the witness that bring his or her evidence into serious question are
identified;
3. the jury is cautioned that although it is entitled to act on the unconfirmed evidence of
such a witness, it is dangerous to do so; and
4. the jury is cautioned to look for other independent evidence which tends to confirm
material parts of the evidence of the witness with respect to whom the warning has been
given.
The trial judge in Brooks did not provide a Vetrovec warning to the jury about the
danger of relying on jailhouse informant testimony. On appeal to the Court, it was held:
87
The Honourable Fred Kaufman, The Morin Inquiry (Kaufman Commission): Guy Paul Morin (Ontario, 1998).
Ibid at p.544.
89
Ibid.
90
[2000] 1 SCR 237.
91
R v Vetrovic [1982] 1 SCR 811.
88
20
There was no error of law on the part of the trial judge in failing to provide a
Vetrovec warning. It was within the discretion of the trial judge whether to give a
warning and there was a foundation for his exercise of discretion…Trial judges must not
pigeon-hole witnesses into categories and should examine all factors that might impair
the worth of a witness. No Vetrovec warning is necessary if the trial judge believes the
witness can be trusted even if the witness is a jailhouse informant. The facts raised
preliminary doubts as to the credibility of the informants but not cogent reasons to
overrule the trial judge’s implicit finding that they were sufficiently trustworthy not to
mandate a caution.92
As such, what is recognized as the most unreliable and potentially dishonest evidence
available that contributes to wrongful convictions is not presumptively excluded in the case
against an accused. Indeed:
Canadian warnings still eschew corroboration by deferring to the ability of the jury to
accept an unsavory witness’s testimony in the absence of any independent confirmation.93
3.6 The Charter and Crown Disclosure
The lack of cooperation and the withholding of evidence, particularly exculpatory
evidence was historically a significant contributor to wrongful conviction cases. At times the
police kept evidence from the Crown which never found its way to the defence and at other times
the Crown had all relevant evidence from the police and yet it kept evidence from defence
counsel.94 For those accused that are factually innocent of the crime for which they have been
charged, the importance of knowing the case they face is significant simply because the Crown is
in possession of and has access to greater resources. In this regard and as stated by Roach:
The Supreme Court’s section 7 jurisprudence giving the accused a broad right to
disclosure of relevant evidence in the possession of the Crown is arguably the most
important development in our criminal justice system in the last quarter century. It has
transformed the way the justice system operates and this new right has been crafted in no
92
Ibid, at pa.1-5.
Roach, Kent “Wrongful Convictions: Adversarial and Inquisitorial Themes” (2010) 35(2) North Carolina Journal
of Int’l Law & Commercial Relations 387 at p.409 with reference to the Lamer Inquiry pertaining to the wrongful
convictions of Ronald Dalton, Gregory Parsons and Randy Druken (2006) at
ttp://www.justice.gov.nl.ca/just/lamer/LamerReport.pdf.
94
See the Reference re Milgaard (1992) 1 SCR 866. The withholding of evidence was often a consequence of
police activity characterized as tunnel vision and noble cause corruption.
93
21
small part as a systemic measure that would apply across cases to lower the risk of
wrongful convictions.95
The failure to disclose exculpatory evidence was shown to be an important contributing
factor in the wrongful conviction of Donald Marshall.96 In this case the Crown did not disclose
to defence counsel inconsistent statements made by the two eye witnesses who provided the
fundamental evidence that led to Marshall’s conviction nor did the Crown tell the defence that
after the conviction alibi evidence came to light that would have cleared Marshall which was not
disclosed for the purposes of an appeal to the Court of Appeal for Nova Scotia.97
Following closely on the release of the Report on Donald Marshall was the Court’s
decision in R. v Stinchcombe98 where the right to disclosure was constitutionalized as a principle
of fundamental justice under s.7. The Court held that all relevant and non-privileged information
in the possession of the Crown should be disclosed without regard to whether the information
was inculpatory or exculpatory and without regard to whether statements related to a person who
might be called as a witness. In coming to this conclusion, the Court reviewed whether “societal
interests” would be harmed by this expanded right. Justice Sopinka predicted that disclosure
disputes could be avoided by the adoption of “uniform, comprehensive rules for disclosure” and
that disclosure could increase efficiency by producing an “increase in guilty pleas, withdrawal of
charges and shortening or waiving of preliminary hearings”.99 For the purposes of making a full
answer and defence to charges in a criminal proceeding, the Stinchcombe rule is now relied upon
in every jurisdiction in Canada as a guarantor of full disclosure. More recently the Court has
reemphasized that:
Unlike the decision to initiate or continue a prosecution, the decision to disclose relevant
information is not discretionary. Rather disclosure is a constitutional obligation which
must be properly discharged by the Crown in accordance with an accused’s right to make
full answer and defence, as guaranteed under ss.7 and 11(d) of the Charter.100
3.7 Charter Remedies at Trial
Roach, Kent “The Protection of Innocence Under Section 7 of the Charter” (2006) Supreme Court Law Review
249 at p.265.
96
The Marshall Inquiry (Hickman Commission) Donald Marshall Jr. (Nova Scotia, 1989)
97
Ibid at p.4. Chief Justice Hickman on the Reference went so far as to criticize the trial judge’s role in the wrongful
conviction. It was found that the trial court took it upon itself to "convict" Marshall of a robbery with which he was
never charged and that the court did not deal with the significant failure of the Crown to disclose evidence to
defence counsel. Reference at p.23.
95
98
[1991] 3 SCR 326.
Ibid at pa.13.
100
Per Moldaver, J. in Henry v. British Columbia (Attorney General) [2015] 2 SCR 214 at pa.59. This action was for
damages resulting from a breach of the Charter. The plaintiff was successful.
99
22
In the event that defence counsel at trial is successful in persuading the court that a
breach of a client’s rights has occurred, it is crucial to appreciate how any such breach will be
treated by the court with respect to the admission of such tainted evidence. The procedural
remedies for breaches of sections 7-14 of the Charter are found in s.24 (1)101 and (2).102
The broad language of s.24 (1)103 authorizes courts to impose creative remedies for Charter
violations, so long as these are "appropriate and just in the circumstances'. Indeed, the Court
held that "it is improper for courts to reduce this discretion by casting it in a straitjacket of
judicially prescribed conditions.”104 The principal limit on judges' remedial powers under s.24(1)
is that they may not encroach on the legitimate powers of the legislative and executive branches
of government, except where this is justified by the language of the Charter right which was
violated. A court ordering a Charter remedy must strive to respect the relationships with and
separation of functions among the legislature, the executive and the judiciary; there is no “bright
line” separating these functions in all cases. A remedy may be appropriate and just
notwithstanding that it might touch on functions that are principally assigned to the executive.
The essential point is that the courts must not, in making orders under s. 24(1), depart unduly or
unnecessarily from their role of adjudicating disputes and granting remedies that address the
matter of those disputes.105
The most dramatic remedy that a judge can order under s.24 (1) within the context of the
trial when there is a Charter breach is a stay of proceedings. It is dramatic because when a stay
is ordered, the prosecution comes to an end and the accused is no longer facing the allegation of
criminality. This particular remedy is most often preserved when an accused’s rights to a speedy
trial have been breached pursuant to s.11 (b).106 This is not endemic to wrongful convictions and
will not be explored further. Section 24(2) on the other hand, is used extensively in the face of
evidence obtained as a result of a breach: the remedy in those cases is the exclusion of the
evidence so obtained.
101
24(1) Anyone whose rights or freedoms, as guaranteed by this Charter, have been infringed or denied may apply
to a court of competent jurisdiction to obtain such remedy as the court considers appropriate and just in the
circumstances.
102
24(2) Where, in proceedings under subsection (1), a court concludes that evidence was obtained in a manner that
infringed or denied any rights or freedoms guaranteed by this Charter, the evidence shall be excluded if it is
established that, having regard to all the circumstances, the admission of it would bring the administration
of justice into disrepute.
103
Justice McIntyre in Mills v the Queen [1986] 1 SCR 863 stated “…it is difficult to imagine language which could
give the court a wider and less fettered discretion.” This decision was one of the earliest decisions of the Court on
the appropriate remedy for a breach of s.11(b) where the right to a speedy trial was infringed.
104
Vancouver (City) v Ward [2010] 2 SCR 28 at pa.18.
105
See: Doucet-Boudreau v. Nova Scotia (Minister of Education), [2003] 3 SCR 3.
106
Now see the Court’s decision in R. v. Jordan [2016] 1 SCR 631 wherein a new framework for a presumptive
ceiling was established beyond which delay from the charge to the actual or anticipated end of trial is presumed to be
unreasonable, absent exceptional circumstances to justify said delay. The presumptive ceiling is 30 months for cases
tried in the provincial superior court and 18 months for cases tried in the provincial court.
23
Prior to the Charter, the law in Canada had always been that evidence that was relevant
to the determination of guilt or innocence would be admissible regardless of the manner by
which it was derived. Any notions of doubt concerning the possibility of adhering to a rule of
exclusion in Canada were laid to rest in R. v. Wray107 in which the Court clearly established an
inclusionary rule with regard to the admissibility of illegally obtained evidence.
As a consequence, prior to the Charter, even if the rights of the individual were violated
in obtaining evidence, it would nevertheless have been admitted if it was considered relevant. In
this respect, the potential remedy in s.24 (2) to facilitate exclusion marked a shift from the crime
control to the due process model. It is clear why an exclusionary remedy would be accepted by
the due process approach as a proper remedy to ensure the integrity of the process. It is equally
clear, however, why such a remedy could not be condoned by the crime control model, as it
sacrifices both efficiency as well as the repression of criminal conduct. This is conveyed by
Packer:
The police are bound to make mistakes, and it is of course desirable that these mistakes
be minimized. Here, as elsewhere, the way to deal with mistakes is to afford a remedy for
actual damages suffered by people whose privacy has been improperly invaded and to
correct, by discipline and education, the future conduct of the officers who make the
mistakes. It is unwise and unnecessary to provide the allegedly injured party with a
windfall in the form of freedom from criminal conviction when his guilt is
demonstrable… In any event, there is no reason why evidence should not be used in the
criminal process without regard to the manner in which it has been obtained108
From a due process point of view however, Packer sets out that that the exclusion of
evidence is appropriate in that:
… departmental discipline is an ineffective deterrent. The only practical way to control
illegal searches is to take the profit out of them. This means that any evidence illegally
obtained cannot be permitted as evidence109
The Court's first major s. 24(2) decision, R. v. Collins110, released in 1987, established
the now-familiar three-part analytical framework for determining the admissibility of
unconstitutionally obtained evidence. The "Collins test" directed judges to consider:
(1) the effect of admitting the evidence on the fairness of the trial;
107
[1971] SCR 272.
Packer, supra at note 3, p.199.
109
Ibid at p.200.
110
[1987] 1 SCR 265.
108
24
(2) the seriousness of the violation; and
(3) the effect of exclusion on the repute of the administration of justice.
This was followed by R. v Stillman111 where the majority of the Court held that
unconstitutionally obtained evidence obtained and otherwise undiscoverable
“conscriptive” 112 evidence “must be excluded”.113 What was referred to as the Collins/Stillman
test for exclusion was dispensed with categorically when R v Grant114 was decided in 2009. In
this case, three police officers were on patrol in a school district that was known for its criminal
activity. Grant, a young black man, was walking down a sidewalk and was seen fidgeting with
his coat and pants in a way that aroused one officer’s suspicions. The officer stopped Grant and
began questioning him which included a request for his name and address. Grant continued to
act suspiciously. At one point he appeared nervous and adjusted his jacket, which prompted the
officer to ask him to keep his hands in front of him. After observing this exchange, two officers
joined in and took up positions behind the first officer clearly obstructing any opportunity for
Grant to move forward. The first officer then asked Grant whether he had anything he should not
have, to which Grant answered that he had “a small bag of weed” and a firearm. Grant was then
arrested and searched and the marijuana and a loaded revolver were seized. Defence counsel, at
trial, argued that Grant’s Charter rights relative to detention under sections 9 and 10 were
breached and as a result, the revolver should be excluded from evidence by virtue of s.24(2). The
Court affirmed that the detention was arbitrary and contrary to the Charter, but did not exclude
the revolver.
The Grant majority's new test for exclusion eliminates the "trial fairness" branch of the
Collins test and repackages the remaining two sets of Collins factors into a new three-prong test.
Significantly, the majority in Grant characterized the s. 24(2) exclusionary remedy as solely
directed at "societal" concerns, stating:
Section 24(2) is not aimed at punishing the police or providing compensation to the
accused, but rather at systemic concerns. The s. 24(2) focus is on the broad impact of
admission of the evidence on the long-term repute of the justice system.115
111
[1997] 1 SCR 607.
Conscriptive evidence is evidence that comes from the accused as a result of a Charter violation by the police.
This type of evidence usually arises when the police question someone without telling them they have the right to
speak to a lawyer, or question them when they have been illegally detained.
113
Stillman, supra at note 111, pa.98.
114
[2009] 2 SCR 353.
115
Ibid at pa.70.
112
25
The Chief Justice and Justice Charron declared that "'trial fairness' in the
Collins/Stillman sense is no longer a determinative criterion for the s. 24(2) inquiry".116 Given
that the ruling in Grant has substantially diminished the prominence of trial fairness, the
connection between good faith police conduct and the exclusion of unconstitutionally obtained
evidence now warrants critical scrutiny. Since incorporating the assessment of investigatory
behaviour into the s. 24(2) calculus, the Court has effectively established a presumption of good
faith with respect to all police conduct. This raises a presumption that is only realistically
rebuttable by specific evidence of flagrant and intentional bad faith on the part of subject
officers. When such evidence is unavailable, police investigators will be considered to have
acted in good faith, a fact that militates strongly against the exclusion of unconstitutionally
obtained evidence. The majority in Grant made it abundantly clear that there is no quasiautomatic exclusionary rule for any form of evidence, including non-discoverable conscriptive
evidence. However, a statement by the Court in R. v. Mann117 still has authority in that “good
faith is but one factor in the analysis and must be considered alongside other factors.”118
Nonetheless, evidence obtained by the police in the exercise of the systemically recognized
evidence gathering tactics characterized as tunnel vision and noble cause corruption will more
than likely not be excluded.119
4.0 Conclusion
As Barbara Hudson states “justice is very much under threat in the risk society.”120 The
interest balancing that is described by Packer’s normative criminal justice models of crime
control and due process have evolved in Canada into considerations by the Court as to how the
rights of an accused are to be offset by public safety concerns best embodied in “societal
interests”. As has been seen, such interests under the Oakes test121 will determine that evidence
prescribed by law will be admitted notwithstanding a breach of the Charter. It is an open
question whether “societal interests” will override s.7 rights without benefit of the Oakes test and
as the majority made clear in Sinclair,122 society’s needs to investigate and solve crimes provides
116
Ibid at pa.121.
[2004] 3 SCR 59.
118
Ibid, Iacobucci, J. at pa.55.
119
Tunnel vision is a narrow focus taken by the police and Crown counsel in investigating and prosecuting a crime
when a particular investigative or prosecutorial theory is accepted to the exclusion of others so as to unreasonably
colour the evaluation of evidence received and the response to said evidence. Tunnel vision leads to a reduction in
critically assessing evidence which might lead away from the truth. Noble cause corruption is police misconduct
committed in the name of perceived justice. Noble cause corruption includes planting or fabricating evidence, lying
or the fabrication and manipulation of facts through testimony in court, and generally abusing police authority to
make a charge stick.
120
Hudson, supra at note 18.
121
Oakes supra at note 42.
122
Sinclair, supra at note 49
117
26
the police with unfettered access to accused persons under interrogation. The Court has defined
the confessions rule and the right to silence finely having regard to the need to investigate and
solve crimes.
With the enactment of the Charter, defence counsel confidently expected that an
infringement of a client’s rights in the course of a police investigation would result in the
exclusion of tainted evidence. Exclusion could be avoided however if a court was convinced that
the breach was justified to advance “societal interests”. Further, to make exclusion even more
difficult, the Court in Grant123 changed the well-known formula under s.24 (2) to effectively
remove trial fairness as a determining factor when considering exclusion. The Court has now
established a presumption of good faith for virtually all police investigatory activity leaving
counsel with the opportunity to exclude constitutionally challenged evidence only where its
discovery can be painted with flagrant and intentional bad faith on the part of the police.
5. References
Beck, Ulrech, Risk Society: Toward a New Modernity (London, SAGE Publishers, 1992).
Blackstone, William, (1765-1769) Commentaries on the Laws of England.
Campbell, Liz. “Decline of Due Process in the Irish Justice System: Beyond the Culture of
Control” (2006) Hibernian Law Journal, 125.
Cohen, Stanley, Visions of Social Control: Crime, Punishment and Classification (Cambridge,
Polity Press, 1985).
Emmerson, Ben, Ashworth, Andrew, Macdonald, Alison (Eds.), Human Rights and Criminal
Justice (2nd) (London, Sweet & Maxwell, 2007).
Ewald. Francois “Insurance and Risk” (Chp.10) and Robert Castel “From Dangerousness to
Risk” (Chp.14) in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Graham Burchell, Colin
Gordon, Peter Miller, eds. (Chicago, The Univ. of Chicago Press, 1991).
Federal Provincial Territorial Heads of Prosecutions Committee, (2011) The Path to Justice:
Preventing Wrongful Convictions.
Feeley, Martin and Jonathan Simon, (1992). The new penology: Notes on the emerging strategy
of corrections and its implications. Criminology, 30, 449; Martin Feeley and Jonathan Simon,
123
Grant, supra at note 114.
27
(1994). Actuarial justice: The emerging new criminal law. In D. Nelken (ed.) The Futures of
Criminology (pp. 173-201). London: Sage Publications.
Foucault, Michael (1978) “Governmentality” in The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality, Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, Peter Miller, eds. (Chicago, The Univ. of
Chicago Press, 1991).
Garland, David, The Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in Contemporary Society
(Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 2001).
Hudson, Barbara, Justice in the Risk Society: Challenging and Re-Affirming Justice in Late
Modernity. (London, Sage Publications, 2003).
Hudson, Barbara “Punishment, rights and difference: defending justice in the risk society”
Chapter 8, at p.144 in K. Stenson and R. Sullivan, (eds.), Risk, Crime and Prudentialism
Revisited. Crime, Risk and Justice: The Politics of Crime Control in Liberal Democracies,
(London, Willan 2012).
Innocence Project, Affiliated with the Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law at Yeshiva
University, New York.
MacFarlane, Bruce “Convicting the Innocent: A Triple Failure of Justice (2006) 31 Man.L. J.
403.
The Marshall Inquiry (Hickman Commission) Donald Marshall Jr. (Nova Scotia, 1989).
Mathews, Jud “Rights in the Balance” (2018) 23 Review of Constitutional Studies 225.
The Morin Inquiry (Kaufman Commission): Guy Paul Morin (Ontario, 1998).
O’Malley, Pat, Governmentality and Risk: Social Theories of Risk and Uncertainty, J. Zinn ed.
(Oxford, Sydney Law School Research Paper, 2008).
O’Malley, Pat, Crime and Risk (London, Sage Publishing, 2010).
Orris, Glen “Section 10(b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Legal Advice”
(2017) The Advocate 355.
Packer, Herbert, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction. (Stanford, Stanford Univ. Press, 1968).
28
Pieters, Selwyn A. and Rick E Frank, “Police Interrogations and The Psychology of False
Confessions”, 2016 CanLII Docs 388.
Reno, Janet, Remarks at the American 2000 National Symposium of Indigent Defence, as noted
in A.P.D. Worden Andrew Lucas, Elizabeth Blaize Brown "Patchwork of Policies: Justice, Due
Process, and Public Defense across American States, A." (2010) Alb. L. Rev. 74: 1423.
Roach, Kent “The Protection of Innocence Under Section 7 of the Charter” (2006) Supreme
Court Law Review 249.
Roach, Kent “Unreliable Evidence and Wrongful Convictions: The Case for Excluding Tainted
Identification Evidence and Jailhouse and Coerced Confessions” (2007) Crim.L. Q 210.
Roach, Roach “Wrongful Convictions: Adversarial and Inquisitorial Themes” (2010) N.C. Int’l.
& Com. Reg. 387.
Roach, Kent “Wrongful Convictions in Canada” (2012) 80(4) U. of Cinn. L.R. 1465.
Sherrin, Christopher “False Confessions and Admissions in Canadian Law (2005) 30 Queens
L.J.602.
The Sophonow Inquiry (Cory Commission): Thomas Sophonow (Manitoba, 2001).
Thompson, Sandra “Beyond a Reasonable Doubt? Reconsidering Uncorroborated Eyewitness
Identification Testimony, (2008) 41 U.C. Davis L.Rev. 1487.