Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Evolution and ontogenesis: The deontic niche of human development

Accepted for publication in Human Development

We explore contemporary evolutionary perspectives on children’s psychological development, questioning the view that high-fidelity, inter-individual transmission of information explains the cumulative character of human cultures, and children’s ontogenesis within these cultures. We argue that humans construct an environmental niche that is unique in being composed of institutions, which function to coordinate activity over multiple time scales. Institutions involve not simply customs or conventions but a deontology of future-binding rights, responsibilities, duties, and obligations. The origins of institutions can be traced in hominin evolution to Paleolithic hunter-gatherers, where kinship, the first institution, made possible community support of an extended and demanding form of ontogenesis. Since the human environmental niche is an institutional reality, children today need to acquire the ability to understand and act effectively within institutions. We propose that this ability emerges not as an adaptation solely to past conditions but through differentiation and reintegration of an ‘extended ontogenetic system’ of which the child is a constituent, leading to a quality of self-consciousness on the part of the child that makes possible the ability to live in an institutional reality.

Running head: The deontic niche 1 Accepted for publication in Human Development Evolution and Ontogenesis: The Deontic Niche of Human Development Martin J. Packer and Michael Cole Contact information: Martin J. Packer [email protected] Michael Cole Communication Department, Psychology Department, and Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition University of California, San Diego La Jolla, California, 92093-0092 [email protected] The deontic niche 2 Abstract We explore contemporary evolutionary perspectives on children’s psychological development, questioning the view that high-fidelity, inter-individual transmission of information explains the cumulative character of human cultures, and children’s ontogenesis within these cultures. We argue that humans construct an environmental niche that is unique in being composed of institutions, which function to coordinate activity over multiple time scales. Institutions involve not simply customs or conventions but a deontology of future-binding rights, responsibilities, duties, and obligations. The origins of institutions can be traced in hominin evolution to Paleolithic hunter-gatherers, where kinship, the first institution, made possible community support of an extended and demanding form of ontogenesis. Since the human environmental niche is an institutional reality, children today need to acquire the ability to understand and act effectively within institutions. We propose that this ability emerges not as an adaptation solely to past conditions but through differentiation and reintegration of an ‘extended ontogenetic system’ of which the child is a constituent, leading to a quality of self-consciousness on the part of the child that makes possible the ability to live in an institutional reality. The deontic niche 3 Evolution and Ontogenesis: The Deontic Niche of Human Development We are developmental psychologists with a longstanding interest in children’s psychological development, that is to say, human ontogenesis, and especially in the role of culture in this process. Our recent inquiries have led us to question the widespread view that an inherited ability to engage in high-fidelity, inter-individual transmission of information, referred to as “cultural learning,” provides an adequate explanation for the cumulative character of human cultures, and for children’s ontogenesis within these cultures. It seems to us that this approach neglects the active role of the built, meaningful environments in which humans live and care for their children. In a previous text (Cole & Packer, 2016) we recommended a “bio-cultural-historical” approach to the study of children’s development and emphasized how the ubiquitous phenomenon of niche construction offers a way to think about the role of culture in both human ontogenesis and human evolution. In this article we take a further step in noting that the human environmental niche is composed of institutions. Others have explored the role of institutions in ontogenesis (Rakoczy & Tomasello, 2007) and in human evolution (Richerson & Boyd, 2001), as we shall describe. What we think is novel in our treatment is our proposal that because institutions define not only customs and conventions but also rights and responsibilities, the human niche is a ‘deontic niche’ in which obligations bind people’s activities not only in the present but also into the future. Institutions coordinate activity over multiple time scales, from moment to moment and from generation to generation. We draw upon recent advances in evolutionary theory to propose that this human niche not only changes selection pressures on people and their offspring, it provides ongoing distribution of key psychological functions (a proposal in line with theories of “4E” cognition: The deontic niche 4 Newen, De Bruin, & Gallagher, 2018) and so permits a specifically human mode of reproduction. These considerations enable us to offer an account of the relations among the “institutional reality” of human communities, evolution (both general and in particular human), and human ontogenesis. We suggest that hominin ancestors evolved increasingly collaborative modes of reproduction by virtue of the niches they constructed. Pleistocene hunter-gatherers engaged in a mode of highly collaborative reproduction that supported an ontogenesis that was long and demanding but highly successful: hunter-gatherers had higher fertility, lower infant mortality, later sexual maturity, and longer lifespans than their predecessors. This brings us to the core of our argument: we propose that this mode of reproduction and its corresponding form of ontogenesis became possible with the emergence of the first institution, kinship. Kinship defined community-wide obligations to collaborate in provisions for childcare, as part of a collective way of understanding and relating to the environment in which reciprocity over time was central. Today, the fact that children are born into a deontic niche means that they need to acquire the ability to understand and act effectively within institutions. We propose that this ability emerges not merely as an adaptation to past conditions but through differentiation and reintegration within an ‘extended ontogenetic system’ of which the child is a constituent. This system creates the conditions for a quality of awareness of self on the part of the child that other primates do not achieve, and which makes possible the ability to live in an institutional reality. What proponents of cultural learning attribute to inherited abilities and dispositions we attribute to the process of reproduction, of which genetic and social mechanisms of inheritance are only parts. The deontic niche 5 We conclude that human ontogenesis is not simply the result of past adaptations to a lost environment, captured in the genes and now programmed to appear. If our analysis is correct, humans do not have a fixed nature that was defined 100,000 years ago: human ontogenesis is a response to the present and it is a preparation for the future. This implies that the ways humans care for children today shape the future evolution of the species. We begin, then, with a discussion of evolution in general, then turn to theories of human evolution in particular. Following that we review the evolution of hominins, then discuss the characteristics of institutions, before drawing conclusions about human ontogenesis. Changing Views of Evolution “At the heart of evolutionary theory is the notion that in order to have left descendants all organisms must have solved the problems of survival, growth and development, and reproduction.” (Chisholm, 1993, p. 2) The contemporary debate over how to think about and understand evolutionary phenomena (e.g., Laland et al., 2014; Wray et al., 2014; Bateson et al., 2017) is challenging assumptions taken for granted in biology and also in efforts to adopt an evolutionary perspective on human psychological processes and phenomena. The terms of the debate are important for understanding the starting places of evolutionary perspectives on human ontogenesis, as well as to make clear our own suggestions. The Modern Synthesis During the second half of the twentieth century, evolutionary biologists came to a clear consensus known as the “Modern Synthesis” (MS) (Huxley, 1942; Scott-Phillips et al., 2014). The focus was on gene distribution in a population rather than on the genes of an individual