The Role Of Work And Play In The Revolution Of Everyday Life
Andrew D R Abbott
Submitted in accordance with the requirements of the degree of Fine Art, Module ARTF
4020, Ba(hons) Fine Art
Tutor: Alexander Parigoris
The University of Leeds, School of Fine Art
April 2005
1
ABSTRACT
A critical discussion of positive and negative aspects of work and play in transcending
the boredom of contemporary capitalist culure. Applying the theory of the Situationist
International, with particular focus on Raoul Vaneigem’s ‘The Revolution of Everyday
Life’ with a close reading of Hannah Arendt’s ‘The Human Condition’ and illustrating
those ideas with post-revolution Soviet art from 1900 to 1940’s and performance work
from the 1960’s Fluxus group. The argument develops from an illustration of Arendt’s
distinction between labour and work to attempt to provide new definitions of play and the
problems that arise when these actions and processes are documented. The essay
concludes with a discussion of productive play and what essential aspects of work and
labour can be employed to develop a new, more satisfying daily existence.
2
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PART 1 WORK, PLAY AND REVOLUTION
4-17
PART2 RUSSIAN WORK
18-32
PART 3 FLUXUS PLAY
33-47
PART 4 GOOD WORK AND PRODUCTIVE PLAY
48 -56
BIBLIOGRAPHY
57,58
3
PART 1 WORK, PLAY AND REVOLUTION
My friends are bored or unhappy a lot of the time, or bored and unhappy. Mostly it can be
blamed on work, which is an unwanted constant in most of our lives but is also necessary
to be able to have free time in which to play. This is an essay that will not only attempt to
define work and play but will also address the problems and potential solutions within
them by finding their position in the quality of day to day living. I will be focusing my
attention on two main time periods and geographical areas; firstly Soviet Russia
following the overthrow of the Tsarist regime in 1917 where the revolution of every day
life was facilitated by the development of communism. The other area I will be
examining is tied to the workers and student riots of 1968 in Paris but the political and
theoretical basis that influenced this event spans a decade before and after this time and is
an international trend. It will include discussion on the texts produced by the Situationist
International and a critical application of these and other work and play related theories to
the Fluxus group of (non) artists who were active throughout the 60’s and 70’s. Through
these various investigations I intend to provide detailed and well illustrated definitions of
work and play and the conditions under which they can become revolutionary forces.
WHAT IS WORK AND PLAY?
To begin to understand the role of work and play it is first necessary to define what work
is. In Situationist terms we are discussing something with overwhelmingly negative
connotations. The Situationist International where a group of writers, thinkers and active
political theoreticians formed from various European avant-garde groups including the
Lettrist International and Imaginist Bauhaus. Throughout the 1960’s their main output
was the journal Internationale Situationniste, a publication that collated ideas on
urbanism, intervention, agitation and promoted a critical response to Western capitalist
society. Although the most famous figurehead of the Situationist International was Guy
Debord, who was responsible for the creation the influential text ‘Society of the
Spectacle’ and developed the theory of the derive, other members of the SI also produced
extended texts.1 One such individual was Raoul Vaneigem who was a member of the SI
in their infancy and key to some of its underlying theory. Vaneigem was later expelled
from the group but not before producing ‘The Revolution of Everyday Life’, a book that
contains ideas and a spirit that will always be affiliated with the more positive elements
of the SI. In ‘The Revolution of Everyday Life’ we find that Vaneigem’s description of
work is ‘forced labour’; a term that describes the job or means of living adopted or thrust
upon the modern proletariat,
‘From adolescence to retirement each twenty four hour cycle repeats the same shattering
bombardment, like bullets hitting a window: mechanical repetition, time-which-ismoney, submission to bosses, boredom, exhaustion. From the crushing of youth’s energy
1
For a full understanding of the formation and development of the Situationist
International please refer to Ken Knabb (ed), Situationist International Anthology,
(Bureau of Public Secrets 1981)
4
to the gaping wound of old age, life cracks in every direction under the blows of forced
labour.’2
It is this definition of work that rings truest in contemporary society, when we talk about
work it is generally a byword for our job. The terminology and images conjured up by the
phrase ‘going to work’ have changed little since Vaneigem’s day when the idea of work
being a creative or productive use of time is substituted by an immediate reference to the
9 to 5 life. However, Vaneigem fails to expand further on this definition of work.
Although he makes a distinction from labour (the action involved in work which carries
the negativity of its Latin root ‘to suffer’) ‘productivity’ is a separate phenomena unconnected and even hindered by ‘work’,
‘It is useless to expect even a caricature of creativity from the conveyer belt. Nowadays
ambition and love of a job well done are the indelible mark of defeat and of the most
mindless submission.”3
Vaneigem and the Situationist International appear less concerned with the question of
what work actually is than its negative effects on commercial society. This could be due
to an assumption on their part that the audience for Situationist theory would already be
familiar with Marxism and this familiarity excuses them from contributing their own full
definition of work. However, in Hannah Arendt’s text ‘The Human Condition’, published
in 1958, around the same time as the Situationist International’s formation, we find that
Marx’s definition is itself lacking in clarity for the purpose of a critical analyses of the
role of ‘work’. Arendt addresses this by drawing distinctions between labour and work.
Firstly we can examine Arendt’s definition of labour, which is an expansion of Adam
Smith and Karl Marx’s labour theories,
‘…the distinction between productive and unproductive labour contains, albeit in a
prejudicial manner, the more fundamental distinctions between labour and work.’4
For Arendt, labour is the action of men as animal laborans – the labour of our bodies as
opposed to homo faber’s activity – the work of our hands. Labour is chiefly characterised
by its link with the cycle of nature and life. Labour is every effort that we must make in
order to survive in the natural world; hunting and gathering food being the most obvious
examples. Although it bears close resemblance to Smith’s ‘unproductive labour’ Arendt’s
labour is a productive action but the things it produces are consumed almost
instantaneously in the life process. Labour leaves no trace or monument to man’s effort
other than the fact that he is still alive.
2
Raoul Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, (Rebel Press/Left Bank Books
1994), p. 52. Hereafter referred to as Vaneigem.
3
ibid, p. 54
4
Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, (University of Chicago Press, 1958), p. 87.
Hereafter referred to as Arendt.
5
‘It is indeed the mark of all labouring that it leaves nothing behind, that the result of it’s
effort is almost as quickly consumed as the effort is spent. And yet this effort, despite its
futility, is born of a great urgency and motivated by a more powerful drive than anything
else, because life itself depends on it.’5
Work, on the other hand, always produces things. Work is the effort of fabrication that
produces objects that become part of the man-made environment in which we spend our
day to day lives, the human artifice. It is the produce of ‘work’ that defines us as humans
instead of animals; the objects that we create play a significant role in understanding
ourselves,
‘They are mostly, but not exclusively objects for use and they posses the durability Locke
needed for the establishment of property, the ‘value’ Adam Smith needed for the
exchange market, and they bear testimony to productivity, which Marx believed to be the
test of human nature. Their proper use does not cause them to disappear and they give the
human artifice the stability and solidity without which it could not be relied upon to
house the unstable and mortal creature which is man.’6
It is important to bear in mind that labour and work are not distinguished by their
negative or positive connotations. Not all useless, futile suffering is labour and similarly
work is not an umbrella term for all productive effort – the key factor that separates work
and labour is the permanence and durability of its produce. Of course work and labour are
distinguished by other elements such as the use of tools and technology, isolated or
collective effort and the means and ends of action but rather than begin an abstract
discussion here I hope to illustrate these factors with reference to specific historical
activities. In this way we will develop a fuller understanding of the nature of work and
also be able to analyse the forms it may take in a revolutionary context.
One of the aims of this essay is to provide, through the investigation into the meaning and
role of work, a satisfactory definition of play that allows us to look at it as a revolutionary
force. A tempting starting point is to define play as all effort and action that is not work
or labour. This is the kind of definition that appears in Arendt’s text,
‘The same trend to level down all serious activities to the status of making a living is
manifest in present-day labour theories, which almost unanimously define labour as the
opposite of play. As a result, all serious activities, irrespective of their fruits, are called
labour, and every activity which is not necessary either for the life of the individual or for
the life process of society is subsumed under playfulness.’7
However, to arrive at a point where we can discuss the role of play in the revolution of
everyday life it will be necessary to formulate an understanding of play as sophisticated
as Arendt’s distinctions between work and labour. There are similarities that can be
5
ibid, p. 87
ibid, p.136
7
ibid, p.127
6
6
drawn between work and play (particularly with the ‘non-productive’ aspect of labour)
and it will be these comparative aspects that I will focus on rather than settling for a
definition of play as what work is not.
WHAT IS A REVOLUTION OF EVERYDAY LIFE?
Now we have outlined what will be covered in the essay I would like to provide some
background to why, that is, an overview of the current and historic climate that
necessitates a ‘revolution of everyday life’. My own interest lies in the boredom and
frustration that surrounds the daily life of the worker, a situation that rapidly approaches
me. The typical course of action for a young graduate in Leeds is to subsidise the time
spent searching for course-related dream career opportunities with any number of
characterless and interchangeable call-centre and office administration jobs. The actual
work involved in these temporary jobs ranges from the insultingly unskilled to the
downright humiliating and unethical. Selling gas over the telephone, data-inputting for
mobile phone service providers, taking orders for catalogue and betting companies are all
part of a circuit of occupations that thousands of university educated twenty-somethings
find themselves caught up in following departure from the education system. Even more
depressing is the manner in which the drudgery endured for the better part of the day
whilst working in these jobs seeps in to the employee’s ‘free time’ by sucking away the
energy and motivation needed for escape. The draining and oppressive nature of doing
nothing all day under the watchful eye of a team leader or office manager erodes the will
to apply for work that might lead to a better lifestyle. Similarly, workers that find
themselves in call centres and offices as stop gaps to erase some student debts before
moving on to looking for ‘real work’ find the requisite retail therapy on the weekends
destroys saving potential.
Clearly this is neither a localised or modern phenomenon. The Situationist International
were identifying and tackling the same problem from the late 50’s and throughout the
1960’s. As mentioned earlier, Raoul Vaneigem identified work or forced labour as one
of the main culprits in the restriction of everyday life being lived to its full potential but it
is only a facet of consumer society’s passive deception,
‘…the monotony of the images we consume get the upper hand, reflecting the monotony
of the action that produces them…There was no VW, only an ideology almost
unconnected with automobiles. Flushed with Chivas Regal, whisky of the elite, we
savour a strange cocktail of alcohol and class struggle. Nothing surprising anymore,
there’s the rub! The monotony of the ideological spectacle makes us aware of the
passivity of life.’8
8
RaoulVaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, p. 25
7
The problem lies within the detachment and alienation man feels (but fails to identify) in
contemporary society. There are fewer and fewer things to relate to, only constructs of
things, and less and less objects and people to interact with, only images of objects and
roles that we adopt to interact socially. The culmination of this is what the Situationists
labelled ‘the spectacle’, developed by Guy Debord in 1958’s ‘Society of the Spectacle’.
If all of life is mediated through images then a distant helplessness will permeate every
action, nothing real can be changed or fabricated because nothing we come into direct
contact with is real. This lack of solidity and permanence is the crux to Arendt’s criticism
of commercial society and her reasoning for the alienation and frustration felt by the
worker.
Man as homo- faber has the ability to create an entire world around him, it fabricates
things from the material found in the natural world. It is in this transformation and
therefore domination of nature that homo-faber finds a reward in work. Unlike labour,
which is a constant fight with the forces of nature where the only outcome is animallaboran’s ability to keep his head above water, in work homo-faber asserts his power
over the whole world. He becomes not only the creator of a human world but, through the
destruction of the natural world, master of the conditions he was born into.
‘The experience of this violence is the most elemental experience of human strength and,
therefore, the very opposite of the painful, exhaustive effort experienced in sheer labour.
It can provide self-assurance and satisfaction and even become a source of self
confidence throughout life.’9
It is insinuated here that work is essential to man’s sense of fulfilment in the world, that
the ability to fabricate objects and assert them over the natural world is part of happiness.
This contrasts the toil and suffering of labour where nature dominates man and highlights
the futility of his efforts. The creation of real, lasting things reifies man’s place in the
world and becomes a reminder that he is both alive and of some importance. However, in
commercial society there are increasingly fewer opportunities to fabricate objects that
demonstrate this assertion over the world. The ‘work of our hands’ in contemporary
society creates objects that are fed back into the cycle of consumption quicker than we
are able to see them. The results of work that were once durable and lasting objects such
as cars, tools, appliances, even houses, are now consumed and disposed of at frightening
rates. The turnover of commodity objects is so high that the durability of work’s produce
is no greater than the things produced by labour.
‘It consists in treating all use objects as though they were consumer goods, so that a chair
or a table is now consumed as rapidly as a dress and a dress used up almost as quickly as
food.’10
It is from this evidence that Arendt attributes the unhappiness and frustration in modern
culture to our acting as a ‘society of labourers’. The permanence and utility that
9
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.140
ibid, p.124
10
8
characterises work is devoured by consumerism so all that was once ‘productive work’
has now become labour. As a society of labourers the quality of our day-to-day life is at
stake; one element is that labour is an essentially privative act that does not sit well with
man’s condition as a public and political being.
‘…the animal laborans was permitted to occupy the public realm; and yet, as long as the
animal laborans remains in possession of it, there can be no true public realm, but only
private activities displayed in the open.’11
The Situationists and Marx discuss this condition in terms of alienation. A problem with
the current social climate is that the jobs we occupy propose that we work together to
create things for a better society but the laborious nature of the work alienates us, through
its futility, from the things we create and the people we interact with in that fabrication. It
is the discrepancy between what we are led to believe we are ‘working’ for and the fruits
of our work that causes the most frustration. Man has the capacity and potential to create
lasting and durable things as homo-faber but instead spends his day labouring like
animal-laborans to eventually create nothing of any significance.
The greatest disappointment in the modern world is that if happiness and fulfilment were
achievable by giving man the opportunity to create ‘the work of the hands’ as he wanted
then the reduction of the working day would lead to a perfect situation. Due to increasing
mechanisation and automation man need only labour for a few hours a day and is left
with hours of free time in which to indulge his urges to create lasting and durable objects,
or ‘working’. However, as Arendt explains the labouring society is conditioned to only
understand the laws of consumption, the animal laborans is a consuming being, always
trapped in natures’ cycle , and the conditions are no different in the modern world,
‘…the spare time of the animal laborans is never spent in anything but consumption and
the more time left to him, the greedier and more craving his appetites…eventually no
object of the world will be safe from consumption and annihilation through
consumption.’12
If the current trend of the transformation of all work into labour continues then the only
escape from an alienating and unfulfilling existence must begin by taking control of our
daily routine. This brings us to the question of the form a revolution of everyday life
should or can take. The intention of this essay is to define everyday life in terms of work
and play, those being the two components of daily existence. A revolutionised daily life
will be a balanced combination of work and play where both activities are devoid of
alienation and frustration. How this situation can be reached can only be revealed through
the development of the essay but as a starting point it will be useful to consider the
Situationist position and Arendt’s ideas found in ‘The Human Condition.’
11
12
ibid, p.134
ibid, p.133
9
The Situationist solution to the boredom and conditioning nature of consumer culture was
based in the creation of moments and spaces of life lived as it should be, or ‘situations’.
The revolution of everyday life will occur through direct lived experience and the
unshackling of conditioning forces, which at present can only exist in moments. The
more numerous and regular these moments of lived experience are instigated then the
greater the chance for the unmasking of the spectacle becomes, the destruction of
commodity culture will be achieved by a process similar to making a thousand pin pricks
in a big black curtain. The revolution of everyday life for the Situationists would be life
lived as if it were one continuous moment unconcerned with the conditions of the human
world. The role of the individual in a Situationist revolution is to live only under his own
conditions rather than those forced upon him by nature or others,
‘The situation is thus made to be lived by its constructors. The role played by a passive or
merely bit-playing ‘public’ must constantly diminish, while that played by those who
cannot be called actors but rather, in a new sense of the term, ‘livers’ must steadily
increase…we have to multiply poetic subjects and objects.13
In this sense the Situationist revolution would be a merging of art and life. It would inject
the ‘creativity, spontaneity and poetry’14 of artistic activity into every element of being.
The Situationists ignored or despised art that took the form of permanent, commodified
objects that would feed into the spectacle but did see art as an indispensable core element
in the initiation of a revolution.
‘In this way the old specialisation of art has finally come to an end. There are no more
artists because everyone is an artist. The work of art of the future will be the construction
of a passionate life.’15
Arendt too saw the artists as playing an ideal or exemplary role in society. A discussion
of a revolution of everyday life in Arendt’s terms would inexorably be linked to the
conditions of work and therefore to link Arendt’s and Situationist theory implies a
revolution of everyday work. A revolution of everyday life would involve the appropriate
application of homo-faber’s abilities to daily existence (rather than the current climate
where his potential is wasted in laborious activity). This does not necessarily entail an
eradication of all labour, as I intend to investigate, but the correct marriage of fabrication
and toil to create a fulfilling balanced lifestyle. Firstly, the current situation where homofaber operates as a society of labourers must be reversed and according to Arendt the one
group who are already in this position are artists,
‘Whatever we do we are supposed to do for the sake of ‘making a living’; such is the
verdict of society, and the number of people, especially in professions who might
13
Guy Debord, in Kenn Knabb ed, Situationist International Anthology, (Bureau of
Public Secrets, 1981), p. 25
14
Please refer to whole of Chapter 20 in Raoul Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday
Life, pp.190-213
15
Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, p. 202
10
challenge it, has decreased rapidly. The only exception society is willing to grant is the
artist, who, strictly speaking, is the only ‘worker’ left in a labouring society.’16
Because the Situationists and Arendt hold the field of art in high regard or at the very
least see the potential for revolution within it, I propose to further investigate the themes
of this essay in two parts, each focused upon artists’ action around the time of
revolutionary activity. To illustrate Situationist ideas and evaluate the role of play I will
discuss the produce and activities of the Fluxus art group. Firstly though, I would like to
discuss the role of work by applying Arendt’s text to Soviet constructivism. Through the
examination of these two main areas I hope to define a revolution of everyday life as both
an escape from old conditions and the creation of new conditions under which we work
and play.
PART 2 RUSSIAN WORK
The Bolsheviks overthrow of the Tsarist regime in 1917 provides a suitable starting point
for a discussion of work and revolution. Activity and thought in Russia from 1917 was
primarily concerned with the growth and development of a society in the unique position
of rebirth. Although this period could technically be labelled as post-revolution, the rise
of communism and the new Soviet state provides an excellent opportunity for a critical
analysis of the role of work in the formation of new lifestyles. Work and labour are
synonymous with a Western understanding of communist Russia; the painting
retrospectives of Soviet art from this period display countless images of men, women and
children happily working alongside heavy machinery in fields, or joyously reaping the
rewards of months of hard labour on the collective farm17. We are informed that the
celebrities and role models of this society were not actors and musicians but miners,
factory workers and of course, political leaders. It seems that every young child’s dream
was to be recognised alongside the Stakhanovites18 for outstanding work, and to one day
shake hands with Stalin. Yet, despite the appeal of work and its omnipresent influence on
Soviet society, little has been written regarding the philosophy behind the work ethic
adopted by the newly empowered working class. Of course, the rhetoric of the period was
full of terms like ‘efficiency’, ‘strength’ and ‘collective effort’ but the nature of this work
is overlooked. In this chapter I propose to analyse the various stages of Soviet communist
16
Arendt, The Human Condition, p. 127
For background reading on this subject please refer to Matthew Cullerne Brown, David
Elliott and Aleksandr Siborov, Soviet Socialist Realist Painting 1930’s-1960’s,
(Exhibition catalogue 1992)
18
The Stakhanovites were a group of workers, many of whom were Metro constructors,
honoured for their outstanding effort and dedication to work. They became poster boys
and women for the working class, often immortalised and made famous in flattering,
dynamic portraits including Kotlyarov’s ‘Portrait of Stakhanov’ (1938). For background
reading on this subject please refer to Matthew Cullerne Bown, and Brandon Taylor, Art
of the Soviets, Manchester University Press 1993).
17
11
development in terms of the kind of work employed or suggested by the state and the
relevance this has to the quality of life of the collective society. This will involve an
application of Arendt’s distinction between labour and work (and the various threads
routed in its discussion) to the themes and practices of Soviet artists. Like Arendt, the
revolutionary Soviets saw the artists’ role as an example to the rest of society; they were
a group who would design the way of life that the workers would live collectively19. In
this sense the world and lifestyle of the Soviet artist would be a microcosm for all of
society and an experimental stage in the development of communism.
The development of art in Soviet Russia can be viewed in three stages; the pre-revolution
avant-garde, the early laboratory experimental stages of constructivism and the later,
developed stage of constructivism that birthed productivism. I intend to investigate each
of these stages chronologically with particular concentration on Vladimir Tatlin who was
responsible for the early experiments in constructivism, and its most ambitious (non)
product ‘The Monument to the Third International’. Investigation in these areas will
allow the discussion of key areas relating to work and revolution including, permanence,
utilitarianism and an illustration of the role of means and ends to work, art and labour in
Soviet society. Through these discussions I hope to provide a better understanding of
both Arendt’s writing (by illustrating her ideas in ‘The Human Condition’) and the role of
work and labour in the creation of a new society.
Before the revolution of 1917 and the formation of the constructivist group, the Russian
avant-garde artists were experimenting with a new style of painting that raised
fundamental questions about the role and necessity for work. The Russian avant-garde
were not working in total isolation from the rest of Europe and the issues in art and
painting crucial to modernism also applied to the Russians. Painting, a medium once
employed for the illustration of religious scenes and capturing of historical events was
now being made redundant with the invention of photography. Once stripped of any
immediate utility, such as representation, painting became a medium concerned with its
own form, it existed with in its own field and in this sense is a form of work that was only
‘about’ work20. The paintings of cubo-futurists and suprematists including Luibov Popova
were non-objective experiments in painting for painting’s sake21 and as such are the
unadulterated ‘work’ of Arendt’s homo-faber. The produce of the Russian avant-garde is
essentially functionless, certainly their function is not as apparent as in an illustration of a
great battle or portrait of a great leader. By referring to Arendt’s thoughts on the produce
of homo-faber we can discover the role that apparently useless objects play in society.
One of the distinctions between work and labour is that homo-faber’s ‘work of the hands’
produces objects that have permanence in the world. The accumulation of these objects
19
Refer to Christina Lodder, Chapter 3 ‘Towards a Theoretical Basis: Fusing the Formal
and Utilitarian’, in, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983), pp73-108
20
Further reading on the effects of modernism and descriptions of modernist painting can
begin with T.J Clark, The Painting of Modern Life, (Thomas and Hudson 1984)
21
For further discussion please refer to Margit Rowell and Angelica Zander Rudenstine,
Chapter 2 in, Art of the Avant-Garde in Russia, (The Solomon R Guggenheim
Foundation, 1981), pp. 32-56
12
becomes the human artifice in which man can recognise all his achievements. The objects
we produce are documentation of our productivity. Furthermore, any object created by
homo-faber becomes a mirror for man’s domination of nature, they show that man is able
to use his surroundings as he sees fit, and once these objects are stripped of any use value
their dominance of the natural world is the only quality they pronounce to the beholder of
that object. It is clear though that both the produce of the Russian avant-garde and of
work in general operates on a higher level than that of pure vanity objects. The essential
quality of an object created by homo-faber lies in its durability and permanence in a
world that is constantly moving and births and destroys other objects continuously. Man
relies on objects that make up the human artifice to exist as a public being,
‘…men, their ever changing nature notwithstanding, can retrieve their sameness, that is,
their identity, by being related to the same chair and the same table. In other words,
against the subjectivity of men stands the objectivity of the man-made world.’22
Man made objects, whether they have a clear function or not, create a human artifice in
which man can hide and momentarily forget about the hostilities of nature. Within this
artifice he feels an affinity with other beings that share this artifice. The ability to create
objects of permanence distinguishes man from all other life and elevates his status in a
world where he is surrounded my immortal nature and immortal gods,
‘…mortals could find their place in a cosmos where everything is immortal except
themselves. By their capacity for the immortal deed, by their ability to leave nonperishable traces behind, men, their individual mortality notwithstanding, attain an
immortality of their own and prove themselves to be divine in nature.’23
Creating objects, any objects, helps man to escape the conditions of nature, that being his
own eventual decay and death. In contrast labour only reinforces nature’s control over
man. Therefore it can be suggested that one of work’s roles is to help man momentarily
transcend the suffering of a labouring existence by touching on the immortal. It is here
that we can relate Arendt’s theory of immortalising work to the Russian avant-garde
artists. They were aware of the immortalisation of their work and took advantage of it to
document their own innovation and the new conditions that allowed it,
‘The intermediate (Russian) futurist generation shared the more transitional view of the
‘god-builders’: the fear of death, if not death itself could be conquered, and immortality
achieved by fame and reputation preserved in the memory of the collective and of future
generations. In this way the Russian avant-garde fused the artistic immortality of
successful innovation and the political immortality of remembered revolution.’24
22
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.137
ibid, p.19
24
Robert Williams, Artists in Revolution Portraits Of The Russian Avant-Garde, 1905 –
1925, (The Scolar Press, 1978), p. 20
23
13
Death and mortality are natural conditions that the Russian avant-garde were exploring
through ‘work’. The exploration of man’s conditions was expanded in the next stage of
Soviet art development to include investigations into the natural environment. It is this
period of art experimentation that produced the early experiments that were to become
the constructivists’ laboratory work. Artists that were part of the avant-garde began to
develop their cubist-influenced paintings into three dimensional reliefs and sculptures.
One such artist was Vladimir Tatlin who was central to the development of the form and
theory of constructivism. Key to Tatlin’s work was an investigation of natural forms and
the inherent properties of materials25. Early experiments in this field resulted in Dadaesque collages of found objects and un-manipulated materials,
‘Larinov – the most enterprising of the scandal-makers – quickly took Tatlin’s caprice
and gave birth to ‘plastic rayonism’ [Rayism] for the exhibition, tacking together a
composition of pieces of wood, plants, rope, coloured paper, bits of cloth, bottles, etc…
they nail together absolutely anything.’26
Tatlin was also known for his search for the perfect form and interest in the Greek’s
golden proportions. He believed that everything was constructed from perfect forms
found in nature; the cube, the sphere, the cone and so on27. In this sense his art became an
assemblage of the material on offer in the natural world rather than an art purely
concerned with the human artifice. This is an interesting detail when trying to define the
type of work the Soviet artists were performing. A distinction between work and labour is
that homo-faber’s action is a transformation and destruction of the natural world; making
a table for instance, is the irreversible transformation of nature into part of the man-made
world, which destroys the tree in the process. When man merely assembles natural
materials to show off their properties rather than manipulating and destroying them by
turning them into utilitarian objects is his action still categorised as work? The
subordination to nature is certainly a characteristic of labour, as is the lack of permanent
transformation of the things it touches. It is unknown whether the artists found this form
of work fulfilling but history shows that it was not long before the artists and the state
wanted to develop this experimental work into something useable. Art work in Soviet
society did not last long as an end in itself.
The result of Tatlin’s development from experimentation with natural forms in to
utilitarian objects was one of the most ambitious constructions of the 20th Century; The
Monument to the Third International. This architectural structure, conceived and
designed by Tatlin, was intended to be the grand result of artistic forms merged with
25
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983),
‘Vladimir Tatlin’, pp.8-18
26
E.Adamov, ‘Pis’mo iz Moskvy, Kievskaya mysl’, 6 May 1915, p.2; translation taken
from Andersen, Vladimir Tatlin, pp. 6-7, in Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale
University Press, 1983), p.18
27
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983),
‘Vladimir Tatlin’, pp.8-18
14
utilitarian aims28. Both a monument and a functioning central administration centre for
the Soviet state, it would house the meeting spaces and technology essential to the
development of a new society,
‘The monument consists of three great rooms of glass, erected with the help of a
complicated system of vertical pillars and spirals. These rooms are placed on top of each
other and have different, harmonically corresponding forms. They are able to move at
different speeds by means of special mechanism. The lower storey, which is in the form
of a cube, rotates on its axis at the speed of one revolution per year. This is intended for
legislative assemblies. The next storey, which is in the form of a pyramid, rotates on its
axis at the rate of one revolution per month. Here the executive bodies are to meet (the
International Executive Committee, the Secretariat and other executive administrative
bodies). Finally, the uppermost cylinder, which rotates at the speed of one revolution per
day, is reserved for information services: an information office, a newspaper, the issuing
of proclamations, pamphlets and manifestos – in short all the means for informing the
international proletariat:; it will also have a telegraphic office and an apparatus that can
project slogans onto a large screen. These can be fitted around the axis of the hemisphere.
Radio Masts will rise up over the monument.’29
We can deconstruct the qualities of the monument to reveal layers that illustrate Arendt’s
writings about work. Firstly, The Monument to the Third International is gigantic and
made from strong, long lasting materials. It was designed to be noticed and stay noticed
for generations. As a product of homo-faber’s ‘work of the hands’ it becomes a
permanent reminder of the achievements of man as a constructor. This quality provides a
link with Tatlin’s previously mentioned work in the avant-garde where the function of his
‘work’ was to immortalise the present. The ambitious scale of Tatlin’s monument (it was
to stand four hundred meters high) abstracts it from its actual functional value and places
it in the realm where it is possible to interpret it purely as an object in its own right. The
role of the artist in this case is to initiate the fabrication of a thing that will require the full
extent of man’s capabilities – to work at the fringe of the humanly possible and then
solidify these achievements in a lasting, permanent object. As a monument, Tatlin’s
construction is an exercise in documenting the work power and technical innovation of a
whole society, and he is quoted as having said that
‘modern technology fully allows for the possibility of constructing such a building.’30
This leads us to the second quality of the monument that embodies Arendt’s theories
relating to work. Obviously the mechanical requirements and technical difficulty in
creating any object that houses three rotating buildings would be immensely problematic.
The creation of the Monument would push Soviet technology to the furthest limit and
28
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983),
‘Tatlin’s Monument To The Third International.’, pp. 55-67
29
N. Punin, ‘Tour de Tatline’, Veshch’, No.1/2, 1922; reprinted in Andersen, Vladimir
Tatlin, p.57, in Lodder, op.cit, p.61
30
Tatlin, Zhizn’ iskusstva, No.315. 1919. in Lodder, op.cit, p. 60
15
demand incredible engineering innovation. This exploitation of tools and technology is
another distinctive feature of homo-faber that is critical in the search for fulfilment and
placement in the forced conditions of the natural world. The mastery of machines is yet
another reminder of our domination over nature and demonstrates that man is able to
create and survive within his own automated world. Work in this sense is the process of
man proving his own self-sufficiency as he is both master of the natural world and the
artifice he creates. However, as Arendt highlights, in the same manner by which man is
conditioned by the objects that he creates (as they become the human artifice which he
must live in), the tools and technology he creates eventually dominate and condition their
users,
‘…if the human condition consists in man’s being a conditioned being for whom
everything, given or man-made, immediately becomes a condition of his further
existence, then man ‘adjusted’ himself to machines the moment he designed them.’31
Furthermore, the exploitation and reliance upon technology in Tatlin’s monument is in
effect sensationalising an element of ‘work’ that can have a destructive impact on man’s
productivity. Arendt explains that the use of tools, which separates labour and work,
actually limits man’s creativity rather than aids it,
‘In place of both utility and beauty, which are standards of the world, we have come to
design products that still fulfil certain ‘basic functions’ but whose shape will be primarily
determined by the operations of the machine…the product itself – not only its variations
but even the ‘total change to a new product’ – will depend entirely upon the capacity of
the machine.’32
We can reveal a further layer of by discussing Tatlin’s monument in terms of its function.
Its daily operation was to broadcast and televise political messages from the huge screens
and radio masts housed at the top of the monument. It was an object that would distribute
propaganda. Also, in more abstract terms we can suggest that the aforementioned giant
scale and technological showcasing of the monument mean that it is also a physical
manifestation of all Soviet potential, and as such the object itself is a piece of
propaganda. Its form and the work performed to create it become its function. This is a
view that coincides with Tatlin’s original brief for his monument,
‘Tatlin had (decided) that the monument should express dynamism, be dynamic and
perform a dynamic function as an agitational and propaganda centre.’33
Therefore we can consider the Monument to the Third International as an essentially
utilitarian and functional object. The importance of function in all works of art was to
become a hallmark of Soviet art and eventually fracture the constructivists in two groups
31
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.147
ibid, p.152
33
Christina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, p.56
32
16
– the new branch of which were hard line utilitarianists who favoured a new ‘production
art’34. This changed the artist’s role from someone who was the creator of objects for the
sake of creating objects (in which the focus was the actual performance of work) , to a
creator of elaborate ‘tools’ (where the focus lies upon the potential use of the object
created). This is a perfect illustration of the negative ramifications of utilitarianism. It
transforms an act that was once and end in itself, into a series of unending, unfulfilling
means. When Tatlin designed the Monument to the Third International its success would
not be measured on its creation (it was actually never built) but on its effectiveness to
distribute propaganda, which in turn is a means to another end. This can be read as a
metaphor for all of Soviet society; for the sake of productivity and efficiency, it
eradicated the exultant possibilities within work by transforming all of the produce of the
worker into a means for some other end. Again, Arendt has written about this in ‘The
Human Condition’,
‘Only in so far as fabrication chiefly fabricates use objects does the finished product
again become a means, and only in so far as the life process takes hold of things and uses
them for its purpose does the productive and limited instrumentality of fabrication change
into the limitless instrumentalization of everything that exists.’35
To develop this idea we can suggest that utilitarianism actually belittles the role of work
in the creation of a new soviet society. The focus was always upon what was made – the
produce of work, rather than the process of how it was made – the action of work. The
artists and worker were to become the designers and fabricators of a ‘new environment’36
but the quality of life during this fabrication was largely overlooked, so it is difficult to
look at the Soviet revolution in terms of a revolution of everyday life in which every
moment is important. This is not to say that the Soviets completely ignored the process of
work, the constructivists were interested in reducing the specialisation of work and the
division of labour by involving the worker in every stage of the making process. Artists
were eventually to become ‘artists-workers’ who not only conceived and designed
products but also were physically in the factories operating the machines that made them,
as suggested by the theoreticians of the time,
‘We want the worker to cease being a mechanical executor of some type of plan
unfamiliar to him. He must become a conscious and active participant in the creative
process of producing an object37
In this sense the work of the Soviet artist-engineer could have been more fulfilling than
the alienation of our present-day specialised work. There would have been more
34
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983), ‘Art
in Production’, pp. 101-103
35
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.157
36
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983),
‘Arvatof and Lef’,pp105-108
37
O.Brik, ‘V poryadke dnya’, in Iskusstvo v proizvodstve (Moscow, 1921), p.4, in
Lodder, op.cit, p.104
17
responsibility and connection with the end product than in many of our modern
administrative and production line jobs. But, in terms of a revolution of everyday life, the
nature of Soviet work is flawed by its overbearing concern with utility.
So, as a conclusion to this chapter, by looking at the various works and output of Soviet
artists we have illustrated a few of Arendt’s key notions on work. It is an action that man
is compelled to perform, as the objects he creates through work both reify his
achievements and toil and, on a grander scale, serve to immortalise him. This was the
action of the Russian avant-garde and early constructivists. Unfortunately, through the
action of work, man inadvertently creates his own prison. One form of this prison is the
human artifice, an accumulation of all the man made objects he creates in order to prove
dominance over nature. This artifice is created so man can live independently of the
conditions under which he exists in nature, but the human artifice becomes yet another
conditioning environment. The machines and tools homo-faber creates eventually limit
his creativity and the technology he invents dominates him. The other form of restriction
work enforces on life is illustrated by the later era of constructivists where an
overwhelming concern with utility prevents any one thing from being appreciated in its
own right. This is exemplified by Tatlin’s monument, which could have been appreciated
as an incredible structure and achievement in itself but its function as a piece of
propaganda would always detract from that. Either way, work and the products of work
create man’s conditions. Similarly, the ‘spectacle’ that the Situationists blame for the
emptiness in consumer society is, in part, an accumulation of artificial objects and
interactions that have created an entire human artifice from which we cannot escape.38 Of
course, if man does not create his own conditions then he must live under the conditions
of nature, a fact that the Soviets were probably aware of when deciding the role of both
worker and artist was to be the decorator and organiser of life39.
The role of work in the revolution of everyday life is paradoxical. It is both a necessity
for the fulfilment and freedom of existence as it fabricates objects that remain permanent
in the world, but it simultaneously creates a conditioning environment. This conditioning
environment reduces action and objects to a means to an end, which restricts the freedom
and enjoyment of life. A potential solution to this situation lies within the potential to
divorce work from utilitarianism. Here we keep the positive aspect of homo-faber’s
‘work of the hands’, that being the manufacture of durable objects, and transform its
produce and activity into something that exists for its own sake. This type of
‘meaningless work’ finds its form in contemporary society as hobbies, in much the same
way that sport is a form of meaningless labour. In the following section I would like to
expand on the importance of games and meaningless work to examine the role of work
within play and the role of play within the revolution of everyday life.
38
refer to Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle, (Zone Books New York, 1994)
refer to Chrisina Lodder, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983), ‘Art
in Production’’, pp.101-103
39
18
PART 3 FLUXUS PLAY
Games are central to our understanding of play – when we play we tend to play games.
Children play games to entertain themselves and in doing so develop an understanding of
the world. Adults play games in the form of sport and also dedicate a lot of leisure time to
watching others play games. Obviously, this kind of passive spectatorship does not itself
fall under the definition of play. The Situationists believed that the revolution of everyday
life would be the equivalent of transforming man’s existence into a game, one that
demanded participation and had no clear winner or loser.40 The elimination of
competition in a game removes its utility and as such strengthens its playfulness. One
group more than aware of the revolutionary qualities of useless games were the Fluxus
artists. Henry Flynt, an artist associated with Fluxus, came close to a definition of this
form of play when he invented the term ‘brend’ in 1963,
‘Consider the whole of your life, what you already do, all your doings. Now please
exclude everything which is naturally physiologically necessary (or harmful) such as
breathing or sleeping (or breaking an arm). From what remains exclude everything which
is for the satisfaction of a social demand, a very large area which includes foremost your
job, but also care of children, being polite, voting, your haircut, and much else. From
what remains exclude everything which is an agency, a ‘means’, another very large area
which overlaps with others to be excluded. From what remains, exclude everything which
involves competition. In what remains concentrate on everything done entirely because
you just like it as you do it.’41
Doing ‘what you just like’ became a dominant characteristic of the Fluxus group. They
are an (art) group with no fixed beginning or end, no fixed geographical location or
centre, not even a definitive list of members. The artists and individuals who were
associated or associated themselves with Fluxus did so because they just liked. Fluxus,
apparently, was not a body of work or set of rules but rather a way of doing things that
many critics saw as just playing around. Therefore, it is impossible to talk about the role
of play in all Fluxus work because the output of Fluxus artists is too diverse to allow
generalisation. Rather, I intend to discuss an element within the work of Fluxus artists
that appears frequently enough to be considered typical and will help provide a fuller
definition of ‘play’.
George Macuinas is popularly known as the central figure in Fluxus; in as much as he
was the only person concerned with labelling and documenting work of Fluxus artists. He
40
refer to Guy Debord, ‘Toward a Situationist International’ in, ‘Situationist
International Anthology’, (Bureau of Public Secrets 1981), pp.22-25
41
Henry Flynt in, Christine Stiles, ‘Between Water and Stone’, in Elizabeth Armstrong
and Joan Rothfuss, In the Spirit of Fluxus, (Walker Art Centre, 1993), p.72. Hereafter
referred to as In the Spirit of Fluxus
19
was responsible for organising the first Fluxfest in 1962 in Wiesbaden and was
subsequently responsible for the organisation and execution of the Fluxus yearbooks and
Fluxboxes that remain one of the few lasting objects from Fluxus activity in the 60’s and
70’s. There is a certain irony that so much of Fluxus’ identity is attributed to Macuinas
when, in essence, his attempts to solidify and control Fluxus as an art movement were at
odds with most of the ideas of the artists involved in it. However, my starting point for a
discussion of play in Flux-terms is from an interview between Larry Miller and George
Macuinas. In the interview Macuinas identifies some key concepts that, for him,
characterise Fluxus. Like the art of the Soviet avant-garde, concreteism is at the heart of
Fluxus; the realisation that art can work with its own qualities, a painting can be about
painting and music can be about music, instead of referring to something outside of itself
or being illusionary. From this interest in the concrete arises a direct link with Dada that
provoked Fluxus activity to be pigeonholed as ‘neo-Dadaist’. The source of most Fluxus
thinking is Duchamp’s use of the ready-made,
‘GM: Well, the ready-made is the most concrete thing. Cannot be more concrete than the
ready-made.
LM: Because it is what it is.
GM: Right, so that’s extreme concrete. There’s no illusion about it, it’s not abstract. Most
concrete is the ready-made. Now, Duchamp thought mainly about ready-made objects.
John Cage extended it to ready-made sound. George Brecht extended it furthermore..
well, together with Ben Vautier.. into ready-made actions.’42
It was Cage’s philosophy of music and sound that is often sited as the theory that
informed Fluxus performance. Many artists that became involved in Fluxus attended John
Cage’s experimental music classes in which the idea that music could incorporate ‘nonmusical’ sounds was developed. Cage demonstrated that music was not reliant upon
tempo, key or rhythm and could be experienced anywhere at any time. Music was not
exclusively defined by the player but could also be defined by the listener. In many
pieces, such as 4’33’’ and 0’00’’ the fabrication of any sound is substituted by the
performer framing (in the former) or amplifying (in the latter) everyday sounds:
‘ 0’00’’… is nothing but the continuation of one’s daily work, whatever it is, providing
its not selfish, but is the fulfilment of an obligation to other people, done with contact
microphones, without any notion of concert or theatre or the public, but simply
continuing one’s daily work, now coming out through loudspeakers.’43
42
Ken Friedman ed, The Fluxus Reader, (Academy Editions, 1998), p.191. Hereafter
referred to as The Fluxus Reader
43
John Cage, quoted in Richard Kostelanetz, ed., Conversing with Cage (New York:
Limelight Editions, 1988),pp. 69-70, in Douglas Kahn, ‘The Latest: Fluxus and Music’,
in Elizabeth Armstrong and Joan Rothfuss, In the Spirit of Fluxus, p.106
20
In this case the artist is no longer acting as homo-faber because he is not concerned with
fabricating – the artist has become someone who simply notices and points out elements
of the world (both natural and man-made) instead of someone who strives to dominate it.
However, the artist is not playing a passive role; despite its incidental character, the
action of noticing becomes the work, it is an active observation. This is a point I would
like to return to and explore in more detail. Beforehand it will be helpful to discuss the
manner in which the sound based work of John Cage developed in to the full
performance events that typify most of the Fluxus output in the early 60’s. After Cage
had opened up the definition of music to include all sounds the next step taken by his
students was to expand this to include the actions that create these sounds,
‘One day in school, while I was performing our improvisational music, I got tired of loud
and rich sounds. I started tossing a bunch of keys to the ceiling to make an ostinato, with
its faint sound. And while I kept doing it, I began to look at my performance objectively
as a whole, and I noticed that I was performing an action of tossing keys, not playing
keys to make a sound. This was the turning point, when I became concerned with action
music or events.’44
In this instance the area defined by the artist is expanded to include not only the ‘useful’
sound-making element of the action but also the ‘meaningless’ or incidental part. This
acceptance of actions without means can be found also in many of George Brecht’s
events, and is key to the work’s playfulness. A good example is Brecht’s ‘Incidental
Music’ where the actions of the performer are essentially purposeless; they are simply a
means with no intentional or predictable end. The performance is executed for the sake
of the performance and the product, ‘art’, or ‘music’ is almost a byproduct,
INCIDENTAL MUSIC (1961)
Three dried peas or beans are dropped one after another, onto the keyboard. Each such
seed remaining on the keyboard and is attached to the key or keys nearest it with a single
piece of pressure-sensitive tape.45
Once the term ‘music’ had been applied to these performances in their entirety the need
for an audible sound was questioned; Fluxus music could take the form of making a salad
(Alison Knowles)46 or drawing a line (La Monte Young)47. The term ‘music’ was still
44
Mieko Shiomi in, The Fluxus Reader, p.110
George Brecht, Water Yam (1963) (Brussels and Hamburg: Edition Lebeer Hossmann,
1986), in Douglas Kahn, ‘The Latest: Fluxus and Music’, in Elizabeth Armstrong and
Joan Rothfuss, In the Spirit of Fluxus, p.105
46
Alison Knowles ‘Proposition’, first performed on 21 October 1962 at the Institute for
Contemporary Arts in London, repr. in David T Doris, ‘Zen Vaudeville’ in, The Fluxus
Reader, p.107
47
La Monte Young ‘Composition #10 1960: ‘Draw a straight line and follow it.’, repr. in
David T Doris, ‘Zen Vaudeville’ in, The Fluxus Reader, p.121
45
21
applied or used in reference to these events because the important element is the
perception of the audience. Sound and music are inescapable to the functioning human,
as Cage pointed out - our ears are always open. So, the audience is meant to be open to
every element of a Fluxus event in the same way you listen to every instrument and
sound in a piece of music.
Fluxus events and music tended to exploit the beauty of simple, everyday things by
altering the viewer’s perception of them. Once every sound or action becomes music, and
anyone that carries out an action is the performer of music, it follows that normal,
everyday tasks such as walking, take on a new significance,
THEATRE MUSIC
Keep Walking Intently48
Another tendency in Fluxus events was to make use of natural processes and objects from
the natural world. Instead of manipulating or changing them in some way, Fluxus artists
would change the audience’s perception of the process or object. Brecht’s Drip Music
(1959) makes us focus on the natural action of water,
DRIP MUSIC (DRIP EVENT)
For single or multiple performance.
A source of dripping water and an empty vessel are arranged so that the water falls
into a vessel49
When looking at Fluxus performance such as this in terms of work and play it is
important to remember that this exploitation of nature, rather than its manipulation,
contradicts the wants of homo-faber. Instead of fabricating or changing processes and in
so asserting man’s domination of nature, the Fluxus artist makes nothing. The
relationship between the performer and nature is neither dominating nor submissive; a lot
of Fluxus art is about noticing and appreciating a natural occurrence in an active way. A
piece like drip music is more than mere spectatorship, Brecht has created a situation
where the natural action of dripping reveals itself as a significant and noteworthy
48
Tokenise Kosygin circa1964, in David T Doris, ‘Zen Vaudeville’, in Ken Friedman ed,
The Fluxus Reader, p.110
49
George Brecht, Drip Music 1959, Repr. In Ken Fiedman ed, The Fluxus Performance
Workbook, special edn. of El Djarida magazine (Trondheim, Norway: Guttorm Nordo,
1990), p.13, in Douglas Kahn, ‘The Latest:Fluxus and Music’, in Elizabeth Armstrong
and Joan Rothfuss, In the Spirit of Fluxus, p. 110
22
occurrence. Brecht is not making a dominating gesture, like work, or one that is prompted
by physical necessity, like labour. The symbiotic relationship with nature, where artist
and the subject of art stand on equal terms, distinguishes ‘play’ as an action separate from
work and labour.
The Fluxus artists referred to the revelation of a thing through a process as ‘exemplative
work’; a term attributed by Dick Higgins. In exemplatitive work, the idea or concept
behind an action only becomes fully clear once the action has been set in motion or
performed. Ken Friedman mentions that not all Fluxus artwork is exemplativist but ‘those
pieces which are exemplative are in some way closer to the ideal than those which are
not.’50 Exemplativism is an excellent illustration of the Fluxus attitude toward performing
for its own sake. Exemplative work is a means without ends, or at the very least, a means
where the ends are not fixed. This theory is embodied in improvised music, which played
a large role in the work of Nam June Paik. In 1978 Paik, alongside sometimes Fluxus
associate Joseph Beuys, performed ‘In memoriam of George Macuinas’51. The piece
consists of 74 minutes of improvised music performed on two pianos with two vocals.
Although a piano based improvisation would appear to be a very conventional framework
for a Fluxus performance, it touches on many attributes that characterise Fluxus work. A
good improvisation is an action without a predisposed idea of the outcome, the
framework is in place in the form of the instruments or objects to be used but the
direction the performance may take is open at all times. The directions taken by ‘In
memoriam of George Macuinas’ are a result of Paik and Beuys playing off each other
and reacting to the both their own, and the other’s actions. There are sections of atonal
mess and intense quiet but the piece remains a constant reaction between the two artists
to the situation they are simultaneously creating and watching unfold in front of them. In
this sense the improvisation is the pinnacle of what we may define as ‘play’. It is an
action without intentionality or preconceived utility. Whether the music will be soothing,
sad, upbeat, confrontational and so on, is only revealed in the actual playing; its function
is a result of it’s undertaking.
Furthermore Paik and Beuys’ performance is an instance of the Fluxus artist’s attempt to
heighten perception. Due to the length and relentlessness of the playing, ‘In memoriam of
George Macuinas’ creates a state of immersion for its audience to enter. The music
performed by Paik and Beuys is constant in its form, in that there are no breaks, but is
also constantly changing and non-repetitive. The effect on the viewer is that of a slow
losing of self. At the same time as being incredibly focused on the actual movements of
the player’s hands and voice, as an audience member one becomes more aware of the
surroundings and environment; the concentration required to keep focused on the
performance begins to dissolve the boundaries between what is and what is not the work.
The result of this immersion is that we begin to look at the event in its entirety in a new
way; Paik and Beuy’s ‘playing’ is the instigator for a revolution in perception. Therefore,
the revolutionary potential of play lays in its ability to make us appreciate new, unseen
50
Ken Friedman, The Fluxus Reader, p.250
I was fortunate enough to see a video documentation of this performance entitled ‘In
memoriam of George Macuinas’ as part of a Nam June Paik installation in Musee d’art
moderne et contemporain de Strasbourg on 15 December 2004.
51
23
qualities in each moment experienced in everyday life. Cage recognised this
revolutionary quality in music and performance,
‘As a vehicle of signification, this approach could ‘open the minds of the people who
make them or listened to them to other possibilities than they had previously
considered… To widen their experience; particularly to undermine the making of valuejudgements.’52
In many cases Fluxus events literally involved their entire surroundings and environment.
Like Allan Kaprow’s ‘happenings’ of the early 60’s in America, Fluxus artists sought to
transform an entire area of social exchange. The Fluxus festival that toured Europe in the
60’s took over entire towns, in part due to the sensational press response to their avantgarde performances. In 1996 Roskilde played host to a Fluxus festival thirty years after
its first. Eric Andersen’s description of events highlights the ambitious nature of the
festival and the effect it would have on every aspect of the town and people that visited it,
‘Of main importance was to occupy the town… the performances became the traffic.
They moved in different directions through the streets and lanes. Made stops on squares,
in churches, convents, shops and parks. They met, crossed each other to part again.
Mountain climbers scrambled up buildings and towers while the audience dragged
themselves up the hill in 200 wheelchairs. Men were handcuffed by WPC’s and nurses
took blood samples. A lamb was slaughtered every hour. Flocks of sheep were herded by
resolute dogs. A baby was born. The audience walked past spaces of sound as
guardsmen, bagpipes, building machinery, traffic accidents and the emergency services
conducted complicated scores with fire and water. Around midnight 40 parachutists
jumped with blinking blue lights attached to their helmets resembling falling stars. The
effect was that of the sky itself falling down over Roskilde.’53
The artists involved in the organisation of this festival managed to create a temporary
situation where every action or happening was performed in the spirit of play. All the
events throughout the festival were carried out, not for a utilitarian end, but to be
incredible things in their own right. For the festival period, the people involved were
living an alternative existence, as if existing in a giant playground. It is at this point we
are able to introduce the writings of the Situationist International. To put the festival at
Roskilde into a revolutionary context we can refer to the early Situationist manifestos,
‘Our central idea is that of the construction of situations, that is to say, the concrete
construction of momentary ambiances of life and their transformation into a superior
passional quality.’54
52
John Cage in, The Fluxus Reader, p.96
Eric Andersen, (n.d)‘What is ….?’, performance-festival-odense.dk[online], available:
http://performance-festival-odense.dk/pfo01/whatis.html, [accessed 16 April 2005]. See
Appendix 1.
54
Guy Debord, op.cit, p.22
53
24
It is easily imaginable that for the three days that the festival ran, every moment would
have consisted of a ‘superior passional quality’, every action took on a new significance
and every object perceived in a new light. However, the Situationists failed to outline or
exemplify the qualities of a constructed situation that would be necessary for a revolution
of everyday life. The primary function of the created situation would be to destroy the
spectacle by forcing individuals in that situation to have an active role55. There may be
some discrepancy between what the Situationists perceived to be an ideal situation and
the type of environment created by Fluxus artists at their festivals. Although Roskilde
became an all-encompassing situation it, like most Fluxus performance, still maintained a
divide between audience and performer.
‘The role played by a passive or merely bit-playing ‘public’ must constantly diminish,
while that played by those who cannot be called actors, but rather in a new sense of the
term, ‘livers’, must steadily increase.’56
The audience of a Fluxus concert or event may become a participant in the work but they
are never playing at the same level as the creator of the situation: the artist is the creator
of the framework that the audience is then invited to operate within. The revolutionary
quality of the Fluxus concert may lie in the lasting effects it has on its spectators once
returning to everyday life. If the audience is willing to transfer the level of perception
achieved at the festival to the working day then it transforms those mundane, normal
situations into a more fulfilling experience altogether.
Similarly, the spectator at a Fluxus concert or event may be inspired to create their own
version of Fluxus work in new surroundings, outlined by them. Pieces like George
Brecht’s ‘Three telephone events57’ and Alison Knowles ‘Proposition58’ are examples of
Fluxus work that can be reinterpreted and performed by anyone in their daily living. They
open up the possibility of becoming the artist to the audience through the simplicity of
the action required to perform the work; Brecht’s telephone events covers every
eventuality when a telephone rings and Knowles’ proposition is simply ‘make a salad’.
This brings us one step closer to the Situationist ideal where everyone becomes an artist;
a crucial strategy in the abolition of Arendt’s ‘society of labourers’.
However, the Fluxus embracement of play and performance is not without its problems,
one being that, in many cases its action leaves no physical trace or document. The actual
performance of Fluxus work is primarily unproductive. It is not an action that is
concerned with making anything durable to serve as a utility object or immortalise its
creator. Fluxus may improve the quality of everyday life by stripping actions of the utility
that masks their natural ‘goodness’, but in doing so it is unable to produce anything that
sustains that life. Macuinas was practically the only figure in Fluxus who tackled this
55
refer to Guy Debord, ‘Toward a Situationist International’ in, ‘Situationist
International Anthology’, (Bureau of Public Secrets 1981), pp.22-25
56
Guy Debord, op.cit, p.25
57
repr. in David T Doris, ‘Zen Vaudeville’ in, The Fluxus Reader, p.97
58
first performed on 21 October 1962 at the Institute for Contemporary Arts in London,
repr. in David T Doris, ‘Zen Vaudeville’ in, The Fluxus Reader, p.107
25
problem and this is one of the reasons he has become its most identifiable personality.
For Macuinas, Fluxus was always designed to take the form of objects,
‘GM: Meanwhile we thought, well, we’ll do concerts, that’s easier than publishing… the
idea was to do concerts as a promotional trick for selling whatever we were going to
publish or produce.’59
These realised themselves as the two Fluxus yearboxes (themselves a collection of
objects and written matter) and also the written documentation of Fluxus performance,
which took the form of instruction cards, such as George Brecht’s Water Yam box set.
Furthermore, Macuinas was responsible for the creation of various other artefacts ranging
from mail order multiples to the collective housing for artists that eventually became the
SoHo area. It could be suggested that, employing Arendt’s definition, Macuinas was the
only true ‘worker’ within the Fluxus movement. Not only did he collect and distribute the
objects created by Fluxus artists, in many instances he realised the artists ideas as objects
and films on their behalf. The question that arises when applying this definition of work
and non-work to performance is whether or not the documentation of the performance (be
it in text or recorded form) is altogether separate ‘work’ than the performance of that
piece. To clarify this idea I would like to use one of Brecht’s Water Yam events as an
example,
Turn on a radio
At the first sound, turn it off.60
Do the qualities of this event as a written instruction have any relation to the actual action
of performing the piece? Personally, I have never attempted to perform this event, nor
have I seen or heard it being performed, so, for me, Brecht’s ‘work’ remains merely as a
small offset printed card that I saw exhibited in Straousburg. Arendt addresses this
problematic relation between work and cognition, in ‘The Human Condition’,
‘..reification and materialisation, without which no thought can become a tangible thing,
is always paid for, and that the price is life itself: it is always the “dead letter” in which
the “living spirit” must survive, a deadness from which it can be rescued only when the
dead letter comes again into contact with a life willing to resurrect it, although this
resurrection of the dead shares with all living things that it, too, will die again.’61
The ramification for play is that without any form of work, play will fade from existence.
Documenting Fluxus performance as written scores provides the opportunity for that
action to be performed an infinite number of times, and that it will survive in the same
way as an object produced by homo-faber would. Additionally, it means that such an
59
George Macuinas in, The Fluxus Reader, p.187
This was an art work that I saw first hand exhibited alongside the Nam June Paik
installation at Musee d’art moderne et contemporain de Strasbourg on 15 December
2004. refer to note 45 for publishing details.
61
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.169
60
26
action is free to be reinterpreted by an infinite amount or performers and therefore take
on new forms and meanings throughout time. This keeps the action of playing relevant to
the context in which it is performed; instead of becoming a dusty document of a passed
society the Fluxus game can be played in any new environment. In doing so, it heightens
the perception of its performer and audience to that new situation. In the final section of
this essay I would like to develop this relation between work and play, discussing the
possibilities of ‘productive play’ and the role this would have in the revolution of
everyday life.
PART 4 GOOD WORK AND PRODUCTIVE PLAY
To begin the concluding section I would like to begin with a summary of the negative
qualities of work and labour that have arisen from the investigation of their role in the
revolution of everyday life. The main problem with work is that it is an action solely
concerned with its produce and as such is only judged on its results. To have worked hard
is the equivalent of having created a great object or a great number of things. This is the
only way in which the action of work can reify itself in the world. The nature of work is
quantitative rather than qualitative meaning that the most productive society or, more
rightly, the hardest working society will unavoidably have the most number of objects to
prove it. It is here that the destructive and restrictive effects of work manifest themselves.
Firstly, work constantly destroys the natural world and burns up resources because it is a
process of transformation. In order to create lasting, durable objects that withstand nature,
the source material must be changed irreversibly. For example, stacking wooden blocks
to form a tower is indeed the work of homo-faber and is not a destructive action.
However, to ensure the durability of that tower the blocks must be joined together to form
a new permanent object. Without the durability of its produce work becomes labour, so
work always consumes the elements it utilises, otherwise it is not work.
Furthermore, the creation of objects becomes a conditioning force. The multitude of
things that we, as homo-faber are driven to produce, collectively form an artificial
environment to which we must adjust. Every object created and machine invented adds to
the human artifice and, although it is the result of man’s escape from the conditions of
nature, it is also responsible for the new rules and daily struggle man lives under. A
simple example of this is the envious nostalgia felt for the hunter-gatherer’s significantly
shorter working day, when commencing an eight hour day sat in front of a computer.
Work’s most despicable characteristic though, is its ability to transform a world of
objects and actions in to a series of means. In work nothing is evaluated on its own
merits; everything must be utilised for the fabrication and realisation of an end product,
which in turn will also be used to serve another purpose. Work’s utilitarianism prevents it
from becoming an action in itself, it exists only as a series of objects. Work’s success is
measured on what it leaves behind, not what it is, and in the present day’s climate of
insatiable consumerism, it leaves behind less and less.
27
Of course, in Arendt’s terms, work without lasting produce is labour; an eternal battle
with nature to keep bread on the table. Labour has a submissive relationship to nature,
every action defined as labouring is a reaction to the necessities of living under our
conditions. However, now that we exist in the human artifice, our conditions have
become man-made so the labourer is submissive to both nature and himself. This is a
sorry situation. At least in the natural world the resources consumed in labour (wheat for
making bread, fields for agriculture) were eventually fed back into natural world, creating
a cycle. In the human artifice the consumed object, now useless, is buried underground or
burned.
Paradoxically, it is the cyclical nature of labouring that makes it essential to the human
condition. Arendt explains that without life’s imperfections and restrictions there would
be no room for fulfilment in everyday life,
‘Man cannot be free if he does not know that he is subject to necessity, because his
freedom is always won over in his never wholly successful attempts to liberate himself
from necessity.’62
Labour is an infinite number of struggles between man and his conditions that occur in
such quick and constant succession that they take on the character of everyday life. The
labouring individual may be caught in a thousand battles a day but mere survival of the
day is testament to a thousand victories. Labour is not an attempt to dominate nature
permanently, like work, but a continuous call and response much like games and play.
Similarly, there are areas of work that are play-like and also areas of work that satisfy the
needs of man left unfulfilled by labour and play. As exemplified by Macuinas’ role in
Fluxus, without any form of work there is no opportunity for a document of playing to
survive, and be relived by another participant. Work, rightly or wrongly, seeks to
immortalise man’s action but this need not be an immortalisation of man’s work.
Through the ‘dead letter’, written scores, language and instructions work is able to
transcribe play and ensure its survival. Work may also immortalise play in a more
accurate way than the passing down of folk-stories through generations.
Sadly, herein lay work’s revolutionary limitations. Although it may serve to solidify the
result of a process, as an action work is too concerned with utility to be considered a
‘real’, ideal state of living. There is no contentment in work because it always looks
beyond itself. Play, on the other hand, can be defined as a heightened perception of the
now. As demonstrated by Fluxus performance, a playful rather than work-like art results
in an audience paying fresh attention to stale actions and objects. Play instils
revolutionary qualities into everything it comes into contact with. If work is the (futile)
search for the immortalising object then play is the revelation of the eternal moment. Play
produces little in comparison to work but in some sense doesn’t need to produce any
more. Whilst work only perceives the use potential of the thing it is creating or working
with directly, play opens up perception of potential use in all existing things.
62
ibid, p.121
28
In spite of this, it is difficult to deny the inherent passivity of this kind of play when
compared to the continuous activity of work and labour. Many of the benefits of play are
accidental and therefore, never guaranteed to be felt. Nevertheless the Situationists saw
the revolution of everyday life as only possible through the expansion and development
of these playful, eternalising moments,
‘Due to its marginal existence in relation to the oppressive reality of work, play is often
regarded as fictitious. But the work of the situationists is precisely the preparation of
ludic possibilities to come. One can thus attempt to neglect the S.I to the degree that one
easily recognises a few aspects of a great game. ‘Nevertheless’ says Huizinger ‘as we
have already pointed out, the consciousness of play being ‘only a pretend’ does not in any
way prevent it from proceeding with the utmost seriousness.’63
The role of play in a revolution in Situationist terms is very active. As well as
revolutionising everyday life through the heightening of perception, the Situationists
believe that play can actually create new conditions for man. It is in this area that the
notion of ‘productive play’ must be realised. In a utopian society nobody works – both in
the sense that there is no forced labour or jobs, and also in the terms of homo-faber’s
fabrication of the human artifice. An ideal society for the Situationists does not differ too
greatly from ancient Greece, therefore what we are left with, assuming slavery is not an
option in the revolution of everyday life, is a dilemma regarding essential work and how
it is completed. Post-Situationist writer Bob Black addresses this dilemma in his essay
‘The Abolition of Work’. No doubt, influenced by Raoul Vaneigem’s description in ‘the
Revolution of Everyday Life’ of a nail smiths competition64, Black presents a theory of
injecting play into work and simultaneously exploiting play’s productive potential,
‘The secret of turning work into play, as Charles Fourier demonstrated, is to arrange
useful activities to take advantage of whatever it is that at various times we enjoy
doing…
Activities that appeal to some people don’t always appeal to others, but everyone at least
potentially has a variety of interests and an interest in variety… Small children who
notoriously relish wallowing in filth could be organized in ‘little hordes’ to clean toilets
and empty the garbage, with medals awarded to the outstanding’65
Of course, Bob Black’s vision is almost dreamlike in its utopianism and would require a
near impossible upheaval of social and political systems, certainly if it were to happen in
63
S.I, Contribution to a Situationist Definition of Play, Internationale Situationniste #1
(June 1958) [online], available:http://www.cddc.vt.edu/sionline/si/play.html, [accessed
16 April 2005]
64
refer to Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, p.54
65
Bob Black, ‘The Abolition of Work’ in, The Abolition of Work and Other
Essays[online], (Loompanics Unlimited 1985), available:
http://www.zpub.com/notes/black.html, [accessed 16 April 2005], p.9
29
our lifetime. However, it does raise a crucial issue in the possibility of productive play,
that being the ability to take advantage of individual skill. The concept of innate talent or
god-given skill, like genius, obviously does not sit well with any of the writing in this
essay and it is not my intention to rely on them now. However, it cannot be denied that
the skills that many do not posses are present and honed in others through that
individual’s practice. The most obvious examples would be the ability to master a sport
or play a musical instrument.
It is debatable whether the objective to improve one’s skill turns an action that would
otherwise be defined as play into a utilitarian activity, and it can be reduced to a question
of intent. Whether a musical instrument is played so the performer improves playing or if
it is simply played for the enjoyment of playing is both the responsibility of the performer
and is reliant on social conditions. Still, an area where this action is more playful is
improvisation as demonstrated by Paik and Beuy’s piano performance. Improvisation
removes the repeatable nature of practicing or attempting to master a certain
performance. Every action is performed solely to experience its immediate result rather
than to improve on a past performance of that action. Improvisation, like play, is only
concerned with moments, and as such provides an opportunity to experience the eternal.
Furthermore, it has the potential for accidental productivity, which means it fulfils work’s
primary function without its restricting and destructive effects. By returning once more to
concretism the productive potential of play can be identified,
‘George Brecht, two years before the publication of Watts’ essay, appraised the role of
dance in the work of Jackson Pollock, noting that the most remarkable aspects of
Pollock’s work happened beyond the artist’s ability, conscious or unconscious as it may
be, , to assert total control over his materials. Unconscious production, or better,
‘improvisation’, is still a form of control, a framing, a function of the interiorisation and
mastery of a set of learned skills and familiar materials. For the experienced artist such as
Pollock, or Watts’ master photographer, skills have been internalised to the point where
production becomes naturalised, becomes ‘second nature’, as it were; as such, the works
produced by the artist occur with the apparent effortlessness and certainty of natural
force. Ian a sense, this is indeed the ‘Zen’ of the arts.’66
This ‘mindless’ production should be the ultimate, final stage in the revolution of
everyday life, for its very existence demonstrates that we are able to produce objects
without intent and also, therefore, the potential means for survival. In each stage of
labour, work and play there is a condition or impetus for man to change his behaviour;
the animal-laborans is unhappy with the alienating futility of labour so creates objects
and, in turn, the human artifice. The working homo-faber discovers that not only is the
human artifice equally as alienating as the natural world but that, additionally, everything
that exists within it is reduced to a series of unfulfilling means. These are the conditions
of present day society from which we can look beyond to a utopian society of ‘players’
envisioned by the Situationists and the Fluxus group.
66
David T Doris, The Fluxus Reader, p.117
30
Sadly, this utopian society remains beyond reach due in part because it appears to lack
the capacity for productivity that the modern world functions upon. However, with
enough playing and practice of playing, the necessary skills to advance from animallaborans can be internalised and the little human artifice actually necessary to survival,
created by accident. Like the accidental but essential productivity of the hippy ideal of
free love, man is able to live a fulfilling and engaging, playful existence whilst
simultaneously ensuring his and other’s survival.
However, within this final stage of man as a productive player it is possible to predict his
downfall. When all production is dependant on non-intentional actions there must be an
indiscriminate acceptance of everything that is produced. In the same way animallaborans accepts the conditions of nature and homo-faber must accept his own
intentionally created conditions (as exemplified by the Soviet revolution) the man who
lives his life as an eternal game must accept the ‘natural’ conditions of that game and live
without want of change, like animal-laborans. The revolution of everyday life lays
within the acceptance of those conditions produced by play, and that these conditions do
not suffocate or dominate the ‘livers’ but demand a cyclical relationship, similar to that
the Buddhists share with nature.
Of course, this is based on the presumption that man will lead a happier life once
unburdened of domination and suffering . This in itself is questionable, Arendt explains
that part of the human condition is a predisposition towards toil; everyone loves to
complain about work.
‘On its most elementary level the ‘toil and trouble’ of obtaining and the pleasures of
‘incorporating’ the necessities of life are so closely bound together in the biological life
cycle, whose recurrent rhythm conditions human life in its unique and uni-linear
movement, that the perfect elimination of the pain and effort of labour would not only rob
biological life of its most natural pleasures but deprive the specifically human life of its
very liveliness and vitality. The human condition is such that pain and effort are not just
symptoms which can be removed without changing life itself; they are rather the modes
in which life itself, together with the necessity to which it is bound, make itself felt. For
mortals, the easy life of the gods’ would be a lifeless life.’67
67
Arendt, The Human Condition, p.120
31
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arendt, Hannah, The Human Condition, (University of Chicago Press, 1958)
Armstrong and Rothfuss, In The Spirit Of Fluxus, (Walker Art Centre, 1993)
Barker, Emma (ed.), Contemporary Cultures of Display, (Yale University Press 1999)
Bey, Hakim, T.A.Z. The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchy, Poetic
Terrorism, (Autonomedia, 1991)
Clark, T.J, The Painting of Modern Life, (Thomas and Hudson 1984)
Cullerne Bown, Matthew, Art Under Stalin, (Phaidon Press 1991)
Cullerne Bown, Matthew and Taylor, Brandon, Art of the Soviets, (Manchester
University Press 1993)
Cullerne Bown, Matthew, Elliott, David and Siborov, Aleksandr, Soviet Socialist
Realist Painting 1930’s-1960’s, (Exhibition Catalogue, 1992)
Debord, Guy, Society of the Spectacle, third edition, (Zone Books New York, 1994)
Foster, Hal (ed.), Postmodern Culture, (Pluto Press 1983)
Foster, Hal (ed.), Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics, (Bay Press 1993)
Friedman, Ken ed, The Fluxus Reader, (Academy Editions, 1998)
Golomstock, Igor, Totalitarian Art, (Collins Harvill 1990)
Gopnick, Adam and Varnedoe, Kirk, High and Low: Modern Art and Popular Culture,
(Museum of Modern Art 1991)
Groys, Boris, The Total Art of Stalinism, (Princeton University Press 1992)
Harrison, Charles and Wood, Paul (eds.), Art in Theory 1900-1990, (Blackwell 1992)
James, C.Vaughan, Soviet Socialist Realism, (Macmillan Press 1973)
Kapprow, Allan, (ed Jeff Kellry), Essays On The Blurring Of Art And Life, (University
of California Press, 2003)
32
Knabb, Kenn ed, Situationist International Anthology, (Bureau of Public Secrets, 1981)
Lodder, Christina, Russian Constructivism, (Yale University Press, 1983)
Mainz, Valerie and Pollock, Griselda ed, Work And The Image 1 Work, Craft And
Labour, Visual Representations In Changing Histories, (Ashgate, 2000)
Prokhorov, Gleb, Art Under Socialist Realism, (Craftsman House 1995)
Rowell, Margit and Rudenstine, Angelica Zander, Art Of The Avant-Garde In Russia:
Selection From The George Costakis Collection, (The Solomon R Guggenheim
Foundation, 1981)
Simerenko, Alex (ed), Soviet Sociology, (Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967)
Taylor, Brandon, Art and Literature Under the Bolsheviks Volume 2, (Pluto Press 1992)
Vaneigem, Raoul, The Revolution Of Everyday Life, (Rebel Press/Left Bank Books
1994)
Williams, Robert C, Artists In Revolution Portraits Of The Russian Avant-Garde, 1905 –
1925, (The Scolar Press, 1978)
PERIODICALS
Art and Design Magazine, Art And Design Profile, No 28, 1993
October Magazine, No.79, Winter 1997
ONLINE SOURCES
3am Magazine, http://www.3ammagazine.com/artarchives/2003/aug/situ.html
Aspen magazine, http://www.ubu.com/aspen/intro/html
Not Bored magazine, http://www.notbored.org
Nothingness Situationist Library, http://library.nothingness.org
Performance-festival-odense, http://performance-festival-odense.dk
Situationist Online, http://www.cddc.vt.edu/sionline
33