Contemporary Pragmatism
Vol. 8, No. 2 (December 2011), 205–212
Editions Rodopi
© 2011
Feeling Beyond the Text: Reflections on
The Rorty Reader
Richard Shusterman
Examining key themes presented in the excellent Rorty Reader, this essay
also argues that Rorty’s philosophical import extends beyond the propositional content of his texts. After indicating how Rorty’s central philosophical stance of anti-representationalism is expressed in his aestheticist
advocacy of a pluralist literary culture and his theory that ethics and moral
progress can be properly based only on sentiments rather than rationality,
the paper explains why his philosophy should have therefore embraced the
role of embodied experience rather than rejecting it.
1.
On the centenary of Ralph Waldo Emerson’s birth, William James said,
The pathos of death is this, that when the days of one’s life are ended,
those days that were so crowded with business and felt so heavy in their
passing, what remains of one in memory should usually be so slight a
thing. The phantom of an attitude, the echo of a certain mode of
thought, a few pages of print, some invention, or some victory we
gained in a brief critical hour, are all that can survive the best of us. It is
as if the whole of a man’s significance had now shrunk into the
phantom of an attitude, into a mere musical note or phrase suggestive
of his singularity – happy are those whose singularity gives a note so
clear as to be victorious over the inevitable pity of such a diminution
and abridgement.1
In composing my remarks on this Rorty Reader2 as we pass the fourth
anniversary of his death, I could start by asking whether Richard Rorty is happy
by this Jamesian criterion – a paradoxical one that posits happiness as a
posthumous affair. I think he surely should be, as this excellent reader makes
powerfully clear. It is an abundantly rich reader that goes far beyond “a few
pages in print,” running indeed to more than 575 pages. In the wide-ranging
texts that Christopher Voparil and Richard Bernstein have judiciously selected
206
RICHARD SHUSTERMAN
and astutely arranged, many memorable notes are sounded in Rorty’s elegant
prose, whose distinctive style is smooth but not facile, sophisticated but never
stuffy, sometimes engagingly colloquial but never crude, often potently critical
but rarely cruel. Although Rorty never really wrote about music (his artistic
interests appear to be very one-sidedly literary), he certainly was graced with a
talent for textual rhythms and verbal melodies that made reading him a pleasure
even when one found his ideas maddeningly provocative.
Besides his literary skill, another reason why Rorty may be the most
widely discussed American philosopher of the last two decades is the diversity
of important fields and topics about which he had something interesting to say.
Not only did he formulate incisive positions in most of the dominant
philosophical subdisciplines (philosophy of mind and language, epistemology
and hermeneutics, ethics, metaphysics, aesthetics, and philosophy of science and
history), but he also expressed distinctive views on many culturally important
issues in fields beyond philosophy, including literature, feminism, law, politics,
and religion. By redirecting philosophy’s mission and energies away from mere
technical expertise in dealing with narrow academic problems but instead
toward the criticism of contemporary culture that would help individuals
reorient and enrich their efforts in the conduct of life, Rorty rendered philosophy
not merely relevant but even exciting to a wide swath of intellectuals throughout
the arts and human sciences.
Moreover, by reminding us that this exhilarating way of practicing
philosophy as cultural critique and means of edifying self-creation is not simply
a trendy new gospel of European thought but the key philosophical message of
the pragmatist tradition of William James and John Dewey, Rorty revived
pragmatism and gave it a stirringly radical edge, bringing it out of the shadow of
analytic philosophy and erasing its then-current image as old-fashioned,
provincially homey, and dull. Rorty put the American philosophical tradition
onto center stage in the international philosophical scene, bringing its classical
pragmatist thinkers into stimulating dialogue with the twentieth-century masters
of analytic and continental philosophy and presenting those classic American
thinkers as every bit as rewarding and relevant for today’s cultural challenges,
and often even more useful for carrying us forward. At a time (after 1989 and
before 9/11) when America had established itself as an unrivalled, apparently
invincible superpower, Rorty provided a pragmatist philosophy that, while
critical of certain ills in American life, remained resolutely patriotic and internationally influential, a philosophy fitting for the leader of the liberal free world.
For such reasons, every American pragmatist philosopher today owes a
significant debt to Rorty. My debt to him is also more personal and profound.
He was the person who first stimulated my interest in American philosophy and
converted me to pragmatism. Rorty was one of the three master thinkers who
made my career possible, not only by providing inspiring examples of creative
new theorizing but also by personal encouragement and supportive guidance. I
want to record that debt here in reviewing this collection of his work because, in
Reflections on The Rorty Reader
207
the past, I have so often made his views a target of severe criticism.3 I first
established my own distinctive views largely through criticism of Rorty’s and
those of my other two exemplary mentors, Arthur Danto and Pierre Bourdieu.
But Rorty’s influence was the first and indeed facilitated the others.
Though my official task here is reviewing a collection of Rortian texts, I
want to insist that what we can learn from Rorty goes well beyond the textual.
He was a model of philosophical generosity, curiosity, grace, and democratic
openness that expressed itself beyond the written word, in robust real-life
actions. Rorty regularly reached out to philosophers in the margins. I was a
young assistant professor in the Israeli desert when I first met him, and I was
surprised that he gave me so much time and attention, inviting me to contribute
to a special journal issue he was editing on literary theory and encouraging me
to move to America to develop my interest in pragmatism. I later learned that he
regularly gave generous support to young philosophers from Eastern Europe and
South America who wanted to study with him at the University of Virginia. At
conferences, he showed remarkable courtesy, kindness, and patience. I
remember one ten-day conference I attended with him in France. Though other
principal speakers left after the first few days of keynote talks, Rorty stayed to
the end, sitting bravely through even the most tedious and incomprehensible of
the French papers, even though he sometimes dozed off during them.
When Rorty defends the idea of “ethics without principles” (RR 415–
422) people often presume a dubious moral personality. Rorty’s behavior made
clear that by having true generosity of heart and a penetrating sensibility in
understanding people, their needs, and situations, one does not need principles to
be magnificently ethical. Moral principles are crutches for those who lack that
empathetic sensibility, imaginative discernment, and gracious sentiment. I return
to these themes later in this review.
2.
Rorty produced an overwhelming amount of papers on a dizzying variety of
themes. The editors have done an excellent job in selecting texts that represent
Rorty’s best and most influential work, while giving a sense of the whole
trajectory of his career. The first of the Reader’s six parts begin with two essays
that pre-date Rorty’s first masterpiece, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (in
which formulates his radical immanent critique of analytic philosophy and his
turn to what he calls edifying or conversational philosophy) and also includes
some selections from that book and two other seminal essays that explain his
turn from analysis to pragmatism and textualism. The second group of essays
shows his continuing critical dialogue with analytic philosophy, including his
engagement with figures like Davidson and Putnam. The sixth part is devoted to
autobiographical essays and interviews, including a brief but potent text on
poetry that he wrote knowing he would soon die from untreatable pancreatic
cancer.
208
RICHARD SHUSTERMAN
The three core parts of the book are dedicated to themes relating to
pragmatism and political theory: liberalism, democracy, and cultural politics,
human rights, feminism, patriotism, and religion. But they also contain essays
that deal centrally with ethics and aesthetics (especially with literature of the
novel) and with core issues of objectivity and truth, reason and feeling. If editors
Bernstein and Voparil are keen to highlight the political dimension of Rorty’s
thought as what has been most influential of visible to the broadest academic
public, they also recognize that this dimension is integrally woven into his advocacy of an aesthetic turn or literary culture, where sentiment and imagination
supersede reason as the means to moral progress and personal redemption.
Though my main interest in Rorty is not his political thought, I find the editors’
selection extremely astute and helpful. This is clearly an excellent book to use
for teaching a seminar on Rorty. The only text I wish they had included is an
essay “Texts and Lumps,” a gem of an essay in which Rorty’s demonstrates his
virtuosity in connecting literary theory with philosophy of language and
philosophy of science to provide an ingenious solution to common issues of
reference, meaning, and identity.
Rorty claims he has “really only one idea: the need to get beyond
representationalism” (RR 464). Rorty’s anti-representationalism rejects the
notion of “knowledge as the assemblage of accurate representations” of reality
and the idea of philosophy as “a general theory of representation” which
“divides culture up” and sometimes arbitrates between the different fields that
represent reality more or less accurately and in different ways (RR 21). But
Rorty in fact offers many more ideas, even if they are not originally his own,
just as anti-representationalism is an idea he adopted from Dewey, Wittgenstein,
and others. We can note, for example, his idea that philosophical
representationalism should be replaced with an aesthetic culture where logical
justifications by argument are replaced by convincingly attractive rhetoric; his
idea that poetry or literature be substituted for religion and philosophical truth as
sources of personal redemption (together with the view that we have already
reached this “literary culture”); the division of the public and the private realms
and the confinement of redemptive matters to the latter; the idea of ethics as
based on sentiment rather truth, and the utopian goal as moral progress toward
broader sentiments so that we reach “a global civilization in which love is pretty
much the only law” (RR 52).
These ideas can, of course, be related to his anti-representationalism. For
example, Rorty’s anti-representationalism can explain how, on the one hand, he
can utterly repudiate the whole field of aesthetics as “another of Kant’s bad
ideas”4 yet also affirm a strong “aesthetic strain” (RR 463) in his own writing.
His point seems to be that although there is no fixed reality of art or beauty in
themselves for which the distinctive field of aesthetics provides theories that
accurately represent such reality, there is a dimension of life and culture that is
very important and that is called “aesthetic,” though only for various historical
reasons and not because it names an essence whose reality aesthetic theories are
Reflections on The Rorty Reader
209
designed to represent. (If Rorty says very little about Dewey’s aesthetics, then
this may be because he felt it too close in some ways to a representationalist
theory of art as experienced.) It is likewise easy to see how the rejection of
representationalism encourages an ethics based more on sentiment, poetry,
rhetoric, and results than on strictly logical justification and correspondence to
truth.
3.
As Voparil notes in his superb, comprehensive introduction, Rorty’s oeuvre
engages a wide variety of areas in the human sciences and in literature (saying
little about music and visual arts). This breadth befits the pervasive pragmatist
pluralism he inherited from James and Dewey. But there are two areas he
pointedly rejects, and I will close this essay by using texts from the Rorty reader
to question this rejection.
In elevating literature over traditional philosophy, science, or religion as
the source of personal redemption, in advocating the strong poet as an ideal
figure who makes things new and creates himself, Rorty follows Harold Bloom.
I find nothing objectionable in this appreciation of literature. The idea that
poetry (or more generally art) is becoming a substitute for philosophy and
religion is a familiar one that goes back Matthew Arnold and continues into turn
of the century aestheticism. Since Rorty allows a plurality of ideals, since there
is, for him, no one single “really real” ideal that philosophy must represent so
that all individuals must logically embrace it, what could be wrong with
advocating literature, especially since part of Rorty’s affirming literary culture
as eclipsing religious and scientific culture is that its pluralistic openness of
genres means that all genres can be legitimate and “there will be no dominant
form” (RR 476)? What I find objectionable is his joining Harold Bloom in
rejecting the social sciences as merely “dismal” genres.5 This rejection is
inconsistent with Rorty’s pluralism and simply unfair to the wealth of insight
(and even some strong poetry) in the work of some social science (think of
Weber, Simmel, Mauss, and Bourdieu). Moreover, when Rorty criticizes philosophers who do political theory by seeking “theoretical arguments for political
stances,” he argues that “such stances can be justified only by pointing to the
results of actual or imagined social experiments” (RR 464). But what, if not
social science, could provide such results of actual experiments and other
relevant data for determining our positions and strategies toward political
progress?
The nondiscursive and somatic constitute a second area that Rorty
pointedly rejects as unworthy of philosophical consideration but that the logic of
his own arguments should compel him to embrace. His insistence on confining
attention only to the realm of language is expressed in his rejection of the
concept of experience, which constitutes perhaps his principal departure from
the pragmatism of James and Dewey who affirmed the importance of embodied
210
RICHARD SHUSTERMAN
nondiscursive experience in our thought and action, while also insisting on the
centrality of language. In taking the linguistic turn, analytic philosophy sought
to focus all its attention on the greater clarity and precision of language and
logic and abandon the vagueness of experience. Logic and language were linked
with rationality in contrast to the fuzzy subjectivity of emotions. Though Rorty
has come to reject the idea that logic and rational justificatory arguments define
the limits of philosophical and moral thinking, he continues to hold that
language does, insisting on “the linguistic character of rationality” (RR 421) and
even that “all awareness is a linguistic affair.”6 Hence the nondiscursive and
somatic find no place in his thinking, and he has been sharply critical of my
attempt to reintroduce these elements in the pragmatist project of somaesthetics.
But if we consider his increasing emphasis on the sentiments as the key to
ethical positions and moral progress, then we see how important nondiscursive
somatic experience should be for his thought.
Rorty argues that our commitment to human rights and other central
moral principles cannot be effectively justified by appeals to universal rationality. Instead, they depend on shared sentiments about how people should be
treated. Cultures who do not share our moral beliefs are perfectly able to
perform all sorts of difficult rational tasks; so, Rorty argues, their immoral
treatment of certain populations (such as ethnic minorities, women, or children)
is thus not the product of irrationality but rather the result of their not feeling
that the creatures they oppress are fully human. What makes us more moral than
other animals, Rorty claims, is that “We can feel for each other to a much
greater extent than they can,” and we ourselves progress in morality the more we
can feel for more kinds of people (RR 348). Moral progress is thus “a progress
of sentiments” (RR 352). So rather than focusing on the search for universal
rational principles to ground our moral beliefs and convince other, we should,
“putting foundationalism behind us,” instead “concentrate our energies on
manipulating sentiments, on sentimental education,” so that we can empathize
with more kinds of people, imaginatively feel ourselves “in the shoes of the
despised and oppressed” (RR 348, 350). “That sort of education sufficiently
acquaints people of different kinds with one another so that they are less
tempted to think of those different from themselves as only quasi-human. The
goal of this manipulation of sentiment is to expand the reference” class of those
we treat as humans like ourselves, of “people like us” (RR 348), and moral
persuasion is more a matter of “rhetorical manipulation” of feeling than
“genuine validity-seeking argument” (RR 432).
As all sentiments are fundamentally bodily, so are feelings of prejudice,
many of which (I argue) arise from somatic feelings of discomfort aroused by
the bodies of culturally different people. The fact that they look, smell, talk, or
walk differently than we do makes us less likely to consider them as human as
us because our bodies react differently toward them than toward our own
people. These negative reactions are often implicit and do their work beneath the
level of full consciousness, which is another reason why they resist rational
Reflections on The Rorty Reader
211
arguments for tolerance. We can therefore gain greater control of our prejudices
and display greater moral inclusiveness by gaining greater awareness and
control of our bodily reactions through greater somatic consciousness.7
Feelings can be effectively manipulated through somatic as well as
linguistic means. We can bring strangers (and even enemies) to feel more comfortable with each other by having them share the pleasures of eating and
drinking together. As William James long ago famously argued, we can also to
some extent transform our own moods and feelings by taking on the postures
and bodily behaviors of those feelings and moods we wish to feel.8 Moreover, to
imagine empathetically what it feels like to be oppressed or despised (or even
simply insulted or offended) is an act of somatic consciousness that can be done
more powerfully when we have a more developed somatic imagination, when
our somatic sensibility is more sensitive and subtle. There is thus a deep
connection between cultivating somatic sensibility and cultivating the greater
sensibility of sentiment that Rorty seeks as a means to moral progress, but he
neglects this productive connection or continuity by ignoring the body.
In the posthumously published gem that concludes The Rorty Reader, he
offers the following pithy argument for the importance of poetry. “No words, no
reasoning. No imagination, no new words. No such words, no moral or
intellectual progress” (RR 510). Let me conclude by formulating (though far less
elegantly) a similar type of argument for the importance of the body. No moral
progress without cultivating our heightened sensibility and feelings for others;
no successful, systematic cultivation of our powers of feeling without
recognizing and cultivation its bodily base; no moral progress without somatic
cultivation and its heightening of imaginative sensibility; more moral progress
through greater attention to such cultivation of the body and its perceptive,
affective, and imaginative powers.
Despite his outspoken resistance to somaesthetics, Rorty’s later advocacy
of philosophy as cultural politics suggests that he would not be averse to this
sort of argument.9 Rorty, of course, might rightly balk at talk of “the body” as an
essentialist, foundational notion, just as he sometimes criticized the notion of
language as a foundational essence. But as somaesthetics and the above argument for somatic moral cultivation make clear, we are dealing with different,
gendered, culturally-shaped bodies rather than a foundational, fixed, universal
body that defines human identity and limits. Indeed, one key element of the
somaesthetic project that Rorty might favor is its aim to extend our limits
through the meliorative, pluralistic cultivation of our bodies, or what I prefer to
call our somas (the term “soma” denoting what Dewey sometimes called “bodymind”).
212
RICHARD SHUSTERMAN
NOTES
1. William James, “Address at the Emerson Centenary in Concord,” in Ralph
Waldo Emerson, ed. Harold Bloom (New York: Infobase Publishing, 2008), p. 32.
2. Christopher Voparil and Richard Bernstein, ed., The Rorty Reader (Malden,
Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010). References to this work in my review essay are
abbreviated with RR.
3. See, for example, Richard Shusterman, Pragmatist Aesthetics (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1992), Practicing Philosophy (London and New York: Routledge, 1997). For
a recent treatment of Rorty that articulates the lines of my critique and tries to work
toward greater convergence in our views, see my “Pragmatism and Cultural Politics:
From Rortian Textualism to Somaesthetics,” New Literary History 41.1 (2010): 69–94.
4. Richard Rorty, “Response to Richard Shusterman,” in Richard Rorty: Critical
Dialogues, ed. Matthew Festenstein and Simon Thompson (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press,
2001), p. 156.
5. Richard Rorty, Achieving Our Country (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1997), p. 127. In his last book, Rorty expresses his pluralism by urging
philosophy’s greater interaction with many different fields: “The more philosophy
interacts with other human activities – not just natural science, but art, literature, religion,
and politics as well – the more relevant to cultural politics it becomes, and thus the more
useful.” Richard Rorty, Philosophy as Cultural Politics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 2008), p. x. Note how he omits the social sciences from this list of
enriching disciplines.
6. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope (New York: Penguin, 1999), p. 48.
7. For more detailed argument of these points, see Richard Shusterman, Body
Consciousness: A Philosophy of Mindfulness and Somaesthetics (Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 2008).
8. William James, The Principles of Psychology (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1983), chap. 4.
9. For an extended argument to this effect, see my “Pragmatism and Cultural
Politics.”
Richard Shusterman
Humanities and Philosophy
College of Arts and Letters
Florida Atlantic University
777 Glades Road
Boca Raton, Florida 33431-0991
United States