The constitutional impact of
strategic litigation in South Africa
A Klaasen
11232536
Thesis submitted for the degree Doctor Legum in
Constitutional Law at the Potchefstroom Campus of the
North-West University
Promoter: Prof Francois Venter
October 2016
ABSTRACT
The broad focus of the thesis is an analysis of the constitutional limits to strategic
litigation involving the state. The first chapter outlines the background of the
study and defines the concept of strategic litigation. In the following chapter the
application of the Constitution on legal disputes involving the state is analysed. In
the third chapter the concept of strategic litigation is explored within the context
of the doctrine of separation of powers. This analysis seeks to ascertain to what
extent strategic litigation can serve as an effective check on the abuse of power
by organs of state. The fact that the judiciary is the only effective check on the
abuse of power by the executive is acknowledged and the resultant tension
between the different branches of government is analysed. In the subsequent
chapters, the focus shifts to the role of the judge in strategic litigation and the
effect of possible subjective constitutional interpretation on the right of the
strategic litigant to pursue his or her rights through the courts with the
expectation that the court will adjudicate on the matter impartially and fairly and
the expectation that the court will come to a reasoned and just decision. Chapter
5 considers the constitutional limitations of strategic litigation by analysing
different examples of strategic litigation and the findings of the South African
courts. It is shown that constitutional limitations to strategic litigation are in some
instances self-imposed by the courts. Furthermore, procedural rules and
regulations and ethical considerations are not effective in holding the state litigant
accountable for the flouting of constitutionally imposed positive duties. In the final
chapter, a short summary is made and conclusions are drawn. It is argued that
there is a need in South African law of civil procedure for a set of rules or
guidelines to hold the state litigant constitutionally accountable and to force the
state litigant to be the model litigant.
i
OPSOMMING
Die breë fokus van die proefskrif is die analisering van die tekortkominge van
konstitusionele litigasie waar die staat betrokke is. In die eerste hoofstuk word ʼn
uiteensetting van die agtergrond van die studie verskaf en die konsep van
strategiese litigasie word gedefinieer. Vervolgens word die toepassing van die
Grondwet op litigasie waarby ʼn orgaan van die staat ʼn party is geanaliseer. In die
derde hoofstuk word die konsep van strategiese litigasie ondersoek binne die
konteks van die leerstuk van die skeiding van magte. Die analise poog om vas te
stel tot watter mate strategiese litigasie kan dien as ʼn effektiewe teenwig teen die
misbruik van mag deur staatsorgane. Die feit dat die regbank die enigste
effektiewe teenwig is teen die misbruik van mag deur die uitvoerende gesag word
erken en die gevolglike spanning tussen die verskillende regeringsinstansies word
geanaliseer. Die klem verskuif vervolgens na die rol van die regter in strategiese
litigasie en die rol wat moontlike subjektiewe grondwetlike interpretasie mag speel
op die reg van die strategiese litigant om sy of haar regte onpartydig en regverdig
in die hof te laat aanhoor en die reg dat die hof tot ʼn beredeneerde en
geregverdigde beslissing sal kom. Hoofstuk 5 ondersoek die grondwetlike
tekortkominge
van
strategiese
litigasie deur
verskillende
voorbeelde
van
strategiese litigasie en die bevindings van die Suid Afrikaanse howe te analiseer.
Die analise dui daarop dat grondwetlike tekortkominge in strategiese litigasie in
sekere gevalle deur die howe self opgelê word. Verder word aangetoon dat
bestaande prosedurele reëls en regulasies en etiese oorwegings nie effektief die
staatslitigant aanspreeklik hou vir die verontagsaming van grondwetlik ingestelde
positiewe verpligtinge nie. In die finale hoofstuk word ʼn kort opsomming gemaak
en gevolgtrekkings word bereik. Daar word geargumenteer dat daar ʼn
noodsaaklikheid is in Suid Afrikaanse siviele prosesreg vir ʼn stel reëls of riglyne om
die staatslitigant grondwetlik aanspreeklik te hou en om die staatslitigant te
forseer om die model litigant te wees.
ii
KEYWORDS
Application of the Bill of Rights; Bill of Rights; Checks and balances; constitution;
constitutional interpretation; constitutional litigation; constitutional values; constitutional
rights; organs of state; doctrine of separation of powers; judges; justice; justness;
positive constitutional duties; judicial activism; judicial review; judicial impartiality;
judicial independence; rationality; state litigant; strategic litigation.
iii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
ABSTRACT ......................................................................................................... I
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ............................................................................. XIV
Chapter 1: Introduction ..................................................................................1
1.1
Background ....................................................................................1
1.2
The changing face of civil litigation in South Africa ......................5
1.3
Positive constitutional duties imposed on the state when
litigating .........................................................................................5
1.4
Constitutional accountability of organs of state when
litigating .........................................................................................8
1.5
Problem statement ..................................................................... 11
1.6
Research methodology ............................................................... 12
1.7
Overview of study ....................................................................... 12
1.7.1
Chapter 1: Introduction ...................................................................... 12
1.7.2
Chapter 2: Constitutional litigation and the changing face of civil
litigation in South Africa ...................................................................... 13
1.7.3
Chapter 3: Strategic litigation as an effective check to prevent the
abuse of power in the context of the doctrine of the separation of
powers............................................................................................... 14
1.7.4
Chapter 4: The role of the judge in strategic litigation ........................... 16
1.7.5
Chapter 5: Constitutional limitations on strategic litigation..................... 18
1.7.6
Chapter 6: Conclusion ......................................................................... 18
iv
Chapter 2: Constitutional litigation and the changing face of civil
litigation in South Africa ................................................................................ 18
2.1
Introduction ................................................................................ 18
2.2
The pre-constitutional and post-constitutional concepts of
civil litigation .............................................................................. 20
2.2.1
The pre-constitutional concept of litigation ........................................... 20
2.2.1.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 20
2.2.1.2
Pre-constitutional concept of litigation in the United States of
America ............................................................................................. 21
2.2.1.3
Concepts of pre-constitutional litigation in South Africa ......................... 23
2.2.2
The post-constitutional concept of litigation ......................................... 26
2.2.3
Advantages and disadvantages of strategic litigation............................. 32
2.2.3.1
Disadvantages of strategic litigation ..................................................... 32
2.2.3.2
Advantages of strategic litigation ......................................................... 40
2.3
Strategic litigation within the framework of the South
African Constitution .................................................................... 43
2.3.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 44
2.3.2
Direct and indirect application of the Bill of Rights ................................ 45
2.3.3
Just administrative action and the rule of law ....................................... 50
2.4
Justiciability and strategic litigation .......................................... 54
2.4.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 54
2.4.2
Standing ............................................................................................ 55
v
2.4.2.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 55
2.4.2.2
Own-interest standing ......................................................................... 56
2.4.2.3
Surrogate standing ............................................................................. 61
2.4.2.4
Representative standing ...................................................................... 62
2.4.2.5
Public-interest standing ....................................................................... 66
2.4.2.6
Associational standing ......................................................................... 67
2.4.2.7
Standing of amici curiae ...................................................................... 68
2.4.3
Ripeness ............................................................................................ 71
2.4.4
Mootness ........................................................................................... 75
2.4.5
Jurisdiction ......................................................................................... 80
2.4.5.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 80
2.4.5.2
The meaning of constitutional matters ................................................. 80
2.4.5.3
Exclusive jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court ................................... 81
2.4.5.4
Jurisdiction of the High Court .............................................................. 84
2.5
Strategic litigation and cause of action ...................................... 85
2.5.1
Common-law cause of action ............................................................... 86
2.5.2
Statutory-law cause of action .............................................................. 87
2.5.3
Constitutional-law cause of action ........................................................ 91
2.5.3.1
Introduction ....................................................................................... 91
2.5.3.2
Comparable causes of action in foreign jurisdictions ............................. 93
2.5.3.2.1
Position in the United States of America ............................................... 93
vi
2.5.3.2.2
Position in Canada .............................................................................. 96
2.5.3.3
Approach adopted by the South African Constitutional Court ................. 98
2.6
Constitutional remedies ............................................................ 116
2.6.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 116
2.6.2
The range of constitutional remedies available ................................... 119
2.6.2.1
Declaration of rights ......................................................................... 119
2.6.2.2
Interdictory relief .............................................................................. 123
2.6.2.2.1
Requirements for granting an interdict ............................................... 123
2.6.2.2.2
Structural interdicts or supervisory interdicts ...................................... 125
2.6.2.3
Damages ......................................................................................... 127
2.6.2.4
Declarations of invalidity ................................................................... 130
2.6.2.4.1
Declaring legislation and executive conduct constitutionally invalid ...... 130
2.6.2.4.2
Declaring a rule of the common law constitutionally invalid ................. 135
2.6.2.5
The doctrine of vagueness ................................................................ 139
2.6.2.6
Methods of curing constitutional invalidity .......................................... 141
2.6.2.6.1
Actual and notional severance ........................................................... 141
2.6.2.6.2
Reading in........................................................................................ 146
2.7
Crafting appropriate remedies for relief of constitutional
violations................................................................................... 146
2.7.1
Ubi ius ibi remedium ......................................................................... 147
2.7.2
The constitutional principle of ―appropriate relief‖ ............................... 148
vii
2.8
The duty of the state to act fairly in litigation .......................... 154
2.8.1
Principles of co-operative government and intergovernmental
relations ........................................................................................... 154
2.8.2
Constitutional imposition of positive duties on the state ...................... 158
2.8.3
The state‘s compliance with constitutional duties ................................ 162
2.9
Conclusion ................................................................................. 174
Chapter 3:
Strategic litigation as an effective check to prevent the
abuse of powers in the context of the doctrine of the separation of
powers
176
3.1
Introduction .............................................................................. 176
3.2
The development of the doctrine of the separation of powers
and its purpose ......................................................................... 178
3.2.1
Historical development of the doctrine of the separation of powers ..... 178
3.2.1.1
Early philosophers on the concept of the state ................................... 178
3.2.1.2
Germanic influence on the development of the state........................... 180
3.2.1.3
Separation of powers and the state ................................................... 182
3.2.1.4
Development of the doctrine of the separation of powers in England ... 185
3.2.2
Purpose and limits of the doctrine of the separation of powers ............ 187
3.3
The South African model of the separation of powers ............. 190
3.3.1
Pre-constitutional parliamentary sovereignty ...................................... 190
3.3.1.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 190
3.3.1.2
Pre-constitutional parliamentary sovereignty in South Africa ................ 191
viii
3.3.2
Separation of powers in the Interim Constitution ................................ 195
3.3.2.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 195
3.3.2.2
Certification of the Constitution ......................................................... 197
3.3.2.2.1
Objections regarding the doctrine of the separation of powers ............ 197
3.3.2.2.2
Objection about the independence of the judiciary ............................. 201
3.3.3
Separation of powers in the South African constitutional state ............. 204
3.3.3.1
Constitutional provisions ................................................................... 204
3.3.3.2
Constitutional role of the courts ......................................................... 205
3.3.4
The rising tension between the executive and the judiciary ................. 214
3.3.4.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 214
3.3.4.2
International position ........................................................................ 215
3.3.4.2.1
Position in the United States of America ............................................. 215
3.3.4.2.2
Position in European countries ........................................................... 217
3.3.4.3
Position in South Africa ..................................................................... 220
3.3.4.3.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 220
3.3.4.3.2
Historical clashes between the judiciary and executive in South Africa . 221
3.3.4.3.3
Current position in South Africa ......................................................... 224
3.4
Checks and balances on the separation of powers in the
South African constitutional state ............................................ 228
3.4.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 229
3.4.2
Checks and balances: the legislature.................................................. 229
ix
3.4.2.1
Participatory democracy .................................................................... 229
3.4.2.2
General elections .............................................................................. 234
3.4.3
Checks and balances: the executive ................................................... 234
3.4.3.1
Public control ................................................................................... 234
3.4.3.2
Parliamentary control over the executive ............................................ 237
3.4.3.3
Judicial control over the executive ..................................................... 240
3.4.4
Checks and balances: the judiciary .................................................... 245
3.5
Judicial review and strategic litigation .................................... 247
3.5.1
Introduction ..................................................................................... 247
3.5.2
Determination of the ―proper standard‖ for judicial review .................. 248
3.5.3
The direction of the Constitutional Court ............................................ 252
3.6
Conclusion ................................................................................. 261
Chapter 4: The role of the judge in strategic litigation ............................. 266
4.1
Introduction .............................................................................. 266
4.2
The judicial appointment process ............................................. 268
4.2.1
The importance of the judicial appointment process ........................... 268
4.2.2
Appointment of judges in South Africa ............................................... 270
4.2.3
Politics and the judicial appointment process ...................................... 272
4.2.4
Transformation and the judicial appointment process ......................... 273
4.3
Judicial independence and impartiality .................................... 284
x
4.3.1
International law and the independence and impartiality of the
judiciary ........................................................................................... 284
4.3.2
Judicial independence in South Africa ................................................ 287
4.3.3
Judicial impartiality in South Africa..................................................... 292
4.3.3.1
Recusal of judges ............................................................................. 292
4.3.3.2
Judicial impartiality in South Africa..................................................... 294
4.4
Interpretation of constitutional values and rights ................... 299
4.4.1
Sources for constitutional interpretation ............................................. 299
4.4.2
Constitutional interpretation in hard cases .......................................... 300
4.4.3
The interpretation of constitutional values and rights by the courts ...... 302
4.4.4
The transformative nature of the South African Constitution ................ 312
4.5
Rationality and justness in constitutional adjudication ........... 314
4.5.1
Rationality in constitutional adjudication............................................. 315
4.5.2
The concept of justice in adjudication ................................................ 317
4.5.3
Building an acceptable theory of constitutional interpretation .............. 321
4.6
Conclusion ................................................................................. 327
Chapter 5: Constitutional limitations on strategic litigation..................... 332
5.1
Introduction .............................................................................. 332
5.2
Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions ................................. 334
5.2.1
Majority decision .............................................................................. 335
5.2.2
Minority decision............................................................................... 335
xi
5.2.3
Similar examples of strategic litigation ............................................... 336
5.2.4
Conceptual analysis of the decision .................................................... 339
5.3
Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria .............................................. 342
5.3.1
Background to the case .................................................................... 342
5.3.2
Decision of the High Court ................................................................ 343
5.3.3
Decision of the Constitutional Court ................................................... 345
5.3.3.1
Majority decision .............................................................................. 345
5.3.3.2
Minority decision............................................................................... 352
5.3.4
Similar examples of strategic litigation ............................................... 357
5.3.5
Conceptual analysis of the decision .................................................... 360
5.4
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media
Limited ...................................................................................... 363
5.4.1
First hearing in the High Court........................................................... 364
5.4.2
First appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal ...................................... 365
5.4.3
Referral to the Constitutional Court .................................................... 366
5.4.4
Second hearing in the High Court ...................................................... 370
5.4.5
Second appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal .................................. 372
5.4.6
Content of the Khampepe-Moseneke Report ...................................... 375
5.4.7
Similar examples of strategic litigation ............................................... 379
5.4.8
Conceptual analysis of the decision .................................................... 382
5.5
Theoretical approaches to ethics in litigation .......................... 385
xii
5.5.1
Institutions and sources that regulate the conduct of attorneys and
advocates ........................................................................................ 386
5.5.2
Lawyer‘s duties to court .................................................................... 388
5.6
Conclusion ................................................................................. 393
Chapter 6: Conclusions ................................................................................ 396
6.1
Introduction .............................................................................. 396
6.2
Constitutional limitations to strategic litigation ...................... 396
6.3
The model litigant obligation .................................................... 403
6.3.1
The model litigant obligation as applied in Australia ............................ 404
6.3.2
Justifications for the obligation .......................................................... 409
6.3.2.1
Justification in Australia .................................................................... 409
6.3.2.2
Justification in South Africa ............................................................... 410
6.4
Application of the model litigant obligation in South Africa .... 412
6.4.1
To whom should the model apply? .................................................... 412
6.4.2
Structure of the proposed model in South Africa ................................. 414
xiii
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS
ACHPR
African Court of Human and Peoples' Rights
AHRLJ
African Human Rights Law Journal
AIAL
Australian Institute of Administrative Law
ANC
African National Congress
BYU J. Pub. L.
Brigham Young University Journal of Public Law
CAPE
Center for Advances in Public Engagement
CBC
Cape Bar Council
CC
Constitutional Court
CCRF
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
Chap. L. REV
Chapman Law Review
Conn. L. Rev.
Connecticut Law Review
DHA
Department of Home Affairs
DJCIL
Duke Journal of Comparative International Law
ECHR
European Court of Human Rights
Emory Int'l L. Rev.
Emory International Law Review
EU
European Union
Fordham Urb. L.J.
Fordham Urban Law Journal
HARV. J. On Legis
Harvard Journal on Legislation
IDASA
Institute for Democracy in South Africa
J. Pub. L.
Journal of Public Law
JSC
Judicial Service Commission
LAC
Labour Appeal Court
LHR
Lawyers for Human Rights
LRA
Labour Relations Act
MHA
Minister for Home Affairs
xiv
N.C. L. Rev.
North Carolina Law Review
NA
National Assembly
NCOP
National Council of Provinces
NDPP
National Director of Public Prosecutions
NEHAWU
National Health and Allied Workers Union
NLM
National Liberation Movement
Nw. U.L. Rev.
Northwestern University Law Review
PAIA
Promotion of Access to Information Act
PAJA
Promotion of Administrative Justice Act
PELJ
Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal
PER
Potchefstroom Elektroniese Regstydskrif
Pulp
Pretoria University Law Press
SAJHR
South African Journal of Human Rights
SALJ
South African Law Journal
SARS
South African Revenue Service
SCA
Supreme Court of Appeal
Scopa
Standing Committee on Public Accounts
Stan. L. Rev.
Stanford Law Review
Stell LR
Stellenbosch Law Review
THRHR
Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg
TSAR
Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg
UNSW
University of New South Wales
U. Rich. L. Rev.
University of Richmond Law Review
USC
United States Code
WCHC
Western Cape High Court
ZaöRV
Zeitschrift für
Völkerrecht
ausländisches
xv
öffentliches
Recht
und
Chapter 1:
Introduction
1.1 Background
The difficult issues facing communities are often too complex and involve too many
different interests to be successfully resolved at the ballot box alone. Governments and
political parties often act contrary to the wishes of the population, causing citizens to
lose faith in government and government institutions. Furthermore, political parties do
not necessarily act for the public good, but act in what they perceive to be the best
interest of their voters. Leighninger states that people feel entitled to the services and
protection of their government and yet they do not have much faith that the
government will deliver on what they promise.1 This distrust of governments gives rise
to individuals' and organisations' playing a watchdog role over state actions, state
spending and legislation; such individuals and organisations lobby and make demands
on the state for various public goods.2
Ranchod states that, in part, their watchdog role is a way of forcing the government to
remain accountable to its citizens in general and their own membership in particular.
This civil-society engagement with the state can be viewed as part of political
pluralism;3 this implies tolerance and accommodation of diverse views, passions,
interests and demands in the public sphere. According to Ranchod, civil society's
engagement with the state between elections is a form of public political participation,
which ranges from the mobilisation of public opinion to action on the streets and
includes both non-confrontational and confrontational methods of engagement. These
methods include litigation, petitions, media campaigns, mass marches, strikes, and civil
disobedience.4 As part of this political participation, organisations and individuals often
disregard or distrust the political process and approach the courts to advance their own
1
2
3
4
Leighninger 2009 CAPE 2.
Ranchod 2007 Policy: Issues and Actors 3.
Political pluralism indicates a participatory type of government in which the politics of the country
are defined by the needs and wants of many. Political pluralism is a government of the people, by
the people, and for the people. The basic ideas of government become evident through the ideas of
individuals and groups to ensure that all the needs and wants of society are met. There is no right or
wrong idea: everyone's ideas are valid.
Ranchod 2007 Policy: Issues and Actors 3.
1
interests and protect their own rights. Schokman states that the organisation or
individual often takes the legal route as part of a strategy to achieve broader systemic
change. A lawsuit may create change either through the success of the action and its
effect on law, policy or practice, or by publicly exposing injustice, raising awareness and
generating broader change. This type of litigation is called strategic litigation.5
Section 34 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (hereafter the
Constitution) grants South Africans the right of access to the courts.6 The purpose of
this right is threefold: firstly, to protect general and individual rights; secondly, to
support the separation of powers (specifically the separation of the judiciary from the
other branches); and, thirdly, fundamentally to uphold the rule of law. 7 It is a
fundamental principle of the rule of law that anyone may challenge the legality of any
law or conduct.8 When challenging conduct or law in this way, individuals and
organisations often require the courts to adjudicate on matters traditionally reserved for
the executive and legislative branches of government.
Anderson states that, in the absence of clear goals and techniques for programmatic
development, recent developments have emphasised the role of legal institutions in
empowering disadvantaged groups while holding governments and corporations
accountable for anti-humanitarian activities. Anderson continues, however, that legal
procedure places serious constraints on the possibilities for popular participation, but
that political activism can be used to interrogate and even breach those constraints. 9
This concept of activism by litigation or strategic litigation seems at first glance to be
incompatible with the traditional view of litigation.
5
6
7
8
9
Schokman 2012 Advocates for International Development 3. The concept of strategic litigation is
further explored in section 2.2 where the difference between ordinary litigation and strategic
litigation is investigated.
Section 34 reads that everyone has the right to have any dispute that can be resolved by the
application of law decided in a fair public hearing before a court or, where appropriate, another
independent and impartial tribunal or forum.
Bernstein v Bester 1996 (2) SA 751 CC para 105.
The concept of "rule of law" was familiar to ancient philosophers such as Aristotle, who wrote that
"law should govern‖ Aristotle Politics 3.16.
Anderson 1993 Third World Legal Studies 178.
2
It is a feature of strategic litigation that enforcement of the judgment usually lies with
the state. This can be problematic, because an organ of state is usually a participant in
the litigation. Therefore, the changes that may be effected by the litigation are often
contrary to official government policy. In other words, the change required by the
judgment may sometimes be politically unacceptable to government and its mandating
supporters, with the effect that the political will to apply and enforce such judgments
would be lacking. The courts are well aware this, recognising that the institutional limits
of the judiciary ―often result in courts being forced to watch impotently while a
dysfunctional and apparently unrepentant administration continues to abuse its
power‖.10
One of the most important principles of South African law is expressed by the maxim
ubi ius ubi remedium:11 where there is a right, there is a remedy.12 This means that the
existence of a legal rule implies the existence of an authority with the power to grant a
remedy if that rule is infringed. A legal rule or judgment will be deficient if there is no
means of enforcing it and if no sanction attaches to a breach of that rule or judgment.
The Constitution itself provides very little guidance on constitutional remedies,13 but
according to the Constitutional Court in Fose –14
[i]t is left for the courts to decide what would be appropriate relief in any particular
case. Appropriate relief will in essence be relief that is required to protect and enforce
the Constitution. Depending on the circumstances of each particular case the relief
may be a declaration of rights, an interdict, a mandamus or such other relief as may be
required to ensure that the rights enshrined in the Constitution are protected and
enforced. If it is necessary to do so, the courts may even have to fashion new
remedies to secure the protection and enforcement of these all important rights.
Noting the special responsibility of the courts to vindicate individual rights, Ackermann J
identified a judicial obligation to ―forge new tools‖ and shape ―innovative remedies‖.15
10
11
12
13
14
15
Vumazonke v MEC for Social Development and Welfare for Eastern Cape Province 2004 ZAECHC
The basic principle contemplated in the maxim is that when a person's right is violated, the victim
will have an equitable remedy under law. The maxim also means that the person whose right has
been infringed has a right to enforce the infringed right through any action before a court. All courts
of law are guided by the same principle of ubi ius ibi remedium.
Hiemstra Trilingual Legal Dictionary 299.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 195.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) paras 18 and 19.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 69.
3
The powers of the Court in constitutional matters are set out in section 172 of the
Constitution. Section 172(1) reads as follows:
(1)
When deciding a constitutional matter within its power, a court—
(a)
must declare that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the
Constitution is invalid to the extent of its inconsistency; and
(b)
may make any order that is just and equitable, including—
(i)
an order limiting the retrospective effect of the declaration of
invalidity; and
(ii)
an order suspending the declaration of invalidity for any period
and on any conditions, to allow the competent authority to correct
the defect.
Section 172 therefore grants the court the power to make any order that is just and
equitable, giving force to the judicial obligation recognised by Ackermann J to ―forge
new tools‖ and shape ―innovative remedies‖,16 and so it is clear that the Constitution
grants wide powers to the courts to right constitutional violations. One can ask,
however, whether there is a commitment by both the courts and the organs of state to
advance and protect the Constitution. Should the courts or organs of state not honour
their constitutional obligations, it would undermine the rule of law and the legitimacy of
the courts, organs of state and the Constitution. Furthermore, the question must be
asked whether current law of civil procedure is open to abuse by the capricious state
litigant striving to protect organs of state or state individuals who violate the
Constitution. If such constitutional violations occur, are the remedies offered by the
Constitution sufficient to allow the courts to protect the Constitution or should the
courts be forced to watch impotently while a dysfunctional and apparently unrepentant
administration continues to abuse its power? After all, legitimacy and confidence in a
16
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC).
4
legal system demand that an effective remedy be provided in situations where the
interests of justice cry out for one.17
1.2 The changing face of civil litigation in South Africa
In the modern South African constitutional state the concept of litigation has developed
on the basis of the traditional common-law principles of claiming for damages wrought,
correcting a wrong or obtaining relief from another. The traditional cause of action
featured a plaintiff with clear and identifiable rights and a defendant with clear
obligations or liabilities. In terms of the common law, the litigants would pray for a
remedy that would usually involve monetary compensation, and the effect of the
remedy would rarely reach beyond the parties to the case. In modern constitutional
litigation, such cases still reach the courts. However, since 1994, the South African
Constitution provides the strategic litigant with a basis from which to bring before the
court matters not possible in terms of traditional common law.
The advent of the Constitution made possible the judicial review of state actions.
Section 1(c) of the Constitution confirms the supremacy of the Constitution and the rule
of law. Furthermore, section 2 of the Constitution provides that the Constitution is the
supreme law of the Republic, that law or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid, and that
the obligations imposed by the Constitution must be fulfilled. In a growing number of
cases, the post-constitutional concept of litigation sets the tone for strategic litigation in
which the litigants are able to enforce constitutional rights, expose corruption and
shape and influence government policy. This allows litigants to enforce a change in or
to influence or direct executive policy through the courts. Constitutional provisions
therefore make it possible for individuals or organisations to hold organs of state and
state representatives constitutionally accountable.
1.3 Positive constitutional duties imposed on the state when litigating
Van Doren argues that there is a ―fundamental contradiction‖ between the exercise of
state power and individual freedom. This contradiction exists because state power is
17
Molaudzi v S 2015 (2) SACR 341 (CC) para 37.
5
both necessary for, and a great threat to, individual freedom.18 The South African
Constitution seeks to balance the contradiction between the rights of the individual and
the right of the state to exercise power. The constitutional attempt to create a balance
between the exercise of state power and individual rights is also visible when an organ
of state engages in litigation. Section 9(1) of the Constitution highlights that everyone is
equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and benefit of the law.
However, when the private individual litigates against an organ of state, the
constitutional promise of equality before the law and equal protection and benefit of the
law is not always realised. There is sometimes a substantial imbalance of power in
litigation with the government. Organs of state may have access to substantial
resources, powers to investigate and more experience and specialist expertise in
dealing with complex legal matters. To give realisation to constitutional equality before
the law it is necessary for the state litigant to act in a manner which is honest,
consistent, and fair. The state litigant must be held to a different standard than the
private litigant. The state litigant must be the model litigant. It is trite that there is also
a legal duty on the private litigant and private legal representative to behave ethically
and honestly when litigating. However, the state litigant must be held to a stricter and
higher standard than the private litigant. The state litigant has the positive
constitutional duty to uphold, defend and respect the Constitution. Moreover, given that
the state litigant is publically funded, the state litigant must represent the public
interest in litigation. In other words, an organ of state can litigate only when it is in the
public interest to do so and/or it will vindicate the Constitution. The duties placed on
the state litigant and state legal representatives transcend the ethical obligations placed
upon the private litigant and private legal representative.19 Ethical obligations provide
for minimum standards of conduct, whereas the constitutional injunction placed on the
state litigant involves striving for aspirational standards of the highest character. 20
18
19
20
Van Doren 1986 SALJ 648.
State officials ignore their constitutional obligations at their peril. Economic Freedom Fighters v
Speaker of the National Assembly; Democratic Alliance v Speaker of the National Assembly (CCT
143/15; CCT 171/15) [2016] ZACC 11 para 1.
The argument that the state litigant must be held to a different and higher standard than the private
litigant is recognised in a number of foreign jurisdictions. In the European Court of Human Rights, it
is referred to as the ‗Principle of Equality of Arms‘ that forms part of the right to fair trial, regulated
6
Chapter 2 of the Constitution sets out a Bill of Rights, which the state must respect,
protect, promote and fulfil.21 Furthermore, the Bill of Rights applies to all law, and binds
the legislature, the executive, the judiciary and all organs of state.22 A competent court
may be approached with the allegation that a right in the Bill of Rights has been
infringed or threatened.23
The Constitution provides that national legislative authority is vested in Parliament. 24
The President and the National Executive have the powers entrusted to them by the
Constitution and legislation, including those necessary to perform the functions of Head
of State and head of the national executive.25 The judicial authority of the Republic is
vested in the courts.26 An order issued by a court binds all persons to whom and organs
of state to which it applies.27 Therefore, although the executive branch and Parliament
have the constitutional power to fulfil their functions, these powers must be exercised
in a manner consistent with the Constitution and the obligations it imposes on the state.
Du Plessis et al argue that the Constitution places a range of positive duties on organs
of state. These positive duties also apply when an organ of state engages in litigation.
Organs of state must assist and protect the courts to ensure the independence,
impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.28 The duty placed on
organs of state to ensure the effectiveness of the courts entails a positive obligation for
the organs of state to place relevant and material evidence before the courts. 29 There is
also a strong need for government to provide an explanation for the introduction of
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
by art 6 of the European Convention for Human Rights. In Australia it is referred to as the model
litigant obligation. According to Zac Chami ‗The obligation to act as a model litigant‘ (2010) AIAL
Forum 64, the model litigant extends beyond merely obeying the law and abiding by the ethical
obligations that apply to legal practitioners. The ethical obligations provide for minimum standards of
conduct, whereas the model litigant obligation involves striving for aspirational standards of the
highest character.
Section 7(2) of the Constitution.
Section 8(1) of the Constitution.
Section 38 of the Constitution.
Chapter 4 of the Constitution.
Chapter 5 of the Constitution.
Chapter 8 of the Constitution.
Section 165(5) of the Constitution.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
7
legislation.30 Furthermore, public administration should be governed by the democratic
values and principles enshrined in the Constitution, including the following principles:31
(a)
A high standard of professional ethics must be promoted and maintained.
(b)
Efficient, economic and effective use of resources must be promoted.
(c)
Public administration must be development-oriented.
(d)
Services must be provided impartially, fairly, equitably and without bias.
(e)
People's needs must be responded to, and the public must be encouraged to
participate in policy-making.
(f)
Public administration must be accountable.
(g)
Transparency must be fostered by providing the public with timely, accessible
and accurate information.
(h)
Good human-resource management and career-development practices, to
maximise human potential, must be cultivated.
(i)
Public administration must be broadly representative of the South African people,
with employment and personnel management practices based on ability,
objectivity, fairness, and the need to redress the imbalances of the past to
achieve broad representation.
The principles contained in section 195(1) apply to the administration in every sphere of
government, organs of state and public enterprises.32 Therefore, an organ of state must
ensure that it acts in an ethical, economical, impartial, fair, open and accountable
manner when engaging in litigation. The constitutional injunction requiring fairness
from the state litigant can be realised by holding the organ of state, the state legal
representative and the instructing agent for the organ of the state to a different
standard than the private litigant. The constitutional injunction requires the organ of the
state to be the model litigant when it makes use of the court process.
1.4 Constitutional accountability of organs of state when litigating
30
Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) para 109.
31
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
Section 195(2) of the Constitution.
32
8
The courts have indicated that the commencement, defence and conduct of litigation by
the government or government departments constitutes the exercise of public power. 33
Therefore, state litigation is subject to the same scrutiny as any other exercise of public
power. The state litigant has to comply with the principle of legality and the rule of law.
The rule of law, legality and democratic principles are foundational values of the
Constitution.34 When these values are threatened by the organs constitutionally charged
with protecting and furthering them, new strategies are needed to protect these values.
In Permanent Secretary Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v
Ngxuza,35 the respondents brought motion proceedings against the Eastern Cape
Provincial Government to reinstate the disability grants they had been receiving under
the Social Assistance Act,36 which the province terminated without notice to them.37
They also sought to litigate as representatives on behalf of anyone in the Eastern Cape
Province whose disability grants had been cancelled or suspended by the Eastern Cape
Government.38 The applicants challenged both the granting of leave to institute the
class action and the disclosure order, without questioning the merits of the case.39 The
applicants did not dispute that the method the province chose to verify and update its
pensioner records was not just harsh, but also unlawful. This had been previously
established by the Courts.40 Despite the earlier finding that the actions of the province
were unlawful, the applicants again disputed the claims of the respondents.41 The Court
describes the conduct of the applicants as follows:
The applicants did so by recourse to every stratagem and device and obstruction,
every legal argument and non-argument that it thought lay to hand. While offering no
undertaking to implement Bushula in relation to the applicant class, it asserted that
because of the decision the relief sought was moot. It then contended, contradictorily,
that the applicants‘ claim was not yet ripe for adjudication. It tendered no evidence to
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 3.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
2001 (4) SA 1184 SCA.
59 of 1992.
Para 2.
Para 3.
Para 5.
Bushula v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape 2000 (2) SA 849 (E) and
Rangani v Superintendent-General, Department of Health and Welfare, Northern Province 1999 (4)
SA 385 (T).
Para 17.
9
refute the mass of indicia the applicants placed before the Court that showed unlawful
conduct against huge numbers of disability pensioners, yet argued that the applicants‘
evidence was inadmissible hearsay. It obstructed the applicant class‘s entitlement to be
spared physical destitution, yet invoked their privacy rights in contending that the
disclosure order should not have been granted. It did not flinch even from deriding the
first applicant, who adhered to the founding papers with his thumbprint. Its deponent
thought fit to record his doubt that Mr Ngxuza had read the media articles appended to
the papers (a claim the first applicant did not make), while the written argument stated
that it ―boggles the mind‖ that ―a man who never attended school and is presently
illiterate‖ is able to make ―learned submissions‖.
The Court held that all this speaks of contempt for people and process that does not
befit an organ of government under our constitutional dispensation. 42 It is not the
function of the courts to criticise government‘s decisions in the area of social policy, but
–
[w]hen an organ of government invokes legal processes to impede the rightful claims
of its citizens, it not only defies the Constitution, which commands all organs of state
to be loyal to the Constitution,43 and requires that public administration be conducted
on the basis that people‘s needs must be responded to.44
The Court stated that such a process also misuses the mechanisms of the law, which it
is the responsibility of the courts to safeguard. The Court held that the province‘s
approach to the proceedings was contradictory, cynical, expedient and obstructionist. It
conducted the case as though it was at war with its own citizens. This begs the
question of whether existing control mechanisms are sufficient to prevent the state
from acting outside the scope of the Constitution and to ensure that organs of state
comply with their constitutional and legal duties. Should it be found that existing control
measures are not adequate to vindicate the Constitution, is judicial intervention
essential in order to vindicate the rule of law by making certain that the exercise of
power accords with the obligations articulated in the Constitution? In section 1.3 above
it was argued that the state litigant should be held to a different standard than the
private litigant. To conform to the equality clause in section 9(1) of the Constitution and
the basic values and principles that must govern public administration as set out in
section 195 of the Constitution, a new set of procedural rules or guidelines are needed
42
43
44
Para 19.
Section 41(1)(d) of the Constitution provides that all spheres of government and all organs of state
must be loyal to the Constitution, the Republic and its people.
Section 195(1)(e) of the Constitution provides that people‘s needs must be responded to.
10
to hold the state litigant constitutionally accountable. These rules or guidelines could
assist the state litigant to act in the public interest, according to law and the
Constitution. These procedural rules or guidelines are called the model litigant
obligation and are discussed in Chapter 6.
The Constitutional Court has so far played a significant political role in relation to
conflict over the powers of the various levels of government and the extent to which
political parties use the Court to fight political battles. That is of course not the only
types of cases that reach the Court. The Court also adjudicates on ordinary matters in
both civil and criminal law where constitutional questions arise.45 However, the political
role of the Constitutional Court is likely to become increasingly important as more
political struggles are placed before the courts for resolution. This political role of the
courts is not accepted, however, without criticism. The last decade has shown a steadily
rising tension between government and the judiciary in South Africa.
This tide of tension between government and the judiciary reflects the fact that
although the Constitution expressly provides for judicial review, the extent and nature
of such review is neither clear nor settled. It is further clear that the dynamics of the
separation of powers between the executive, the legislature and the judiciary in the
South African constitutional state are far from established and entrenched.
1.5 Problem statement
This study aims to ascertain the constitutional limits to strategic litigation involving the
state in South Africa. The question asked is: What are the constitutional limits to
strategic litigation involving the state? To answer this question, this study starts off in
chapter two by investigating the procedural aspects of constitutional litigation and the
changing face of civil litigation in South Africa after the commencement of the
Constitution. In the third chapter, strategic litigation as an effective check to prevent
the abuse of power is investigated in the context of the doctrine of the separation of
powers. Chapter four examines the role of the judge in strategic litigation. Chapter five
45
The jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court is further investigated in section 2.4.5.
11
explores the constitutional limitations on strategic litigation. The chapters in this study
are separate from each other, but they also overlap and interrelate. In order to reach a
conclusion, they are considered cumulatively in chapter six.
1.6 Research methodology
This study aims to review the constitutional limitations on strategic litigation involving
the state in South Africa. A limited legal comparison is applied in some of the chapters
to give context and depth to the study. The aim is not to transplant developments in
foreign jurisdictions directly into South African law or to compare directly the strengths
and the weaknesses of the legal systems concerned. The study of the position in other
jurisdictions is aimed at distilling lessons from such jurisdictions. This study takes into
account that the jurisprudence is the product of different societies, cultures, and
political and legal systems. Therefore, the study relies heavily on South Africa‘s unique
circumstances and the South African Constitution is used as the main guideline. The
potential value of this methodology for interpreting the constitutional effect and impact
of strategic litigation lies, arguably, in the contribution it can make towards giving
background and context to the South African position. The study comprises a critical
review of relevant legislation and an examination of case law, electronic sources,
textbooks and academic articles, after which the constitutional limitations on strategic
litigation involving the state is critically evaluated.
1.7 Overview of study
1.7.1 Chapter 1: Introduction
The Introduction sets out the basis on which this research was conducted. This covers
the background to this study, the problem statement, the research methodology and an
overview of the five research objectives.
12
1.7.2 Chapter 2: Constitutional litigation and the changing face of civil litigation in
South Africa
This study starts with an investigation of strategic litigation within the framework of the
South African Constitution. The application of the Bill of Rights to legal disputes is
analysed and the justiciability of legal disputes debated. In the pre-democratic era, the
principle of legality – the idea that administrators and other public actors had to act
lawfully – was not always adhered to. The advent of the constitutional era in South
Africa has changed this dynamic. Section 33 of the Constitution provides that everybody
has the right to administrative action that is lawful, reasonable and procedurally fair,
and in terms of section 33(3) national legislation must be enacted to give effect to this
right. This national legislation must impose a duty on the state to give effect to the
right to fair and just administrative action. The concept of legality has a wider meaning
that goes beyond administrative action.46 It also refers to a broad constitutional
principle of legality that governs the use of all public power.47 The principle of legality is
an aspect of the rule of law, a founding value of the constitutional order in terms of
section 1(c) of the Constitution.48 The fundamental idea it expresses is that the exercise
of public power is only legitimate when lawful. The legality of public power exercised by
an organ of state may be challenged by litigants, and should the court find that
constitutional violations occurred; the court may remedy the violation. The prominence
of the rule of law in South Africa is evidenced by the manner in which the courts have
invoked the rule of law as a mechanism to limit, regulate and give meaning to how
state power is exercised.49
46
47
48
49
Hoexter Administrative Law 224.
Hoexter Administrative Law 225.
Section 1 of the Constitution provides that the Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign, democratic
state founded on the following values: … "(c) Supremacy of the Constitution and the rule of law."
According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the rule of law can be defined in the following way:
―[T]he authority and influence of law in society, especially when viewed as a constraint on individual
and institutional behaviour; therefore it is a principle whereby all members of a society (including
those in government) are considered equally subject to publicly disclosed legal codes and
processes.‖ The rule of law is therefore a legal principle that law should govern a nation, as opposed
to being governed by arbitrary decisions of individual government officials and functions as a
constraint upon behaviour, including the behaviour of elected government officials.
De Vos et al South African Constitutional Law in Context 81.
13
The introduction of the Constitution broadened the scope of the law of civil procedure
in South Africa. The procedural aspects of litigation are investigated, with the focus on
the traditional and modern constitutional concept of litigation. The advantages and
disadvantages of strategic litigation are explored.
The application of the Bill of Rights is concerned not only with the question of whether
the Bill of Rights applies, but also with how it applies in a legal dispute. When
interpreting the Bill of Rights, a court must promote the values that underlie an open
and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom.50 When
interpreting any legislation, and when developing the common law or customary law,
every court must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.51 The
procedural process of strategic litigation is explored to identify any constitutional
limitations on constructive strategic litigation. The constitutional remedies available to
courts are investigated with a view to constructing appropriate remedies for
constitutional violations.
The duty of organs of state to act fairly in litigation is explored with particular attention
to the positive duties imposed by the Constitution on organs of state when engaging in
litigation. The constitutional injunction requiring honesty and fairness of the state
litigant requires the state litigant to be the model litigant. Finally, compliance by organs
of state with the constitutionally imposed duties is investigated and the question is
asked whether the state litigant consistently acts like the model litigant.
1.7.3 Chapter 3: Strategic litigation as an effective check to prevent the abuse of
power in the context of the doctrine of the separation of powers
This chapter analyses the procedural aspects of strategic litigation by examining the
concept of the separation of powers in the South African constitutional state and its
effect on strategic litigation. The constitutional principle of the separation of powers is
an essential feature of modern South African government. Constitutional Principle VI, of
the constitutional principles agreed upon during the multi-party negotiating process in
50
51
Section 39(1)(a) of the Constitution.
Section 39(2) of the Constitution.
14
the early 1990s and annexed to the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 200 of
1993 (hereafter the Interim Constitution), was worded as follows:
There shall be a separation of powers between the legislature, executive and judiciary,
with appropriate checks and balances to ensure accountability, responsiveness and
openness.
However, a complete separation of powers is possible neither in theory nor in practice.
At the outset of this chapter, attention is paid to the historical basis of Parliamentary
sovereignty in pre-Constitution South Africa and the subsequent changeover to a
system of constitutional supremacy. The historical background to the doctrine of the
separation of powers is investigated with specific emphasis on the development and
purpose of the doctrine.
The principle of the separation of powers after the commencement of the Constitution,
1996, is investigated and its effect on strategic litigation is explored. Attention is
focused on the fact that the Constitution does not refer explicitly to the separation of
powers, although it is implicit in the document.52 The effectiveness of the constitutional
checks and balances essential for the doctrine of the separation of powers in South
Africa is investigated. The fact that the judiciary serves as a check on the abuse of
power by other organs of state gives rise to tension in the South African constitutional
state. This tension is not new to South Africa, because the judiciary and the executive
have clashed on several infamous occasions in the past.53 The current state of the
relationship between the judiciary and the other branches of government is analysed
and conclusions are drawn.
The judiciary as a check on the abuse of power by organs of state is addressed and its
effect on the supremacy of the Constitution and strategic litigation is discussed. The
52
53
Chapters 4 to 8 of the Constitution provide for a clear separation of powers between three spheres
of government. Section 43 vests the legislative authority of the Republic of the national sphere in
parliament and of the provincial sphere in the provincial legislatures. Sections 85 and 125 vest the
executive authority of the Republic in the president and of the provinces in the premiers,
respectively. Section 165 vests the judicial authority in the courts.
President Kruger of the old South African Republic clashed with Chief Justice Kotzé in Executors of
McCorkindale v Bok 1884 1 SAR 202; in Harris v Minister of the Interior 1952 (4) SA 769 (A) the
government attempted to remove the coloured voters of the Cape Province from the common
voters‘ role.
15
courts subscribe to a self-imposed culture of deference in judicial review. The question
is asked whether a culture of deference places a constitutional limitation on strategic
litigation and whether a standard of judicial review based on constitutional provisions
and values may be of value.
1.7.4 Chapter 4: The role of the judge in strategic litigation
This chapter augments the debate on the constitutional impact of strategic litigation by
investigating the role of the judge in strategic litigation. To view the Constitutional
Court as a strictly legal institution is to underrate its significance in the South African
political system and its constitutional function. It is a political institution as well, often
judging controversial issues of national policy where the ―setting‖ of the case is political.
The effect of the personal prejudices of judges on decisions of the court is therefore
explored. This relates closely to constitutional interpretation, statutory construction, and
separation of powers.54 In the stratum of strategic litigation, where the impact of the
judgment is far reaching, the effect of the personal prejudice by judges is of special
concern.
The chapter begins with a discussion of the judicial appointment process in South Africa
and investigates the role that politics and transformation play in the process of
appointing judges.
The chief characteristic that distinguishes the courts from the political institutions is
judicial independence: independence from government and from political leadership,
independence from political parties and political fashion, independence from popular
feelings.55 Organs of state, through legislative and other measures, must assist and
protect the courts to ensure the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and
effectiveness of the courts.56 Judicial independence in South Africa is regulated by the
Constitution, the Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994 and a Code of Judicial
54
55
56
Definitions.net.STANDS4LLC Oct. 2014. http://www.definitions.net/definition/judicial activism.
Koopmans Courts and political institutions 250.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
16
Conduct.57 Judicial independence is discussed with reference to the constitutional
provisions guaranteeing the independence of the judiciary.
While judicial independence is objective, judicial impartiality is subjective, because its
realisation is dependent on the judge. Impartiality is that ―quality of open-minded
readiness to persuasion – without unfitting adherence to either party, or to the judge‘s
own predilections, preconceptions and personal views – that is the keystone of a
civilised system of adjudication‖.58 This does not mean absolute neutrality, however,
because judges are human and there is no human being who is not the product of his
or her own social experience, education and human interaction. What is possible and
desirable is impartiality:59
The wisdom required of a judge is to recognize, consciously allow for, and perhaps to
question, all the baggage of past attitudes and sympathies that fellow citizens are free
to carry, untested, to the grave. True impartiality does not require that the judge have
no sympathies or opinions; it requires that the judge nevertheless be free to entertain
and act upon different points of view with an open mind.
When adjudicating, judges are realising legal and social order. The strategic litigant
should have the real and tangible opportunity of pursuing his rights through the courts
with the expectation that the court will adjudicate the matter impartially and fairly and
that the court will come to a reasoned and just decision. This requires impartial judges
that function with skill, efficiency and professionalism, and asks of judges to deliver
judgments that are just, lawful, reasonable and well argued – all principles that are
requirements for a fair trial.
Judicial impartiality is investigated with specific reference to the interpretation of
constitutional rights and values in what is called ―hard cases‖. Attention is paid to how
constitutional interpretation gives rise to the principles of rationality and justice in
strategic litigation, and then an acceptable theory of constitutional interpretation based
on the underlying moral value system of the Constitution is proposed.
57
58
59
Adopted in terms of s 12 of the Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994, published in Government
Gazette No. 35802 of 18 October 2012.
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
705 (CC) para 14.
Canadian Judicial Council: Commentaries on Judicial Conduct (1991) https://www.cjcccm.gc.ca/cmslib/general/news_pub_judicialconduct_Principles_en.pdf 12 accessed December 2015.
17
1.7.5 Chapter 5: Constitutional limitations on strategic litigation
Strategic litigation aims to effect social and political change while avoiding the
traditional field of and vehicles for such change. The wide impact of and consequences
ascribed to such judgments beg the question whether litigational activism through
strategic litigation is desirable in the South African constitutional state. This chapter
examines different examples of strategic litigation and the findings of the courts are
discussed and analysed.
The strategic litigation case studies fall into three broad categories: firstly, that of
strategic litigants who attempt to ―shape‖ societal norms and values by seeking to
change the common or statutory law; secondly, that of strategic litigants who attempt
to influence or change executive policy; and thirdly, that of strategic litigants who
attempt to hold organs of state accountable to the Constitution. The state litigant‘s
compliance with positive constitutional duties is investigated and it is asked whether
organs of state involved in the litigation were model litigants. These examples are
analysed with reference to the findings and conclusions in the previous chapters.
1.7.6 Chapter 6: Conclusion
Finally, this study concludes with chapter 6, entitled Conclusion. It concludes the
research by revisiting the five research objectives.
18
Chapter 2:
Constitutional litigation and the changing face of
civil litigation in South Africa
2.1 Introduction
Scholars disagree about the defining features of public litigation, a term often used to
refer to the diverse proceedings of modern, non-traditional litigation.1 Commentators
refer to this type of litigation with various terms, including public litigation, modern
litigation, post-constitutional litigation and strategic litigation. In this work, the term
strategic litigation is adopted. In references to work of other authors, the terms
employed by them are used.
The term strategic litigation is used consistently in this chapter to refer to the growing
body of lawsuits challenging legislative or executive action, seeking policy changes
within government, seeking to restructure the organisation of public institutions or
exposing corruption.2 A focal point of strategic litigation in this sense is that a
legislature or the executive will always be a party to the proceedings. Although strategic
litigation suits are typically brought following specific violations of constitutional rights,
values or obligations, the primary aim is usually not redress for past damages. Unlike
the traditional plaintiffs in South African common law, strategic litigants use judicial
activism to rectify constitutional violations not easily definable in terms of personal
financial loss or other damages claimable at common law. Although the motives for the
litigation may vary, strategic litigants may seek to reform the institutional structure from
which constitutional violations arose and similar wrongs may arise again. Strategic
litigation therefore allows for individuals, minorities and groups that are politically
marginalised to participate in the political decision-making process.
1
2
Traditional litigation refers to the common-law principles of litigation as defined in Ferreira v Levin
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para 229. Litigation is instituted to claim damages, to correct a wrong or to
obtain relief from another. The traditional cause of action featured a plaintiff with clear and
identifiable rights and a defendant with clear obligations or liabilities. In terms of the common law,
the litigants would pray for a remedy, which would usually involve monetary compensation, and the
effect of the remedy would rarely reach beyond the parties to the case.
In drafting these paragraphs, the work of Fallon 1984 N.Y.U. L. Rev 3-5 was consulted and adapted
to fit South African circumstances.
18
Litigants seek to enforce constitutional principles and values that affect others as
directly as they themselves are affected, and that are valued for moral or political
reasons; economic interests are usually not the interest driving the litigation. Strategic
litigants therefore seek to regulate executive and legislative action in accordance with
the Constitution. The relief claimed aims to restructure the public organisation or
conduct by the legislature and/or executive to eliminate a threat to constitutional
principles and values enshrined in the Constitution or to align unconstitutional conduct
by the executive or the legislature with the Constitution. A study of case law shows,
however, that there are areas where the law of civil procedure inadvertently imposes
constitutional limitations on strategic litigation involving organs of the state.
The South African law of civil procedure underwent great changes since the
commencement of the Constitution. The Constitution changed the structure of courts,
defined the jurisdictional powers of courts regarding constitutional issues and requires
the courts to develop the common law.3 The changes to the common-law concepts of
civil procedure by the adoption of the Constitution profoundly affected litigation in
South Africa.
In this chapter the characteristics of pre-and post-constitutional litigation is
investigated. The advantages and disadvantages of strategic litigation are discussed
with reference to both the primary and secondary advantages and disadvantages of
strategic litigation.
The Bill of Rights may apply to a legal question in different ways. The direct and
indirect application of the Bill of Rights is examined and the application of the principle
of legality and the rule of law is analysed. The principle of justiciability refers to the
types of matter that the courts can adjudicate. If a case is not justiciable, a court
cannot hear the matter. The principle of justiciability is considered by investigating how
standing, mootness and ripeness affect strategic litigation. The jurisdictions of the High
Court, Supreme Court of Appeal and Constitutional Court are also analysed and
discussed.
3
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 1.
19
When a litigant approaches a court, he or she relies on a cause of action to put the
facts of the case before the court. A cause of action is a set of facts giving rise to a
claim recognised in law. The Constitution and the Bill of Rights contain positive rights
that are justiciable if breached or threatened. This could give rise to a parallel system of
law when there are common-law remedies available to a litigant to enforce such a
breach or when legislation has been adopted to give effect to the realisation of these
positive duties. The common law, statutory law and constitutional causes of action
available to litigants are considered and the effect of the parallel system of law on
strategic litigation is determined. The remedies available to rectify failure to meet
constitutional obligations are discussed and the state‘s compliance with court orders is
investigated.
The final section of this chapter examines the constitutional imposition of positive duties
on the state and the state‘s compliance with these duties, as well as the constitutional
remedies available to the courts to hold the state legal representative, the state
instructing agent and the organs of state constitutionally accountable.
2.2 The pre-constitutional and post-constitutional concepts of civil litigation
2.2.1 The pre-constitutional concept of litigation
2.2.1.1 Introduction
Litigation can be described as legal proceedings in a court or a judicial contest between
parties with contesting rights to determine and enforce legal rights. The earliest known
example of a lawsuit is the trial depicted as a series of events on the shield of Achilles
as described in the eighteenth book of the Iliad,4 verses 497-508. The scene describes a
primitive but genuine legal procedure, which is seen as the original source of social
control of private disputes exercised at law.5
According to Wolf, the public administration of justice developed from a prehistoric
habit of settling disputes between individuals by voluntarily dispensing with pursuing
4
5
Attributed to Homer and dated 760–710 BC.
Wolf 1946 Tradition 34.
20
justice personally and resorting to arbitration.6 This tradition was gradually refined into
a system under which the parties were prohibited from taking the law into their own
hands and forced to bring their cases to bodies designated and empowered to hear the
matter and hand down binding judgments. Wolf states that the development of public
authorities hearing cases and handing down judgments was encouraged by the
pressure of public opinion, as well as by the growing power of the rulers. The purpose
of this was to restrain citizens from armed feuds and blood vengeance, and to force
them to seek the decision of rulers who, by virtue of their position and authority, were
competent to hear such matters. When states developed, the jurisdiction of these
authorities passed, after the abolishment of the early monarchy, to the aristocratic city
magistrates and, in democracies, to the popular courts.7
In the modern South African constitutional state, the concept of litigation has developed
on the basis of the traditional common-law principles of claiming for damage wrought,
correcting a wrong or obtaining relief from another. The traditional cause of action
featured a plaintiff with clear and identifiable rights and a defendant with clear
obligations or liabilities. In terms of the common law, the litigants would pray for a
remedy, which would usually involve monetary compensation, and the effect of the
remedy would rarely reach beyond the parties to the case. Since 1994, the South
African Constitution provides the strategic litigant with a basis on which to bring before
a court matters not possible in terms of traditional common law.
2.2.1.2 Pre-constitutional concept of litigation in the United States of America
Chayes states that in the American legal tradition the lawsuit is a vehicle for settling
disputes between private parties about private rights. This predominating influence of
the private-law model can be seen in constitutional litigation, which, from its first
appearance in Marbury v Madison,8 was understood as an outgrowth of the judicial duty
6
7
8
Wolf 1946 Tradition 31.
Wolf 1946 Tradition 32.
Marbury v Madison 5 U.S. 137 1803 was a landmark United States Supreme Court case in which the
Court formed the basis for judicial review in the United States under Article III of the American
Constitution. The decision helped define the boundary between the constitutionally separate
executive and judicial branches of the American form of government.
21
to decide otherwise-existing private disputes.9 Chayes argues that litigation also
performed another important function, namely the clarification of the law to guide
future private actions. This understanding of the legal system, read with the commonlaw doctrine of stare decisis, focused attention on adjudication at the appellate level, for
only there did the process reach beyond the immediate parties to achieve a wider
import through the elaboration of generally applicable legal rules. He then lists the
defining features of what he calls the traditional conception of adjudication:10
(a)
The lawsuit is bipolar. Litigation is organised as a contest between two
individuals or at least two unitary interests, diametrically opposed, to be
decided on a winner-takes-all basis.
(b)
Litigation is retrospective. The controversy is about an identified set of
completed events: whether they occurred and, if so, with what
consequences for the legal relations of the parties.
(c)
Right and remedy are interdependent. The scope of the relief is derived
more or less logically from the substantive violation under the general
theory that the plaintiff will get compensation measured by the harm
caused by the defendant's breach of duty: in contract, by paying plaintiff
the money he would have had in the absence of the breach; in tort
(delict) by paying the value of the damage caused.
(d)
The lawsuit is a self-contained episode. The impact of the judgment is
confined to the parties. If the plaintiff prevails, there is a simple
compensatory transfer, usually of money, but occasionally the return of a
thing or the performance of a definite act. If defendant prevails, a loss lies
where it has fallen. In either case, entry of judgment ends the court's
involvement.
9
10
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1282.
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1282.
22
(e)
The process is party-initiated and party-controlled. The case is organised
and the issues are defined by exchanges between the parties.
Responsibility for fact development is theirs. The trial judge is an objective
arbiter of their interactions who decides questions of law only if they are
put in issue by an appropriate move of a party.
Chayes found that because the immediate impact of the judgment was confined to the
parties, the traditional model was relatively relaxed about the accuracy of its factfinding and that compensatory monetary relief was the usual form of redress.
Chayes‘s theory of litigation is based on the concept of litigation as found in the United
States of America. The traditional South African concept of litigation shows remarkable
similarities to the American model.
2.2.1.3 Concepts of pre-constitutional litigation in South Africa
South Africa subscribes to an adversarial system of law. In an adversarial system,
judges are impartial in ensuring the fair play of the civil process or fundamental justice,
preside over the proceedings and maintain order but does not actively engage with
witnesses. The judge is therefore a neutral arbiter between the parties.
In the South African case of Whittaker,11 the Court found that the purpose of procedural
law is to –
(a)
do justice between the parties;
(b)
to ensure that the proceedings are in place for the purpose of seeing that a
true account of what actually took place in the matter is placed before the
court; and
(c)
to ensure that the matter before the court is so that the court can make a
declaration based on the facts of the case.
11
Whittaker v Roos 1911 TS 1092 para 1102.
23
The proceedings therefore aim to regulate a dispute between the parties to the
litigation and do not involve or interact with other parties. The proceedings are limited
to the facts of the case; no other information or facts are investigated by the court.
In Ferreira v Levin12 O‘Regan J, in a minority judgment, explored the traditional concept
of litigation.13 She stated that the existing common-law rules of standing have
developed in the context of private litigation.14 She accordingly defined the concept of
private litigation as follows:
Generally, private litigation is concerned with the determination of a dispute between
two individuals, in which relief will be specific and, often, retrospective, in that it
applies to a set of past events. Such litigation will generally not directly affect people
who are not parties to the litigation. In such cases, the plaintiff is both the victim of
the harm and the beneficiary of the relief.
This complies with Chayes‘s concept of traditional litigation. The dispute is limited in
scope; the relief is specific and backward-looking and does not affect parties outside
the scope of the litigation.
In Dalrymple v Colonial Treasurer,15 Innes J explained the principle of standing in preconstitutional litigation:16
The general rule of our law is that no man can sue in respect of a wrongful act, unless
it constitutes the breach of a duty owed to him by the wrong-doer, or unless it causes
him some damage in law. This principle runs through the whole of our jurisprudence.
It is not confined merely to the civil side: it is of equal force concerning criminal
procedure. Just as no man can claim damages in a civil action unless he has himself
been injured, so no man may institute a private prosecution unless he has been
specially affected by the crime. Moreover, the rule applies to wrongful acts that affect
the public, as well as to torts committed against private individuals. The acts
complained of in this instance fall within the former category.
From this dictum, it is clear that litigation proceedings are confined to parties with clear
rights in the proceedings. Without a clearly identifiable right, a party will not have the
necessary standing to bring the matter before court. This was confirmed in Roodepoort-
12
13
14
15
16
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC).
Para 229.
The term pre-constitutional or traditional litigation is used in the same context as the concept of
private litigation used by the judge.
1910 TS 372.
Para 379.
24
Maraisburg Town Council v Eastern Properties (Prop) Ltd,17 in which the Court held that
in order to be accorded standing a litigant was required to have ―a direct interest in the
matter and not merely the interest which all citizens have‖.
The pre-constitutional concept of litigation in South Africa therefore reflects the
following characteristics:
(a)
The purpose of litigation is to do justice between the parties.
(b)
The proceedings are in place to see to it that the court has a true account
of what transpired in the matter.
(c)
The matter is before the court so that the court can make a declaration
based on the facts of the case.
(d)
The litigation is concerned with the resolution of a dispute between two
individuals.
(e)
The relief sought will be specific and retrospective, applying to a set of past
events.
(f)
The litigation will generally not directly affect people who are not parties to
the litigation.
(g)
The plaintiff is both the victim of the harm and the beneficiary of the relief.
(h)
A litigant cannot sue in respect of a wrongful act, unless it constitutes the
breach of a duty owed to him by the wrongdoer, or unless it causes him
some damage in law.
(i)
The litigant is required to have a direct interest in the matter and not
merely the interest that all citizens have.
The traditional South African model of litigation is similar to the traditional American
concept of litigation as outlined by Chayes. It is submitted that the traditional model of
17
1933 AD 87, 100.
25
litigation as found in South Africa and the United States is similar across Western
adversarial systems of law.
2.2.2 The post-constitutional concept of litigation
The concept of civil litigation changed over time as more countries subscribed to a
constitutional form of government and the consequent review powers of constitutional
bodies. Nordht states that the post-industrial society of today is characterised in several
respects by social, industrial, commercial and environmental structures, which are
different from those that existed when the legislation in many fields was developed.
Nordht further states that modern society has given rise to new forms of needs and
claims that were previously unknown. He postulates that these new forms of needs and
claims create problems associated with litigation and states that this applies to new as
well as traditional kinds of litigation.18 Although Nordht was writing on procedural-law
changes in Sweden after the Swedish Code of Judicial Procedure was enacted in 1948,19
South Africa finds itself in the same boat. South Africa also experienced significant
procedural-law changes after the adoption of the current constitutional order.
Chayes, writing about the American system of litigation, states that the traditional
model of litigation is no longer compatible with the features of some modern civil
lawsuits. According to him, the private-law theory of civil adjudication became
increasingly problematic in the face of a growing body of legislation designed expressly
to reshape and regulate social and economic affairs. In describing the predominant
attributes of modern litigation, he states that the majority of civil federal lawsuits (in
the United States of America) do not arise out of disputes between private parties
about private rights. Instead, the purpose of such litigation is the affirmation of
constitutional or statutory policies. The change in the legal foundation of the lawsuit
explains many, but not all, facets of what is ―in fact‖ going on in federal trial courts. For
this reason, although the designation is not wholly adequate, Chayes calls this emerging
model ―public law litigation‖. He states that this ―new‖ public law litigation appears in
18
19
Nordht 2001 DJCIL 381.
The Swedish Code of Judicial Procedure was promulgated in 1942 (1942:740) and came into force
on 1 January 1948.
26
most areas of the law where all these fields display, in varying degrees, the features of
public law litigation.20
It is clear from reading Chayes that the object of litigation is shifting from a contest
between two individuals, or at least two unitary interests, diametrically opposed, to
lawsuits challenging constitutional or statutory policy by actors, who in some instances
do not have a clearly identifiable right or action. However, this does not mean that
lawsuits fitting the traditional mould of litigation do not still occur. Lawsuits founded on
delict, contract, labour rules or divorce still reach the courts.
Chayes indicates the difference between the public law litigation model and the
traditional concept of litigation by listing the characteristics of the former:21
(a)
The extent of the lawsuit is not necessarily fixed, but is fashioned primarily
by the court and the parties.
(b)
The party structure is not inflexibly correlative but sprawling and unfixed.
(c)
The fact inquiry is not historical and adjudicative but anticipating and
legislative.
(d)
The relief sought by the parties is not seen as compensation for a past
wrong in a structure logically acquired from the substantive liability and
limited in consequence to the immediate parties; instead, it is forwardlooking, fashioned ad hoc on flexible and broadly remedial lines, often
having important consequences for many persons, including absentees.
(e)
The judgment does not end judicial involvement in the matter: its
administration requires the continuing participation of the court.
(f)
The judge is not passive, his function limited to analysis and statement of
governing legal rules; he is active, with responsibility not only for credible
20
21
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1284-1285.
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1296-1302.
27
fact assessment but also for organising and shaping the litigation to ensure
a just and viable outcome.
(g)
The subject matter of the lawsuit is not a dispute between private
individuals about private rights, but a grievance about the operation of
public policy.
In Chayes‘s ―public litigation‖, – the modern construct of litigation – the traditional
features of the plaintiff and defendant are changing. The conception of litigation as a
mechanism for private dispute settlement only is no longer viable. The same also holds
true for the concept of strategic litigation in constitutional South Africa.
In Ferreira v Levin,22 O‘Regan J investigated the difference between private and public
litigation. She states that in contrast with private litigation, where the plaintiff is both
the victim of the harm and the beneficiary of the relief, in litigation of a public
character, that nexus is rarely so intimate. The relief sought in public litigation is
generally forward-looking and general in its application, so that it may directly affect a
wide range of people. In addition, the harm alleged may often be quite diffuse or
amorphous. She concedes that no clear line can be drawn between private litigation
and litigation of a public or constitutional nature:23
Not all non-constitutional litigation is private in nature. Nor can it be said that all
constitutional challenges involve litigation of a purely public character: a challenge to a
particular administrative act or decision may be of a private rather than a public
character. Nevertheless, it is clear that in litigation of a public character, different
considerations may be appropriate to determine who should have standing to launch
litigation.
Although the concept of litigation was explored with the object of finding whether the
parties to the dispute had the necessary standing to bring the matter before the court,
it still serves a meaningful purpose in distinguishing between the traditional concept of
litigation and strategic litigation.
22
23
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para 229.
Ferreira para 229.
28
In Ngxuza v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape,24 the Court
held as follows:25
The principle of legality implies that public bodies must be kept within their powers.
There should, in general, be no reason why individual harm should be required in
addition to the public interest of the general community. Public law litigation may also
differ from traditional litigation between individuals in a number of respects. A wide
range of persons may be affected by the case. The emphasis will often not only be
backward looking, in the sense of redressing past wrongs, but also forward-looking, to
ensure that the future exercise of public power is in accordance with the principle of
legality.
Another feature of post-constitutional litigation is the positive duties that are placed on
the state as litigant. In terms of section 165(4) of the Constitution, organs of state,
through legislative and other measures, must assist and protect the courts to ensure
the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.
Therefore, organs of state are constitutionally obligated to place all relevant information
in its possession before the courts when litigating. Organs of state must assist the
courts in reaching the most correct decision. Section 195(1) of the Constitution also
requires organs of state to display a high standard of professional ethics when litigating.
Therefore, in strategic litigation, the state must be the model litigant.
South African post-constitutional strategic litigation can therefore be described as
follows:
(a)
In strategic litigation, individual harm is not required for a litigant to have
standing; public interest of the general community would be enough.
(b)
A wide range of persons may be affected by the issues raised in the case.
(c)
The relief required may directly affect a wide range of people with broader
goals than the settling of a dispute between individuals.
(d)
24
25
The harm alleged may often be quite diffuse or unstructured.
2001 (2) SA 609 (E).
Para 619C-D.
29
(e)
The emphasis would often not only be backward-looking, in the sense of
redressing past wrongs, but also forward-looking and general in its
application to ensure that the future exercise of public power is in
accordance with the principle of legality.
(f)
The judge may stay involved in the proceedings after the final order is
granted. Although South African courts have been reluctant to grant
supervisory orders or structural interdicts,26 courts have more recently
granted supervisory orders in several cases.27
(g)
The judge is active, with responsibility not only for credible fact assessment
but also for organising and shaping the litigation to ensure a just and viable
outcome.28
(h)
Constitutional provisions require organs of state to be model litigants.
Post-constitutional litigation may be more ambiguous than private litigation. In private
litigation, the outcome of the judgment is clear, indicating which of the parties has the
strongest right. In post-constitutional litigation, it is often difficult to measure the effect
of the litigation on the protection of constitutional rights.
The description of litigation as provided by the courts in the Ferreira and Ngxuza cases
conforms to the American model of litigation as set out by Chayes. It is clear that the
constitutional era in South Africa wrought great procedural structure changes in
lawsuits. In a growing number of cases, the post-constitutional concept of litigation sets
the tone for strategic litigation, with the litigants able to enforce constitutional rights,
expose corruption and shape and influence government policy. The purpose of this
26
Modderfontein Squatters, Greater Benoni Council v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 2004 (6) SA 40
27
Residents of Joe Slovo Community, Western Cape v Thubelisha Homes 2010 (3) SA 454 (CC); Nyathi
v Department of Health, Gauteng 2008 (5) SA 94 (CC); Sibiya v The Director of Public Prosecutions,
Johannesburg High Court 2005 (5) SA 315 (CC).
Director of Public Prosecutions, Transvaal v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development 2009
(SCA).
28
(4) SA 222 (CC); here the Court called for information as the first step in the supervisory process
and ordered the Director-General of the Department of Justice to submit a report to the Court with
detailed information relating to the matter.
30
activism by litigation is often to enforce a change in, or to influence or direct,
government policy or legislation.
Chayes, in his investigation of public law litigation, finds as follows:29
In public law litigation, then, fact-finding is principally concerned with "legislative"
rather than "adjudicative" fact. In addition, "fact evaluation" is perhaps a more
accurate term than "fact finding." The whole process begins to look like the traditional
description of legislation: Attention is drawn to a "mischief", existing or threatened,
and the activity of the parties and court is directed to the development of on-going
measures designed to cure that mischief. Indeed, if, as is often the case, the decree
sets up an affirmative regime governing the activities in controversy for the indefinite
future and having binding force for persons within its ambit, then it is not very much of
a stretch to see it as, pro tanto, a legislative act.
The traditional model of litigation was primarily concerned with assessing the
consequences for the parties of specific past instances of conduct. This post factum
look is often dispensable in strategic litigation, where the lawsuit generally seeks to
address future or threatened action, or to modify a current course of conduct or a
condition existing at present. The outcome of the litigation then directly affects large
interest groups outside the immediate scope of the litigation with the same
consequence of a legislative act or an executive decision. This gives rise to very
pronounced social and political considerations.
South African courts have a constitutional base that affords them a special status in the
state dispensation. When acting judicially, the courts should not be subject to
government control, and they serve as the final means of ensuring that the
constitutional rights of private persons are upheld and protected in relation to the
state.30 When asking the courts to formulate public policy, litigants are requesting the
courts to adjudicate on matters traditionally falling within the executive and legislative
spheres of government – something the courts may not always be in the best position
to do. Because of its function, constitutional adjudication will always have some flavour
of politics,31 with the judgment of the court affecting a wide range of parties beyond the
29
30
31
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1297.
See also Nordht 2001 DJCIL 86.
In In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC), the
Court found that, admittedly, a constitution, by its very nature, deals with the extent, limitations and
31
original concept of plaintiff and defendant. Because of the far-reaching consequences of
the judgment, the law is often used in this way to produce rapid and comprehensive
social transformation. The notions of the law as a tool to produce social reform is,
however, open to criticism.
2.2.3 Advantages and disadvantages of strategic litigation
2.2.3.1 Disadvantages of strategic litigation
According to Anderson, plans for legally induced social revolutions are often frustrated
at implementation, and when social changes do conform to the planned objectives, they
are mostly ascribed to non-legal causes. He claims that new laws often have
unintended consequences that either nullify the required change or create new
problems for policy makers.32 Little supports this claim and states that the question
most overlooked in the heat of the litigation is where this all will lead to at the end of
the day and, ex ante, whether lawyers, litigants and judges are the actors to create
such change.33
Public interest litigation can be faulted on three grounds: firstly, it is wrong for judges
to authorise social reform in a democracy, and, secondly, courts, because of the fact
that the judiciary is the weakest of the branches of government owing to financial
constraints and political vulnerability, are destined to see their reform efforts defeated. 34
The third objection relates to the fact that decisions affecting social reform influence
executive policy issues, while the courts are not always in a position to decide on the
best options available. The first objection deals with the counter-majoritarian difficulty,
which in South Africa gives way to constitutional provisions allowing courts to test
legislative and executive action against the Constitution.35 The second and third
32
33
34
35
exercise of political power as also with the relationship between political entities and with the
relationship between the state and persons (para 27).
Anderson 1993 Third World Legal Studies 177.
Little 2001 Conn. L. Rev. 178.
Denvir 1975 N.C. L. Rev. 1133.
Section 2 of the Constitution provides that the Constitution is the supreme law of the country and
any law or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid. In terms of s 167 the Constitutional Court is the
final arbiter of constitutional matters. See S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 87, where the
32
objections relate directly to South Africa. Socio-economic development is one of the
main development goals of the government.36 The question should be asked whether
litigants, activists and judges are the right players to drive such goals. The state
allocates the budget for development needs and is in a better position to determine
where the finite resources are most needed. Judgments of the court relating to socioeconomic issues could mean that money allocated for development in one area must be
allocated to the issue raised in the court‘s judgment. Sometimes this may not serve the
best interest of all citizens, especially those who fall outside the scope of the litigation
but are affected by the judgment.
In Soobramoney v Minister of Health (KwaZulu-Natal),37 the appellant needed
immediate regular renal dialysis to prolong his life.38 He sought treatment from the
renal unit of the Addington state hospital in Durban. The hospital could only give
dialysis treatment to a limited number of patients and the applicant was refused
because of the limited facilities that were available. The hospital budget did not make
provision for more expenditure in this regard and no extra funds were available from
the provincial budget.
The appellant approached the High Court,39 claiming that in terms of the Constitution
the Addington Hospital is obliged to make dialysis treatment available to him. His
application was dismissed. The applicant approached the Constitutional Court relying on
sections 27(3) and 11 of the Constitution.40
36
37
38
39
40
Court held that what the majority of South Africans believe to be a proper sentence for murder is
irrelevant. The question the Court had to decide was whether the Constitution allows such sentence.
Majority opinion therefore may have some relevance, but it is no substitute for the duty vested in
the courts to interpret the Constitution and to uphold its provisions without fear or favour.
The
Millennium
Development
Goals
of
South
Africa
2015
http://www.parliament.gov.za/content/MDG%20Report2011_Web.pdf accessed January 2016.
1998 (1) SA 765 (CC).
Paras 1-2.
Thiagraj Soobramoney v Minister of Health: Province of KwaZulu-Natal D&CLD 5846/97, 21 August
1997 (unreported).
Section 27(3) of the Constitution states that no one may be refused emergency medical treatment.
Section 11 stipulates that everyone has the right to life.
33
The respondent stated that the obligations imposed on the state by sections 2641 and
2742 of the Constitution concerning access to housing, health care, food, water and
social security are dependent upon the resources available for such purposes, and that
the corresponding rights themselves are limited owing to the lack of resources.43 Given
this lack of resources and the significant demands on them, an unqualified obligation to
meet these needs is not capable of being fulfilled.
The Court found that although the Constitution imposes positive obligations on the
state, and a generous interpretation must be given to a right to ensure that individuals
secure the full protection of the Bill of Rights, this will not always be the case.44 The
context may indicate that in order to give effect to the purpose of a particular provision
a narrower or specific meaning should be given to it. Therefore, the state has to
manage its limited resources in order to address social issues.45 There will be times
when this requires it to adopt a holistic approach to the larger needs of society rather
than to focus on the specific needs of particular individuals within society.
In a separate and concurring judgment, Madala J found that the fundamental issue is
whether the Court should require a health authority to adopt a course of treatment,
which in the judgement of the practitioner will not cure the patient but merely prolong
his life for some time.46 He held that the Court could not.
Sachs J attempted to justify the decision of the Court by stating that section 27 should
be construed to read that it provides for unexpected accidents and that emergency
departments will be available to deal with the unforeseeable catastrophes that could
41
42
43
44
45
46
Housing: (1) Everyone has the right to have access to adequate housing. (2) The state must take
reasonable legislative and other measures, within its available resources, to achieve the progressive
realisation of this right.
Health care, food, water and social security: (1) Everyone has the right to have access to: (a) health
care services, including reproductive health care; (b) sufficient food and water; and (c) social
security, including, if they are unable to support themselves and their dependants, appropriate social
assistance. (2) The state must take reasonable legislative and other measures, within its available
resources, to achieve the progressive realisation of each of these rights. (3) No one may be refused
emergency medical treatment.
Para 11.
Paras 16-17.
Para 31.
Para 45.
34
befall any person, anywhere and at any time.47 The applicant therefore does not qualify
because his condition, although life-threatening, does not fit those criteria. Sachs J
referred to Canadian jurisprudence,48 and found as follows:
The inescapable fact is that if governments were unable to confer any benefit on any
person unless it conferred an identical benefit on all, the only viable option would be to
confer no benefit on anybody.
In the light of the need for equality expressed in the Constitution,49 this view cannot be
supported. The provisions contained in the Bill of Rights are available to all citizens of
South Africa on an equal basis.50
Sachs further argued that the provisions of the Bill of Rights should not be interpreted
in a way that results in courts feeling themselves unduly pressurised by the fear of
gambling with the lives of claimants into ordering hospitals to furnish the most
expensive and improbable procedures, thereby diverting scarce medical resources and
prejudicing the claims of others.51 This argument cannot be supported either. The
applicant approached the Court in terms of constitutional provisions, which he felt had
been breached. In such circumstances, the applicant has a constitutional right to
approach the courts,52 no matter how unpleasant it would be for the court to hear such
matters.
In Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom,53 the respondents had
been evicted from their informal houses situated on private land earmarked for formal
low-cost housing development. They applied to the High Court for an order requiring
the government to provide them with adequate basic shelter or housing until they
obtained permanent accommodation.54
47
Para 51.
48
Brown v British Columbia (Minister of Health) (1990) 48 CRR 137 paras 157-158.
Section 1(a) and s 3(2)(a) of the Constitution.
See also Wesson 2004 SAJHR 293.
Para 58.
Section 38 of the Constitution provides that everyone can approach a competent court with the
allegation that a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened.
2001 (1) SA 46 (CC).
Paras 3-4.
49
50
51
52
53
54
35
The High Court held that, in terms of the Constitution, the state was obliged to provide
children and their parents with rudimentary shelter on demand if the parents were
unable to shelter their children; that this obligation existed independently of, and in
addition to, the obligation to take reasonable legislative and other measures in terms of
the Constitution; and that the state was bound to provide this rudimentary shelter
irrespective of the availability of resources. The respondents in the High Court case
were accordingly ordered by that Court to provide those among respondents who were
children, as well as their parents, with shelter.
The appellants appealed against this decision. The respondents based their claim on
two constitutional provisions:55 firstly, on section 26 of the Constitution, which provides
that everyone has the right to have access to adequate housing, with subsection (2)
imposing an obligation on the state to take reasonable legislative and other measures
to ensure the progressive realisation of this right within its available resources, and,
secondly, on section 28(1)(c) of the Constitution, which provides that children have the
right to shelter.
The Court held that section 7(2) of the Constitution requires the state ―to respect,
protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights‖ and the courts are
constitutionally bound to ensure that they are protected and fulfilled. 56 The question is
therefore not whether socio-economic rights are justiciable under the Constitution, but
how to enforce them in a given case. The Court refused to issue an order placing a
minimum core obligation on the state in respect of social rights. 57 The Court held that,
although it may be possible to do so, sufficient information have not been placed before
the Court to determine what would comprise the minimum core obligation in the
context of the Constitution.
Referring to section 27(2) of the Constitution, the Court held that the section requires
the state to devise a comprehensive and workable plan to meet its obligations in terms
55
56
57
Para 13.
Para 20.
Para 33.
36
of the subsection.58 However, subsection (2) also makes it clear that the obligation
imposed on the state is not an absolute or unqualified one. The extent of the state‘s
obligation is defined by three key elements that are considered separately: (a) the
obligation to ―take reasonable legislative and other measures‖; (b) ―to achieve the
progressive realisation‖ of the right; and (c) ―within available resources‖.
The Court stated that in the realisation of the positive obligation the Constitution places
on the state, the state must implement measures to ensure the realisation of those
rights.59 The measures must establish a coherent public housing programme directed
towards the progressive realisation of the right of access to adequate housing within
the state‘s available means. The programme must be capable of facilitating the
realisation of the right. The precise contours and content of the measures to be
adopted are primarily a matter for the legislature and the executive. However, they
must ensure that the measures they adopt are reasonable. The reasonableness of the
measures put in place by the state will be evaluated by the courts on a case-to-case
basis.
The Court stated the following:60
I am conscious that it is an extremely difficult task for the state to meet these
obligations in the conditions that prevail in our country. This is recognised by the
Constitution, which expressly provides that the state is not obliged to go beyond
available resources or to realise these rights immediately. I stress however, that
despite all these qualifications, these are rights, and the Constitution obliges the state
to give effect to them. This is an obligation that courts can, and in appropriate
circumstances, must enforce.
The Court therefore held that the programme that had been adopted, and was in force
in the Cape Metro at the time that the application was brought; fell short of the
obligations imposed upon the state by section 26(2) in that it failed to provide for any
form of relief to those desperately in need of access to housing.61
58
59
60
61
Para
Para
Para
Para
38.
41.
94.
95.
37
The Court issued a declaratory order stipulating that section 26(2) of the Constitution
required the state to act to meet the obligation imposed upon it to devise and
implement a comprehensive and coordinated programme to realise progressively the
right of access to adequate housing.62 This included the obligation to devise, fund,
implement and supervise measures to provide relief to those in desperate need within
its available resources. The Court confirmed that section 7(2) of the Constitution
mandates the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights,
including housing rights. The Court indicated that the measures adopted must establish
a coherent public housing programme, directed towards the progressive realisation of
the right of access to adequate housing within the state‘s available resources.
The Court noted that ―legislative measures will invariably have to be supported by
appropriate, well-directed policies and programmes implemented by the executive‖. The
Court therefore instructed the government to comply with its constitutional obligation,
but left the realisation of this obligation up to the state.
For Sunstein, the outcome of Grootboom meant that the South African government is
required to pay close attention to the human interests at stake and to sensible priority
setting, without mandating protection for each person whose socio-economic needs are
at risk. The virtue of this approach by the Court is that it is respectful of democratic
prerogatives and of the limited nature of public resources, while also requiring special
deliberative attention to those whose minimal needs are not being met.63
In Grootboom, the Court recognised that circumstances exist in which the plight of
people are so desperate that the courts must interfere with the prerogative of the
executive and the legislature to ensure the enforcement of constitutional provisions
relating to socio-economic rights. However, the Court clearly interpreted the rights in
the Constitution as not absolute. In Soobramoney, the situation of the applicant was
even worse than that of the applicants in Grootboom. However, the principle of nonabsolute constitutional rights was applied and the applicant was denied relief, although
62
63
Para 96.
Sunstein 2001 Constitutional Forum 123.
38
his need was pressing. It has to be asked, however, whether the applicants in
Grootboom were offered real relief by the Court.
The decision in Grootboom laid the foundation for the future adjudication of socioeconomic rights.64 Roux argues, however, that the decision of the Court was not priority
setting. In fact, the Court‘s reluctance to engage in priority setting in the strict sense
affected the nature of the order made. Therefore, rather than setting priorities, the
Court in Grootboom simply expressed a view on what could not reasonably be left out
of the housing program.65
Both Sunstein and Roux are, to a certain extent, correct in their arguments. In the
Grootboom-case, the Court held the state to account for its failure to realise the
obligations imposed on it in terms of the Constitution. However, although the Court
ordered the state to amend its housing programme to make provision for those in need,
it left the realisation of the consequent obligation to the state. It set no timetable for
the accomplishment of its order, although it acknowledged the desperate circumstances
of the applicants. In fact, the Court subscribed to and acknowledged one of the
disadvantages of strategic litigation referred to above, namely that the courts are not
always in a position to decide what the best options available are and that some
decision-making should be left to other organs of state. This means that the courts will
not make orders that interfere with the budgetary allocations of the other organs of
state, as was the case in Grootboom and Soobramoney. What is of further interest in
Grootboom and Soobramoney is the approach of the state litigants to the litigation. In
both cases, the organs of state fulfilled their constitutional duties to place relevant
information before the courts66 and conducted the litigation honestly and fairly.67 In
both cases the state litigants were model litigants.
64
65
66
67
Wesson 2004 SAJHR 1-2; Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC);
Khosa v Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); and Rail Commuters Action Group v
Transnet 2005 (2) SA 359 (CC).
Roux 2002 Forum Constitutionnel 46-47.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution that requires that organs of state must assist and protect the
courts to ensure the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
39
South African courts are not constitutionally mandated to initiate proceedings in order
to bring matters before the court.68 Courts and judges have to wait until appropriate
proceedings are initiated by a party before the court can adjudicate on executive or
legislative action. Courts are therefore powerless to enforce the Constitution without a
case being brought before it, even in the face of flagrant constitutional violations by
other branches of government. The courts cannot order a person to stand trial or tell
the executive or the legislature to charge a person even if the court found that that
person exceeded his or her power or was corrupt.69
2.2.3.2 Advantages of strategic litigation
Chayes argues that there are various reasons why the judiciary may have some
important institutional advantages in the tasks it is assuming in public interest
litigation.70 A judge‘s professional tradition insulates him from political pressures and
most judges are likely to have experience of the political process and public policy
problems. Judges are also able to make difficult or unpopular decisions that politicians
are unable or unwilling to make because of electoral pressure. Justice Harms uses the
example of the abolition of the death penalty in South Africa, which the executive left to
the courts. Politicians could then hide behind the judgment of the Constitutional Court,
which declared it unconstitutional, if the matter became unpopular in public opinion.71
Chayes states that the public-law model permits ad hoc applications of broad national
policy in situations of limited scope. The courts can flexibly tailor the judgment to the
needs of the particular situation. This conforms to the Court‘s decision in Grootboom,72
where the Court stated that the reasonableness of the measures put in place by the
executive to effect the realisation of the particular constitutional provisions would be
evaluated and tested on a case-by-case basis and, if necessary, adapted by the courts
to suit specific situations.
68
69
70
71
72
This is in contrast with the extensive original jurisdiction of the Indian Supreme Court in terms of
Article 32 of the Constitution of India, 1950.
Shaik v The State (1) [2006] SCA 134 (RSA).
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review 1307-1309.
Harms 2009 PELJ 7.
Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 41.
40
According to Chayes, the public-law model also permits a high degree of participation
by representatives of those who will be directly affected by the decision. It is submitted
that the South African Constitution already allows for participation of members of the
public in the legislative process.73 In such instances, the legislator may receive a higher
degree of participation in its proceedings than when the matter is heard by the courts.
The Constitution does not allow for participation by members of the public in the
executive sphere, but the courts may be approached for review of executive action. The
danger remains that the court will not hear the view of the full spectrum of people that
could be affected by its decision. Section 38(c) allows class action lawsuits to be
brought. In the certification of class action lawsuits, the courts have to determine if the
people who would be affected by the court judgment are sufficiently represented to
allow them to air their views.74
The requirements for standing are discussed more fully in section 4.2.2 below. It is
submitted that Chayes's statement about representation in the public law model is also
applicable in South Africa.
Chayes argues that the courts have an advantage in gathering and assessing
information. He states that there is a strong incentive for parties before the court
proceedings to furnish information during litigation. In South Africa, this statement is
even more relevant because of the fact that amici curiae are allowed to join
proceedings and present evidence to allow the courts to make decisions. According to
Chayes, because of the limited scope of the proceedings, the information required can
be effectively focused and specified. Moreover, the information that is produced will not
be filtered through the rigid structures and preconceptions of bureaucracies.
Chayes states that, unlike other organs of state, the judiciary must respond to
complaints of the aggrieved. The legislature and the executive can and do address
specific situations, but only from a position of commitment to particular policy interests.
73
74
Sections 59 and 118 of the Constitution.
In Ferreira v Levin; Vryenhoek v Powell 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para 235, the Court held that the
certification of a class action lawsuit will depend on the range of persons who may be affected by
any order made by the court and the opportunity that those persons have had to present evidence
and argument to the court.
41
The executive and the legislature are composed of members of political parties and
therefore there is a danger that the focus of policy would be on the interest of their
supporters.
In
South
Africa,
bureaucratic
inefficiency
has
reached
epidemic
proportions.75 In some instances this leaves the judiciary as the only recourse for
aggrieved parties to turn to in order to enforce constitutional rights that have been
breached or threatened.
It is submitted that the structural institutional advantages of the judiciary to adjudicate
on strategic litigation allow the courts to play an important role in shaping social justice
in South Africa. However, strategic litigation can only be effective if the state, as party
to the litigation, upholds its constitutional duty to assist and ensure the effectiveness of
the courts.76 This constitutional obligation requires of an organ of state to place all
relevant information available to it before the court and further requires the organ of
state not to abuse the legal process. The constitutional duty of organs of state to act
fairly in litigation, in other words, to be the model litigant, will be discussed in section
2.8 and the final chapter of this work.
Denvir argues that there are secondary uses of litigation that influence its effectiveness.
Public-interest litigation takes place in a political context and when properly designed
will have an immediate and long-term impact on political actors. He then lists two
advantages of public-interest litigation:77
First, and especially in the short run, litigation creates pressures on bureaucratic
administrators that cause them to take actions that otherwise would not be taken.
Secondly, in the longer run, the facts and value judgments reflected in court decisions
help change the perceptions of what administrators, legislators, judges, and the public
believe to be proper or legitimate.
According to Denvir litigation is often the only means available to keep large
bureaucracies receptive to the lawful demands of the public they are to serve. 78
Litigation would not be necessary in every case; bureaucracies will always attempt to
keep themselves from being monitored by other agencies, such as the courts. The
75
76
77
78
Amit 2011 SAJHR 20-23 and Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 209.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Denvir 1975 N.C. L. Rev. 1134-1135.
Denvir 1975 N.C. L. Rev. 1136-1138.
42
threat of a credible court challenge is a sufficient deterrent against engaging in illegal
action. Lawsuits, or the threat thereof, then serves as deterrence to illegal conduct by
state departments. Denvir also links the deterrence factor to the publicity that strategic
litigation generates. The decisions of government departments often have little visibility,
despite their far-reaching effects, and as a result escape public notice. Filing lawsuits
encourages media coverage, which focuses public attention on actions that often are
both morally and politically indefensible. The litigation then creates new forums for the
public to express its views, so forcing the agency to accept more input.
Denvir also describes the delaying function of public litigation as another socially
beneficial advantage of legal activism.79 Two important functions are performed here.
Firstly, notice is served on the government department of the intensity of the opposition
to the project. Secondly, the delay resulting from a lawsuit provides the necessary time
delay in which interested groups are able to organise opposition on the political front.
Strategic litigation plays an effective and necessary part in the South African
constitutional landscape. The institutional advantages of the courts allow them to make
decisions that other organs of state are not always able to make. The secondary effects
of strategic litigation must also be kept in mind. The final judgment should not be the
only concern or strategy for the strategic litigant. It is submitted that the ripple effects
of the litigation often hold more benefits than the judgment. The court case may
generate awareness among the public about the issues raised by the litigation. This
allows the public to put pressure on the elected representatives to correct constitutional
violations. The controversy raised by gross constitutional violations might also be
enough to ensure that members of the executive or legislature responsible for such
violations are not re-elected in the next election.
2.3 Strategic litigation within the framework of the South African
Constitution
79
Denvir 1975 N.C. L. Rev. 1142.
43
2.3.1 Introduction
A litigant may approach the courts in terms of section 3880 of the Constitution if a right
in the Bill of Rights has been breached or threatened. Such litigant will rely on a direct
application of the Constitution to enforce the breached or threatened right. However, a
litigant may also approach the court relying on an indirect application of the Bill of
Rights. Section 39(2) provides that a court, when interpreting legislation and developing
the common law or customary law, must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the
Bill of Rights. According to Currie and De Waal, the Constitution and the Bill of Rights
therefore establish an objective normative system. The normative system consists of
values that must be respected whenever the common law or legislation is interpreted,
developed or applied.81 This vertical application of the Bill of Rights performs the task of
protecting individuals against the state by imposing a duty on all state institutions to
respect the provisions of the Bill of Rights.82
The infringement of a fundamental right does not provide the only basis on which the
courts may be approached in terms of the Constitution. Section 33 of the Constitution
provides for administrative action that is lawful, reasonable and procedurally fair, and
obliges the decision-maker to give reasons for a decision to everyone whose rights have
been adversely affected by the administrative action. This opens the way for judicial
review of administrative action.83
Section 33 also embodies the principle of legality. Hoexter writes that the principle of
legality goes beyond administrative action. It refers to a broad constitutional principle of
legality that governs the use of all public power rather than the traditionally narrower
realm of administrative action. The principle of legality is an aspect of the rule of law,
80
81
82
83
Section 38 deals with the enforcement of rights and provides that anyone listed in the section has
the right to approach a competent court, alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed
or threatened.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 32.
Section 8(1) of the Constitution provides that the Bill of Rights binds the legislature, the executive,
the judiciary and all organs of state.
Hoexter Administrative Law 114.
44
which is a founding value84 of the Constitution. This principle requires the holder of
public power to act in good faith and exercise power legally.85
2.3.2 Direct and indirect application of the Bill of Rights
According to Woolman, the unqualified and direct application of the Bill of Rights stems
from the interaction of two axioms. Firstly, the state constructs and enforces all law, no
matter what form it takes. Secondly, legislation, subordinate legislation, common law
and customary law shape relationships between the state and its citizens, as well as
relationships between individuals. This means that because the state constructs and
enforces all laws, all laws should be measured against constitutional standards.86
In terms of section 8 of the Constitution, the Bill of Rights applies to all law, and binds
the legislature, the executive, the judiciary and all organs of state. When interpreting
the Bill of Rights, a court must promote the values that underlie an open and
democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom. 87 When interpreting
any legislation, and when developing the common law or customary law, every court
must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.88 This distinguishes
two forms of application of the Bill of Rights. According to Currie and De Waal, direct
application entails the imposition of duties by the Bill of Rights on specified actors; a
breach of such a duty is a violation of a constitutional right. They write that the indirect
application of the Bill of Rights occurs where there is a provision of the ordinary law
that mediates between the Bill of Rights and the actors who are subject to that law.
Then it is the court‘s duty to ensure that the ordinary law conforms to the Bill of
Rights.89
According to Currie and De Waal, the Bill of Rights applies directly to a legal dispute–
84
85
86
87
88
89
In terms of s 1(c) of the Constitution South Africa is founded on the supremacy of the constitution
and the rule of law.
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 2000 (1) SA 1 (CC)
para 148 and Hoexter Administrative Law 116-117.
Woolman ―Application‖ 31-32.
Section 39(1)(a) of the Constitution.
Section 39(2) of the Constitution.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 32.
45
(a)
when a right of a beneficiary of the Bill of Rights has been infringed by a
person or entity on whom the Bill of Rights has placed a duty not to
infringe the right;
(b)
during the period of operation of the Bill of Rights; and
(c)
in the national territory.
Within this area of application, the Bill of Rights overrides ordinary law and conduct that
are inconsistent with it. Currie and De Waal explain that in this context, direct
application entails the imposition of duties by the Bill of Rights on specified actors; a
breach of such a duty is a violation of a constitutional right.90
The Bill of Rights applies directly to state institutions in the following instances:91
(a)
To the common law and to legislation of the central, provincial and local
government legislatures, as well as to non-legislative conduct of these
legislatures;
(b)
to administrative action, which, in addition, must comply with the criteria
listed in the right to just administrative action in section 33 92 of the
Constitution and in the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act (PAJA);93
(c)
to the conduct of organs of state as defined in section 239 of the
Constitution;94
(d)
to the conduct of the executive; and
(e)
to non-law-making conduct of the judiciary.
Currie and De Waal state that the indirect application of the Bill of Rights means that
the influence of the Bill of Rights is mediated through statutory or common law,
90
91
92
93
94
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 35.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 49-50.
The right to just administrative action.
3 of 2000.
Section 239 defines the meaning of ―organ of state‖.
46
because all law must be developed, interpreted and applied in a way that conforms to
the Bill of Rights.95 When applied indirectly, the Bill of Rights does not override ordinary
law, nor does it generate its own remedies. Instead, law is interpreted or developed in
such a way that it conforms to the Constitution.96 They continue by stating that the Bill
of Rights respects the procedural rules, the purpose and the remedies of ordinary law,
but demands the furtherance of its values through the operation of ordinary law. 97 This
is called the principle of avoidance.
The principle of avoidance requires a court first to try to resolve a dispute by applying
ordinary legal principles, as interpreted or developed with reference to the Bill of Rights,
before applying the Bill of Rights directly to the dispute.98 According to Currie and De
Waal, an important implication of the principle of avoidance is that the special rules in
the Bill of Rights relating to the standing of litigants and the jurisdiction of the courts
apply only when it is impossible to give effect to the values in the Bill of Rights by
applying the ordinary law. Similarly, constitutional remedies are only relevant when the
Bill of Rights is applied directly to an issue. If it is possible to resolve the dispute
through indirect application, ordinary procedural rules and remedies apply to the
dispute.99
The Bill of Rights applies to all laws, including pre- and post-constitutional legislation
and the uncodified common law. This means that there is only one system of law. This
system of law is shaped by the Constitution, which is the supreme law, and all law,
including the common law, derives its force from the Constitution and is subject to
constitutional control.100
95
96
97
98
99
100
Section 39(2) of the Constitution reads as follows: ―When interpreting any legislation, and when
developing the common law or customary law, every court, tribunal or forum must promote the
spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.‖
Batchelor v Gabie 1999 2 ALL SA 65 (C).
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 64-65.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 75.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 77.
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa: In re Ex Parte President of the Republic
of South Africa 2000 (2) SA 674 para 44 and Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 34.
47
In NEHAWU v University of Cape Town,101 the National Education Health & Allied
Workers Union (NEHAWU) contended that the interpretation of section 197102 of the
Labour Relations Act103 (LRA) adopted by the majority of the Labour Appeal Court (LAC)
infringed the right of the workers to fair labour practices conferred by section 23(1) of
the Constitution.104 NEHAWU also raised the contention that the interpretation of section
197 adopted by the majority of the LAC fails to promote the spirit, purport and objects
of the Bill of Rights.105
The Court held that the LRA was enacted ―to give effect to and regulate the
fundamental rights conferred by the Constitution‖. In doing so, the LRA gives content to
section 23 of the Constitution and must therefore be construed and applied consistently
with that purpose.106 Section 3(b)107 of the LRA underscores this by requiring that the
provisions of the LRA be interpreted ―in compliance with the Constitution‖. Therefore,
the proper interpretation and application of the LRA will raise a constitutional issue. This
is because the legislature is under an obligation to ―respect, protect, promote and fulfil
the rights in the Bill of Rights‖.108
The respondents contended that where one is dealing with a statute that gives effect to
fundamental rights guaranteed in the Constitution, the only constitutional matter that
may arise relates to the constitutionality of its provisions.109 The Court rejected this
argument as follows:
This contention has no merit. In relation to a statute, a constitutional matter may arise
either because the constitutionality of its interpretation or its application is in issue or
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
2003 (3) SA 1 (CC).
In terms of this section, when a business is transferred to a new owner as a going concern, the new
employer is automatically substituted in the place of the old employer in respect of all contracts of
employment in existence immediately before the date of transfer, and all the rights and obligations
between the old employer and an employee at the time of the transfer continue in force as if they
had been rights and obligations between the new employer and the employee.
66 of 1995.
Section 23(1) provides that everyone has the right to fair labour practices.
NEHAWU para 13.
Para 14.
The section provides that any person applying the Act ―must interpret its provisions … in compliance
with the Constitution‖.
Section 7(2) of the Constitution provides that ―the state must respect, protect, promote and fulfil the
rights in the Bill of Rights‖.
NEHAWU para 15.
48
because the constitutionality of the statute itself is in issue. A challenge to the manner
in which the statute has been interpreted or applied does not require the litigant to
challenge the constitutionality of the provision the construction of which is in issue.
Moreover, in the case of a statute such as the one in issue in this application, which
has been enacted to give content to a constitutional right, the proper interpretation of
the statute itself is itself a constitutional matter.
The case did not require the Court to go beyond the regulatory framework established
by the LRA; the Court had to find whether the interpretation of the statute conformed
with the constitutional provisions giving rise to it. The Court argued as follows:110
In many cases, constitutional rights can only effectively be honoured if legislation is
enacted. Such legislation will of course always be subject to constitutional scrutiny to
ensure that it is not inconsistent with the Constitution. Where the legislature enacts
legislation in the effort to meet its constitutional obligations, and does so within
constitutional limits, courts must give full effect to the legislative purpose. Moreover,
the proper interpretation of such legislation will ensure the protection, promotion and
fulfilment of constitutional rights and as such will be a constitutional matter. In this
way, the courts and the legislature act in partnership to give life to constitutional
rights.
Although the state was not a party to this case, it is important for this study because
the Court distinguished between the application of the Bill of Rights to legal rules and
its application to the actions of organs of state and private institutions executed in
terms of those legal rules. The Court further distinguished between the constitutionality
of a legal norm and the constitutionality of the application of that norm. In a particular
case, only the constitutionality of the legal rules or only the action performed in terms
of a constitutionally valid legal rule may be questioned.
Indirect application occurs when there is a provision of ordinary law that mediates
between the Bill of Rights and the actors who are subject to that law. The duty then
rests on the courts to ensure that the ordinary law conforms to the Bill of Rights in the
rights and duties it confers.111 Therefore, instead of the Bill of Rights directly imposing
duties and conferring rights, rights and duties are imposed by the common law or
legislation.112 In principle, a legal dispute should be decided in terms of the existing
110
111
112
NEHAWU para 14.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 35.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 43.
49
legal rules or principles of ordinary law prior to any direct application of the Bill of
Rights.
2.3.3 Just administrative action and the rule of law
According to Woolman and Bishop, the rule of law is a fundamental principle of any
constitutional democracy. In its most basic form –113
[i]t reflects, in Thomas Jefferson‘s well-turned phrase, the idea that a free people
should have a government of law, not men. That is, all actors, the governors and the
governed, are bound by the same set of rules. Legality, an earlier incarnation of the
rule of law doctrine, requires that any act, which does not comply with the law and the
Final Constitution, must be found invalid.
Michelman states that the rule of law and the legality doctrine, married to various other
constitutional injunctions – for example the requirement of section 39(2) to interpret
statutes and to develop the common law in the light of constitutional dictates – have
the potential to turn legal disputes into constitutional matters. As a result, ―no case, as
a matter of logic, falls beyond the jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court‖.114
The rule of law is invoked in constitutional jurisprudence not only as a pervasive value
that informs the interpretation of many other rights, but also as a self-standing
justifiable and enforceable claim.115 Fundamental to the rule of law is the notion that
government acts in a rational rather than an arbitrary manner.116
In Prinsloo v Van der Linde,117 the Court described this as follows:
[T]he constitutional state is expected to act in a rational manner. It should not regulate
in an arbitrary manner or manifest naked preferences that serve no legitimate
governmental purpose, for that would be inconsistent with the rule of law and the
fundamental premises of the constitutional state. This has been said to promote the
need for governmental action to relate to a defensible vision of the public good, as well
as to enhance the coherence and integrity of legislation. In Mureinik‘s celebrated
113
114
115
116
117
Woolman and Bishop Constitutional Conversations 7.
Michelman ―Constitutional supremacy‖ 56-61.
Michelman ―The rule of law‖ 11-12.
Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South A frica 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) para 100.
1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC) para 25.
50
formulation, the new constitutional order constitutes a bridge away from a culture of
authority to a culture of justification.118
The Constitution therefore requires that all legislation be rationally related to a
legitimate government purpose. If not, it is inconsistent with the rule of law and
invalid.119 Therefore, the exercise of all public power must be authorised by law.
In Democratic Alliance v Ethekwini Municipality,120 the Supreme Court of Appeal
remarked that the act of a municipality in changing street names was executive action.
Although not administrative action, it nevertheless was not immune from judicial
review. The Supreme Court of Appeal found that –121
[t]he fundamental principle, deriving from the rule of law itself, is that the exercise of
all public power, be it legislative, executive or administrative — is only legitimate when
lawful … . This tenet of constitutional law which admits of no exception, has become
known as the principle of legality … .
In the Fedsure Life Assurance-case,122 the Court found that the fundamental idea that
the principle of legality expresses is that the exercise of all public power is only
legitimate where lawful. Therefore, when a legislature, whether national, provincial or
local, exercises the power to raise taxes or rates, or determines appropriations to be
made out of public funds, it is exercising a power that under the Constitution is a power
peculiar to elected legislative bodies.
This power is exercised by democratically elected representatives after due deliberation.
The Court clearly stated that in this instance the power exercised by the legislature did
not constitute an administrative decision.123 The Court found that the question then to
be considered is the extent of the constitutional controls on the exercise of the powers
118
119
120
121
122
123
Mureinik 1986 SAJHR 32.
United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of South Africa (2) 2003 (1) SA 495 (CC)
para 55.
2012 (2) SA 151 (SCA).
Para 21.
Fedsure Life Assurance v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council 1999 (1) SA 374.
Para 45.
51
of local government legislatures. The Court held that a local government might only act
within the powers lawfully conferred upon it and found:124
There is nothing startling in this proposition – it is a fundamental principle of the rule
of law,125 recognised widely, that the exercise of public power is only legitimate where
lawful. The rule of law – to the extent at least that it expresses this principle of legality
– is generally understood to be a fundamental principle of constitutional law.
According to the Court, it is central to the conception of our constitutional order that
the legislature and executive in every sphere are constrained by the principle that they
may exercise no power and perform no function beyond that conferred upon them by
law.126
In Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa,127 the Court had to deal
with the issue of the role of the courts in controlling public power. It raised the question
whether a court has the power to review and set aside a decision by the President to
bring an Act of Parliament into force.128 The matter arose when the Transvaal High
Court was requested to review and set aside the President‘s decision to bring the South
African Medicines and Medical Devices Regulatory Authority Act, 1998, into operation.
The Court held that the exercise of all public power must comply with the Constitution,
which is the supreme law, and the doctrine of legality which is part of that law.129 The
Court further held that ultimately, all public power, whether exercised by the legislative,
executive or judiciary, is controlled by the Constitution.130
The Court noted the ―reluctance‖ of courts in other countries to review decisions of this
nature because of the political nature of the judgment required and its closeness to
124
125
126
Paras 55-56.
The Court referred to Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution 193, in which
Dicey refers to this aspect of the rule of law in the following terms: ―We mean in the second place,
when we speak of the ‗rule of law‘ as a characteristic of our country, not only that with us no man is
above the law, but (what is a different thing) that here every man, whatever be his rank or
condition, is subject to the ordinary law of the realm and amenable to the jurisdiction of the ordinary
tribunals.‖
Para 58 of the Fedsure case.
127
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA in Re: The Ex Parte Application of the President of
the Republic of South Africa 2000 (2) SA 674.
128
Para 1.
Para 19.
Para 20.
129
130
52
legislative powers.131 The Court held that the power was not ―administrative action‖ as
contemplated in the administrative justice clause in the Bill of Rights, and therefore did
not fall within the controls of public power set out in that clause.132 Rather, it was a
power of a special nature, the character of which is neither legislative nor
administrative although it is more closely linked to the legislative than the
administrative function. However, the exercise of such a power is not beyond the reach
of judicial review, because the exercise of all power must conform with the Constitution,
and, in particular, the requirements of the rule of law: a foundational principle in the
Constitution.133
The Court held that this includes the requirement that a decision, viewed objectively,
must be rationally related to the purpose for which the power was given. 134 Thus, even
if the President acts in good faith, his decision may be invalid if it does not meet this
objective requirement.135 This does not mean that a court can interfere with a decision
simply because it disagrees with it or considers that the power was exercised
inappropriately. The Court must find that the decision taken by the President was
objectively irrational and therefore unlawful.
The Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012 expanded the jurisdiction of the
Constitutional Court. The Court may now hear any matter, if it grants leave to appeal
because the matter raises an arguable point of law of general public importance that
ought to be considered by it.
The strategic litigant can therefore rely on the Constitution to approach the courts in
the following circumstances:
(a)
When there is direct application of the Bill of Rights in terms of section 8(2)
of the Constitution.
131
132
133
134
135
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
70.
45.
79.
85.
90.
53
(b)
When there is an indirect application of the Bill of Rights in terms of section
39(2) of the Constitution. In this instance, the common-law principles and
remedies or statutory law will stand and the court can rule on the
constitutionality or interpretation of the provisions.
(c)
In terms of section 33 of the Constitution a claim should be brought in
terms of PAJA when the matter relates to administrative action only,,
except if the question relates to the interpretation of the Act by
functionaries or the constitutionality of its provisions.
(d)
In terms of section 33 of the Constitution, if a decision or act by the
executive relates to the legality principle and the rule of law, and such a
decision or act is not an administrative action as defined in PAJA.
The application of the Constitution is not the only question the litigant should
contemplate before an action is brought before the courts. The principle of justiciability
should be considered. Justiciability refers to the question of jurisdiction, standing and
the timing of the case.
2.4 Justiciability and strategic litigation
2.4.1 Introduction
The courts will not hear every constitutional argument raised by litigants. According to
Currie and De Waal, the limitations on the constitutional issues that the courts will hear
are governed by jurisdiction and justiciability. Justiciability encompasses three
considerations: standing, which relates to the relationship between the applicant and
the relief sought, ripeness and mootness, which relate to the timing of the
application.136 Strategic litigants must ensure that the legal rules relating to these
considerations are fully understood before embarking on litigation.
136
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 79.
54
2.4.2 Standing
2.4.2.1 Introduction
Section 34 of the Constitution provides that everyone has the right to bring a dispute
that can be resolved by the application of law before an independent and impartial
body for a decision. Before a person can bring a matter before a court, that person
must be entitled to do so, in other words, the person must have standing (locus standi)
to bring the matter before the court.
The rules of standing are based on the principle that a litigant must have capacity to
sue and must have a sufficient interest in the proceedings.137 The rules operate to allow
certain cases through the doors of the court and to keep others out.138 According to
Plasket, the operation of the rules of standing is both important and controversial:139
The drawing of lines by courts to distinguish between those litigants allowed through
their doors and those kept outside has obvious implications for the right of the citizenry
to access to justice. Standing therefore has constitutional significance.
Cameron states that the elements of the common-law rules are highly manipulable, and
the question of whether an applicant‘s interest is only academic or whether the
litigation is premature involves a value judgment that will differ from judge to judge
and from case to case. The standing requirement can be manipulated by judges who
feel ―disinclined to hear certain cases or to decide certain issues for reasons which are
not openly expressed‖.140
Section 38 of the Constitution deals with the matter of standing in constitutional
litigation and anyone listed in the section has the right to approach a competent court
alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened. The following
persons may approach a court:
(a)
137
138
139
140
Anyone acting in their own interest;
Baxter Administrative Law 644.
Craig Administrative Law 479.
Plasket 2009 The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 1.
Cameron ―Legal Standing and the Emergency‖ 65.
55
(b)
anyone acting on behalf of another person who cannot act in their own
name;
(c)
anyone acting as a member of, or in the interest of, a group or a class of
people;
(d)
anyone acting in the public interest; and
(e)
an association acting in the interest of its members.
Section 38 considerably broadened the standing of people and organisations wishing to
enforce constitutional rights and radically altered the common-law rules of standing.141
The section only applies in cases where a right of a litigant in the Bill of Rights has been
infringed or threatened. It will therefore not apply if a provision of the Constitution
outside of the Bill of Rights has been violated.142 In such cases, the much narrower
common-law principles of standing will apply.
2.4.2.2 Own-interest standing
In Giant Concerts CC v Rinaldo Investments (Pty) Ltd,143 the Constitutional Court
investigated the standing of a person acting in his or her own interest. In this matter
the eThekwini Municipality sold a plot of land to Rinaldo Investments (Rinaldo) at a
vastly reduced price on the understanding that Rinaldo develop the land at its own
expense to further the development needs of the Municipality.144 The statutory
foundation for the transaction was a provision of the KwaZulu-Natal Local Authorities
Ordinance145 (the Ordinance) that permits the Municipality to sell immovable property by
private bargain under certain circumstances.146 Giant Concerts (Giant) launched review
proceedings to set aside the Municipality‘s and the MEC‘s decisions.147
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 43.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 81.
2013 (3) BCLR CC.
Para 7.
25 of 1974.
Section 233(8) of the Ordinance.
Para 13.
56
The matter was first heard in the KwaZulu-Natal High Court, Pietermaritzburg, where
the Municipality and Rinaldo contended that Giant had no standing to challenge the
validity of the sale.148 The High Court rejected this argument. Giant claimed on a
number of grounds, including lawfulness, procedural fairness and reasonableness, that
the decisions were invalid. In its judgment, the High Court upheld all Giant‘s arguments.
It set aside the Municipality‘s decision to sell the property to Rinaldo, as well as the
MEC‘s approval of the sale.149
The Supreme Court of Appeal overturned the High Court judgment on the narrow basis
that Giant lacked standing to bring the review.150 It therefore did not find it necessary to
comment on the substance of Giant‘s complaints. In essence, the Court found that
―only those with an interest in the ‗interests of the borough‘ have standing‖ to challenge
decisions under the Ordinance since it ―concerns itself with local interests‖. The
provisions of the Ordinance regulating the sale of immovable property are designed to
protect the interests of the local community only. The Court reasoned that Giant
claimed to act only in its own interest. Its registered address was not in Durban, but in
Pietermaritzburg. It therefore did not have ratepayer status in the Municipality.151
In its review application, Giant relied on the jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court to
argue that the Bill of Rights, in section 38 of the Constitution, requires a broader
approach to standing (even where the provision is not of direct application). Giant‘s
objection ought therefore not to be dealt with under the restrictive common-law
approach to standing.152 Giant contended the Supreme Court of Appeal‘s restrictive
approach to standing is inconsistent with the right to just administrative action and the
principle of legality. It argued that its involvement in the objection process constituted
an exercise of its right to political participation and that the judgment undermines this
148
149
Giant Concerts CC v Minister of Local Government, Housing and Traditional Affairs, KwaZulu-Natal
2011 (4) SA 164 (KZP)
Para 15.
150
Rinaldo Investments (Pty) Ltd v Giant Concerts CC [2012] 3 All SA 57 (SCA).
151
Para 16.
Para 18.
152
57
by precluding it from challenging a sale of municipal land on the basis that it is not a
ratepayer.153
Rinaldo argued that, despite the constitutional approach to standing being generous,
the indispensable requirement remains that a litigant must show ―sufficient interest‖,
and that the case was not on of public-interest standing. It supported the finding of the
Supreme Court of Appeal that even a generous approach to constitutional standing
―does not mean that everyone who alleges an infringement of a fundamental right has
an unfettered right of access to court‖.154
The Court stated that in dealing with matters relating to the standing of a party, it must
be assumed that its complaints about the lawfulness of the transaction are correct. This
is because in determining a litigant‘s standing, a court, as a matter of logic, must
assume that the challenge the litigant seeks to bring is justified.155 It quoted approvingly
from Hoexter: ―The issue of standing is divorced from the substance of the case. It is
therefore a question to be decided in limine, before the merits are considered‖.156
The Court pointed out that standing determines solely on whether a particular litigant is
entitled to mount the challenge: a successful challenge to a public decision can be
brought only if ―the right remedy is sought by the right person in the right
proceedings‖. The Court continued by stating that the interests of justice under the
Constitution may require courts to be hesitant to dispose of cases on standing alone
when broader concerns of accountability and responsiveness may require investigation
and determination of the merits. The Court noted the following:157
By corollary, there may be cases where the interests of justice or the public interest
might compel a court to scrutinise action even if the applicant‘s standing is
questionable. When the public interest cries out for relief, an applicant should not fail
merely for acting in his or her own interest.
153
154
155
156
157
Para 20.
Para 23.
Jacobs v Waks 1992 (1) SA 521 (A) 536A.
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 488.
Rinaldo Investments para 34.
58
Therefore, when a litigant acts solely in his or her own interest, there is no broad or
unqualified capacity to litigate against illegalities. Something more must be shown. The
Court referred approvingly to the Ferreira case,158 in which it was held that the
Constitutional Court should adopt a ―broad approach‖:159
This would be consistent with the mandate given to this Court to uphold the
Constitution and would serve to ensure that constitutional rights enjoy the full measure
of protection to which they are entitled.
The object of the standing requirement is therefore that courts ―should not be required
to deal with abstract or hypothetical issues and should devote its scarce resources to
issues that are properly before it‖. Own-interest standing does not require that a litigant
must be the person whose constitutional right has been infringed or threatened: ―What
the section requires is that the person concerned should make the challenge in his or
her own interest‖.160
The Court found that, while constitutional own-interest standing is broader than the
traditional common-law standing, a litigant must nevertheless show that his or her
rights or interests are directly affected by the challenged law or conduct. Therefore:161
(a)
To establish own-interest standing under the Constitution, a litigant need
not show the same ―sufficient, personal and direct interest‖ that the
common law requires, but must still show that a contested law or decision
directly affects his or her rights or interests, or potential rights or interests.
(b)
This requirement must be interpreted generously and broadly to accord
with constitutional goals.
(c)
The interest must be real and not hypothetical or academic.
(d)
Even under the requirements for common-law standing, the interest need
not be capable of monetary valuation, but in a challenge to legislation,
158
159
160
161
Ferreira v Levin; Vryenhoek v Powell 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC).
Rinaldo Investments para 36.
Para 37.
Para 41; Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 45.
59
purely financial self-interest may not be enough; the interests of justice
must also favour affording standing.
(e)
Standing is not a technical or strictly defined concept. In addition, there is
no magical formula for conferring it. It is a tool employed by the courts to
determine whether a litigant is entitled to claim court time and to put the
opposing litigant to trouble.
(f)
Each case depends on its own facts. There can be no general rule covering
all cases. In each case, an applicant must show that he or she has the
necessary interest in an infringement or a threatened infringement.
Moreover, here a measure of pragmatism is needed.
The Court noted that the own-interest provision in section 38(a) is not isolated; it
stands alongside section 38(b)-(e). These provisions create scope for public interest,
surrogate, representative and associational challenges to illegality. The risk that an
unlawful decision could stand because an own-interest litigant cannot establish standing
is diminished by the fact that broad categories of other litigants, not acting in their own
interest, are entitled to bring a challenge.162
Own-interest litigants must therefore demonstrate that their interests or potential
interests are directly affected by the unlawfulness they seek to impugn. The Court
found that Giant lacked standing and that the Ordinance does indeed focus on local
interests, but determining own-interest standing under it should be done broadly and
generously to ensure that any litigant who establishes that his or her interests or
potential interests may be directly affected by a transaction can challenge it. 163
Nevertheless, while constitutional own-interest standing is broad, it is not limitless. 164
Giant never demonstrated that it had any serious commercial interest in the site.
In saying that it wanted to develop the site, but never saying how, the interest Giant
claimed remained hypothetical. A hypothetical interest is one that is expressly claimed,
162
163
164
Para 42.
Para 45.
Para 50.
60
but is neither real nor true, and an academic interest is one that is not related to a real
or practical situation and is therefore irrelevant. Giant, when it lodged its legal
challenge, had to show that its complaint – that it should have been given an
opportunity to present its own proposal – was well-grounded because it had the
capacity to make a realistic counterproposal.
It did not have to show that its proposal would have carried the day. Giant never
showed any intention of making such a counterproposal.165 The consequence was that
Giant lacked standing, since its interest remained incipient and never became direct or
substantial.166 Currie and De Waal state that as long as the causal link between the
applicant‘s interest and the requested remedy is not too tenuous, the courts should
grant standing to the applicant.167
The courts confirmed the standing of a person to challenge laws when that person has
not yet been affected by the law and the threat of application of the law has fallen
away. In exceptional circumstances, attorneys may also institute proceedings on behalf
of clients who are unable to do so.168
2.4.2.3 Surrogate standing
It is possible for a person to act on behalf of another who is not able to act in his or her
own name. According to Currie and De Waal the most obvious example is that of a
person being detained and prevented from approaching a court him- or herself. The
represented person must consent to the representation, and if that is not possible, it
must be clear from the circumstances that he or she would have consented to the
action.169
165
166
167
168
169
Para 54.
Para 55.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 81.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 46.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 87.
61
In Oostelike Gauteng Diensteraad v Transvaal Munisipale Pensioenfonds ,170 the Court
confirmed this broader approach to standing:
The category of persons empowered to bring a constitutional matter to a competent
court of law is broader than the category of persons who have hitherto been allowed
standing in cases where it is alleged that a right has been infringed or threatened. To
that extent, the section demonstrates a broad and not a narrow approach to standing.
The Court stated, however, that even if such a broad approach to standing is allowed,
the applicant who claims to act on behalf of others must set out the nature and basis
for this claim fully and clearly. In this case, the applicant did not claim or specify that he
was acting on behalf of persons who were unable to bring the matter to court
themselves. In such matters, even a broad approach to standing would not save the
applicant and standing would not be granted.
2.4.2.4 Representative standing
Section 38(c) of the Constitution allows class action lawsuits to be brought. In The
Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v
Ngxuza,171 the applicants, assisted by the Legal Resources Centre, litigated as
representatives on behalf of anyone in the Eastern Cape Province whose disability
grants had, between specified dates, been cancelled or suspended by the Eastern Cape
provincial government.172 The Court explained the class action as follows:173
In the type of class action at issue in this case, one or more claimants litigate against a
defendant not only on their own behalf but on behalf of all other similar claimants. The
most important feature of the class action is that other members of the class, although
not formally and individually joined, benefit from, and are bound by, the outcome of
the litigation unless they invoke prescribed procedures to opt out of it.
The Court explained that the issue between the members of the class and the
defendant is tried once. The judgment binds all, and the benefits of its ruling accrue to
all. The procedure has particular utility where a large group of plaintiffs each has a
170
Oostelike Gauteng Diensteraad v Transvaal Munisipale Pensioenfonds 1997 (8) BCLR 1066 T para 9.
171
2001 (4) SA 1184 (SCA).
Para 3(3).
Para 4(7).
172
173
62
small claim that may be difficult or impossible to pursue individually.174 The reason that
the procedure is invoked so frequently lies in the complexity of modern social
structures, and the attendant cost of legal proceedings:175
Modern society seems increasingly to expose men to such group injuries for which
individually they are in a poor position to seek legal redress, either because they do
not know enough or because such redress is disproportionately expensive. If each is
left to assert his rights alone when he can, there will at best be a random and
fragmentary enforcement, if there is any at all.
Because so many in South Africa are in a poor position to seek legal redress and
because the technicalities of legal procedure may unduly complicate the attainment of
justice, the Constitution created the express entitlement that anyone asserting a right in
the Bill of Rights could litigate as a member of a group or class of persons.
The Court found that the situation seemed pattern-made for class proceedings:176
The class the applicants represent is drawn from the very poorest within our society;
those in need of statutory social assistance. They also have the least chance of
vindicating their rights through the legal process. Their individual claims are small: the
value of the social assistance they receive – a few hundred rands every month – would
secure them hardly a single hour‘s consultation at current rates with most urban
lawyers. They are scattered throughout the Eastern Cape Province, many of them in
small towns and remote rural areas. What they have in common is that they are
victims of official excess, bureaucratic misdirection and unlawful administrative
methods.
The Court therefore held that it is the needs of persons who are most lacking in
protective and assertive armour that the Constitutional Court has repeatedly
emphasised must animate the court‘s understanding of the Constitution‘s provisions.177
In addition, it is against the background of their constitutional entitlements that the
Court must interpret the class action provision in the Bill of Rights.
The respondents objected to the standing of the applicants, arguing that their class was
not clearly defined. The court judged that there could be no conceptual complaint about
174
175
176
177
Para 6(1).
Kalven and Rosenfield 1941 University of Chicago Law Review 686.
Ngxuza para 9(11).
Para 9(13).
63
the clarity of the group‘s definition. From the point of view of practical definition, it was
beyond dispute that –
(a)
the class is so numerous that joinder of all its members is impracticable;
(b)
there are questions of law and fact common to the class;
(c)
the claims of the applicants representing the class are typical of the claims
of the rest; and
(d)
the applicants through their legal representatives, the Legal Resources
Centre, will adequately protect the interests of the class.178
The quintessential requisites for a class action are therefore present.
What is of further importance in this judgment is that the court held that the class
action doctrine allowed a court with jurisdiction over part of a cause to assume
jurisdiction over the remainder of the cause for reasons of justice, convenience and
good sense. The objection of the organ of state to the standing of the applicants must
also be faulted when the positive constitutional obligations placed on the state litigant
are analysed. Section 195(1)(e) of the Constitution demands that people‘s needs be
responded to, and the public must be encouraged to participate in policy-making. In
Ngxuza, the organ of state did not encourage the participation of the applicants in
policy-making as is constitutionally required. Instead, the organ of state relied on
technical arguments to discourage the participation of a wide range of vulnerable
people in policy-making. In section 1.4 it was argued that, because of positive
constitutional obligations borne by the state litigant, the state litigant should be the
model litigant. The state litigant must therefore be held to a different set of rules than
the private litigant. The organ of state must ensure that, when it engages in litigation,
the reason for the litigation is the vindication of the Constitution or because it is in the
public interest to do so. In Ngxuza, it was not in the public interest to deny a range of
people the opportunity to participate in policy-making nor could the litigation vindicate
178
Para 12(21).
64
the Constitution in any way. The requirement that organs of state should be model
litigants therefore requires that the state litigant should not rely on arguments of a
technical nature alone when engaging in litigation unless such a strategy is necessary to
vindicate the Constitution or it is in the public interest to do so.
In the Children's Resource Centre case,179 the applicants attempted to bring a class
action based on the common-law cause of action of delict. The Court set the
requirement that the applicant class include in its application of certification a draft set
of pleadings and a set of affidavits setting out the basis for the proposed action:180
(a)
The court had to be asked at the outset, and before issue of summons, to
certify the action as a class action.
(b)
This would involve the definition of the class.
(c)
A common claim or issue that can be determined by way of a class action
should be determined.
(d)
Evidence of the existence of a valid cause of action should be presented.
(e)
The court should be satisfied that the representative is suitable to represent
the members of the class.
(f)
The court should be satisfied that a class action is the most appropriate
procedure to adopt for the adjudication of the underlying claims.
The Court found the following:181
Unless it is plain that the claim is not legally tenable, certification should not be
refused. The court considering certification must always bear in mind that once
certification is granted the representative will have to deliver a summons and
particulars of claim and that it will be open to the defendant to take an exception to
those particulars of claim.
179
Children's Resource Centre Trust v Pioneer Food 2013 (2) SA 213 (SCA).
180
Para 23.
Para 39.
181
65
The applicant class should therefore file the requisite papers on the basis that ―the
application must be accompanied by a draft set of particulars of claim in which the
cause of action is pleaded, the class defined and the relief set out‖, which would make
the process of certifying the class clearer.182
2.4.2.5 Public-interest standing
Currie and De Waal are of the opinion that public-interest standing is the most difficult
of the section 38 categories.183 In Ferreira,184 the Court investigated the requirements
for standing when a litigant is claiming to appear in the public interest.185 The Court said
that it would be circumspect in affording applicants standing by way of this provision of
section 38 and would require an applicant to show that he was genuinely acting in the
public interest. Factors relevant to determining whether a person was genuinely acting
in the public interest would include considerations such as –
(a)
whether there was another reasonable and effective manner in which the
challenge could be brought;
(b)
the nature of the relief sought, and the extent to which it was of general
and prospective application; and
(c)
the range of persons or groups who might be affected directly or indirectly
by any order made by the court and the opportunity that those persons or
groups had had to present evidence and argument to the court.
These factors would need to be considered in the light of the facts and circumstances
of each case. The court found that applicants are required to allege an infringement of
or a threat to a right contained in the Bill of Rights, but need not point to an
infringement of or a threat to the right of a particular person. They need to allege that,
objectively speaking, the challenged rule or conduct is in breach of a right. This flows
182
183
184
185
Para 43.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 89.
Ferreira v Levin; Vryenhoek v Powell 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC).
Paras 234-235.
66
from the notion of acting in the public interest. The public would ordinarily have an
interest in the infringement of rights generally, not particularly.
The Ferreira case was heard in terms of the Interim Constitution. The requirements set
out in that case were confirmed as consistent with section 38(c) of the Constitution,
1996, in Lawyers for Human Rights v Minister of Home Affairs.186
The Court stated that the issue always is whether a person or organisation genuinely
acts in the public interest.187 A distinction should be made between the subjective
position of the person or organisation claiming to act in the public interest, on the one
hand, and, on the other, whether it is, objectively speaking, in the public interest for
the particular proceedings to be brought. It is ordinarily not in the public interest for
proceedings to be brought in the abstract. This is, however, a variable principle. There
may be circumstances in which it will be in the public interest to bring proceedings even
if there is no live case. The Court further found that the list of relevant factors is not
closed. The Court added that the degree of vulnerability of the people affected, the
nature of the right said to be infringed, and the consequences of the infringement of
the right are also important considerations in the analysis.
2.4.2.6 Associational standing
When an association acts in the interest of its members, it must show that the
members have sufficient interest in the remedy it seeks. In terms of the common law,
an association must possess a certain corporate character. In Highveldridge Residents,
the Court held that section 38(e) of the Constitution should not be interpreted to
include the common-law restrictions placed on the legal standing of voluntary
associations. It is therefore not necessary for an association to show that its
186
187
2004 (4) SA 125 (CC).
Para 18.
67
constitution allows it to sue, that the association has continued existence and a
separate identity, and that it can own property, acquire rights, and incur obligations.188
In Transvaal Agricultural Union v Minister of Land Affairs,189 the applicant was a body
established to represent the interest of its members. It applied to the court for an order
declaring certain provisions of the Restitution of Land Rights Act190 and rules regarding
the procedure of the Commission on Restitution of Land Rights unconstitutional. The
Court stated that the provisions were material to the interests of the applicant‘s
members and it qualified for this category of standing without any difficulty.
In South African National Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence,191 the applicant
acted in its own interest and in the interests of its members. It sought to have certain
sections of the Defence Act192 declared unconstitutional and invalid to the extent that it
prohibits members of the South African National Defence Force from participating in
public protest and from joining trade unions.193 It also sought to act on behalf of those
Defence Force members who were not members of the applicant but who wished to
join. It asserted that the criminal sanction for which members of the Permanent Force
would be liable if they joined the applicant deterred many potential members from
joining. The Court found that the applicant had sufficient standing to seek relief in this
matter based on its own interest and that of its existing members, so that no further
requirements for standing were necessary.194
2.4.2.7 Standing of amici curiae
Rule 8 of the Constitutional Court Rules,195 deals with the issue of the intervention of
parties in the proceedings. Rule 8(1) provides that any person entitled to join as a party
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
Highveldridge Residents Concerned Party v Highveldridge Transitional Local Council 2002 (6) SA 66
(T); Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 91; Peté et al Civil Procedure a Practical Guide
15.
1997 (2) SA 621 (CC) para 1.
22 of 1994.
1999 (3) BCLR 321 (T) para 4.
44 of 1957.
Para 1.
Para 4.
Government Gazette No. 25726 of 31 October 2003.
68
or liable to be joined as a party in the proceedings may, on notice to all parties, at any
stage of the proceedings apply for leave to intervene as a party. Persons or
organisations who are not a party to a case and who can offer information that may
help the court decide the matter before it may apply to be admitted as a party to the
case. The standing of amici curiae in proceedings is regulated by Rule 10 of the
Constitutional Court Rules.196
There are two procedures for admission. The amicus may seek the written consent of
all the parties in the matter before the court and may agree in writing with all the
parties before the court to certain terms and conditions and to certain rights and
privileges, subject to any directions by the Chief Justice.197 If the written consent has
not been secured, any person who has an interest in any matter before the court may
apply to the Chief Justice to be admitted therein as amicus curiae, and the Chief Justice
may grant such application on such terms and conditions and with such rights and
privileges as he or she may determine.198
In Fose v Minister of Safety and Security,199 the Court stated the following regarding
amicus curiae:
It is clear from the provisions of Rule 9 that the underlying principles governing the
admission of an amicus in any given case, apart from the fact that it must have an
interest in the proceedings, are whether the submissions to be advanced by the amicus
are relevant to the proceedings and raise new contentions which may be useful to the
court.
In Hoffmann v South African Airways,200 the Court explained the position and role of
amicus curiae in court proceedings:
An amicus curiae assist the court by furnishing information or argument regarding
questions of law or fact. An amicus is not a party to litigation, but believes that the
court‘s decision may affect its interest. The amicus differs from an intervening party,
who has a direct interest in the outcome of the litigation and is therefore permitted to
participate as a party to the matter. An amicus joins proceedings, as its name
suggests, as a friend of the court. It is unlike a party to litigation who is forced into the
196
197
198
199
200
Part V Rule 10 of the Constitutional Court Rules.
Rule 10(1).
Rule 10(4).
1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 9.
2000 Case CCT 17/00 (CC) para 63.
69
litigation and thus compelled to incur costs. It joins in the proceedings to assist the
court because of its expertise on or interest in the matter before the court. It chooses
the side it wishes to join, unless requested by the court to urge a particular position.
An amicus, regardless of the side it joins, is neither a loser nor a winner and is
generally not entitled to be awarded costs.
In Children's Institute v Presiding Officer, Children's Court, Krugersdorp201 the issue
before the Court was whether an amicus curiae may adduce evidence in court along
with its submission. The South Gauteng High Court held that it was not permissible for
the amicus in the matter, the Children's Institute at the University of Cape Town, to
adduce evidence.202 It further held that a High Court may not use its inherent power to
regulate its own process, under section 173 of the Constitution,203 to allow an amicus to
adduce evidence because to do so would amount to creating a new substantive right.
According to the High Court, the admission of amici curiae is governed by Rule 16A.204
The rules provide that, subject to the provisions of national legislation enacted in
accordance with section 171 of the Constitution, and the rules themselves, any
interested party in a constitutional issue raised in proceedings before a court may, with
the written consent of all the parties to the proceedings, given not later than 20 days
after the filing of the affidavit or pleading in which the constitutional issue was first
raised, be admitted therein as amicus curiae upon such terms and conditions as may be
agreed upon in writing by the parties. If such written consent cannot be obtained, the
amicus may apply to the court to be admitted as amicus curiae in the proceedings.205
The High Court found that Rule 16A only permits amicus curiae to be admitted to the
proceedings but prohibits it from leading evidence:206
201
202
203
204
205
206
2013 (2) SA 620 (CC).
SS (A Minor Child) v Presiding Officer of the Children‘s Court, District Krugersdorp [2011] ZAGPJHC
139; [2012] 1 All SA 231 (GSJ)
Section 173 of the Constitution reads: ―The Constitutional Court, Supreme Court of Appeal and High
Courts have the inherent power to protect and regulate their own process, and to develop the
common law, taking into account the interest of justice.‖ ―The Constitutional Court, the Supreme
Court of Appeal and the High Court of South Africa each has the inherent power to protect and
regulate their own process, and to develop the common law, taking into account the interests of
justice.‖
Uniform Rules of Court.
Para 7.
Para 8.
70
I am of the view that pursuant to Uniform Rule 16A(2) an interested party may be
admitted as amicus curiae in proceedings by the court after exercising its discretion
judicially whether to admit a party to the proceedings after consideration of all the
relevant facts. The admission of additional facts is an entirely different question as
there is no provision in Rule 16A for the admission of such evidence.
On appeal, the Constitutional Court found that, properly interpreted, Rule 16A is
permissive and allows for an amicus to adduce evidence. Both a textual and purposive
interpretation of the rule support this conclusion. The Court further found that even if
Rule 16A does not provide for evidence to be adduced by an amicus, section 173 of the
Constitution gives courts the inherent power to regulate their own process and this
includes the ability to allow amici to adduce evidence if the interests of justice so
demand.207 The Court examined the role of amici curiae and stated:208
[T]he role of an amicus envisioned in the Uniform Rules is very closely linked to the
protection of our constitutional values and the rights enshrined in the Bill of Rights.
Indeed, Rule 16A(2) describes an amicus as an ―interested party in a constitutional
issue raised in proceedings‖. Therefore, although friends of the court played a variety
of roles at common law, the new rule was specifically intended to facilitate the role of
amici in promoting and protecting the public interest. In these cases, amici play an
important role, first, by ensuring that courts consider a wide range of options and are
well informed; and second, by increasing access to the courts by creating space for
interested non-parties to provide input on important public interest matters,
particularly those relating to constitutional issues.
The courts therefore made it clear that amici may join proceedings if they are
promoting and protecting the public interest. Their participation in a case is not
restricted to the filing of documentary evidence before the court. They will also be
allowed to adduce evidence during the proceedings.
2.4.3 Ripeness
According to Du Plessis, the doctrine of ripeness determines that a court will not hear a
matter if it is premature in the sense that a right or interest has not been infringed or
threatened yet. The term ripeness is also used where alternative remedies available
have not been exhausted and where an issue can be resolved without recourse to the
207
208
Para 17.
Para 26.
71
Constitution.209 Motala and Ramaphosa describe ripeness as a court-created barrier to
adjudication. According to them, ripeness means that a matter which is premature
should not be decided until all the factors necessary for a decision have developed.210
In Ferreira v Levin,211 the Court highlighted that the essential flaw in the applicant‘s
case is one of timing or ―ripeness‖. The Court noted that the doctrine of ripeness
―serves the useful purpose of highlighting that the business of a court is generally
retrospective; it deals with situations or problems that have already ripened or
crystallised, and not with prospective or hypothetical ones‖.
In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs,212 the
respondents raised the issue of ripeness and contended that the applicants had failed to
pursue a non-constitutional remedy, which, if successful, might have rendered it
unnecessary to consider the constitutional validity of the section of the Act in question.
Such failure was in conflict, so it was contended, with the general principle of ripeness.
Where it is possible to decide any case without reaching a constitutional issue, that
course should be followed. The Court rejected this argument stating that in the that
matter it was unlikely that any other avenue would have brought relief to the
applicants.
In De Vos v Minister of Constitutional Development,213 the respondents raised a point in
limine as to the ripeness of the proceedings. They pointed out that in both matters the
proceedings in the magistrate‘s courts were incomplete, with the result that the
applicants had brought the proceedings prematurely.214 In this context, the respondents
relied on Motsepe v Commissioner for Inland Revenue,215 in which the court judged the
referral defective because of the general principle that ―where it is possible to decide
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 38.
Motala and Ramaphosa Constitutional Law: Analysis and Cases 112.
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para 199.
2000 (1) BCLR 39 (2 December 1999) para 22.
De Vos v Minister of Constitutional Development; Snyders v Minister of Constitutional Development
No 4502/10; Case No 5825/14 WC 2015.
The principle of avoidance.
1997 (2) SA 897 (27 March 1997) para 21.
72
any case, civil or criminal, without reaching a constitutional issue that is the course
which should be followed‖.216
In De Vos, the Court recognised the undesirability, in general, of adjudicating on
constitutional issues that may arise in criminal proceedings prior to the conclusion of
such proceedings. The Court noted, however, that the rule is flexible and the court may
depart from it when the interests of justice so require, depending on the circumstances
of the individual case. The Court stated that section 38 of the Constitution provides that
persons, like the applicants, have the right to approach a competent court alleging that
a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened. The Court referred to the
case of Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement of SA,217 where the Constitutional Court
confirmed that ―where a law threatens constitutional rights, it is not necessary for the
applicants to wait until the law has been implemented and the accused person is
detained before approaching a court‖.
The Court found that this principle is also applicable in the matter under discussion
because section 77(6)(a)218 of the Criminal Procedure Act219 threatens the constitutional
rights of the accused persons, inasmuch as the result in their criminal cases is
predetermined, that is, they will be detained even if they are found not to have
committed any offence.
The Court then pointed out that the complaint of the applicants is directed against the
scheme of section 77(6)(a) and not against the conduct or findings of the individual
judicial officers involved. The Court also referred to the case of Ferreira v Levin;
216
217
218
219
The court found it unnecessary to decide the constitutional issue because the applicant had failed to
follow objection and appeal procedures available to her.
Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement SA v Premier of the Province of Kwazulu-Natal 2010 (2) BCLR
99 (CC).
Section 77 deals with the capacity of accused to understand proceedings and s 77(6)(a) states that
when the accused is not capable of understanding the proceedings so as to make a proper defence,
the court may, if it is of the opinion that it is in the interests of the accused, taking into account the
nature of the accused's incapacity and unless it can be proved on a balance of probabilities that, on
the limited evidence available the accused committed the act in question, order that such
information or evidence be placed before the court as it deems fit so as to determine whether the
accused has committed the act in question and the court shall direct that the accused be detained in
a psychiatric hospital or a prison pending the decision of a judge.
51 of 1977.
73
Vryenhoek v Powell,220 in which the Constitutional Court confirmed that the enquiry into
the constitutionality of a statute is an objective one:221
The answer to the first question is that the enquiry is an objective one. A statute is
either valid or ―of no force and effect to the extent of its inconsistency‖. The subjective
positions in which parties to a dispute may find themselves cannot have a bearing on
the status of the provisions of a statute under attack. The Constitutional Court, or any
other competent court for that matter, ought not to restrict its enquiry to the position
of one of the parties to a dispute in order to determine the validity of a law. The
consequence of such a (subjective) approach would be to recognise the validity of a
statute in respect of one litigant, only to deny it to another. Besides resulting in a
denial of equal protection of the law, considerations of legal certainty, being a central
consideration in a constitutional state, militate against the adoption of the subjective
approach.
The Court therefore dismissed the in limine application of ripeness.222 The De Vos
decision and the case of Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement of SA223 are in clear
contradiction to an earlier decision by the Constitutional Court in Transvaal Agricultural
Union v The Minister of Land Affairs and the Commission of Restitution of Land
Rights,224 in which the applicants argued that the Act violated their rights as
landowners. The Court ruled that the claim of violation of constitutional rights depended
on how the Land Restitution Commission interpreted the Act (and their mandate). In
addition, it ruled that there was a need for all the factors that are necessary for the
resolution of a dispute to develop before the courts will consider the matter. In Ferreira
v Levin,225 the Court held that the business of a court is generally retrospective; it deals
with situations or problems that have already ripened or crystallised, and not with
prospective or hypothetical ones.
It is submitted that the approach adopted by the courts in De Vos and in Abahlali
baseMjondolo Movement of SA is the correct application of the doctrine of ripeness. In
the Transvaal Agricultural Union case, the Court held that the applicants had to wait
220
Ferreira v Levin; Vryenhoek v Powell 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (6 December 1995)
221
Para 13.
De Vos paras 25-29.
222
223
224
225
Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement SA v Premier of the Province of Kwazulu-Natal 2010 (2) BCLR
99 (CC).
1996 (12) BCLR 1573 CC paras 25-26; Motala and Ramaphosa Constitutional Law: Analysis and
Cases 113.
Case Number CCT 5/95 1995 (CC) para 199.
74
until the respondents had shown how the impugned law would be interpreted and
applied. In Ferreira, the Court held that it would only deal with matters in retrospect.
Such an approach could lead to legal uncertainty. The Constitution is forward-looking to
ensure that the future exercise of public power is in accordance with the principle of
legality.226 As such, the courts are clearly mandated to look at the future consequences
of legislation. After all, such a policy would allow the court to prevent constitutional
violations before they occur, something that is unquestionably in the public interest.
Therefore, the decisions in Ferreira and Transvaal Agricultural Union cannot be
supported. The Ferreira and Transvaal Agricultural Union decisions can further be
faulted because of the fact that the organs of state relied on purely technical arguments
to deny the applicants the right to participate in policy-making. This is counter to the
requirement set out in section 195(1)(e) of the Constitution that requires organs of
state to respond to people‘s needs and to encourage the public to participate in policymaking. To act as the model litigant, the state litigant should refrain from relying on
technical arguments alone when litigating. This obligation is discussed in chapter 6 of
this work.
2.4.4 Mootness
Mootness refers to the principle that a matter is not justiciable by the court if it no
longer presents an existing or live controversy or the prejudice or threat thereof to the
party no longer exists.227 Where ripeness prevents a court from hearing a matter
because it is too early, mootness prevents a court from hearing the matter because it
was brought too late.228 Mootness can also arise from a succession of developments
that brought about a change in the circumstances of the case that will result in the
plaintiff no longer having a stake in the outcome of the case; the courts would then not
hear the matter because it has become moot. Therefore, mootness can refer to the
plaintiff‘s interest in the outcome of the case after its commencement and it can
226
227
228
Ngxuza v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape 2001 (2) SA 609 (E) para
619c-d.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 39.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 94.
75
become moot because of a variety of circumstances, including the death of a party or
the repeal of the offending law.229
In JT Publishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Safety and Security,230 the Court was asked for a
declaratory order that provisions of the Publications Act231 were unconstitutional.232 The
Court cautioned that the policy that directs the courts not to decide issues that are
abstract, academic or hypothetical is well established. The Court found no reason why
the Constitutional Court should not adhere ―to a rule that sounds so sensible‖.233 The
Court stated that a new statute had been enacted, but had not yet been brought into
operation. The old statutes, which were already obsolete, would then terminate. The
Court ruled that neither of the applicants, nor for that matter anyone else, stood to gain
the slightest advantage from an order dealing with the moribund and futureless
provisions of the old Acts.234
In Children's Institute v Presiding Officer, Children's Court, Krugersdorp,235 the Court
had to deal with the issue of mootness. The question before the Court was whether
appeal against a decision by the High Court on the admissibility of evidence by an
amicus should be allowed when the main matter had already been successfully
concluded without the assistance of additional evidence by the amicus.
The Court found that it could not be said that the issue was moot with regard to other
amici seeking to adduce evidence in the High Court. Since the decision of the High
Court was made by a full bench, it would be highly persuasive to judges hearing an
application of this sort and be binding on judges in the South Gauteng High Court,
Johannesburg. Under these circumstances, the potential limitation on amici's ability to
adduce evidence, and therefore render effective assistance to courts in the future, was
significantly crippling. This was further exacerbated by the fact that the Supreme Court
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
Motala and Ramaphosa Constitutional Law: Analysis and Cases 116.
1997 (3) SA 514 (CC).
42 of 1974.
Para 1.
Para 15.
Para 16.
2013 (2) SA 620 (CC).
76
of Appeal refused leave to appeal. This meant that the High Court's decision stood and
was binding.236
Counsel for the amicus emphasised that because of the High Court judgment, amici had
been hesitant, on the strength of that decision, to apply for leave to adduce evidence.
Given the important role played by amici curiae in advocating on behalf of vulnerable
groups, clarity on the question of their ability to adduce evidence was warranted and
their participation in litigation was to be welcomed and encouraged.237 The Court judged
that, given the importance of the constitutional issues to be determined in the matter
and because the order would be final in effect, it was in the interests of justice that
leave to appeal be granted.238
In Pheko v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality,239 the Municipality evicted the
applicants from a settlement because of sinkholes that posed a danger to the welfare of
the community. The evictions were justified in terms of the Disaster Management Act.240
The occupiers unsuccessfully challenged the actions in a High Court and the evacuation
and demolition went ahead. In issue on appeal was whether the section permitted an
eviction and demolition without a court order.241
The Municipality contended that the relief sought had largely become moot as the
applicants and their dependants had already been evacuated from the area.242 The
Court referred to National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home
Affairs,243 in which it was stated: ―A case is moot and therefore not justiciable if it no
longer presents an existing or live controversy which should exist if the Court is to avoid
giving advisory opinions on abstract propositions of law.‖
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
Para 14.
Para 15.
Para 16.
2012 (2) SA 598 (CC).
57 of 2002.
Para 1.
Para 19.
2000 (2) SA 1 (CC) (2000 (1) BCLR 39 fn18.
77
The Court also approvingly referred to the following dictum in Independent Electoral
Commission v Langeberg Municipality:244
This Court has discretion to decide issues on appeal even if they no longer present
existing or live controversies. That discretion must be exercised according to what the
interests of justice require. A prerequisite for the exercise of the discretion is that any
order which this Court may make will have some practical effect either on the parties
or on others. Other factors that may be relevant will include the nature and extent of
the practical effect that any possible order might have, the importance of the issue, its
complexity and the fullness or otherwise of the argument advanced. Indeed, if the
applicants' rights were not infringed and are no longer threatened, or the applicants
have no interest in the adjudication of the dispute, it will not be in the interests of
justice to grant leave to appeal directly to this court.
The Court found it beyond question that the interdictory relief sought would be of no
consequence as the applicants had already been evicted. Although the removal had
taken place, the case still presented a live controversy regarding the lawfulness of the
eviction. Generally, unlawful conduct is inimical to the rule of law and to the
development of a society based on dignity, equality and freedom. The Court judged
that the applicants had an interest in the adjudication of the constitutional issue at
stake. The matter could therefore not have been said to be moot.245
In Gaertner v Minister of Finance,246 officials of the South African Revenue Service
searched the applicant‘s company premises and home, and copied documents and
computer data. The actions were taken under section 4(4) of the Customs and Excise
Act247. The directors of the company applied for a declaration that section 4 was
unconstitutional in permitting targeted non-routine searches without a judicial
warrant.248 The South African Revenue Service (SARS) tendered to return all seized
material and to pay the applicants' costs to date on a party and party scale.
SARS did not concede that section 4 was invalid or that the searches had been
unlawful.249 The respondents in their answering affidavits asserted that the
244
245
246
247
248
249
2001 (3) SA 925 (CC) (2001 (9) BCLR 883.
Pheko para 32.
2013 (4) SA 87 (WCC).
91 of 1964.
Paras 3-7.
Para 8.
78
constitutionality of section 4 and the lawfulness of the searches were moot in the light
of the tender that the applicants had accepted. They denied in any event that section 4
was in any respect invalid, asserting that any encroachment on the right to privacy was
justifiable under section 36250 of the Constitution.251
The Court found the contention of mootness without merit. Section 4 had not been
repealed. The case was quite different from the situation in JT Publishing (Pty) Ltd v
Minister of Safety and Security252 (referred to above). There the impugned provision had
been repealed and the repeal was shortly to take effect. The Court noted that the
respondents did not say, and could not say, that the applicants would not in the future
be subjected to a search or inspection under the authority of section 4. The
respondents themselves asserted, in relation to questions of retrospectivity and
suspension, that it was of the utmost importance that SARS should have the powers
contained in section 4, indicating their intention to keep on using the section. An
enquiry into the validity of section 4 was thus not an academic matter without practical
consequence.
The doctrine of mootness will therefore not stand if it is in the interest of justice that
the matter be heard. Furthermore, should the case present a live controversy, and if
the applicants have an interest in the adjudication of the constitutional issue at stake,
the matter will not be moot.
When mootness is offered as a defence by the state litigant, the courts should be
circumspect in granting the state litigant the relief asked for. In section 1.4 it was
argued that, because of the imposition of positive constitutional duties on the state
litigant, the state litigant should be held to a different standard than the private litigant.
Therefore, the courts should be hesitant to deny the private litigant the opportunity to
250
251
252
The limitation of rights.
Par 10.
1997 (3) SA 514 (CC) (1996 (12) BCLR 1599.
79
have their grievance heard by the courts should the state litigant rely on a purely
technical defence.253
2.4.5 Jurisdiction
2.4.5.1 Introduction
Jurisdiction is defined as the power or competence that a particular court has to hear
and determine an issue between parties brought before it.254 This work focuses on the
constitutionality of strategic litigation when the state is a party to the proceedings.
Consequently, the discussion of jurisdiction will be limited to jurisdictional issues
relating to the High Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal and the Constitutional Court.
2.4.5.2 The meaning of constitutional matters
In Pharmaceutical Manufacturers of South Africa: In re: ex parte President of the
Republic of South Africa,255 the Court found that the exercise of all public power must
comply with the Constitution, which is the supreme law of the country, and the doctrine
of legality, which is part of that law. According to Currie and De Waal, this holds the
implication that any challenge to the validity of any exercise of public power is a
constitutional matter, and is ultimately susceptible to the Constitutional Court‘s
jurisdiction.256
Constitutional matters include any issue involving the interpretation, protection or
enforcement of the Constitution.257 The jurisdiction to determine constitutional matters
is an extensive jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court.258 Constitutional matters
encompass the direct application of the Bill of Rights and the direct application of
constitutional provisions, as well as the indirect application of the Bill of Rights. 259
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
This issue is more fully discussed in the final chapter of this work.
Graaff-Reinet Municipality v Van Ryneveld‘s Pass Irrigation Board 1950 (2) SA 420 (A) para 424.
2000 (2) SA 674 (CC) para 20.
Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security 2001 (4) SA 938 (CC) para 54; Currie and De Waal The
Bill of Rights Handbook 104.
Section 167(7) of the Constitution.
S v Boesak 2001 (1) SA 912 (CC) para 14.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 19-20.
80
Although the jurisdiction conferred upon the Constitutional Court is wide, it is limited
and does not include hearing purely factual matters,260 unless the Constitutional Court
grants leave to appeal because the matter raises an arguable point of law of general
importance which ought to be considered by the court.261
Most of the matters coming before the Constitutional Court are referred to it on appeal
from the Supreme Court of Appeal or the High Court, but there are certain types of
constitutional matters which are reserved for the exclusive and original jurisdiction of
the Constitutional Court and which are initiated only in the Constitutional Court.
2.4.5.3 Exclusive jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court
The jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court is set out in section 167 of the Constitution.
The Constitutional Court is the highest court of the Republic.262 Although section
167(3)(b) originally provided that the Constitutional Court may only decide
constitutional matters, this provision was amended by the Constitution Seventeenth
Amendment Act of 2012.263 The section now provides that the Constitutional Court may
decide constitutional matters and may decide any other matter, if the Constitutional
Court grants leave to appeal because the matter raises an arguable point of law of
general public importance that ought to be considered by the court.
In terms of section 167(4) only the Constitutional Court may–
(a)
decide disputes between organs of state in the national or provincial sphere
concerning the constitutional status, powers or functions of any of those
organs of state;
(b)
decide on the constitutionality of any parliamentary or provincial Bill;
(c)
decide applications by members of the national Parliament and provincial
legislatures to declare all or part of an Act to be unconstitutional;
260
261
262
263
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 23.
Section 167(3)(b)(ii).
Section 167(3)(a).
Government Gazette No. 36128 of 1 February 2013.
81
(d)
decide on the constitutionality of any amendment to the Constitution;
(e)
decide that Parliament or the President has failed to comply with a
constitutional duty; and
(f)
certify a provincial constitution.264
The Constitutional Court makes the final decision whether an Act of Parliament, a
provincial Act or conduct of the President is constitutional, and must confirm any order
of invalidity made by the Supreme Court of Appeal, the High Court of South Africa, or a
court of similar status, before that order has any force.265
All matters concerning constitutional issues, other than those listed in section 167(4),
will commence in a High Court, unless the Constitutional Court grants an application for
direct access to it in terms of section 167(6) of the final Constitution, read with Rule 18
of the Constitutional Court Rules.266
In Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly,267 the Court
explained the rationale for the exclusive jurisdiction of the Court:
The purpose of giving the Constitutional Court exclusive jurisdiction to
that have important political consequences is to preserve the comity
judicial branch of government and the other branches of government by
the highest court in constitutional matters intrudes into the domain
branches of government.
decide issues
between the
ensuring only
of the other
The principle underlying the exclusive jurisdiction of this Court in terms of section
167(4) is that disputes that involve important questions relating to sensitive areas of
the separation of powers must be decided by this Court only. Therefore, the closer the
issue to be decided is to the sensitive area of the separation of powers, the more likely
it is that the issue will fall within the ambit of section 167(4).
264
265
266
267
In terms of s 144 of the Constitution.
Section 167(5) of the Constitution.
Constitutional Court Rules, 2003 published in GN R1675 in GG 25726 of 31 October 2003.
2006 (6) SA 416 (CC) para 23-24.
82
Under the Superior Courts Act ,268 whenever the Supreme Court of Appeal or a High
Court declares an Act of Parliament, a provincial Act or conduct of the President invalid
as contemplated in section 172(2)(a) of the Constitution, that court must refer the
order of constitutional invalidity to the Constitutional Court for confirmation.269
The Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012 expanded the jurisdiction of the
Constitutional Court. The Court may now hear any matter, if the Constitutional Court
grants leave to appeal because the matter raises an arguable point of law of general
public importance that ought to be considered by that court.
The Constitution, after amendment by the Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act,
provides that the Constitutional Court may decide –270
(a)
constitutional matters; and
(b)
any other matter, if the Constitutional Court grants leave to appeal because
the matter raises an arguable point of law of general public importance that
ought to be considered by the Constitutional Court.
The Court may therefore decide to grant leave to appeal in a non-constitutional matter
if –271
(a)
the matter raises an arguable point of law;
(b)
it is of general public importance, that is, the matter should be important
not only for the litigants but for the general public; and
(c)
the matter ought to be considered by the Constitutional Court.
This allows the Court to filter out non-constitutional matters it deems not
sufficiently important.
268
269
270
271
10 of 2013.
S 15 .
Section 167(3)(b)(i) and (ii).
Paulsen v Slip Knot Investments 777 (Pty) Limited 2015 (3) SA 479 (CC) paras 13-17 and Du Plessis,
Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 34.
83
2.4.5.4 Jurisdiction of the High Court
The High Court has wide powers to hear constitutional matters. The High Court may
hear any constitutional matter, except where the Constitutional Court has exclusive
jurisdiction over the matter.272 The Supreme Court of Appeal and the High Court have
the inherent power to regulate their own process and to develop the common law,
taking into account the interests of justice.273
The High Court derives its jurisdiction from national legislation,274 and from the common
law.275 The common law grants inherent jurisdiction to the High Court, the Supreme
Court of Appeal and the Constitutional Court. The inherent jurisdiction to adjudicate on
cases means that the courts may override the rules of the court or provide a procedural
remedy where none existed.276 The High Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal and the
Constitutional Court are therefore enabled to promote a range of innovative new orders
to promote the interests of justice.
In Mjeni v Minister of Health and Welfare, Eastern Cape,277 the Court rejected section 3
of the State Liability Act,278 which precluded the imprisonment of state officials, and the
argument that contempt proceedings were principally inappropriate in respect of
judgments ad pecuniam solvendam.279 The Court found that –280
[i]n more recent years, and in particular the period from 2002 onwards, the courts
have been inundated with situations where court orders have been flouted by state
functionaries, who, on being handed such court orders, have given very flimsy excuses
which in the end only point to their dilatoriness. The public officials seem not to
understand the integral role that they play in our constitutional state, as the right to
access to courts entails a duty not only on the courts to ensure access but on the state
to bring about the enforceability of court orders.
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
Section 169(a) of the Constitution.
Section 173 of the Constitution.
Section 171 of the Constitution.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 112.
Peté et al Civil Procedure 88.
2000 4 SA 446 (TkH).
20 of 1957.
Judgments in which the debtor is ordered to pay a sum of money; Kelbrick Civil Procedure 121.
Para 60.
84
In Nyathi v MEC for Department of Health, Gauteng,281 section 3 of the State Liability
Act was declared unconstitutional because it did not provide for the effective
enforcement of court orders against the state. The Court found justification for its
decision in section 173 of the Constitution, which allows the courts the inherent power
to protect and regulate their own process and to develop the common law, taking into
account the interests of justice. The Court thus held that the Minister could be held in
contempt of court for non-compliance with court orders. The declaration of invalidity
was confirmed by the Constitutional Court.282 The courts will exercise its inherent
jurisdiction only in exceptional cases where ordinary procedure is not provided for in
law.283
The doctrine of effectiveness is the most important general principle underlying the
jurisdiction of the High Court. The doctrine effectively states that a litigant should not
waste the court‘s time by bringing a matter before it if it is clear that the court‘s
judgment would not be effective.284 In this instance, an effective judgment means one
that can be enforced.
2.5 Strategic litigation and cause of action
To bring a claim in South African courts, the plaintiff must rely on a cause of action.
The enquiry into the cause of action is an enquiry into substantive law, assisting in the
determination of the appropriate civil procedure to be followed. One of the first
questions to be asked what the basis is on which the claim is founded; in other words,
what the cause of action is. The cause of action is essential in identifying the elements
that must be proved for a successful claim. According to Marnewick, a cause of action is
a set of facts that gives rise to a claim recognised by law. This means that the court has
to grant judgment for the plaintiff if those facts are proved to the required standard of
proof.285
281
[2008] ZACC 8.
282
Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development v Nyathi 2010 (4) BCLR 293 (CC).
Krygkor Pensioenfonds v Smith 1993 (3) SA 459 (A) para 469G-J.
Peté et al Civil Procedure 71.
Marnewick Litigation skills 79.
283
284
285
85
In principle, it is undesirable for a court in a matter to raise a fresh legal issue not relied
upon by the applicants, and upon which the applicants do not wish to rely.286 The role
of a court is essentially to be responsive to litigation brought before it. In the Matatiele
Municipality case, the Court held as follows:287
As a general matter, a court should decide issues raised by the parties in their
pleadings and in argument. They should not embark upon a judicial frolic and decide
matters that are not before them. The adjudication of disputes between the parties is
not an occasion to engage in an academic exercise of deciding a whole range of issues
that are not before a court. But, like all general rules, this too is subject to exceptions.
It must yield to the interests of justice.
It is trite that a court is not bound by a legal concession if it considers the concession
wrong in law.288 Were it to be otherwise, this could lead to an intolerable situation in
which the Court would be bound by a mistake of law on the part of a litigant.
In South Africa, a cause of action can be derived from common law, statutory law and
the Constitution.
2.5.1 Common-law cause of action
In South African constitutional law, claims are usually brought against the state based
on the common-law principles of delict and contract. In the pre-constitutional era, the
review of administrative action could only be sought in terms of the common law. The
realm of administrative action at common law was broad, with administrative law
viewed as an essential bulwark against the abuse of public power.289 South Africa has
also followed the example of other Commonwealth jurisdictions by adopting the
common-law cause of action based on bureaucratic negligence.
In South Africa, public servants have been found liable where officials –290
286
287
288
289
290
Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) paras 66-67.
Para 66.
In Azanian People‘s Organisation v President of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 671 (CC)
para 16, the Court firmly rejected the proposition that it is bound by an incorrect legal concession,
holding that if that concession was wrong in law, it would have no hesitation whatsoever in rejecting
it.
Hoexter Administrative Law 165.
Okpaluba and Osode Government liability 109.
86
(a)
took no steps to investigate the information supplied by an applicant for a
firearm;291
(b)
failed to investigate the extent to which admissions by an applicant
rendered him unfit to possess a firearm;292
(c)
failed to investigate whether a licence should be withdrawn when members
of the Police Service held information that the holder of the firearm was
fond of alcohol and misused firearms;293 or
(d)
failed to oppose the bail application of a sex offender by not bringing
information known to the police and the prosecutor to the attention of the
magistrate.294
Problems may arise when the applicant approaches the courts claiming that a right, in
the Bill of Rights, has been infringed or threatened. As will be shown in paragraph
2.5.3.3, the litigant might have access to both a constitutional cause of action, because
of the breach of a constitutional right, and a common-law cause of action, usually in the
form of delict. An example of this may be found in section 12(1)(d) of the Constitution,
which provides that everyone has the right not to be tortured. If the plaintiff is arrested
by the police and then tortured, he or she will have access to a constitutional cause of
action because of the breach of his or her section 12(1)(d) constitutional right, but the
plaintiff can also rely on the common-law cause of action based on the delict caused by
the police. This parallel system of law, or multiple causes of action, is discussed in
paragraph 2.5.3.3.
2.5.2 Statutory-law cause of action
A statutory-law cause of action is a civil cause of action created by legislation. A
statutory-law cause of action is created to provide a remedy where the common law is
291
292
293
294
Minister of Safety and Security v Hamilton 2004 (2) SA 216 (SCA).
Minister of Safety and Security v De Lima 2005 (5) SA 575 (SCA).
Minister of Safety and Security v Van Duivenboden 2002 (6) SA 431 (SCA).
Carmichele v Minster of Safety and Security 2003 (2) SA 656 (CC).
87
inadequate or to provide a statutory remedy where the common-law remedy, though
adequate in theory, is not available in practice.
The Human Rights Act, 1998, of the United Kingdom is an example of statutory law
introducing a cause of action into national jurisprudence.295 Section 8 of the Act offers a
judicial remedy when rights contained in the European Convention for the Protection of
Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms296 are breached, and provides, inter alia, the
following:
(a)
In relation to any act of a public authority, which the court finds is
unlawful, it may grant such relief or remedy within its powers as it
considers just and appropriate.
(b)
Damages may, however, be awarded only by a court that has power to
award damages, or to order the payment of compensation, in civil
proceedings.
(c)
No award of damages is to be made unless, taking account of all the
circumstances of the case, including (a) any other relief or remedy granted,
or order made, in relation to the act in question, and (b) the consequences
of any decision in respect of that act, the court is satisfied that the award is
necessary to afford just satisfaction to the person in whose favour it is
made.
The Human Rights Act therefore incorporated the provisions of the European
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms into British
domestic law.297 This is a marked departure from the traditional way in which civil
liberties have been viewed under British law. Vick states that British constitutional law
traditionally refrained from a textual pronouncement of fundamental rights, instead
viewing rights as residual, relying on the democratic process, the rule of law, and a
295
Okpaluba and Osode Government liability 78.
296
European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms November 4
297
1950 213 U.N.T.S. 221.
Ewing 2003 The Modern Law Review 1.
88
complex system of checks and balances to safeguard civil liberties. Before the Human
Rights Act was enacted, enforcement of the European Convention for the Protection of
Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms could be asserted by individuals in the
European Court of Human Rights. The Human Rights Act puts courts and other public
authorities under a positive duty to give effect to the rights guaranteed under the
European Convention.298
In South Africa, statutory causes of action include the Promotion of Administrative
Justice Act,299 the Promotion of Access to Information Act300 and Promotion of Equality
and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act.301
The purpose of the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act is to give effect to the right
to administrative action that is lawful, reasonable and procedurally fair and the right to
written reasons for administrative decisions.302 In terms of section 6 of the Act any
person may institute proceedings in a court for the judicial review of an administrative
action and the court may review the administrative action if the requirements of
subsection (2) are met.
The purpose of the Promotion of Access to Information Act is to give effect to the
constitutional right of access to any information held by the State and any information
that is held by another person and that is required for the exercise or protection of any
right.303 The Act gives effect to section 32 of the Constitution, which provides for access
to any information held by the state and access to any information that is held by
another person that is required for the exercise of any rights.
In terms of section 78 of the Act, a person who requested information from the state or
a private party may institute proceedings in a court if the request is refused but only
298
299
300
301
302
303
Vick 2002 Texas International Law Journal 330.
3 of 2000.
2 of 2000.
4 of 2000.
Long title of the Act.
Long title of the Act.
89
after exhausting the internal appeal procedures. The court hearing an application may
grant any order that is just and equitable, including orders –304
(a)
confirming, amending or setting aside the decision that is the subject of the
application concerned;
(b)
requiring from the information officer or relevant authority of a public body
or the head of a private body to take such action or to refrain from taking
such action as the court considers necessary;
(c)
granting an interdict or a declaratory order;
(d)
granting compensation;
(e)
as to costs.
The Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act gives effect to
section 9 of the Constitution, which provides for the enactment of national legislation to
prevent or prohibit unfair discrimination and to promote the achievement of equality.
The objects of the Act are –305
(a)
to enact legislation required by section 9 of the Constitution;
(b)
to give effect to the letter and spirit of the Constitution, including the equal
enjoyment of all rights and freedoms by every person, the promotion of
equality, the values of non-racialism and non-sexism, the prevention of
unfair discrimination and protection of human dignity, and the prohibition of
advocacy of hatred, based on race, ethnicity, gender or religion, that
constitutes incitement to cause harm;
(c)
to provide for measures to facilitate the eradication of unfair discrimination,
hate speech and harassment, particularly on the grounds of race, gender
and disability;
304
305
Section 82 of the Act.
Section 2 of the Act.
90
(d)
to provide for procedures for the determination of circumstances under
which discrimination is unfair;
(e)
to provide for measures to educate the public and raise public awareness of
the importance of promoting equality and overcoming unfair discrimination,
hate speech and harassment;
(f)
to provide remedies for victims of unfair discrimination, hate speech and
harassment, and for persons whose right to equality has been infringed;
(g)
to set out measures to advance persons disadvantaged by unfair
discrimination; and
(h)
to facilitate compliance with obligations under international law.
The Act provides for the creation of equality courts,306 in which actions under the Act
may be instituted.307
The courts can therefore be approached when a right in the Bill of Rights has been
breached or threatened by relying on a cause of action created by the statute enacted
to realise of the right that has been breached.
2.5.3 Constitutional-law cause of action
2.5.3.1 Introduction
Section 38 of the Constitution provides that the categories of person listed in this
section may approach a competent court alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has
been infringed or threatened, and that the court may grant appropriate relief. The
Court may, furthermore, make any order that is just and equitable. 308 The Constitution
contains no definition of what would constitute ―appropriate‖ relief or ―just and
equitable‖ relief. The South African Constitution does not specifically recognise damages
306
307
308
Section 16 of the Act.
Section 20 of the Act.
Section 172(1)(b) of the Constitution.
91
or compensation as appropriate relief for any breach of constitutional rights and
freedoms,309 unlike the constitutions of Namibia,310 the Seychelles311 and the Solomon
Islands.312
Anderson writes that where law presumes to "empower" the disadvantaged, a variety of
questions arises. Those he raises are:313
Are new mechanisms of accountability actually designed to translate social demands
into effective policy? Is access to a legal remedy genuinely widespread or only
available to particular groups aided by legal and political professionals? Are legal
categories sufficiently sensitive to popular conceptions of justice, so that democratic
voices may find expression in legal form? Finally, are the disadvantaged or injured
parties active participants in the legal process, or do they remain alienated,
disempowered "victims" at the mercy of an ambivalent altruism?
These questions are especially valid in a constitutional sense when a constitution
provides for far-reaching protection for human rights and places a positive duty on the
state to protect and give effect to such rights, as is the case in South Africa. 314 The
imposition of positive constitutional duties on the state also raises the question of
whether the litigant should approach the courts relying on the constitutional provisions
that impose such duties. If the state has legislated to give effect to positive duties
imposed on the state by the constitution, or the common law provides remedies that
the litigant could use to enforce the breach of these duties, which remedy should the
litigant employ? Does this create a parallel system of law that is available to the
litigant?
309
310
311
312
313
314
Okpaluba and Osode Government liability 52.
Constitution of Namibia 1990 Art. 25(4).
Constitution of Seychelles 1983 s 46(5)(d).
Constitution of Solomon Islands 1978 s 17.
Anderson 1993 Third World Legal Studies 178.
Section 7(1) of the Constitution states that the Bill of Rights is a cornerstone of democracy in South
Africa and that it enshrines the rights of all people in the country. Section 7(2) places an obligation
on the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights contained in the Bill of Rights.
92
2.5.3.2 Comparable causes of action in foreign jurisdictions
2.5.3.2.1 Position in the United States of America
In the United States of America, the federal/state divide plays a significant role in the
United States jurisprudence in this regard,315 and remedies for constitutional
infringement arise from two sources: the relief provided by Section 1983 of the Civil
Rights Act,316 and constitutional damages based directly on the Constitution. Claims in
tort also fall within the jurisdiction of state courts and there is an element of state
immunity when claims are based on tort.
Section 1983 United States Code (U.S.C.) has been an important federal statutory
remedy, in respect of which the states have concurrent jurisdiction, to enforce rights
protected by the Constitution.317 In American jurisprudence, a system of duality exists
between constitutional (federal) tort actions and torts under state law. Whitman states
that constitutional and common law often provide protections that seem to encompass
very similar interests. For example, a state may provide personal or property protection
that parallels the Fourth Amendment's guarantee against unreasonable searches and
seizures.318 She continues by stating that certain constitutional interests, such as the
right to equal treatment, the right to vote or the right to procedural due process, have
no equivalent in tort. Other constitutional rights, such as the right to choose to have an
abortion or the right of free speech, are uniquely rights against government action. 319
The United States‘ Congress passed a statute,320 as part of a Civil Rights Act,321 which
allowed civil damage actions to be brought against those who, under colour of state
law, have deprived others of their constitutional rights.
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
As discussed in Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) paras 25-37.
17 Stat. 13 1871.
The Fourteenth Amendment, which, in Section 1, provides for the extension of certain guaranteed
rights against the states, and in addition, in Section 5, empowers Congress to enforce, by
appropriate legislation, the provisions of this article.
Amendment IV: The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects,
against unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated, and no warrants shall issue, but
upon probable cause, supported by oath or affirmation, and particularly describing the place to be
searched, and the persons or things to be seized.
Whitman 1980 Michigan Law Review 14.
42 U.S.C. 1983.
17 Stat. 13 1871.
93
In Monroe v Pape,322 the Court held that a plaintiff whose constitutional rights have
been infringed by one acting under colour of state law could bring a federal cause of
action under Action 1983 even where the state provides an adequate remedy through
its common law of tort. Section 1983 afforded a federal remedy that was
supplementary to any appropriate state remedy and that the latter need not be
exhausted before invoking the federal one.323 The Court found that –324
[o]ne reason the legislation was passed was to afford a federal right in federal courts
because, due to prejudice, passion, neglect, intolerance or otherwise, state laws might
not be enforced and the claims of citizens to the enjoyment of rights, privileges, and
immunities guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment might be denied by the state
agencies.
Punitive damages are, however, not available against municipalities.325 The Court, after
reviewing common-law authorities covering more than a century, which had
consistently denied such punitive damages, examined the objectives of punitive
damages in general and their relationship to the goals of Section 1983. The Court
rejected the concept of retribution against a municipality, pointing out that punitive
damages only punished innocent taxpayers and constituted a windfall to a fully
compensated plaintiff. When constitutional damages have been proved, no damages for
the abstract value of the right infringed would be awarded, but only nominal damages,
which requires actual damages to be proved.326
In Bivens v Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Bureau of Narcotics, 327 the Supreme
Court held that it had the power to fashion a damages remedy directly under the
Constitution for the invasion of the petitioner‘s personal interests protected by the
Fourth Amendment, despite the fact that the Fourth Amendment made no express
provision for a remedy in damages.328 The petitioner‘s action was therefore not limited
to seeking a remedy under ordinary tort law. The Court held that the local trespass laws
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
365 US 167 1961 5.
Para 183.
Para 180.
Newport v Facts Concerts Inc 453 US 247, 271 (1981) paras 266-267.
Carey v Piphus 435 US 247 (1978).
403 US 388 (1971).
Para 396.
94
were remedially inadequate,329 and that the interests protected by state laws regulating
trespass and the invasion of privacy might be inconsistent with the Fourth Amendment
guarantee.330 The Court stressed the completely independent nature of the
constitutional damages remedy to protect Fourth Amendment rights.331
The Fourth Amendment right in question is an independent limitation on the exercise of
federal power.332 The Court stressed the different function of the law when dealing with
the rights of individuals inter se as compared to dealing with individual rights against
the state333 and highlighted the particular responsibility of the judiciary to vindicate the
constitutional interests of individuals entrenched in the Bill of Rights.334
In Carlson v Green,335 the court pointed out that a case brought before it based on a
constitutional cause of action can be defeated inter alia when the defendant shows that
Congress has provided an alternative remedy that is explicitly declared a substitute for
recovery directly under the Constitution and viewed as equally effective.336
This gave rise to an explosion of actions and has become a subject of considerable
comment and consternation.337 The dual system of remedies in place in American
jurisprudence has generated dissatisfaction since its inception.338 Although the American
system of torts and constitutional damages differs markedly from the South African
model, the South African courts found the views concerning the essential nature of the
remedy, in a more general normative sense, instructive.339 However, the Fose court
remarked on the difference between state liability in the United States and South Africa,
and counselled caution against seeking guidance from the United States jurisprudence
regarding the content of a suitable constitutional damages remedy. Claims against the
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
Paras 393-394 and 409-410.
Para 394.
Paras 390-395.
Para 394.
Paras 391-392.
Para 407.
446 US 14, 28, 28 n 1 (1980).
Paras 18-19.
Whitman 1980 Michigan Law Review 6.
Whitman 1980 Michigan Law Review 9.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 33.
95
state in the United States340 are far more limited in scope and content than similar
claims in South Africa.341 However, when a petitioner to the United States Supreme
Court has no other remedy to rely on, the Court readily grants relief in the form of
constitutional damages.342 This principle is also applied by the South African courts, as
will be shown in Section 2.5.3.3.
2.5.3.2.2 Position in Canada
Section 24(1) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms343 (CCRF) states that
anyone whose rights or freedoms, as guaranteed by the Charter, have been infringed or
denied may apply to a court of competent jurisdiction to obtain such remedy as the
court considers appropriate and just in the circumstances.
In R v Mills,344 the Court described the broad discretion the courts are allowed in section
24(1) of the CCRF:345
What remedies are available when an application under Section 24(1) of the Charter
succeeds? Section 24(1) again is silent on the question. It merely provides that the
appellant obtain such remedy, as the court considers appropriate and just in the
circumstances. It is difficult to imagine language, which could give the court a wider
and less fettered discretion. It is impossible to reduce this wide discretion to some sort
of binding formula for general application in all cases, and it is not for the appellate
courts to pre-empt or cut down this wide discretion.
The plaintiff in Canada is not limited to an action based on the general law of civil
liability, but can seek compensatory and punitive damages as an appropriate relief
under
section
24(1).346
The
Saskatchewan
Court
of
Appeal
has
held
that
appropriateness relates to the efficacy and suitability of the remedy viewed from the
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
The Federal Tort Claims Act 28 U.S.C. 2680(h) prohibits recovery against the Government for any
claim arising out of assault, battery, false imprisonment, false arrest, malicious prosecution, abuse of
process, libel, slander, misrepresentation, deceit, or interference with contract rights.
Section 1 of the State Liability Act 20 of 1957 provides as follows: Any claim against the State which
would, if that claim had arisen against a person, be the ground of an action in any competent court,
shall be cognizable by such court, whether the claim arises out of any contract lawfully entered into
on behalf of the State or out of any wrong committed by any servant of the State acting in his
capacity and within the scope of his authority as such servant.
Davis v Passman 442 US 228 (1979).
Part 1 of the Constitution Act, 1982.
(1986) 29 DLR (4th) 161.
Para 181.
Okpaluba and Osode Government liability 62.
96
perspective of the complainant and the right violated, whereas justness is a wider
concept relating to the interests of all affected by the remedy.347 The Court described
this as follows:
Appropriateness connotes efficaciousness and suitability from the standpoint of the
violation itself – a remedy ―to fit the offence‖ as it were. It suggests a remedy that,
from the perspective of the person whose right was violated, will effectively redress the
grievance brought about by the violation. The quality of justness, on the other hand,
has a broader scope of operation. It must fill a more extensive set of criteria than the
quality of appropriateness. To be just a remedy must be fair to all who are affected by
it. That group may well include persons other than the person whose right was
violated.
The Canadian Supreme Court has not yet pronounced on the question of whether
constitutional damages would constitute, in suitable cases, an appropriate and just
remedy for Charter violations, but it appears to be generally accepted that this would
be the case,348 although such a remedy has not yet been extensively used.349
In Nelles v Ontario,350 the Court found that a constitutional damages claim could run
concurrently with one for malicious prosecution.
In Vespoli v The Queen,351 the Federal Court of Appeal did not doubt that the court, in
terms of section 24(1), has the power to award damages to those whose rights and
freedoms have been infringed. However, the Court did not consider it appropriate and
just under the circumstances because there was no solid evidence that the appellants
really suffered damage because of the illegal seizures.
In Patenaude v Roy,352 exemplary damages were awarded by the Court for a deliberate
violation of the Quebec Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms 353 when police officers
used excessive and unnecessary force in executing a search warrant.
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
Saskatchewan Human Rights Commission v Kodellas (1989) 60 DLR (4th) 143 162.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 39; Cooper-Stephenson Charter
Damages Claims 1.
Roach Constitutional Remedies in Canada 11.10.
60 DLR (4th) 609 1989 (SCC) paras 640-643.
12 CRR 185 (1984) (Fed CA) para 189.
(1994) 123 DLR (4th) 78 (Que CA).
Charte des Droits et Libertés de la Personne, a statutory bill of rights and human rights code passed
by the National Assembly of Quebec on 27 June 1975.
97
In Vorvis v ICBC,354 the Court rejected limitations on the awarding of punitive damages
for constitutional violations.
Exemplary or punitive damages as Charter remedies have been awarded in several
cases.355 This must, however, be seen in the light of the fact that Canada‘s private law
system of torts recognises, in common with that of other common-law countries,
exemplary or punitive damages in appropriate circumstances in ordinary tort claims. 356
It is trite that, in South African law, no exemplary or punitive damages are awarded by
the courts. The plaintiff is awarded the damages he can prove, which means a person
can claim compensation from another for harm the claimant has suffered.357 The
common-law principles for awarding damages in South Africa and Canada are markedly
different. Currently there is a parallel system of claims in Canada that recognises a
claim for damages based on tort and, at the same time, a claim based on the breach of
a constitutional right. This dual system of claims has been expressly rejected by the
South African Constitutional Court.
2.5.3.3 Approach adopted by the South African Constitutional Court
Currie and De Waal maintain that constitutional rights and remedies, like their
counterparts in the common law, are complementary. The difference, however, lies in
the harm caused. The harm caused by violating a constitutional right is not merely
harm to an individual; it harms society as a whole. They argue that violation of a
constitutional right impedes the realisation of the constitutional project of creating a
just and democratic society. The object of the remedy should therefore be to vindicate
the Constitution and deter future infringements. Therefore, constitutional remedies are
―forward-looking, community-orientated and structural rather than backward-looking,
individualistic and retributive‖.358
354
355
356
357
358
58 DLR (4th) 193 (1989) (SCC) para 206.
Collin v Lussier 6 CRR (1983) 89 para 107; Lord v Allison 3 BCLR (2d) 300 (1986) (SC) para 324.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 40, footnote 88.
Loubser and Midgley The Law of Delict 4.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 196.
98
In S v Mhlungu,359 the Court held that where possible any case, civil or criminal, should
be heard without reaching a constitutional issue.360 This supports the principle of
subsidiarity, which means that if there is an adequate private-law remedy, whether in
common law or statute, that vindicates the right, it should be used. Only if the remedy
supplied by existing law is insufficient to fully vindicate the right, should direct reliance
be placed on constitutional remedies.361
In Fose v Minister of Safety and Security,362 the issue was raised whether constitutional
damages could and ought to be awarded as appropriate relief in terms of the provisions
of section 7(4)(a)363 of the Interim Constitution for a breach of the plaintiff‘s right
guaranteed by section 11(2)364 of the Interim Constitution. This included the right not to
be tortured and not to be subjected to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment 365 and
constituted an infringement of the plaintiff‘s fundamental rights as entrenched in
Chapter 3 of the Interim Constitution.366
The infringement of the plaintiff‘s fundamental rights formed part of widespread and
persistent similar infringements of the fundamental rights of other South African citizens
by members of the South African Police Service. The plaintiff‘s first two claims were
based on pain and suffering, loss of enjoyment of the amenities of life and shock,
contumelia and special damages in respect of past and future medical expenses. The
first claims were therefore based on delict.367 The plaintiff also claimed for constitutional
damages to be awarded, which included an element of punitive damages. The claim for
constitutional damages were sought in consequence of the same events and conduct
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
1995 (3) SA 867 (CC).
Para 59.
Bishop ―Remedies‖ 9-80.
1997 (3) SA 786 (CC).
Section 7(4)(a) of the Interim Constitution read: ―When an infringement of or threat to any right
entrenched in this Chapter is alleged, any person referred to in paragraph (b) shall be entitled to
apply to a competent court of law for appropriate relief, which may include a declaration of rights.‖
Section 11(2) read: ―No person shall be subject to torture of any kind, whether physical, mental or
emotional, nor shall any person be subject to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or
punishment.‖
Para 1.
Para 12.
Para 13.
99
that founded the first two delictual claims, but only in respect of the infringement of
plaintiff‘s Chapter 3 rights.
The plaintiff therefore limited his relief to the recovery of specific damages over and
above those to which he would have been entitled at common law. The respondent
took exception to the third claim on the basis that it did not disclose a cause of action,
alleging the following:368
(a)
An action for damages in the nature of constitutional damages does not
exist in law.
(b)
An order for the payment of damages does not qualify as appropriate relief
as contemplated in section 7(4)(a) of the Interim Constitution.
The Court found that the issue before it was whether, for the same assaults as were
pleaded in the first two claims, the plaintiff is entitled, in addition to the damages
claimed for those assaults in those claims, to recover ―constitutional damages‖ which
include ―an element of punitive damages‖.
The plaintiff argued:369
Section 7(4)(a) of the Interim Constitution establishes a separate cause of action, a
public law action directed against the state, based on the infringement of a
fundamental right entrenched in Chapter 3. The objectives of the law of delict differ
fundamentally from those of constitutional law. The primary purpose of the former is
to regulate relationships between private parties whereas the latter, to a large extent,
aims at protecting the Chapter 3 rights of individuals from state intrusion. Similarly the
purpose of a delictual remedy differs fundamentally from that of a constitutional
remedy.
The former seeks to provide compensation for harm caused to one private party by the
wrongful action of another private party whereas the latter has as its objective (a) the
vindication of the fundamental right itself so as to promote the values of an open and
democratic society based on freedom and equality and respect for human rights; (b)
the deterrence and prevention of future infringements of fundamental rights by the
legislative and executive organs of state at all levels of government; (c) the
punishment of those organs of state whose officials have infringed fundamental rights
in a particularly egregious fashion; and (d) compensation for harm caused to the
368
369
Para 14.
Para 17.
100
plaintiff in consequence of the infringement of one or more of the plaintiff‘s rights
entrenched in Chapter 3.
The common law remedies are not directed to the achievement of the first three of
these objectives and the common law should not be distorted by requiring it to
perform these functions and fulfil the purposes of constitutional law.
The Court found that the issues raised by the plaintiff turned on the proper construction
of section 7(4)(a) of the Interim Constitution, which entitles any person contemplated
in subsection (b) to apply to a competent court of law for appropriate relief, which may
include a declaration of rights.370 Before the adoption of the 1996 Constitution, the
Interim Constitution was the supreme law. It conferred rights on persons and told them
that they might look to the courts for the protection and enforcement of such rights.
This revolves around the question of appropriate relief and it is left to the courts to
decide what would be appropriate relief in any particular case.
The Court found that appropriate relief would in essence be relief that was required to
protect and enforce the Constitution.371 Depending on the circumstances of each
particular case, the relief might be a declaration of rights, an interdict, a mandamus or
such other relief as might be required to ensure that the rights enshrined in the
Constitution were protected and enforced. The Court held that, if it was necessary to do
so, the courts might even have to fashion new remedies to secure the protection and
enforcement of these all-important rights. However, the Court declined to award
punitive damages to the plaintiff.
In NAPTOSA v Minister of Education, Western Cape Government,372 the applicants
argued that the Constitution elevates the entitlement to fair labour practices to a
fundamental right.373 Relying on this constitutionalisation of labour rights, the applicants
contended that an employee whose fundamental right to fair labour practices had been
violated might, instead of relying on the provisions of the Labour Relations Act (LRA),374
370
371
372
373
374
Para 18.
Para 19.
2001 (2) SA 112 (C).
Section 23(1) of the Constitution provides that everyone has the right to fair labour practices.
66 of 1995.
101
rely directly on the Constitution.375 The respondent argued that the High Court had no
jurisdiction to grant the relief sought in the notice of motion and that the application
should have been brought in the Labour Court. The Court found that section 23(1) of
the Constitution provides that everyone has the right to fair labour practices. The Court
ruled that in concluding a contract with the applicants in terms that financially
discriminated against them, the respondent committed an unfair labour practice and
since the Bill of Rights binds the legislature, the executive, the judiciary and all organs
of state,376 the respondent violated the applicant‘s constitutional right to fair labour
practices. The Court justified its ruling as follows:
The high court has the primary responsibility for the enforcement of fundamental
rights. It has jurisdiction to pronounce upon all violations of fundamental rights. This is
plain from section 169 of the Constitution. The qualification in section 157(2) of the
LRA is intended to restrict the competence of the labour court to fundamental rights
issues in the employment sphere. The applicants have ―alleged‖ a violation of their
fundamental right to fair labour practices. It does not matter whether the claim is good
or bad. That goes to the merits. If it appears from supporting information that the
allegation is without substance a court may already at the stage of the jurisdictional
enquiry decide that the case cannot concern a violation of a fundamental right and
decline to exercise jurisdiction. This is not such a case. In this case and, I would think
generally, once the allegation has been made, the high court would have jurisdiction.
The Court, relying on the judgment in Fose v Minister of Safety and Security,377 stated
that there might be circumstances in which a litigant against the state would be entitled
to rely directly on a breach of a fundamental right. Whether this would be permissible,
would depend, however, on the availability of ―appropriate relief‖.378
Appropriate relief in these circumstances would in essence be relief that is necessary to
protect and enforce the Constitution. In deciding what appropriate relief is, the interests
not only of the complainant but also of society as a whole ought to be served. 379
Constitutional rights have complementary remedies and they should be of a kind that
vindicates the Constitution. Current statutory and common-law remedies may be
sufficient for this purpose.
375
376
377
378
379
NAPTOSA page 6.
Section 8(1) and (2) of the Constitution.
1997 (3) SA 786 (CC).
NAPTOSA page 11.
NAPTOSA page 7.
102
There were powerful reasons for not excluding common-law and statutory relief from
the ambit of section 7(4)(a).380 The Court found that statutes, such as the LRA, seek to
codify constitutional rights, and are expressly designed to provide suitable relief for the
infringement of constitutional rights.381 It would undermine the best efforts of the
legislature if these remedies were to be excluded from a court‘s arsenal of remedial
options.
The Court stated that the drafters of the Constitution did not intend to exclude
common-law and statutory remedies from the remedial scheme. A court has a wide
range of remedies at its disposal when exercising its section 7(4)(a) powers. These
remedies include common-law relief, statutory relief, declaratory relief and a number of
potential remedies in terms of sections 98 and 101(4).382 The Court found that no
remedy is excluded, provided the remedy serves to vindicate the Constitution and deter
its further infringement. Section 1 of the LRA provides that the primary objects of the
Act are, inter alia, to give effect to and regulate the fundamental rights conferred by
the Constitution, and to promote the effective resolution of labour disputes.383 The Court
argued that –
[o]ne would expect the LRA, if it were true to its stated objectives, to marry the
enforcement of fundamental rights with the effective resolution of labour disputes. This
is exactly what it seeks to do. It provides mechanisms for the enforcement of such
labour practices as the legislature considers to be fair and the suppression of any
labour practice considered to be unfair. If an employer adopts a labour practice which
is thought to be unfair, an aggrieved employee would in the first instance be obliged to
seek a remedy under the LRA. If he or she finds no remedy under that Act, the LRA
might come under constitutional scrutiny for not giving adequate protection to a
constitutional right. If a labour practice permitted by the LRA is not fair, a court might
be persuaded to strike down the impugned provision.
The Court stated that to grant relief would encourage the development of two parallel
systems and that this would be inappropriate. The right to fair labour practices was not
380
381
382
383
Section 7(4)(a) of the Interim Constitution read: ―When an infringement of or threat to any right
entrenched in this Chapter is alleged, any person referred to in paragraph (b) shall be entitled to
apply to a competent court of law for appropriate relief, which may include a declaration of rights.‖
NAPTOSA page 8.
Sections 98 and 101(4) of the Interim Constitution dealt with the jurisdiction and powers of the
Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court, respectively.
Section 1(a) and (d) of the LRA.
103
a right that could be applied directly in the workplace without an intervening regulatory
framework.384 The social and policy issues were too complex for that, because the issue
of the horizontal application of the labour relations rights to private citizens would be
mainly academic. Existing labour legislation already regulated, to a large degree, private
conduct between employers and employees. The horizontal reach of the labour rights
therefore extend to matters falling within the scope of the rights but not covered by
existing legislation.385
The Court, however, stated that section 19(1)(a)(iii) of the Supreme Court Act386 gave
the High Court jurisdiction in its discretion, and at the instance of any interested
person, to enquire into and determine any existing, future or contingent right,
notwithstanding that such person cannot claim any relief consequential upon the
determination.387 Although it may be competent for a court to make a declaratory order
in any particular case, granting such is dependent on the judicial exercise by that Court
of its discretion with due regard to the circumstances of the matter before it.
The Court approvingly referred to the case of Adbro Investment Company Limited v
Minister of the Interior,388 in which it was found that –389
the Court in each case must … carefully determine whether or not the particular case
in question is a proper case for the exercise of its discretion. For a case to be a proper
case, in my view, generally speaking it should require to be shown that despite the fact
that no consequential relief is being claimed or perhaps could be claimed in the
proceedings, yet justice or convenience demands that a declaration be made.
A declaratory order is an order by which a dispute over the existence of some legal
right or entitlement is resolved. The right can exist, be prospective or contingent. 390 A
declaratory order need have no claim for specific relief attached to it, but it would not
ordinarily be appropriate where one is dealing with events that occurred in the past.
Such events, if they gave rise to a cause of action, would entitle the litigant to an
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
NAPTOSA page 9.
Page 10.
59 of 1959 (subsequently repealed by Act 10 of 2013).
NAPTOSA page 11.
(3) 283 (T).
Para 285B-D.
NAPTOSA page 12.
104
appropriate remedy. The Court found, however, that substantial delay in bringing the
proceedings was a reason for exercising the Court‘s discretion against the grant of a
declaratory order; because of the lateness of the application, a declaratory order would
be of academic value only.391
In Chirwa v Transnet Limited,392 the applicant approached the High Court in respect of a
claim relating to unfair dismissal. She relied on two causes of action available to her:
one under the LRA393 and the other flowing from the Bill of Rights, read with the
provisions of the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act394 (PAJA).395
The High Court assumed that it had jurisdiction in the matter, but did not reach this
conclusion based on the alleged violation of the provisions of PAJA as pleaded by the
applicant. Instead, the High Court decided the matter based on common-law rules of
natural justice, and concluded that the rules of natural justice had been breached.396
The Constitutional Court found that the High Court erred in that it did not consider the
applicant‘s claim in the context of PAJA. The cause of action of what is claimed to be an
administrative action now arises from PAJA and not from the common law, as it would
have in the past.397 The Court further held that when an alternative cause of action can
be sustained in matters arising out of an employment relationship in which the
employee alleges unfair dismissal or an unfair labour practice by the employer, it is in
the first instance through the mechanisms established by the LRA that the employee
should pursue her or his claims.398 The constitutional right the applicant sought to
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
NAPTOSA page 13.
(2008) 29 ILJ 73 (CC).
66 of 1995.
3 of 2000.
Para 19 of Transnet .
Para 21. The High Court based its decision on Administrator, Transvaal v Zenzile 1991 (1) SA 21 (A),
in which it was held that dismissal of a public sector employee was not simply the termination of a
contractual relationship but the exercise of a public power which required the employer to apply the
rules of natural justice.
Para 23.
Para 41.
105
vindicate was regulated in detail by the LRA and, as such, the Labour Court should have
been approached.399
The applicant was, in the Court's view, not at liberty to relegate the finely tuned dispute
resolution structures created by the LRA. If that were allowed, a dual system of law
would fester in cases of dismissal of employees by employers, one applicable in civil
courts and the other applicable in the forums and mechanisms established by the LRA.
Further, even if the applicant sought to challenge the dismissal by relying on a
constitutional issue other than one implemented through PAJA (as has been done in the
current case by relying on section 195 of the Constitution), it was necessary to exhaust
all remedies under the LRA before raising such an issue in a different forum.400
However, this line of reasoning would not apply if an applicant sought to challenge the
provisions of the LRA on the basis that they were inadequate in providing protection to
employees in the form contemplated by section 23 of the Constitution. That would raise
a constitutional matter that was justiciable in the High Court.401
In Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Re-
integration of Offenders,402 the Court found that –
[t]he values enunciated in section 1 of the Constitution are of fundamental importance.
They inform and give substance to all the provisions of the Constitution. They do not,
however, give rise to discrete and enforceable rights in themselves. This is clear not
only from the language of section 1 itself, but also from the way the Constitution is
structured and in particular the provisions of Chapter 2 which contains the Bill of
Rights.
In Modderklip,403 the Court used section 34404 to develop a general right to an effective
constitutional remedy and granted constitutional damages based on the breach of this
right. The Court made the strong statement that if a constitutional breach is established
399
400
401
402
403
404
Para 64.
Para 68.
Para 69.
2005 (3) SA 280 (CC) para 21.
Modder East Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd, President of the Republic of South Africa v
Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 3 All SA 169 (SCA) 2004.
Section 34 of the Constitution provides that everyone has the right to have a dispute resolved by a
court.
106
courts are mandated to grant appropriate relief.405 The Court found that the applicant‘s
right not to be arbitrarily deprived of property406 have been breached.407 The state failed
in its constitutional duty to protect the rights of the applicant. It failed to provide the
occupiers with land that would have enabled the applicant to enforce an eviction order.
Instead, it allowed the burden of the occupiers' need for land to fall on an individual,
the applicant in the matter.408
Section 9(1) of the Constitution provides that everyone is equal before the law and has
the right to equal protection and benefit of the law, while section 9(2) provides that
equality includes the full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms.409 The
applicant was not treated equally because as an individual it had to bear the heavy
burden, which rests on the state, to provide land to some 40 000 people. The right of
access to adequate housing is not one enforceable at common law, or in terms of the
Constitution, against an individual landowner and in no legislation has the state
transferred this obligation to such an owner.410
The Court found that the only appropriate and justified remedy in those circumstances
was that of ―constitutional‖ damages due to the breach of a constitutionally entrenched
right.411 The constitutional damages had the advantage that the occupiers could remain
where they were while the applicant was recompensed for that which it had lost. The
Court justified and based its ruling on the breach of a constitutional right, even though
no common-law or statutory remedy existed for the enforcement of such a right.
The duality that exists when a constitutional principle guaranteeing a basic right is
given effect through enabling legislation can best be described with reference to section
32 of the Constitution.412 Section 32(2) provides that legislation must be enacted to give
effect to the right entrenched in subsection (1). The legislature complied by adopting
405
406
407
408
409
Para 18.
Section 25(1) of the Constitution.
Para 21.
Para 30.
Para 31.
410
Theewaterskloof Holdings (Pty) Ltd, Glaser Afdeling v Jacobsen 2002 (3) SA 401 (LCC) para 18.
411
Para 43.
The right to access to information.
412
107
the Promotion of Access to Information Act (hereafter PAIA).413 This, however, left the
question of whether, once the envisaged legislation had been enacted, such legislation
would be the sole means of enforcing one's right of access to information, effectively
causing a ―permanent constitutional lock-out‖.414 Botha et al argue that a constitutional
cause of action would be supplemental to legislative and executive measures without
terming those measures themselves unreasonable.415
In Institute for Democracy in South Africa v African National Congress ,416 the Court held
that access to information might only be pursued through PAIA and not through section
32 of the Constitution. In this case, the Institute for Democracy in South Africa
(IDASA), a non-profit organisation, sent requests to four political parties asking for
detailed information about each party‘s private donations. After all requests were
denied, IDASA sought judicial review in the High Court of South Africa in the interests
of all South African citizens and in the public interest.417 The Court addressed three
main issues:
(a)
Whether IDASA must seek relief under PAIA as opposed to seeking relief
directly under section 32 of the Constitution.418
(b)
Whether political parties are ―public bodies‖ or ―private bodies‖ under
PAIA.419
(c)
Whether records relating to private fund-raising are ―required for the
exercise or protection of any rights‖.420
For the purpose of this work, only the first question is relevant and is discussed here.
The Court concluded that section 32 of the Constitution is not capable of serving as an
independent cause of action for enforcement of access-to-information rights because to
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
2 of 2000.
Van Heerden , Govindjee and Holness 2014 Speculum Juris 30-31.
Botha, Van der Walt AJ and Van der Walt CJ Rights and Democracy 114-115.
2005 (5) SA 39 (CC).
Paras 9-18.
Para 22.
Para 37.
Para 53.
108
conclude otherwise would cause a confusing juxtaposition with PAIA by encouraging
the development of two parallel systems, which would be singularly inappropriate. 421
The Court argued that section 32(2) of the Constitution merely provided a transitional
provision to govern access-to-information rights for a three-year period until the
legislation envisaged by that section was enacted. Because PAIA has since been
enacted, the only possible cause of action that could be brought pursuant to section 32
is a challenge to the constitutionality of PAIA itself.422
Therefore, as soon as the legislature promulgates legislation protecting a right
contained in the Bill of Rights, the statutory cause of action provided for in the enabling
legislation provides the basis for a claim, and not the original constitutional principle.
This is clearly designed to deny the litigant the choice of whether to proceed with a
claim based on the enabling legislation or a claim based on the breach of a
constitutional right. This prevents a duality of claims being available to the litigant.
However, a claim can still be brought in terms of the Constitution when the litigant
challenges the constitutionality of the enabling legislation. This means that when the
enabling legislation does not sufficiently provide for the protection of the right in
question, a challenge can still be brought to the validity and constitutionality of the
legislation based on the constitutional right.
In Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet,423 the Court found that private-law
damages claims are not always the most appropriate method of enforcing constitutional
rights. Private-law remedies tend to be retrospective in effect, seeking to remedy loss
caused rather than to prevent loss in the future. Moreover, the use of private-law
remedies to claim damages to vindicate public-law rights may place heavy financial
burdens on the state.424 This does not mean that delictual relief should not lie for the
infringement of constitutional rights in appropriate circumstances. There will be
circumstances in which delictual relief is appropriate. It is important, however, that the
value of public-law remedies as effective and appropriate forms of constitutional relief is
421
422
423
424
Paras 33-36.
Paras 23 and 33.
2005 (2) SA 359 (CC).
Para 80.
109
not overlooked.425 The Court unfortunately did not set out the circumstances in which
public-law remedies would be the appropriate basis on which to approach the courts.
In Steenkamp v Provincial Tender Board of the Eastern Cape,426 the Court considered
the future impact of the judgment and refused to award delictual liability for expenses
suffered by the applicant for the following reason:427
The chilling effect of the imposition of delictual liability on tender boards in a young
democracy with limited resources, human and financial, on balance, is real because if
liability were to be imposed, the potentiality of a claim by every successful tenderer
would cast a shadow over the deliberations of a tender board on each tender and may
slow the process down or even grind it to a halt.
Although it is important for the Court to consider the future effect of its judgments, the
reasoning of the Court cannot be correct. In Mhlungu,428 the Court held that the
principle of subsidiarity is relevant in South African law.429 Therefore, when there is an
adequate private-law remedy, whether in common law or statute, that vindicates the
right, it should be used. In Steenkamp, the plaintiff used the law of delict to pursue a
claim for just administrative action but the Court, although convinced that the plaintiff
did indeed suffer damages, refused to grant compensation.
Bishop argues that, while the principle of subsidiarity is fine in theory, it gives rise to
two practical drawbacks. Firstly, the individual litigant is primarily interested in securing
individual compensation for the breach of constitutional rights and less concerned about
preventing future violations. Broader problems with constitutional violations from state
or private action may go unnoticed. Constitutional remedies by necessity need to
address systemic problems of constitutional breach and must hold out the promise that
future violations of the constitution concerned would be curtailed or at least addressed.
The second problem with the doctrine relates to a business-as-usual approach to
425
426
427
428
429
Para 81.
2007 (3) BCLR 280 (CC).
Para 40.
1995 (3) SA 867 (CC).
Para 59.
110
remedies. Bishop asks what the court would have done if Steenkamp had approached
the court directly, therefore on a constitutional basis, to found his claim. 430
In Steenkamp,431 the Court held that the plaintiff‘s constitutional rights had been
breached but that this did not entitle him to delictual damages. The principle of
subsidiarity requires the plaintiff to frame his constitutional claim in delictual terms but
then allows the law of delict to prevent the vindication of the constitutional right. Bishop
proposes that the principle of subsidiarity should be modified to the extent that where
the private law remedy only partially vindicates the constitutional right breached, the
plaintiff is entitled to rely solely on constitutional law for all aspects of his or her relief.
Should the plaintiff do so, the private-law remedy should not be a bar to granting the
same relief under constitutional law.432
In MEC for the Department of Welfare v Kate,433 the Court applied a modified version of
the subsidiarity principle. The case relates to section 27 of the Constitution that obliges
the state to achieve the progressive realisation of the right that everyone has to social
security – including, if they are unable to support themselves and their dependants,
appropriate social assistance – by taking reasonable legislative and other measures
within its available resources towards that end. In the realisation of this right, the state
promulgated the Social Assistance Act.434 The Act obliges the provincial government
(subject to the provisions of the Act and the concurrence of the member of the
Executive Council responsible for the provincial budget) to make social grants to
disabled persons out of moneys appropriated by the provincial legislature for that
purpose.435
The Court stated that the establishment of a legislative and administrative structure by
the state for the making of social grants and the appropriation of moneys for that
purpose together went a long way to fulfilling the state‘s constitutional obligation, but
430
431
432
433
434
435
Bishop ―Remedies‖ 9-80.
Steenkamp v Provincial Tender Board of the Easter Cape 2007 (3) BCLR 280 (CC).
Bishop ―Remedies‖ 9-81.
2006 (4) SA 478 (SCA).
59 of 1992.
Section 2(a) of the Act.
111
by themselves they were not enough. Reasonable measures to make the system
effective were required. On that score, there had been conspicuous and endemic failure
in the Eastern Cape for a considerable time,436 the result of which was a plethora of
litigation in the High Court between the poor of that province and the provincial
administration.437 Regulations were promulgated on the day the Act came into
operation.438 The 1996 regulations required an applicant for a grant to complete and
sign an application form in the presence of an attesting officer,439 and the date on which
that was done was deemed the date on which the application was made.440 The
defendant completed and signed the grant application on 16 April 1996 and therefore
the disability grant, once approved, accrued from 16 April 1996.441
The defendant was advised in August 1999 that her application had been approved,
with no explanation at all for the thirty-seven month delay.442 On 15 October 2003, an
application was launched in the High Court in which declaratory relief was sought
together with orders for the recovery of the balance of the accrual and interest on that
amount.443 The outstanding balance was paid over to the defendant, so the principal
issue that remained in dispute when the matter came before the court was whether the
defendant was entitled to the interest that she had claimed on the accrual.444 The court
a quo granted declaratory relief and ordered the appellant to pay the interest
claimed.445
On appeal, the appellant submitted that the claim for payment of the accrual, and for
interest on it from the date that it became payable, ought to have been pursued by
ordinary action in the magistrates‘ courts and not by review proceedings in the High
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
Kate para 3.
Para 4.
Regulations Regarding Grants, Social Relief Of Distress And Financial Awards In Terms Of The Social
Assistance Act, 1992, promulgated under Government Notice R.373 in Government Gazette No.
17016 of 1 March 1996.
Regulation 8 of the 1996 Regulations.
Regulation 9 of the 1996 Regulations
Kate para 9.
Para 10.
Para 13.
Para 14.
Para 15.
112
Court.446 Interest during that period was claimed and awarded as a measure of
constitutional damages for the unreasonable delay the defendant was constrained to
endure. The defendant‘s case was that the unreasonable delay in considering her
application deprived her during that period of her constitutional right to receive a social
grant, and for that deprivation, she ought to be recompensed by an order for
damages.447
The Court held that the matter of constitutional damages should not be approached
narrowly.448 The realisation of substantive rights is usually dependent upon an
administrative process. Rights that protect that process are essentially ancillary to the
realisation of those substantive rights. Without protection being given to the process,
the substantive rights are capable of being denied. Where, as in the case under
discussion, the realisation of the substantive right to social assistance is dependent on
lawful and procedurally fair administrative action, and the diligent and prompt
performance by the state of its constitutional obligations, the failure to meet those
process obligations denies to the beneficiary his or her substantive right to social
assistance.
The Court found that what had been denied to the defendant was not merely the
enjoyment of a process in the abstract, but, through denial of that process, she was
denied her right to social assistance, which was dependent for its realisation on an
effective process. The denial of that substantive right by the state lay at the centre of
her claim. As to appropriate relief, the court held as follows:449
Whether relief in that form is appropriate in a particular case must necessarily be
determined casuistically with due regard to, amongst other things, the nature and
relative importance of the rights that are in issue, the alternative remedies that might
be available to assert and vindicate them, and the consequences of the breach for the
claimant concerned.
The appellant submitted that the defendant had delictual remedies that were
restorative of any loss that had been caused to her by the failure of the administration
446
447
448
449
Para
Para
Para
Para
16.
17.
22.
25.
113
to perform its constitutional duties and that in those circumstances a remedy of
constitutional damages was not required.
The Court rejected the submission, stating that delictual principles are capable of being
extended to encompass state liability for the breach of constitutional obligations. 450
Nevertheless, the relief permitted by section 38 of the Constitution is not a remedy of
last resort, to be looked to only when there is no alternative, and indirect, means of
asserting and vindicating constitutional rights. The Court stated that there was no
reason why a direct breach of a substantive constitutional right (as opposed to merely a
deviation from a constitutionally normative standard) should be remedied indirectly.
The endemic breach of the rights that were in issue justified the clear assertion of their
independent existence. It is submitted that the Court followed the correct approach in
allowing the claim to be brought under the auspices of section 38, that is, the right to
approach a competent court should a constitutional right be breached or threatened.
This broad interpretation of section 38 gives sufficient effect to the section to allow for
the comprehensive protection of fundamental rights. The Court listed two reasons for
allowing direct constitutional damages. Firstly, the constitutional breach was a direct
breach of a specific fundamental right and, secondly, the breach was endemic and
required a clear assertion of the importance of the constitutional right. 451 Therefore,
although a common-law remedy in the form of delict was available, the court allowed
the defendant compensation whilst relying on a direct constitutional cause of action.
O‘Regan J, in assessing the relationship between common-law remedies in areas of the
law covered by the Bill of Rights and direct constitutional remedies, argued that there
was no doubt that the Constitution required infringements of the Constitution to be
remedied.452 The question is whether the Constitution, properly interpreted, permits a
claim under common law as well as a simultaneous constitutional claim directly under
the provisions of section 24 of the Interim Constitution, which entrenched the right to
administrative justice. She continued by arguing as follows:
450
451
452
Para 27.
Bishop ―Remedies‖ 9-82.
O‘Regan ―On the reach of the Constitution‖ 71-72.
114
Bear in mind that if that were to be so, it might have been quite possible to have a
successful claim under say, the Constitution, but not under the common law, or vice
versa. The two systems could have co-existed side by side, perhaps based on entirely
different rules. Two causes of action could have arisen, for example, where a person
complained of an infringement of dignity, or personal liberty, or security of the person.
The first would have been under the actio legis aquiliae or actio injuriarum (depending
on the nature of the claim) and the other a constitutional remedy. Duplication could
have arisen in labour law, administrative law, environmental law, the right to freedom
and security of the person and even criminal procedure. Again, with the distinction
between the jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court, on the one hand, and the Supreme
Court of Appeal, on the other, these claims could have been resolved in different
courts, with potentially very different outcomes and scant jurisprudential crosspollination.
She reasoned that the question of whether the Constitution always gave rise to a
freestanding cause of action, even where an appropriate common-law or statutory
remedy already existed, had been answered in the negative by the Constitutional Court.
Textual support for this conclusion is to be found in sections 39(2)453 and 173(2).454
The courts use a wide interpretation of the right of access to court to develop a number
of constitutional principles and doctrines, which are not expressly mentioned in the
Constitution, but have been increasingly used by the courts.455 Some, like the principle
of legality, provides an independent cause of action,456 while the court has also
employed the doctrine of the separation of powers457 and the principle of ubuntu458 to
support its decisions.
In summary, the following points can be highlighted:
(a)
The courts subscribe to the principle of subsidiarity, meaning that when
there is an adequate private-law remedy, whether of statute or common
law, that vindicates a constitutional right it should be used.
453
454
455
456
457
458
Section 39(2) requires the courts to develop the common law and interpret statutes in a manner that
is consistent with the spirit, purport and object of the Bill of Rights.
Section 173(2) states that the Constitutional Court has the inherent power to develop the common
law.
Hoexter The judiciary in South Africa 380.
Fedsure paras 56-59; Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association paras 83-85.
Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa 2009 (1) SA 287 (CC).
Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC) para 37.
115
(b)
A constitutional right can be directly relied on if the remedy provided by the
existing common or statutory law is insufficient to fully vindicate the right.
(c)
The court will grant damages arising from a breach of a constitutionally
entrenched right if no common-law or statutory remedy exists for the
enforcement of the right. Furthermore, when there is an endemic breach of
constitutional rights, a public-law remedy based on constitutional rights
would be acceptable to the courts.
(d)
When legislation has been enacted to give effect to a constitutional right,
such legislation would be the sole means of enforcing the right, effectively
causing a permanent constitutional lockout. In such an instance, the
constitutional right can only be used to attack the constitutionality of the
legislation in question.
(e)
The courts will not grant punitive damages when a constitutional right has
been breached. The traditional approach to damages, which requires a
plaintiff to claim only the damages that can be proved, is followed.
(f)
The relief that a court grants for breach of a constitutional right is not
centred on the individual whose right has been breached. The relief granted
will be relief that is required to protect and enforce the Constitution and
must be to the benefit of the plaintiff and society as a whole.
(g)
Although the constitutional values enunciated by section 1 of the
Constitution are of fundamental importance, they do not give rise to
discrete and enforceable rights by themselves.
2.6 Constitutional remedies
2.6.1 Introduction
A judicial remedy is the method by which the courts enforce a right, impose a penalty
or make an order to impose its will. In the context of constitutional litigation, the
remedy is the means by which a court enforces the Constitution and corrects the
116
violation of a constitutional right or holds the legislature and executive accountable to
the Constitution. Therefore, a remedy is a mechanism used to repair an infringement of
rights once a court has interpreted the right and found the conduct of a government
department or a private individual to be lacking.459
In Fose,460 the Court asked the question what, if constitutional rights have
complementary remedies, these remedies should be.461 The Court answered that the
nature of a remedy is determined by its object. According to the Court, the harm
caused by violating the Constitution ―is harm to the society as a whole, even where the
direct implications of the violation are highly parochial‖. Therefore, the rights violator
not only harms a particular person, but also impedes the realisation of the constitutional
promise. The object of constitutional remedies should be addressing these kinds of
harm, vindicating the Constitution, and deterring its further infringement.462
Vindication is used by the Court here to mean defending against encroachment on or
interference with the Constitution. It suggests that certain harms, if not addressed,
diminish faith in the Constitution. It recognises that a constitution has as little or as
much weight as the prevailing political culture affords it. The defence of the
Constitution, its vindication, is a burden imposed primarily on the judiciary. When
exercising discretion to choose between appropriate forms of relief, the courts must
carefully analyse the nature of the constitutional infringement, and strike effectively at
its source.
The remedies offered by the Constitution are dependent on the manner in which the Bill
of Rights applies to the dispute. The application of the remedies can be described as
follows:463
(a)
Direct and vertical application of the Bill of Rights: Sections 38 and 172(1)
of the Constitution apply. The sections provide for the following remedies:
459
460
461
462
463
De Vos and Freedman South African Constitutional Law 390.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 94.
Para 95.
Para 96.
De Vos and Freedman South African Constitutional Law 391-392.
117
Declaration of invalidity, declaration of rights, interdicts, constitutional
damages and meaningful engagement.
(b)
Direct and horizontal application of the Bill of Rights: Section 8(2) and (3)
of the Constitution applies. The section provide for the following remedies:
Remedies derived from legislation giving effect to the Bill of Rights,
developing the common law to give effect to the Bill of Rights.
(c)
Indirect application of the Bill of Rights: Section 39(2) of the Constitution
applies. The section provide for the following remedies: Common-law
remedies and customary-law remedies.
Section 38 of the Constitution provides that anyone listed in the section may approach
the courts alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened. In
terms of section 38, a court may grant appropriate relief, including a declaration of
rights. Section 38 therefore provides for a flexible approach to remedies. 464 When courts
grant relief, they attempt to synchronise the real world with the ideal construct of a
constitutional world. This relates to the principle that rights and remedies are
complementary.
By contrast, section 39(2) of the Constitution provides that when interpreting the Bill of
Rights, courts must promote the values that underlie an open and democratic society
based on human dignity, equality and freedom.
The powers of courts in constitutional matters are set out in section 172 of the
Constitution. Section 172(1) reads as follows:
When deciding a constitutional matter, a court –
(a)
must declare that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the
Constitution is invalid to the extent of its inconsistency; and
(b)
may make any order that is just and equitable, including –
(i)
464
an order limiting the retrospective effect of the declaration of
invalidity; and
Sanderson v Attorney-General, Eastern Cape 1998 (2) SA 38 (CC) para 38.
118
(ii)
an order suspending the declaration of invalidity for any period
and on any conditions, to allow the competent authority to correct
the defect.
Section 172 therefore grants the court the power to make any order that is just and
equitable, giving force to the judicial obligation recognised by Ackermann to ―forge new
tools‖ and shape ―innovative remedies‖.465
In terms of section 172(1)(b) of the Constitution, courts have the power to order any
just and equitable remedy ―that would place substance above mere form by identifying
the actual underlying dispute between the parties‖.466 Therefore, the discretion provided
for in section 172(1)(b) to make a just and equitable order is in force even when the
outcome of a constitutional dispute is not contingent upon the constitutional invalidity
of legislation or conduct.467
South African courts have a wide range of powers at their disposal to ensure that the
Constitution is upheld.468 These include mandatory and structural interdicts. How they
exercise those powers should depend on the circumstances of each particular case. In
this regard the appropriate constitutional remedy would arise from constitutional
interpretation. Due regard should be paid to the roles of the legislature and the
executive in a democracy. However, when it is appropriate to do so, courts may, and if
need be must, use their wide powers to make orders that affect policy as well as
legislation.
2.6.2 The range of constitutional remedies available
2.6.2.1
Declaration of rights
A declaration of rights allows a party to approach the court to declare what the law is
on a specific issue and, consequently, what the rights are of parties affected by the
465
466
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC)
Head of Department of Education: Free State Province v Welkom High School 2014 (12) SA (CC)
467
para 107.
Para 108.
468
Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 113.
119
issue.469 A declaration of rights is not a declaration of invalidity; the aim of the
declaration of rights is to resolve a dispute between parties and it may be given even
where no law or conduct has been found to be inconsistent with the Constitution.470
The High Court may make a declaratory order in terms of section 21(1)(c) of the
Superior Courts Act (previously section 19(1)(a)(iii) of the Supreme Court Act).471 The
section provides that a division has the power, in its discretion, and at the instance of
any interested person, enquire into and determine any existing, future or contingent
right or obligation, notwithstanding that such person cannot claim relief consequential
upon the determination. In Ex parte Nell,472 the Court held that for the granting of a
declaration of rights in terms of the provisions of section 19(1)(c) of the Supreme Court
Act an existing dispute is not a prerequisite to jurisdiction under this section. However,
there must be interested parties on whom the declaratory order would be binding.
More recently, the Court confirmed the Nell decision in Myburgh Park Langebaan (Pty)
Ltd v Langebaan Municipality,473 holding that in deciding whether a declarator should be
granted, the Court must consider whether the applicant has an interest in existing,
future or contingent rights or obligations as intended in section 19(1)(a)(iii) of the
Supreme Court Act. If so satisfied, the Court must decide whether the case is a proper
one for the exercise of its discretion. The Court confirmed that an existing dispute is not
a prerequisite for jurisdiction, but there must be interested parties on whom the
declaratory order would be binding.
In Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet Ltd t/a Metrorail,474 the question was raised
of who bears responsibility for ensuring the safety of passengers travelling on
commuter trains. The applicants therefore sought declaratory relief. The Court relied on
section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution, which provides that the Court must declare ―any
law or conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution‖ invalid to the extent of its
469
470
471
472
473
474
Peté et al Civil Procedure 426.
De Vos and Freedman South African Constitutional Law 406.
10 of 2013 and 59 of 1959, respectively.
1963 (1) SA 754 (A) paras 759A-B.
2001 (4) SA 1144 (C) paras 1153B-1154B.
2005 (2) SA 359 (CC).
120
inconsistency.475 Section 172(1)(a) is a special constitutional provision, different from
the common-law rules governing the grant of declaratory orders. This does not prevent
a court from making declaratory orders when constitutional inconsistency is not found.
Litigants may rely on section 38 of the Constitution,476 in terms of which a court may
grant a declaration of rights if it would constitute appropriate relief. The Court further
held that, in contrast to section 172(1)(a), section 38 does not oblige the courts to
grant a declaration of rights, but they may do so if they deem it appropriate relief.
In Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority,477 the Court
examined the difference between the jurisdiction of the High Court to grant declaratory
relief and section 172 of the Constitution. The Court held that –
[a] court‘s power under section 172 of the Constitution is a unique remedy created by
the Constitution. The section is the constitutional source of the power to declare law or
conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution invalid. It provides that when a court
decides a constitutional matter, it must declare invalid any law or conduct inconsistent
with the Constitution. It does not however expressly regulate the circumstances in
which a court should decide a constitutional matter.
The Court stated that in determining when a court should decide a constitutional
matter, the jurisprudence developed under section 19(1)(a)(iii) 478 would have relevance;
however, the constitutional setting may introduce considerations different from those
which are relevant to the exercise of a judge‘s discretion in terms of section
19(1)(a)(iii). The Court highlighted some of these differences:
(a)
A court should not ordinarily decide a constitutional issue unless it is
necessary to do so.
(b)
475
476
477
478
A court should not ordinarily decide a constitutional issue that is moot.
Para 106.
Section 38 provides that anyone listed in this section has the right to approach a competent court,
alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened, and the court may grant
appropriate relief, including a declaration of rights.
2002 (4) SA 294 (CC); 2002 (5) BCLR 433 (CC) paras 8-12.
Supreme Court Act 59 of 1959 (repealed).
121
(c)
The decision as to whether a court should decide a constitutional matter
remains one governed by the Constitution and its imperatives, not one
determined solely by a consideration of the circumstances in which
declaratory relief in terms of section 19 of the Supreme Court Act479 would
be granted.
The difference between the jurisdiction of the High Court to grant declaratory relief and
section 172 of the Constitution may lead to legal uncertainty.
In the Islamic Unity Convention case, the Court took the applicant‘s request for a
declaration that the provision480 was inconsistent with the Constitution to be a prayer for
a declaratory order in terms of section 19(1)(a)(iii) of the Supreme Court Act. The High
Court refused to deal with the constitutionality of the matter in terms of section
19(1)(a)(iii), holding that, on the assumption that section 19(1)(a)(iii) gave the Court
the power to decide the constitutional issue, this was not an appropriate case to decide
so important a matter. The applicant appealed directly to the Constitutional Court
against the High Court‘s decision not to deal with the constitutionality of the impugned
provision.
The Constitutional Court held that the relief was sought in terms of the Constitution
itself and not under the Supreme Court Act and, accordingly, that the High Court should
have dealt with the constitutionality of the provision which formed the basis of the
dispute between the applicant and the Board.481
It is submitted that there are two different approaches to obtaining declaratory relief in
the High Court. The first would be in terms of s 21(1)(c) of the Superior Courts Act482
and the second in terms of section 172 of the Constitution. Section s 21(1)(c) does not
seem suited for constitutional issues, given the fact that the court must decide whether
the case is a proper one for exercising its discretion. Section 172 does not allow for
479
480
481
482
59 of 1959 (subsequently repealed by Act 10 of 2013).
Code of Conduct for Broadcasting Services, Schedule 1 to the Independent Broadcasting Authority
Act 153 of 1993.
Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority 2002 (4) SA 294 (CC); 2002 (5)
BCLR 433 (CC) para 14.
10 of 2013.
122
such discretion and states that, when the constitutionality of an Act is in question, the
courts must declare invalid law or conduct inconsistent with the Constitution. Until more
clarity is obtained from the courts about the difference in jurisdiction implied by section
s 21(1)(c) of the Superior Courts Act and section 172 of the Constitution when
approaching the courts seeking a declaratory order, a litigant should rely directly on the
Constitution and avoid using section s 21(1)(c).
2.6.2.2
Interdictory relief
2.6.2.2.1 Requirements for granting an interdict
An interdict is a court order which either orders a person to refrain from doing
something or orders a person to perform a certain act.483 The requirements for an
interdict as a constitutional remedy are the same as the requirements for an interdict
under the common law.484 For an interim interdict the requirements are as follows:485
(a)
There should be a prima facie right.
(b)
There should be an apprehension of irreparable harm if relief is not
granted.
(c)
The balance of convenience should favour the granting of the interdict.
(d)
No other satisfactory remedy is available for the applicant.
The requirements for the granting of a final interdict are the following:486
483
484
485
486
(a)
A clear right.
(b)
Actual harm or a reasonable apprehension of harm.
(c)
No alternative remedy available.
Peté et al Civil Procedure 404.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 121.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 121-122.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 123.
123
In Veeron Rambali v Ethekwini Municipality,487 the state was interdicted from harassing,
intimidating or otherwise interfering with informal street traders at the market and the
court prohibited officials from impounding goods without an order of court.
In Motswagae v Rustenburg Local Municipality,488 the case started as an application for
an interdict in the High Court aimed effectively at prohibiting the respondents from
unlawfully disturbing or interfering with the applicants‘ peaceful possession of their
homes.489
The High Court held that the applicants had no clear right to interdict the construction
activities because their right to privacy and to remain in the structures had not been
affected.490 Furthermore, the Court held that the applicants would not suffer irreparable
harm because their rights to privacy and to remain in their homes would be preserved
and that they should have objected to the decision to redevelop the land occupied by
them when that decision had been taken by the municipality. The High Court therefore
refused to interdict the municipality.
The Constitutional Court held that the work authorised by the respondent did interfere
with the applicants‘ peaceful and undisturbed occupation of their homes.491 The
intrusion was plainly so significant a disturbance to the applicants‘ occupation that it
constituted a form of eviction.
The Court held that the respondent should be interdicted from interfering with the
applicants‘ occupation of their homes492 and stated that the requirements for granting
the interdict were the same as those required in terms of the common law. The
applicants had a clear right not to be disturbed in the peaceful occupation of their
487
488
489
490
Case no. 11162/09 (KZD) (unreported).
2013 (3) BCLR 271 (CC).
Paras 1-3.
Motswagae v Rustenburg Local Municipality (1413/2009) [2011] ZANWHC 61 (15 September 2011)
paras 1-5.
491
492
Motswagae v Rustenburg Local Municipality 2013 (3) BCLR 271 (CC) para 13.
Para 18.
124
homes, they were suffering irreparable harm, and no alternative remedy was available
to them.
2.6.2.2.2 Structural interdicts or supervisory interdicts
In certain circumstances, the courts may grant structural interdicts either to force an
organ of state to comply with its orders or to assist the organs of state to comply with
the order. A structural interdict is a remedy in terms of which the court orders an organ
of state to perform its constitutional obligations and to report to the court on its
progress in doing so.493. Structural interdicts have a tendency to blur the distinction
between the executive and the judiciary and have an effect on the separation of
powers.494 They tend to deal with policy matters and not with the enforcement of
particular rights. The court therefore plays a supervisory role in ensuring state
compliance with its order.495
The issue of structural interdicts was first raised in City Council of Pretoria v Walker,496
in which the court held that the applicant could be given a chance to fashion
appropriate remedies to ensure that any strategy pursued by the applicant would
comply with the court order, with the court supervising the implementation of the
remedies.
In Head of Department, Mpumalanga Department of Education v Hoërskool Ermelo the
Court stated:497
In several cases this court has found it fair to fashion orders to facilitate a substantive
resolution of the underlying dispute between the parties. Sometimes orders of this
class have taken the form of structural interdicts or supervisory orders. This approach
is valuable and advances constitutional justice, particularly by ensuring that the parties
themselves become part of the solution.
493
De Beer and Vettori 2007 PELJ 10.
494
Modder East Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd, President of the Republic of South Africa
and v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 3 All SA 169 (SCA) 2004 para 39.
Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 107.
495
496
497
1998 (3) BCLR 257 (17 February 1998) para 139.
2010 (2) SA 415 (CC) para 97.
125
The courts therefore view structural interdicts as a tool to advance constitutional rights
and hold organs of state accountable to court orders and the Constitution.
In Minister of Home Affairs v Somali Association of South Africa,498 the Court found that
government had done little to aid the respondents and that previous orders of the
courts appeared to have done little to cause the relevant authorities to comply with
their obligations. The Court further held that it might be necessary to issue a structural
interdict when there is a failure to heed declaratory orders or other relief granted by a
court. Therefore, given the intransigence on the part of the relevant authorities, it was
important to provide a remedy to the respondents that was effective and meaningful.
The Court therefore held that this was an appropriate case for a court to exercise its
supervisory jurisdiction to secure compliance with its order.499
This was the case for three reasons. Firstly, it was necessary that the respondents
should know what progress was being made by the relevant authorities. Secondly, the
relevant authorities could always approach the court to extend the period, should it turn
out to be too short. Thirdly, the procedure allowed the court to be informed about the
progress made in the implementation of its order.
It is clear that the courts will only issue structural interdicts in exceptional
circumstances, because it blurs the distinction between the judiciary and other organs
of state and raises the issue of the separation of powers. However, if an organ of state
wilfully ignored previous orders by a court, the courts would not hesitate to issue
structural interdicts to force the organ of state to comply with its orders. A remedy in
the form of a structural interdict can therefore be used to ensure that organs of state
comply with their constitutional obligations and duties. This includes the positive
constitutional duties in place to regulate the conduct of the state litigant. 500 However,
such relief is given after the constitutional violation by the organ of state has already
occurred. The Constitution is forward-looking in nature.501 What is needed is a set of
498
499
500
501
2015 (3) SA 545 (SCA) para 37.
Para 39.
Sections 1.3 and 1.4 above.
Soobramoney v Minister of Health, Kwazulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) para 42.
126
rules or guidelines in civil procedural law that clearly state what the constitutional
obligations of the state litigant are. This could prevent constitutional violations by the
litigating organ of state before it occurs.502
2.6.2.3 Damages
In Fose v Minister of Safety and Security,503 the appellant claimed constitutional
damages for a breach of his right, guaranteed by section 11(2) of the Interim
Constitution, not to be tortured and not to be subject to cruel, inhuman or degrading
treatment.504 The Court had to decide whether a remedy of punitive damages is
appropriate relief for the infringement of constitutional rights.505 The test applied by the
Court was whether granting punitive damages to the appellant would serve to vindicate
the Constitution and deter its further violation. The Court regarded as crucial to the
case an averment by the appellant, who contended that the infringement of his
fundamental rights form part of widespread and persistent similar infringements of the
fundamental rights of other South African citizens by members of the South African
Police Services.
The Court held that isolated acts of torture, which do not point to a pattern of more
widespread harms, might require only the application of standard delictual remedies in
order to meet the demands of the constitutional rights. Therefore, when there are
systematic, pervasive and enduring infringements of constitutional rights, delictual relief
is not an adequate means of vindicating the Constitution and deterring further
violations of it.506
However, the Court held that the relief in the form of damages would come from the
public coffers. The implicated police officers could not possibly be deterred by a
payment of damages bearing no relation to their own finances. 507 Furthermore, the
Constitution is not vindicated by enriching a particular claimant at the cost of the
502
503
504
505
506
507
Such guidelines, known as the model litigant obligation, are discussed in chapter 6 of this work.
1997 (3) SA 786 (CC).
Para 1.
Para 101.
Para 102.
Para 103.
127
taxpayer, particularly when the problem is far larger than the claimant concerned.
Granting punitive damages therefore does not adequately defend the Constitution.
However, the Court did not hold that punitive damages would never be appropriate
relief for constitutional violations. The facts of a particular case would determine
whether an order of damages would be appropriate.
In Van Eeden v Minister of Safety and Security,508 the Court held that the right of
freedom and security of the person entrenched in section 12(1)(c)509 of the Constitution
included the right to be free from all forms of violence from either private or public
sources.510 Freedom from violence was fundamental to the equal enjoyment of human
rights and fundamental freedoms, and section 12(1)(c) required the state to protect
individuals, both by refraining from such invasions itself and by taking active steps to
prevent violation of the right. It therefore placed a positive duty on the state to protect
everyone from violent crime.
The Court further held that section 12(1)(c) had to be read with section 7(2) of the
Constitution,511 which imposes a duty on the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil
the rights in the Bill of Rights.512 Therefore, there was a positive obligation on the state
to act in protecting the rights contained in the Bill of Rights.
Section 39(1)(b)513 of the Constitution furthermore imposed the duty on the state to
recognise its obligation under international law to protect women against violent crime
and against the gender discrimination inherent in violence against women. The Court
recognised that the entrenchment of the right to be free from violence in section
12(1)(c), read with section 205(3),514 of the Constitution would, in appropriate
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
2003 (1) SA 389 (SCA).
―Everyone has the right to freedom and security of the person, which includes the right … to be free
from all forms of violence from either public or private sources.‖
Para 13.
―The state must respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights.‖
Paras 14-15.
―When interpreting the Bill of Rights, a court, tribunal or forum … must consider international law‖.
―The objects of the police service are to prevent, combat and investigate crime, to maintain public
order, to protect and secure the inhabitants of the Republic and their property, and to uphold and
enforce the law.‖
128
circumstances, be strongly indicative of a legal duty resting on the police to act
positively to prevent violent crime.515
The police therefore acted wrongfully, and in view of the admission of negligence,
vicarious liability and causation the state had to be held liable for any damages suffered
by the appellant.516 The Court awarded punitive damages to the appellant for the failure
of the state to protect her constitutionally enshrined rights.
In Modder East Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd, President of the Republic of
South Africa v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd,517 the Court held that, in the particular
circumstances of the case, the only appropriate relief available was that of
constitutional damages, or damages due to the breach of a constitutionally entrenched
right. No other remedy was apparent.
The Court issued a declaratory order. The order had the effect that the applicant would
not receive more than what it had lost, while the respondent had already received value
for what it had to pay. The order also solved the immediate social problem, while the
medium- and long-term problems could be solved as and when the state could afford it.
In summary, the courts will decide on a case-by-case basis whether to award
constitutional damages. Constitutional damages may be awarded where such an award
would vindicate the Constitution and deter its further violation. Where there is evidence
of systematic, pervasive and enduring constitutional violations, a delictual remedy is not
an adequate remedy to vindicate the Constitution. Where no apparent remedy is
available for the appellant, constitutional damages may be granted by the court.
However, constitutional damages would not prevent future constitutional violations by
organs of state. Payment for the damages ultimately comes from the taxpayer and the
organ of state would not be deterred from future constitutional violations. Constitutional
damages are therefore not an effective remedy to cure and prevent constitutional
violations by organs of state.
515
516
517
Para 18.
Para 24.
(2004) 3 All SA 169 (SCA) (27 May 2004) para 43.
129
2.6.2.4
Declarations of invalidity
2.6.2.4.1 Declaring legislation and executive conduct constitutionally invalid
The courts must, when deciding a constitutional matter, declare any law or conduct that
is inconsistent with the Constitution invalid to the extent of its inconsistency.518 The
courts may make any order that is just and equitable, including limiting the
retrospective effect of the declaration of invalidity519 or suspending the invalidity for any
period and on any conditions, in order to allow the competent authority to correct the
defect.520 Another principle in play is that, where possible, legislation ought to be
construed in a manner that is consistent with the Constitution.521 Furthermore, the
courts subscribe to a rule that requires courts, where possible, to decide cases without
reaching constitutional issues.522
In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs,523 the
Court had to determine whether the provisions of section 25(5) of the subsequently
repealed Aliens Control Act524 (hereafter ―the Act‖) were constitutional. Section 25(5)
read as follows:
Notwithstanding the provisions of subsection (4), but subject to the provisions of
subsections (3) and (6), a regional committee may, upon application by the spouse or
the dependent child of a person permanently and lawfully resident in the Republic,
authorize the issue of an immigration permit.
The High Court declared section 25(5) of the Act invalid to the extent that the benefit
conferred exclusively on spouses is inconsistent with section 9(3) of the Constitution.525
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
Section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution.
Section 172(1)(b)(i) of the Constitution.
Section 172(1)(b)(ii) of the Constitution.
Zondi v MEC, Traditional and Local Government Affairs 2005 (4) BCLR 347 (CC) para 102
S v Mhlungu 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC) para 59; Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei 1995 (4) SA 615 (CC)
paras 2-5.
2000 1 BCLR 39 (CC).
96 of 1991.
The equality section.
130
The Court held that it discriminated against same-sex life partners on the grounds of
sexual orientation.526
The applicants appealed to the Constitutional Court in terms of the provisions of section
172(2)(d) of the Constitution,527 seeking a variation of the order granted by the High
Court.
The Court firstly referred to the reading down principle, stating that:528
There is, it is true, a principle of constitutional interpretation that where it is reasonably
possible to construe a statute in such a way that it does not give rise to constitutional
inconsistency, such a construction should be preferred to another construction which,
although also reasonable, would give rise to such inconsistency.
However, such a construction would not be a reasonable one when it can be reached
only by distorting the meaning of the expression being considered. The Court stated
that there was a clear distinction between the process of reading words into or severing
them from a statutory provision that was a remedial measure under section 172(1)(b)
and a declaration of constitutional invalidity under section 172(1)(a).529
The Court emphasised the fundamentally different nature of the two processes as
follows:
The first process, being an interpretative one, is limited to what the text is reasonably
capable of meaning. The latter can only take place after the statutory provision in
question, notwithstanding the application of all legitimate interpretative aids, is found
to be constitutionally invalid.
Because the word spouse had not been defined in the Act, effect would have to be
given to its ordinary meaning, which connotes ―married person; a wife, a husband‖. The
context of the Act precluded a wider meaning being given to the word.
Whether or not legislation is deemed unconstitutional will depend on whether there is a
rational connection between the legislation and the achievement of a legitimate
526
527
528
529
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 1999 (3) BCLR 280 (C).
Any person or organ of state may appeal directly to the Constitutional Court to confirm or vary an
order of constitutional invalidity by a court.
Para 23.
Para 24.
131
government purpose.530 The Court held that the rational connection test is the standard
for reviewing legislation, holding that –
[t]he first of the constitutional constraints placed upon Parliament is that there must be
a rational relationship between the scheme which it adopts and the achievement of a
legitimate governmental purpose. Parliament cannot act capriciously or arbitrarily. The
absence of such a rational connection will result in the measure being unconstitutional.
In Zondi v MEC for Traditional and Local Government Affairs,531 the Court had to decide
on the constitutionality of certain sections of the Pound Ordinance (KwaZulu-Natal) (the
Ordinance).532 The question before the Court was whether the impugned provisions
unjustifiably limited the right of access to courts;533 the right to equality;534 the right to
administrative action535 and the other rights asserted by the applicant.536 The most
important of the impugned sections made provision for the immediate seizure and
impoundment of trespassing animals by a landowner without notice to the livestock
owner, unless the livestock owner happens to be an owner of land immediately
adjacent and the livestock bears the registered brand of that owner.537
The Court held that section 34 is an express constitutional recognition of the
importance of the fair resolution of social conflict by impartial and independent
institutions.538 The section therefore requires not only that individuals not be permitted
to resort to self-help, but also that potentially divisive social conflicts be resolved by
courts.539 The Court found that the scheme set in place by the Ordinance denied the
livestock owner the protection of the judicial process and supervision exercised by the
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
New National Party of South Africa v Government of the Republic of South Africa (3) SA 191 (CC)
para 19.
2005 (3) SA 589 (CC).
32 of 1947.
Section 34 of the Constitution.
Section 9 of the Constitution.
Section 33 of the Constitution.
Including section 25(1): the right against arbitrary deprivation of property; section 27(1)(b): the
right to have access to sufficient food; section 28(1)(c): every child‘s right to basic nutrition; section
10: the right to dignity; sections 30 and 31: the right to enjoy one‘s culture; and section 7(2): the
obligation of the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights.
Zondi para 2.
Para 61.
Para 63.
132
courts.540 Throughout the whole process, there was no prospect of judicial intervention.
Therefore, the Court held that the scheme manifestly limited the right of access to
courts,541 and it was therefore inconsistent with the right of access to courts. 542 The
Court found that five sections of the Ordinance were constitutionally invalid,543 but
suspended the declaration of invalidity for a period of twelve months to enable the
provincial legislature to correct the inconsistency that has resulted in the declaration of
invalidity.544
In Affordable Medicines Trust v Minister of Health,545 the Court had to decide on the
constitutional validity of certain aspects of a licensing scheme introduced by the
government to regulate members of the health profession.546
The Court held that the Constitution must be construed in the light of our constitutional
scheme and our jurisprudence.547 The Court explained that under our jurisprudence, the
exercise of legislative and executive power is subject to two constraints, namely that it
must meet the minimum threshold requirement of rationality and that it must not
infringe any of the rights contained in the Bill of Rights. If the exercise of power limits
any such rights, it must pass the section 36(1)548 test.
Whether or not legislation is deemed unconstitutional will depend on whether there is a
rational connection between the legislation and the achievement of a legitimate
government purpose.549 A constitutional state presupposes a system the operation of
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
Para 74.
Para 77.
Para 86.
Para 135(1)(e).
Para 135(2).
2006 (3) SA 247 (CC).
Para 1.
Para 91.
The limitation section.
New National Party of South Africa v Government of the Republic of South Africa (3) SA 191 (CC)
para 19.
133
which can be rationally tested.550 In the New National Party of South Africa case, the
Court held that the rational connection test is the standard for reviewing legislation:551
The first of the constitutional constraints placed upon Parliament is that there must be
a rational relationship between the scheme which it adopts and the achievement of a
legitimate governmental purpose. Parliament cannot act capriciously or arbitrarily. The
absence of such a rational connection will result in the measure being unconstitutional.
Should legislation fail the rational connection test, the legislation would be declared
constitutionally invalid. The same principle holds true in the exercise of public power by
members of the executive. The Constitution places ―significant constraints upon the
exercise of public power through the Bill of Rights and the founding principle enshrining
the rule of law‖.552 The exercise of such power must be rationally related to the purpose
for which the power was given. If it does not, it falls short of the standards demanded
by the Constitution for such action.
In summary, when there is a constitutional challenge to legislation, the test for its
constitutional validity is twofold.553 First, there is the threshold enquiry aimed at
determining whether the enactment in question constitutes a limitation on some
guaranteed right or another. This entails examining (a) the content and scope of the
protected right(s) concerned and (b) the meaning and effect of the impugned
enactment.
Should the impugned legislation limit a guaranteed right, the second question is
whether the limitation is reasonable and justifiable, regard being had to the
considerations stipulated in section 36.554 If the impugned legislation does not satisfy
the justification standard and a remedial option, through reading in notional or actual
severance, is not competent, it must be declared unconstitutional and invalid.555
550
551
S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 156.
New National Party of South Africa v Government of the Republic of South Africa (3) SA 191 (CC)
para 20.
552
553
554
555
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA: In re Ex Parte President of the Republic of South
Africa 2000 (2) SA 674 (CC) paras 83 and 85.
Ex Parte Minister of Safety and Security: In Re S v Walters 2002 (4) SA 613 (CC) para 26.
The limitation section.
Thebus v S 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC) para 30.
134
2.6.2.4.2 Declaring a rule of the common law constitutionally invalid
In Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security,556 the Court was primarily concerned
with the development of the common-law delictual duty to act. The Court relied on
section 39(2) of the Constitution, which provides that when developing the common
law, every court must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.557
Therefore, when the common law deviates from the spirit, purport and objects of the
Bill of Rights the courts have an obligation to develop it by removing that deviation.
The section 39(2) objectives are not discretionary; they are implicit in section 39(2),
read with section 173558, of the Constitution. Where the common law is deficient in
promoting the section 39(2) objectives, the courts are under an obligation to develop it
appropriately.559
Should the courts be asked to find whether the existing common law requires
development in accordance with section 39(2), a twofold enquiry ensues.560 Firstly, it
requires a reconsideration of the common law in the light of section 39(2). If this
inquiry leads to a positive answer, the second stage concerns itself with how such
development is to take place in order to meet the section 39(2) objectives.
The Court stated that the Constitution requires a court, when developing the common
law, to promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Constitution.561 The obligation
imposed on courts by section 39(2)562 of the Constitution is thus extensive, ―requiring
courts to be alert to the normative framework of the Constitution not only when some
startling new development of the common law is in issue, but in all cases where the
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
2001 (4) SA 938 (CC).
Para 33.
―The Constitutional Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal and the High Court of South Africa each has
the inherent power to protect and regulate their own process, and to develop the common law,
taking into account the interests of justice.‖
Para 39.
Para 40.
Para 15.
―When interpreting any legislation, and when developing the common law or customary law, every
court tribunal or forum must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.‖
135
incremental development of the rule is in issue‖.563 The normative influence of the
Constitution must be felt throughout the common law.
In Thebus v S,564 the Court had to find whether the Supreme Court of Appeal failed to
develop the common-law doctrine of common purpose in conformity with the
Constitution, as required by section 39(2) and thereby failed to give effect to the
applicants‘ rights to dignity, freedom of the person and a fair trial.565
The applicants contended that the pre-constitutional requirements of common purpose
unjustifiably limited the appellants‘ rights to dignity, freedom and security of the person
and a fair trial, including the right to be presumed innocent.566 It was in this context
that courts had to apply and develop the common law in order to give effect to a
protected right.567 The Court found that when developing the common law, a court is
obliged to ―promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights‖.568
The Court held that since the advent of constitutional democracy, all law must conform
to the command of the supreme law, the Constitution, from which all law derives its
legitimacy, force and validity.569 The Court confirmed the two-stage enquiry developed
in Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security.570 Furthermore, the Court confirmed
that the Constitution embodied an ―objective normative value system‖ and that the
influence of the fundamental constitutional values on the common law is authorised by
section 39(2).571 Therefore, it is within the matrix of this objective normative value
system that the common law must be developed.
The Court stated that the need to develop the common law as required by section
39(2) could arise in at least two instances.572 Firstly, when a rule of the common law is
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
Para 17.
2003 (6) SA 505 (CC) para 17.
Sections 10, 12 and 35(3) of the Constitution.
Para 23.
Para 25.
Section 39(2) of the Constitution.
Para 24.
2001 (4) SA 938 (CC).
Thebus para 27.
Para 28.
136
inconsistent with a constitutional provision, and, secondly when a rule of the common
law is consistent with a specific constitutional provision but falls short of its spirit,
purport and objects. In the first instance, the Court would have to adapt the common
law to resolve the inconsistency. In the second instance, the common law must be
adapted so that it grows in harmony with the ―objective normative value system‖ found
in the Constitution, and the Court held that the influence of the fundamental
constitutional values on the common law is authorised by section 39(2).573
Therefore, a different approach to the challenge of constitutional validity of legislation
and executive conduct is required when a court deals with a constitutional challenge to
a rule of the common law:574
Superior courts are protectors and expounders of the common law. The superior courts
have always had an inherent power to refashion and develop the common law in order
to reflect the changing social, moral and economic make-up of society. That power is
now constitutionally authorised and must be exercised within the prescripts and ethos
of the Constitution.
Should the common law be found to be inconsistent with constitutional provisions, the
court is again required to do a threshold analysis. The question is whether the
common-law rule limits an entrenched right. If the limitation is not reasonable and
justifiable, the court itself is obliged to adapt, or develop, the common law in order to
harmonise it with the constitutional norm.575
In this case, the appellants argued that the doctrine of common purpose undermined
the fundamental dignity of each person convicted of the same crime with others
because it de-individualised him or her. Therefore, it effectively de-humanised people
by treating them ―in a general manner as nameless, faceless parts of a group‖. 576
The Court held that the doctrine of common purpose sets a standard of criminal
culpability.577 It defined the minimum elements necessary for a conviction in a joint
criminal enterprise. The standard set by the rule must be constitutionally permissible.
573
574
575
576
577
Thebus para 27.
Para
Para
Para
Para
31.
32.
35.
36.
137
Therefore, it may not unjustifiably invade the fundamental rights or principles of the
Constitution. The norm may only ―impose a form of culpability sufficient to justify the
deprivation of freedom without giving rise to a constitutional complaint‖. Should the
culpability norm pass constitutional muster, an appropriate deprivation of freedom is
permissible.
The Court argued that the doctrine of common purpose did not amount to an arbitrary
deprivation of freedom,578 and held that the doctrine is rationally connected to the
legitimate objective of limiting and controlling joint criminal enterprise. It serves vital
purposes in the criminal-justice system and the need for a strong deterrent to violent
crime is well acknowledged. Therefore, the Court found that a person who knowingly,
and bearing the requisite intention, participates in the achievement of a criminal
outcome cannot after conviction in a fair trial validly claim that his or her rights to
dignity and freedom have been invaded.579 The Court, therefore, found the common-law
principle of common purpose was sufficiently aligned with the spirit, purport and
objects of the Bill of Rights and that there was no inconsistency.
In K v Minister of Safety and Security,580 the Court held that the common-law rule of
vicarious liability should be developed to render it consistent with the spirit, purport and
objects of the Bill of Rights, and to vindicate the applicant‘s constitutional rights and
provide a remedy to correspond to the respondent‘s constitutional duties.581
The Court stated that the Constitution requires a court, when developing the common
law, to promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Constitution.582 The obligation
imposed on courts by section 39(2)583 of the Constitution is therefore extensive,
―requiring courts to be alert to the normative framework of the Constitution not only
when some startling new development of the common law is in issue, but in all cases
578
579
580
581
582
583
Para 40.
Para 41.
2005 (6) SA 419 (CC).
Para 14.
Para 15.
―When interpreting any legislation, and when developing the common law or customary law, every
court, tribunal or forum must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.‖
138
where the incremental development of the rule is in issue‖.584 The normative influence
of the Constitution must be felt throughout the common law. This influence required
the Court to develop a broader remedy of vicarious liability to allow the applicant to be
awarded damages after the violation of her constitutional rights by the state.
In Paulsen v Slip Knot Investments 777 (Pty) Limited,585 the Court confirmed its
conclusion in K v Minister of Safety and Security:
It is well within the place of courts to shape the common law in a way that advances
constitutional values. The authority imposed upon courts by section 39(2) of the
Constitution is thus extensive, requiring courts to be alert to the normative framework
of the Constitution not only when some startling new development of the common law
is in issue, but in all cases where the incremental development of the rule is in issue.
Although the courts have consistently developed the common law to conform to the
object, purport and spirit of the Bill of Rights, it does not mean that they have to
develop the common law in each instance when a common-law rule is before it.586 The
courts will have to develop the common law in cases where the development of the rule
is in issue.587
2.6.2.5
The doctrine of vagueness
In Affordable Medicines Trust v Minister of Health,588 the Court referred to the doctrine
of vagueness, one of the principles of common law that was developed by courts to
regulate the exercise of public power. The doctrine of vagueness is founded on the rule
of law, which is a foundational value of constitutional democracy. It requires that laws
must be written in a clear and accessible manner. The law must indicate with
reasonable certainty to those who are bound by it what is required of them so that they
may regulate their conduct accordingly.589 The Court held that where it is contended
that the regulation under consideration is vague for uncertainty, a court must first
construe the regulation applying the normal rules of construction including those
584
585
586
587
588
589
Para 17.
[2015] ZACC 5 para 116.
De Vos and Freedman South African Constitutional Law 342.
K v Minister of Safety and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC) para 17.
2006 (3) SA 247 (CC) para 108.
Para 109.
139
required by constitutional adjudication. The ultimate question is whether so construed,
the regulation indicates with reasonable certainty to those who are bound by it what is
required of them.
Should regulations contain provisions that allow for discretionary powers of state
officials, such powers must be constrained. If the regulations do not contain constraints
then –590
[t]hose who are affected by the exercise of the broad discretionary powers will not
know what is relevant to the exercise of those powers or in what circumstances they
are entitled to seek relief from an adverse decision. In the absence of any clear
statement to that effect in the legislation, it would not be obvious to a potential
applicant that the exercise of the discretion conferred upon the officials is constrained
by the provisions of the Bill of Rights and, in particular, what factors are relevant to the
decision. If rights are to be infringed without redress, the very purposes of the
Constitution are defeated.
Another effect of the doctrine of vagueness is that statutory powers enabling officials to
remedy contraventions, remove hazards or mitigate dangerous situations should state
precisely the extent of the powers and the circumstances in which they may be
exercised.591 If it is not practical to particularise, then the statute should specify that the
powers should be exercised consistent with the purposes of the legislation. The purpose
of the legislation should then be clearly spelled out.
Legislation should also specify entry, search and seizure powers to facilitate trouble-free
exercise of such powers.592 This will enable members of the public to understand the
extent and conditions of the powers so that they can assess whether officials act within
the scope of the powers. Legislation permitting seizure of property should also provide
for the return of the property and payment of compensation, should that be
necessary.593
The principle of vagueness underlies the rule of law to the extent that the exercise of all
public power must be authorised by law, which must be clear and accessible to those
590
591
Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home
Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) para 47.
Makwickana v Ethekwini Municipality 2015 (3) SA 165 (KZD) para 38.
140
bound by it. The principle of vagueness is a tenet of constitutional law and admits to no
exception.594
2.6.2.6
Methods of curing constitutional invalidity
2.6.2.6.1 Actual and notional severance
Severance aims to cure the legislation of any constitutional defects.595 Any legislation or
conduct inconsistent with the Constitution is invalid only to the extent of the
inconsistency.596 A court can cure legislation of constitutional defect by either actual
severance or notional severance.597 Actual severance means striking down the
inconsistent section, phrases or words, while notional severance entails leaving the
language of the provisions intact but subjecting them to a condition for proper
application.598
In Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa,599 the Court explained the
concept of severance in constitutional interpretation. The issue before the Court was
the constitutional validity of the provisions of sections 65A to 65M600 of the Magistrates‘
Courts Act601 relating to the imprisonment of judgment debtors. The question before the
Court was whether the procedure in the sections concerned was wholly or partially
invalid due to inconsistency with one or more of the rights guaranteed in Chapter 3.602
The Court held that, although the sanction of imprisonment was seemingly aimed at the
debtor who would not pay, it was unreasonable in that it also struck at those who could
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
Thornton Legislative Drafting 238.
Thornton Legislative Drafting 239.
Democratic Alliance v Ethekwini Municipality 2012 (2) SA 151 (SCA) para 21.
South African Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC) para 14.
Section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution.
Govindjee et al Introduction to Human Rights Law 263.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 201.
1995 (4) SA 631 (22 September 1995).
The sections make provision for a system to enforce judgment debts and provide for the magistrate
to issue an order to commit the judgment debtor to prison for contempt of court for failure to pay
the debt.
32 of 1944.
Fundamental Rights, Interim Constitution.
141
not pay and simply failed to prove this at a hearing, often because of circumstances
created by the provisions themselves.603
In considering the question of severability, the Court stated that two questions had to
be answered with regard to the possible severance of the provisions of the law not
consistent with the Interim Constitution.604 Firstly, could the provisions that rendered
the option of imprisonment unconstitutional because they did not distinguish between
those who could pay but would not from those who could not pay be excised? If not,
could the provisions which provided for imprisonment itself be severed from the rest of
the system for enforcement of judgment debts? The Court applied the following test to
answer the questions:605
If the good is not dependent on the bad and can be separated from it, one gives effect
to the good that remains after the separation if it still gives effect to the main objective
of the statute.
The test therefore had two parts: Was it possible to sever the invalid provisions and, if
so, was the remainder giving effect to the purpose of the legislative scheme? The Court
held that in the matter under discussion it was possible to sever the provisions that
made up the option of imprisonment.606 The Court then asked whether in severing the
provisions the object of the statute would nevertheless remain to be carried out. The
Court held that it would. Therefore, the infringing provisions could be severed and the
balance of the system could usefully remain in force. The Court therefore cured the
constitutional invalidity in the legislation by actual severance.
In First National Bank of SA Limited v Commissioner for the South African Revenue
Services,607 the Court explored the concept of notional severance. The Court found
certain provisions of the Customs and Excise Act608 (the Act) constitutionally invalid.609
The Court held that it was textually impossible to sever the good from the bad in the
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
Para 13.
Para 15.
Para 16.
Para 17.
2002 (7) BCLR 702 (16 May 2002).
91 of 1964.
Para 113.
142
impugned provisions of the Act without embarking on an extensive redrafting of the
provision, an action that would have impermissibly trespassed on the terrain of the
legislature and would have been inappropriate in that case. 610 Therefore, the Court
stated that –
[c]onsidering only the successful property attack, the appropriate remedy would be an
order declaring the provisions of section 114 to be constitutionally invalid to the extent
that they provide that the goods of persons other than the customs debtor referred to
in the section are subject to a lien, detention and sale; ...
The Court stressed that it was not possible to tailor a narrower order of constitutional
invalidity and held that it might be possible to draft a statutory provision that would be
more suitable, but that was the task of the legislature and not the court. The Court
therefore resorted to notional severance by restricting the overbroad application of the
Act.
Notional severance can therefore be used by the courts when the scope of the
legislation is overbroad and therefore constitutionally invalid or when the presence of a
provision is constitutionally offensive.611
In Makwickana v Ethekwini Municipality,612 the Court scrutinised the constitutionality of
the Businesses Act613 and the eThekwini Municipality: Informal Trading By-law, 2014,
(the By-law) pertaining to the removal and impoundment of the trading goods of
informal or street traders by the municipal police.
Section 35(1) of the By-law permits an official to remove and impound goods on the
mere suspicion, reasonably held, that the informal trader has contravened a provision
of the By-law.614 Effectively, the street trader suffers punishment and dispossession of
his property before a court of law has determined his guilt. This is compounded by the
power of the respondent‘s officials to sell, destroy or otherwise dispose of perishable
610
Para 114.
611
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para
612
613
614
64.
2015 (3) SA 165 (KZD).
71 of 1991.
Para 80.
143
goods and foodstuff not fit for human consumption.615 Furthermore, the property of
street traders is sold without notice to the owners and the street traders and without a
reserve price.
The Court held that section 35 of the By-law limits the right of access to courts
contained in section 34 of the Constitution616 in so far as –617
(a)
the impoundment and disposal of the street traders‘ property for alleged
non-compliance with the legal formality of producing a licence or permit to
trade; and
(b)
the indiscriminate disposal of the street traders‘ property for noncompliance with any restriction or contravention are not supervised by a
judicial officer,
did not take place under judicial supervision.
To deprive street traders of their property permanently, section 35 of the By-law had to
overcome additional hurdles of fair procedure, rationality and proportionality to be
valid.618 According to the Court, procedural fairness required notification to the owners
that they are accused of a breach of the By-law before their goods are impounded and
disposed of, an obligation that the By-law did not impose on officials. The purpose of
the deprivation in terms of the By-law, in this instance to compel the applicant to
produce a licence or permit, was not sufficiently compelling to render the deprivation
rational in the constitutional sense of the means being proportional to the ends.
The Court further held that section 35 of the By-law limited the right not to be deprived
of property contained in section 25 of the Constitution619 in that –620
615
616
617
618
619
620
Para 81 and section 35(6) of the By-law.
The right to have any dispute resolved by the application of law in a fair hearing before a court.
Para 91.
Para 96.
―No one may be deprived of property except in terms of law of general application, and no law may
permit arbitrary deprivation of property.‖
Para 99.
144
(a)
the impoundment and disposal of the street traders‘ property for alleged
non-compliance with the legal formality of producing a licence or permit to
trade; and
(b)
the indiscriminate disposal of the street traders‘ property for noncompliance with any restriction or prohibition,
are irrational and give rise to arbitrary, deprivation of property of street traders.
The Court also held that section 35 of the By-law limited the right to trade in terms of
section 22 of the Constitution,621 and that section 35 of the By-law amounts to
discrimination in terms of section 9(3) of the Constitution.622
The Court further held that section 39 of the By-law, which provides for immunity from
liability for officials who acted in good faith, was unconstitutional;623 the possible
dishonesty of the officials made an exemption from liability for damages and
compensation an unhealthy disincentive to act fairly and reasonably towards street
traders.624
Concerning an appropriate remedy, the Court found that the scheme of the By-law was
incapable of giving effect to important constitutional rights and values.625 The Court
decided that amending the By-law to curtail the power of officials to impound and
confiscate property, to substitute fines for impoundment and to bring judicial or similar
independent scrutiny to bear on the conduct of officials as soon as possible could
prevent abuse of power.626 The Court therefore declared sections 35 and 39 of the By-
law unconstitutional, invalid and unlawful, but the declaration was suspended pending
the reform of the By-law. The Makwickana case is a clear example of actual severance
with the Court striking down the impugned sections of the By-law.
621
622
623
624
625
626
Freedom of trade, occupation and profession.
Para 125; the right to equality.
Para 127.
Para 135.
Para 138.
Para 145.
145
2.6.2.6.2 Reading in
Reading in is used by the courts to address a constitutional inconsistency resulting from
an omission in legislation. It is therefore a constitutional remedy used by the courts
after concluding that a provision is constitutionally invalid.627
In Gory v Kolver NO,628 the Constitutional Court used the reading-in principle to great
effect to cure the constitutional validity of section 1(1) of the Intestate Succession Act629
to the extent that it conferred rights of intestate succession on heterosexual spouses
but not on permanent same-sex life partners.
The Court held that the most fitting way to cure this unconstitutionality was by reading
in after the word ―spouse‖, wherever it appears in section 1(1) of the Act, the words ―or
partner in a permanent same-sex life partnership in which the partners have
undertaken reciprocal duties of support‖.630
The courts therefore have the power to cure the unconstitutionality of an Act or
provision by inserting a word or phrase into the offending legislation.
2.7 Crafting appropriate remedies for relief of constitutional violations
627
628
629
630
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 204.
2007 (3) BCLR 249 (CC).
81 of 1987.
Para 43.
146
2.7.1 Ubi ius ibi remedium
One of the most important principles of South African law is expressed by the maxim
ubi ius ibi remedium631: Where there is a right, there is a remedy.632 This means that the
existence of a legal rule implies the existence of an authority with the power to grant a
remedy if that rule is infringed. A legal rule or judgment will be deficient if there is no
means of enforcing it, and if no sanction attaches to a breach of that rule or judgment.
In the British case of Bremer Vulcan Schiffbau und Maschinenfabrik v South India
Shipping Corp,633 the Court described the need for judicial remedies as follows:
Every civilised system of government requires that the state should make available to
all its citizens a means for the just and peaceful settlement of disputes between them
as to their respective legal rights. The means provided are courts of justice to which
every citizen has a constitutional right of access in the role of plaintiff to obtain the
remedy to which he claims to be entitled in consequence of an alleged breach of his
legal or equitable rights by some other citizen, the defendant.
In Taylor634, the British Court held that ―the need to maintain confidence in the
administration of justice makes it imperative that there should be a remedy‖.
The South African Constitution itself provides very little guidance on constitutional
remedies.635 Therefore, according to the Constitutional Court in Fose –636
[i]t is left to the courts to decide what would be appropriate relief in any particular
case. Appropriate relief will in essence be relief that is required to protect and enforce
the Constitution. Depending on the circumstances of each particular case the relief
may be a declaration of rights, an interdict, a mandamus or such other relief as may be
required to ensure that the rights enshrined in the Constitution are protected and
enforced. If it is necessary to do so, the courts may even have to fashion new
remedies to secure the protection and enforcement of these all important rights.
631
632
633
634
635
636
The basic principle contemplated in the maxim is that, when a person's right is violated, the victim
will have an equitable remedy under law. The maxim also states that the person whose right has
been infringed has a right to enforce the infringed right through any action before a court. All law
courts are also guided with the same principle of ubi ius ibi remedium.
Hiemstra Trilingual Legal Dictionary 299.
[1981] 1 All ER 289 para 295.
Taylor v Lawrence [2002] 2 All ER 353 para 55.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 195.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) paras 18 and 19.
147
In August v Electoral Commission,637 the Court approvingly referred to the judgment by
Centlivres CJ in Minister of the Interior v Harris:638
As I understand Mr Beyers‘ argument the substantive right would, in the event of such
an Act having been passed, remain intact but there would be no adjective or
procedural law whereby it could be enforced: in other words the individual concerned
whose right was guaranteed by the Constitution would be left in the position of
possessing a right which would be of no value whatsoever. To call the rights
entrenched in the Constitution constitutional guarantees and at the same time to deny
to the holders of those rights any remedy in law would be to reduce the safeguards
enshrined in section 152 to nothing. There can to my mind be no doubt that the
authors of the Constitution intended that those rights should be enforceable by the
Courts of Law. They could never have intended to confer a right without a remedy.
The remedy is, indeed, part and parcel of the right. Ubi jus, ibi remedium.
The Court confirmed that a right requires an appropriate remedy.639 Where a remedy is
not readily available, the courts may construct such remedy by relying on section
172(1)(b) of the Constitution.640
It would therefore seem as if the maxim is no longer a binding norm in South Africa, at
least in constitutional adjudication. When the Constitution confers a right on an
individual and there is no appropriate remedy available for the realisation of that right,
the courts are empowered by section 172(1)(b) of the Constitution to craft such a
remedy.
2.7.2 The constitutional principle of ―appropriate relief‖
The United States Supreme Court held in Milliken v Bradley641 that the nature of
remedies is determined by the nature and scope of the constitutional violation; the
remedy therefore, must be related to the condition alleged to offend the Constitution.
The court order must be designed with the purpose of restoring the victim to the
condition they would have occupied in the absence of the constitutional violation.
However, the courts must take into account the interests of the state and local
authorities in managing their own affairs, consistent with the Constitution.
637
638
639
640
641
1999 (3) SA 1 (CC).
1952 (4) SA 769 (A) paras 780-781.
August para 34.
When deciding a constitutional matter, a court may make any order that is just and equitable.
433 US 267 (1977) 281.
148
In South African jurisprudence, the Court defined the principle of appropriate relief in
constitutional adjudication as follows:642
Appropriate relief will in essence be relief that is required to protect and enforce the
Constitution. Depending on the circumstances of each particular case the relief may be
a declaration of rights, an interdict, a mandamus or such other relief as may be
required to ensure that the rights enshrined in the Constitution are protected and
enforced. If it is necessary to do so, the courts may even have to fashion new
remedies to secure the protection and enforcement of these all-important rights.
Therefore, where the restoration of a violation of constitutional rights in American
jurisprudence is individually focussed – in other words, the focus of the restoration is on
the victim of the violation – in South African constitutional jurisprudence, the focus of
the relief is to protect and enforce the Constitution itself. This provides the reason for
the Constitutional Court‘s rejecting proposed out-of-court settlements between the
parties if such would result in a benefit of a constitutional right only to the parties.643
Therefore, as is the case in American constitutional jurisprudence, South African courts
should be considerate to not only the interests of the parties, but also the interests of
society.644
Something will be appropriate when it is specially fitted or suitable.645 Suitability, in the
context of court orders, is measured by the extent to which a particular form of relief
vindicates the Constitution and acts as a deterrent against further violations of rights.
When deciding on appropriate relief, the courts should consider the nature of the
infringement and the probable effect of a particular remedy. The court will therefore
analyse the facts surrounding a violation of rights to determine what form of relief is
appropriate. The courts do not have to rely only on constitutional remedies to provide
appropriate relief for constitutional violations. Common-law and statutory remedies as
well as the wide range of common-law administrative remedies can also be suitable for
642
643
644
645
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 19.
Khosa v Minister of Social Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) BCLR
596 (CC) para 35. The Court held that an offer to settle a dispute made by one litigant to the other,
even if accepted, could not cure the ensuing legal uncertainty, as it would settle the dispute only
between litigants. According to the Court, this would not resolve the unconstitutionality of impugned
provisions and the interest they have for the broader group of persons who may qualify for a similar
benefit.
Currie and De Waal The new constitutional and administrative law 195.
Fose para 97.
149
this purpose.646 As long as a remedy serves to vindicate the Constitution and deter its
further infringement, it might be ―appropriate relief‖.647 The courts have a particular
responsibility in this regard and are obliged to forge new tools and shape innovative
remedies, if need be, to achieve this goal.648
When there is an infringement of the Bill of Rights, the courts have a constitutional duty
to ensure that appropriate relief is afforded to those who have suffered the
infringement of their constitutional rights.649 This includes a breach of socio-economic
rights.650 The harm caused by violating the Constitution is harm to society as a whole,
even if the direct implications of the violation are highly paraxial. 651 The rights violator
not only harms a particular person, but also impedes the fuller realisation of the
constitutional promise and the object of remedying this kind of harm should be to
vindicate the Constitution and to deter its further infringement. Legitimacy and
confidence in a legal system demand that an effective remedy be provided in situations
where the interests of justice cry out for one.652 The nature of the right infringed and
the nature of the infringement will provide guidance as to the appropriate relief in a
particular case.653
The circumstances of each case will determine the appropriateness of a court order.654 A
remedy issued by the courts should instil humility without humiliation, and should bear
the message that respect for the Constitution protects and enhances the rights of all.655
However, the problem of sensible enforcement requires that the state must be able to
comply with the order within the limits of its capabilities, financial or otherwise.656 This
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
Para 98.
Para 100.
Para 69.
Mohamed v President of the Republic of South Africa 2001 (3) SA 893 (CC) para 71.
Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 106.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 835G.
Molaudzi v S 2015 (2) SACR 341 (CC) para 37.
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC) para 45.
City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (17 February 1998) para 91.
Marlboro Crisis Committee v City of Johannesburg 2012 ZAGPJHC 187 para 101.
Modder East Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd, President of the Republic of South Africa v
Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 3 All SA 169 (SCA) 2004 para 39.
150
led the courts on occasion to decline to award remedies even when a violation of a
constitutional right had been proved if the interests of good governance require this.657
Section 172(1)(b) of the Constitution states that when deciding a constitutional matter,
a court may make any order that is just and equitable. Therefore, the order of the court
should be based on what is morally right and fair and the order should be fair and
impartial.658 In terms of section 38 of the Constitution, a person alleging that a right in
the Bill of Rights has been infringed is entitled to appropriate relief by the courts,
―appropriate‖ meaning suitable and proper for the circumstances. Both of these
constitutional provisions provide flexibility for the courts to provide appropriate relief for
constitutional violations.
In Hoffmann v South African Airways,659 the appellant was discriminated against
because of his HIV status. The Court had to decide on the appropriate relief for the
constitutional violation of his right to equality.660 The Court held as follows:661
Section 38 of the Constitution provides that where a right contained in the Bill of Rights
has been infringed, ―the court may grant appropriate relief‖. In the context of our
Constitution, ―appropriate relief‖ must be construed purposively, and in the light of
section 172(1)(b), which empowers the Court, in constitutional matters, to make ―any
order that is just and equitable‖.
Appropriate relief must therefore be fair and just in the circumstances of the particular
case. Appropriateness, in the context of the Constitution, imports the elements of
justice and fairness. Fairness requires a consideration of the interests of all those who
might be affected by the order.662 The Court will have to take into consideration the
interests of the individual affected, the employer as well as the broader interest of the
community. Therefore, the determination of appropriate relief –663
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
East Zulu Motors (Pty) v Empangeni/Ngwlezane Transitional Local Council 1998 (2) SA 61 (CC);
Steyn v The State 2001 (1) SA 1146 (CC).
Based on the accepted legal definition of the words ―just‖ and ―equitable‖; Hiemstra Trilingual Legal
Dictionary 46 and 68.
2001 (1) SA 1 (CC).
Section 9 of the Constitution.
Para 42.
Para 43.
Para 45.
151
... calls for the balancing of the various interests that might be affected by the remedy.
The balancing process must at least be guided by the objective, first, to address the
wrong occasioned by the infringement of the constitutional right; second, to deter
future violations; third, to make an order that can be complied with; and fourth, of
fairness to all those who might be affected by the relief. Invariably, the nature of the
right infringed and the nature of the infringement will provide guidance as to the
appropriate relief in the particular case.
In determining appropriate relief, the courts must ―carefully analyse the nature of the
constitutional infringement, and strike effectively at its source‖.
The test for the effectiveness of the courts‘ remedies, therefore, is whether the remedy
is appropriate, just and equitable. The court judgment must be fair and just in the
context of the particular dispute before the court.664 The Court highlighted the flexibility
of the remedial powers of the courts as follows:665
It is clear that section 172(1)(b) confers wide remedial powers on a competent court
adjudicating a constitutional matter. The remedial power envisaged in section
172(1)(b) is not only available when a court makes an order of constitutional invalidity
of a law or conduct under section 172(1)(a). A just and equitable order may be made
even in instances where the outcome of a constitutional dispute does not hinge on
constitutional invalidity of legislation or conduct. This ample and flexible remedial
jurisdiction in constitutional disputes permits a court to forge an order that would place
substance above mere form by identifying the actual underlying dispute between the
parties and by requiring the parties to take steps directed at resolving the dispute in a
manner consistent with constitutional requirements. In several cases, this Court has
found it fair to fashion orders to facilitate a substantive resolution of the underlying
dispute between the parties. Sometimes orders of this class have taken the form of
structural interdicts or supervisory orders. This approach is valuable and advances
constitutional justice particularly by ensuring that the parties themselves become part
of the solution.
In Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers,666 the Court had the unenviable task
of deciding on an appropriate remedy where groups of indigent families were unlawfully
living on private land.667 The remedy required an appropriate constitutional relationship
664
665
666
667
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC) para 42.
Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education v Hoërskool Ermelo 2010 (3) BCLR 177
(CC) para 97.
2005 (1) SA 217 (CC).
Paras 1-3.
152
between rights in the Bill of Rights,668 in the matter under discussion between property
rights,669 and housing rights.670
The Court described the process of deciding on a remedy as follows:671
The courts are to seek concrete and case-specific solutions to the difficult problems
that arise. The courts are to consider all relevant factors but the manner in which the
courts are to manage the process have been left open. In managing the process, the
Courts should not establish a hierarchical arrangement between the different interests
involved. Rather it is to balance out and reconcile the opposing claims in as just a
manner as possible taking account of all the interests involved and the specific factors
relevant in each particular case.
This confirms that constitutional remedies will differ by circumstance.672
When deciding on an appropriate remedy the court should consider the different
fundamental rights involved, determine whether they had been breached and then
judge whether and, if so, what appropriate relief should be granted.673 In realising
constitutional rights, the courts should not be overawed by practical problems.674 Courts
should attempt to synchronise the real world with the ideal construct of a constitutional
world675 and they have a duty to mould an order that will provide effective relief to
those affected by a constitutional breach.676 However, despite the wide powers of the
courts to grant appropriate relief when a constitutional right has been breached, current
case law illustrates the magnitude of the lack of political commitment to implement
judicial orders and underscores the urgency of the need to devise strategies to ensure
compliance with court orders.677 The lack of political commitment to implement judicial
orders places unwarranted constitutional limitations on strategic litigation. Such
limitations can be cured by setting out the positive constitutional obligations that the
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
Para 19.
Section 25 of the Constitution.
Section 26 of the Constitution.
Port Elizabeth Municipality paras 22-23.
Modder East Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd, President of the Republic of South Africa v
Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (2004) 3 All SA 169 (SCA) (27 May 2004) para 43.
Para 20.
Para 42.
675
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 94.
676
Para 102.
677
Vumazonke v MEC for Social Development and Welfare for Eastern Cape Province 2004 ZAECHC;
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC).
153
state litigant must comply with, including respecting and implementing the order of the
court as soon as it is possible to do so, in a set of guidelines or rules. These guidelines
or rules, known as the model litigant obligation, are discussed in chapter 6 of this work.
2.8 The duty of the state to act fairly in litigation
2.8.1 Principles of co-operative government and intergovernmental relations
Chapter 3 of the Constitution sets out the principles relating to co-operative
government to which all spheres of government must adhere and within the parameters
of which they must conduct all activities. In terms of section 41(1)(e) all spheres of
government and organs of state must respect the constitutional status, institutions,
powers and functions of government in the other spheres. Section 41(1)(f) and (g)
provide that organs of state may not assume powers or functions not conferred on
them by the Constitution and may not exercise their powers and perform their functions
in a manner that encroaches on the integrity of government in another sphere. The
spheres of government are expected to co-operate with one another in mutual trust
and good faith by fostering friendly relations and assisting one another.678
Organs of state involved in an intergovernmental dispute must make reasonable efforts
and must exhaust all other remedies to settle that dispute before approaching the
courts.679 If a court finds that no such efforts have been made, the court may refer the
dispute back to the organs of state involved for compliance.680
The Constitution allocates powers to three spheres of government: the national, the
provincial and the local spheres. One sphere of government may not usurp the powers
of another sphere. Section 100 of the Constitution, however, allows the national
government to intervene in a provincial administration in certain defined instances.
Section 100(1) provides that, when a province cannot or does not fulfil an executive
obligation in terms of the Constitution or legislation, the national executive may
678
679
680
Section 41(1)(h) of the Constitution.
Section 41(3) of the Constitution.
Section 41(4) of the Constitution.
154
intervene by taking any appropriate steps to ensure fulfilment of that obligation,
including –
(a)
issuing a directive to the provincial executive, describing the extent of the
failure to fulfil its obligations and stating any steps required to meet its
obligations; and
(b)
assuming responsibility for the relevant obligation in that province to the
extent necessary to (i) maintain essential national standards or meet
established minimum standards for the rendering of a service; (ii) maintain
economic unity; (iii) maintain national security; or (iv) prevent the province
from taking unreasonable action that is prejudicial to the interests of
another province or to the country as a whole.
In Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality v Gauteng Development Tribunal, 681 the
Constitutional Court explored the effect of section 100(1)(b):682
The scope of intervention by one sphere in the affairs of another is highly
circumscribed. The national and provincial spheres are permitted by sections 100 and
139 of the Constitution to undertake interventions to assume control over the affairs of
another sphere or to perform the functions of another sphere under certain welldefined circumstances, the details of which are set out below. Suffice it now to say that
the national and provincial spheres are not entitled to usurp the functions of the
municipal sphere, except in exceptional circumstances, but then only temporarily and
in compliance with strict procedures.
The Intergovernmental Relations Framework Act683 (hereafter the Framework Act) was
enacted to provide appropriate mechanisms and procedures to facilitate settlement of
intergovernmental disputes. The long title of the Framework Act sets out its purpose as
follows:
To establish a framework for the national government, provincial governments and
local governments to promote and facilitate intergovernmental relations; to provide for
mechanisms and procedures to facilitate the settlement of intergovernmental disputes;
and to provide for matters connected therewith.
681
682
683
2010 (6) SA 182 (CC).
Para 44.
13 of 2005.
155
The Act applies to the national government, all provincial governments and all local
governments.684 It does not apply to the following institutions:685
(a)
Parliament.
(b)
The provincial legislatures.
(c)
The courts and judicial officers.
(d)
Any independent and impartial tribunal or forum contemplated in section 34
of the Constitution and any officer conducting proceedings in such a
tribunal or forum.
(e)
Any institution established by Chapter 9 of the Constitution.
(f)
Any other constitutionally independent institution.
(g)
Any public institution that does not fall within the national, provincial or
local sphere of government.
The object of the Act is to provide within the principle of co-operative government set
out in Chapter 3 of the Constitution a framework for the national government,
provincial governments and local governments, and all organs of state within those
governments, to facilitate co-ordination in the implementation of policy and legislation,
including –
684
685
(a)
coherent government;
(b)
effective provision of services;
(c)
monitoring implementation of policy and legislation; and
(d)
realisation of national priorities.
Section 2(1).
Section 2(2).
156
Chapter 2 of the Act provides for the creation of a President‘s Co-ordinating Council,
national intergovernmental forums, provincial intergovernmental forums, municipal
intergovernmental forums and intergovernmental technical support structures aimed at
facilitating the implementation of the objectives of the Act. Chapter 3 regulates the
conduct of intergovernmental relations. Chapter 4 relates to the settlement of
intergovernmental disputes.
Section 40(1) of the Act provides that all organs of state must make every reasonable
effort to avoid intergovernmental disputes when exercising their statutory powers or
performing their statutory functions and to settle intergovernmental disputes without
resorting to judicial proceedings. An organ of state that is a party to an
intergovernmental dispute with another government or organ of state may declare the
dispute a formal intergovernmental dispute by notifying the other party of such
declaration in writing.686
Once a formal intergovernmental dispute has been declared, the parties to the dispute
must promptly convene a meeting between themselves or their representatives and
appoint a facilitator to assist in settling the dispute.687 In terms of section 45 of the Act,
no government or organ of state may institute judicial proceedings in order to settle an
intergovernmental
dispute
unless
the
dispute
has
been
declared
a
formal
intergovernmental dispute in terms of section 41 and all efforts to settle the dispute in
terms of this Chapter were unsuccessful.
In Centre for Child Law v Minister of Basic Education,688 the Minister of Basic Education
and the Director-General of Basic Education were cited as respondents. The Minister
took a decision to place the Eastern Cape Department of Basic Education under the
administration of the national government in terms of section 100(1)(b) of the
Constitution, and the Director-General is the functionary responsible for the execution
of that administration.689 The question before the Court was what the implications of the
686
687
688
689
Section 41 of the Act.
Section 42 and 43 of the Act.
2013 (3) SA 183 (ECG).
Para 4.
157
intervention in terms of section 100(1)(b) were in respect of the powers, functions and
duties of the Minister and the Director-General. The Court referred approvingly to the
dictum in the above-mentioned Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality case.690 The
Court found that while the latter case dealt with powers assigned to the local sphere of
government, the observations that that court made applied equally to a situation in
which the national sphere of government has, in terms of section 100(1)(b), intervened
in a province‘s administration.691 When the national sphere does so, it assumes the
powers of the provincial administration, and it assumes its obligations.
Such an intervention must be done in the light of what the Constitutional Court said of
the purpose of the section 100 power in Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional
Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996.692
In the Certification judgment, the Court explained that section 100 provides that when
a province cannot or does not fulfil an executive obligation, the national executive may
take appropriate steps to ensure fulfilment of that obligation.693 What is contemplated is
that the national executive either put the province on terms to carry out its obligations
or assume responsibility for such functions itself to the extent that it is necessary to do
so for any of the purposes set out in section 100(1)(b).694
In Centre for Child Law, the Court held that the respondents were obliged to fulfil the
obligations of the provincial departments, including the recruitment and appointment of
staff for public schools in the province.695
2.8.2 Constitutional imposition of positive duties on the state
The executive, the judiciary, the legislature and all organs of state are bound by the Bill
of Rights.696 The Constitution further imposes general duties on those bound by it to
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
Para 7.
Para 8.
1996 (4) SA 744 (CC).
Para 263.
Para 265; New Text 100(1)(b): The text drawn up by the Constitutional Assembly in terms of the
Constitutional Principles of the Interim Constitution.
Para 34.
Section 8(1) of the Constitution.
158
respect, protect, fulfil and promote the rights in the Bill of Rights.697 The state,
therefore, has the duty to comply with all these obligations.
Du Plessis et al argue that the Constitution places a range of positive duties on organs
of the state. Organs of state must assist and protect the courts to ensure the
independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.698 The
duty placed on organs of state to ensure the effectiveness of the courts puts a positive
obligation on the organs of state to place relevant and material evidence before the
courts.699 This duty was articulated by the Court in Matatiele Municipality v President of
the Republic of South Africa700 as follows:
In this respect, the Constitution requires candour on the part of government. What is
involved is not simply a matter of showing courtesy to the public and to the courts,
desirable though that always is. It is a question of maintaining respect for the
constitutional injunction that our democratic government be accountable, responsive
and open. Furthermore, it is consistent with ensuring that the courts can function
effectively, as section 165(4) of the Constitution requires.
A lack of information may disempower a court, making it unable to reach a decision.
The Court continued by stating that the notion that ―government knows best, end of
enquiry‖ is not compatible with a democratic government based on the rule of law as
envisaged by the Constitution.701 There is a strong need for government to provide an
explanation for the introduction of legislation. The foundational values of the rule of law
and of accountable government do not exist in discreet categories; they overlap and
reinforce each other.702 Openness of government promotes both the rationality the rule
of law requires, and the accountability multi-party democracy demands.
The Bill of Rights regulates laws affecting human rights, and such laws may be tested
against the Constitution to determine their constitutionality. The Bill of Rights also
regulates all conduct, including state conduct. The Constitution and the Bill of Rights
697
698
699
700
701
702
Section 7(2) of the Constitution, which requires the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the
rights in the Bill of Rights.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) para 107.
Para 109.
Para 110.
159
thus prevent the individual from being placed in a vulnerable position and the state
from abusing its powers. The Bill of Rights performs this task by protecting individuals
against the state through imposing duties on all branches of the state to respect its
provisions. The executive, the judiciary, the legislature and all organs of state are
bound by the Bill of Rights in terms of section 8(1) of the Constitution. In addition, the
Constitution imposes general duties on those bound by the Constitution to respect,
protect, fulfil and promote the rights in the Bill of Rights. The state has the duty to
comply with all these obligations.
Public administration must further be governed by the democratic values and principles
enshrined in the Constitution, including the following principles:703
(a)
A high standard of professional ethics must be promoted and maintained.
(b)
Efficient, economic and effective use of resources must be promoted.
(c)
Public administration must be development-oriented.
(d)
Services must be provided impartially, fairly, equitably and without bias.
(e)
People's needs must be responded to, and the public must be encouraged to
participate in policy-making.
(f)
Public administration must be accountable.
(g)
Transparency must be fostered by providing the public with timely, accessible and
accurate information.
(h)
Good human-resource management and career-development practices, to
maximise human potential, must be cultivated.
(i)
Public administration must be broadly representative of the South African people,
with employment and personnel management practices based on ability,
objectivity, fairness, and the need to redress the imbalances of the past to achieve
broad representation.
The principles contained in section 195(1) apply to the administration in every sphere of
government, organs of state and public enterprises.704
703
704
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
Section 195(2) of the Constitution.
160
Du Plessis et al state that the Constitutional Court has frequently confirmed that there is
a duty on the state to ensure that all relevant evidence is placed before the court.705
In Khosa v Minister of Social Development,706 the Court held that if the necessary
evidence were not placed before the courts by the state, the courts‘ ability to perform
their constitutional mandate would be hampered and the constitutional scheme itself
put at risk. It is government‘s duty to ensure that the relevant evidence is placed before
the court.
In Gory v Kolver,707 the Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development did not see
fit to oppose the applicant‘s challenge to the constitutional validity of section 1(1) of the
Intestate Succession Act.708 The Court, dissatisfied with the state‘s failure to form part
of the proceedings and therefore placing much needed information before the Court,
declared its displeasure as follows:
To my mind, something more substantive is required when a state official is called
upon to deal with the constitutionality of a statutory provision falling under his or her
administration and with the formulation of an appropriate remedy in the event that
such provision is held to be constitutionally invalid is under consideration by a court.
According to Malherbe and Van Eck, the Constitution implies a social contract between
the state and its citizens.709 It controls, instructs and directs the state in its actions and
limits the state‘s powers and prevents their abuse. It is therefore imperative that the
state comply with the provisions of the Constitution and with all the duties contained in
it. The duties imposed on the state form the bedrock of the Constitution and the state
must comply with them to ensure the legitimacy of the Constitution and the realisation
of its democratic objectives and ideals. Non-compliance with the duties undermines the
foundations of the Constitution, and may jeopardise the existence and future
development of a constitutional democracy in South Africa.
705
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 5.
706
Khosa v Minister of Social Development, Mahlaule v Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) SA 505
707
708
709
(CC) para 19.
2007 (4) SA 97 (CC) para 64.
81 of 1987.
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 212.
161
2.8.3 The state‘s compliance with constitutional duties
The courts have indicated that the commencement, defence and conduct of litigation by
the government or government departments constitute the exercise of public power.710
As such, state litigation is subjected to the same scrutiny as any other exercise of public
power. Therefore, state litigation must comply with the principle of legality and the rule
of law. Malherbe and Van Eck711 note that the state can fail to comply with its
constitutional duties in two ways:
The first instance is where the state bona fide misinterprets legislation or makes a
mistake. The second instance is where the state negligently ignores or wilfully
disregards its duties, or deliberately takes on ―imagined powers‖.
They continue that the rule of law, legality and democratic principles are foundational
values of the Constitution.712 A bona fide misinterpretation of constitutional duties by an
organ of the state can be rectified with a structural interdict setting out the duties and
monitoring the compliance thereof. However, the second example of non-compliance
with constitutional duties mentioned by Malherbe and Van Eck raises serious concern.
The rule of law, legality and democratic principles are foundational values of the
Constitution. It is therefore inconceivable that these basic principles might be under
threat by the structures set in place to ensure that these foundational values are
realised.713
In Abdi v Minister of Home Affairs714 the Court expressed its displeasure at the
respondent (officials of the Department of Home Affairs) to be open and honest with
the Court in its submission. The persons appearing for the Minister of Home Affairs
(MHA) misrepresented the case in its founding and supporting affidavits. The
respondent adopted an evasive approach by refusing to disclose certain information in
its possession. The information – the fact that the applicant was issued with a valid
Refugee Status Permit – made the applicant's arrest illegal. The respondent knew of
710
711
712
713
714
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 3.
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 211.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 212.
(734/10) [2011] ZASCA 2 (2011) para 34.
162
that fact, continued to detain the applicant, and resisted the attempt to have him
released.
The respondents were duty-bound to set the record straight, but continued in their
heads of argument with the denial of being in possession of any record relating to the
appellants, putting them to needless effort and expense to meet that spurious
defence.715
The Court noted:716
Our courts have on several occasions expressed their disquiet at the failure of
Government officials, including the Department‘s officials, to respect the rights of
individuals they deal with and to act in accordance with their duties imposed by the
Constitution.717
The Court held that the respondent caused unnecessary litigation and wasted costs.
In Permanent Secretary Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v
Ngxuza,718 the respondents brought motion proceedings against the Eastern Cape
Provincial Government seeking to reinstate the disability grants they had been receiving
under the Social Assistance Act,719 which the province had terminated without notice to
them.720 They also sought to litigate as representatives on behalf of anyone in the whole
of the Eastern Cape Province whose disability grants had been cancelled or suspended
by the Eastern Cape government.721 The applicants attacked both the grant of leave to
institute the class action and the disclosure order, without questioning the merits of the
case.722 The applicants did not dispute that the method the province chose to verify and
update its pensioner records was not just harsh, but also unlawful. This had been
715
716
Para 35.
Para 36.
717
Eveleth v Minister of Home Affairs 2004 (11) BCLR 1223 (T) paras 45 to 48; Nyathi v MEC for the
Gauteng Department of Health 2008 (5) SA 94 (CC); Total Computer Services (Pty) Ltd v Municipal
Mayor, Potchefstroom Local Municipality 2008 (4) SA 346 (T) para 21; Van Straaten v President of
the Republic of South Africa 2009 (3) SA 457 (CC).
718
2001 (4) SA 1184 SCA.
Act 59 of 1992.
Para 2.
Para 3.
Para 5.
719
720
721
722
163
previously established by the Courts.723 Despite the previous findings of the
unlawfulness of the actions of the province, the applicants again assailed the claims of
the respondents.724 The Court described the conduct of the applicants as follows:
The applicants did so by recourse to every stratagem and device and obstruction,
every legal argument and non-argument that it thought lay to hand. While offering no
undertaking to implement Bushula in relation to the applicant class, it asserted that
because of the decision the relief sought was moot. It then contended, contradictorily,
that the applicants‘ claim was not yet ripe for adjudication. It tendered no evidence to
refute the mass of indicia the applicants placed before the Court that showed unlawful
conduct against huge numbers of disability pensioners, yet argued that the applicants‘
evidence was inadmissible hearsay. It obstructed the applicant class‘s entitlement to be
spared physical destitution, yet invoked their privacy rights in contending that the
disclosure order should not have been granted. It did not flinch even from deriding the
first applicant, who adhered to the founding papers with his thumbprint. Its deponent
thought fit to record his doubt that Mr Ngxuza had read the media articles appended to
the papers (a claim the first applicant did not make), while the written argument stated
that it ―boggles the mind‖ that ―a man who never attended school and is presently
illiterate‖ is able to make ―learned submissions‖.
The Court held that all this spoke of contempt for people and process that did not befit
an organ of government under our constitutional dispensation.725 It was not the function
of the courts to criticise government‘s decisions in the area of social policy, but –
[w]hen an organ of government invokes legal processes to impede the rightful claims
of its citizens, it not only defies the Constitution, which commands all organs of state
to be loyal to the Constitution,726 and requires that public administration be conducted
on the basis that people‘s needs must be responded to. It also misuses the
mechanisms of the law, which it is the responsibility of the courts to safeguard. 727
The Court held that the province‘s approach to the proceedings was contradictory,
cynical, expedient and obstructionist. It conducted the case as though it was at war
with its own citizens, the more shamefully because those it was combatting were the
neediest of the poor. The Court was harsh in its description of the applicants‘ objection
723
724
725
726
727
Bushula v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape 2000 (2) SA 849 (E); Rangani
v Superintendent-General, Department of Health and Welfare, Northern Province 1999 (4) SA 385
(T).
Para 17.
Para 19.
Section 41(1)(d) of the Constitution requires all spheres of government and all organs of state to be
loyal to the Constitution, the Republic and its people.
Section 195(1)(e) of the Constitution requires public administration to respond to people‘s needs.
164
relating to jurisdictional issues in the matter, stating that it was of a piece with the rest
of its filibustering approach to the litigation as a whole, and as devoid of substance. 728
In Van Der Merwe v Taylor,729 the case concerned the right to claim the return of
property, in the light of the Constitution, following its seizure by the State. Specifically,
the case was about the seizure of a large sum of foreign currency by state officials and
a claim for its return.730 The applicant submitted that the respondents‘ conduct as
organs of state conflicted with their duties under the Constitution, in particular sections
1 and 195.731 They had acted contrary to the basic values governing public
administration contained in section 195 of the Constitution. These provisions require,
among others things, a high standard of professional and ethical conduct and
accountability, with which the respondents had failed to comply.732 The State, they
submitted, did not lead by example.733
The Court held that the case raised a constitutional issue relating to section 25(1) of the
Constitution.734 In terms of this section, no one, including those accused of
contraventions of the law, as in this case, may be deprived of property except in terms
of a law of general application. That law, however, may not permit the deprivation of
property in an arbitrary manner. Section 25(1) generally protects all rights held in
relation to property, including ownership.
The Court asked whether the respondents had acted contrary to sections 1 and 195 of
the Constitution and held that, although the seizure of the foreign currency was lawful
and was a justified basis for the applicant‘s arrest, the conduct of the respondents
created circumstances of grave legal uncertainty and compelled the applicant to seek
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
Paras 1-7.
2008 (1) SA 1 (CC).
Para 1.
Para 15.
The applicants relied on the following case law: President of the Republic of South Africa v South
African Rugby Football Union 2000 (1) SA 1 (CC) paras 133-134; Reuters Group PLC v Viljoen NO
2001 (2) SACR 519 (C) paras 2-4 and 33-35; Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet Ltd t/a
Metrorail 2005 (2) SA 359 (CC) para 74; York Timbers Ltd v Minister of Water Affairs and Forestry
2003 (4) SA 477 (T) para 506B.
Mohamed v President of the Republic of South Africa 2001 (3) SA 893 (CC) para 68.
Para 25. Section 25(1) provides that no one may be deprived of property except in terms of law of
general application, and no law may permit arbitrary deprivation of property.
165
answers from the courts.735 The respondents‘ constant vacillation with regard to the
legal basis for the seizure and holding of a substantial amount of foreign currency made
it difficult for the applicants to formulate their case before the courts with the necessary
precision.
The Court held that section 1, read with section 195, of the Constitution sets high
standards of professional public service.736 The Court framed this as follows:737
The democratic approach to public service accountability is broadly based in
comparison with the past. Read together with section 195(1) of the Constitution, the
public service policy of Batho Pele requires that public administration should serve the
best interests of the public by enabling the achievement of individual rights
encompassed in the provisions of the Constitution. In the past accountability was
focused on the reporting by state parties to Parliament and not to the public. In those
days even if the public was to approach courts for relief, the courts‘ hands were tied by
the principle that they could not interfere with executive action unless gross
unreasonableness was alleged.
A professional public service requires ethical, open and accountable conduct towards
the public by all organs of state.738 These are basic values for achieving a public service
envisaged by the Constitution, which requires the state to lead by example. In this
case, the state failed to do so.
The Court held that the remissness by the respondents should not be countenanced:739
In this constitutional era, where the Constitution envisages a public administration,
which is efficient, equitable, ethical, caring, accountable and respectful of fundamental
rights, the execution of public power is subject to constitutional values.
According to the Court, section 195 reinforces these constitutional ideals. It
contemplates a public service in the broader context of transformation as envisaged in
the Constitution and aims to reverse the disregard, disdain and indignity with which the
public in general had been treated by administrators in the past. Section 195 envisages
that a public service reminiscent of that era has no place in our constitutional
735
736
737
738
739
Para 70.
Para 71.
Footnote 81.
Para 71.
Para 71.
166
democracy and must be discouraged.740 In that context, the conduct of the respondents
was indeed contrary to sections 1 and 195 of the Constitution.
In Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa, 741 legislative
enactments742 altered the boundaries between the provinces of KwaZulu-Natal and the
Eastern Cape, with the effect that the area of the Matatiele Local Municipality was
transferred from KwaZulu-Natal to the Eastern Cape; new municipal boundaries were
consequently created.743
One of the issues before the Court was whether the Demarcation Board, the authority
determining municipal boundaries, was independent of outside influence. The Court
stated that the independence of the Board is crucial to constitutional democracy. 744 One
of the founding values of our constitutional democracy is ―a multi-party system of
democratic government, to ensure accountability, responsiveness and openness‖.745
The Court stated that this founding value had to be given expression at the level of
national, provincial and local government. Therefore, one of the objects of local
government was to provide democratic and accountable government for local
communities.746 The purpose of section 155(3)(b)747 was ―to guard against political
interference in the process of creating new municipalities‖.748 The Court held that if
municipalities were to be established along party lines or if there was to be political
interference in their establishment, this would undermine a multi-party system of
democratic government. A deliberate decision had therefore been made to confer the
power to establish municipal areas on an independent authority.
740
741
Para 72.
2006 (5) SA 47 (CC).
742
Constitution Twelfth Amendment Act of 2005 and the Cross-boundary Municipalities Laws Repeal
and Related Matters Act 23 of 2005.
743
Para 1.
Paras 39-41.
Section 1(d) of the Constitution.
Section 152(1)(a) of the Constitution.
Section 155(3)(b) provides that national legislation must establish criteria and procedures for the
determination of municipal boundaries by an independent authority.
Executive Council, Western Cape Legislature v President of the Republic of South Africa 2000 (1) SA
661 (CC) para 50.
744
745
746
747
748
167
The Court found that it was clear that the purpose of the Constitution Twelfth
Amendment Act of 2005 (hereafter the Amendment Act) was to re-determine the
geographical areas of the nine provinces of the Republic.749 The Amendment Act
therefore had the effect of re-determining the boundaries of the Sisonke and Alfred Nzo
District Municipalities.750 The applicants contended that Parliament could not do this
because it amounted to performing the functions that vest in the Board in terms of
section 155(3)(b). The issue that arose from the applicants‘ contention was the
following: Did Parliament, in the exercise of its constitutional authority to redefine
provincial boundaries, have the authority to alter municipal boundaries? The Court
answered the question in the negative, stating that in altering provincial boundaries the
Amendment Act did not usurp the powers conferred upon the Municipal Demarcation
Board by section 155(3)(b) of the Constitution and was therefore not inconsistent with
the Constitution on that ground.751
In a concurring judgement, Sachs J was critical of the paucity of information from the
government as to the objectives intended to be served by the relocation of Matatiele
from KwaZulu-Natal to the Eastern Cape.752 He stated:753
Our country has moved a long way since Stratford CJ said that ―Parliament may make
any encroachment it chooses upon the life, liberty or property of any individual subject
to its sway, and that it is the function of courts of law to enforce its will‖. For a decade,
we have now lived in a constitutional democracy in which all power, whether
legislative, executive or judicial, has had to be exercised in keeping with the
Constitution.
He quoted approvingly from S v Acheson,754 where Mahomed AJ said:
The Constitution of a nation is not simply a statute which mechanically defines the
structures of government and the relations between the government and the
governed. It is a mirror reflecting the national soul, the identification of the ideals and
aspirations of a nation; the articulation of the values bonding its people and disciplining
its government. The spirit and the tenor of the Constitution must therefore preside and
permeate the processes of judicial interpretation and judicial discretion.
749
750
751
752
753
754
Matatiele para 46.
Para 48.
Para 85.
Para 95.
Para 96.
1991 (2) SA 805 (NmHC) para 813.
168
Sachs J stated that the spirit of the Constitution was not a ghostly presence that
attaches itself to the text.755 Rather, it was immanent in the text itself,756 which clearly
established the structures, overall design, above all the fundamental values of the
Constitution as set out in its section 1.757 These fundamental values set positive
standards with which all law must comply in order to be valid. A founding value of
particular relevance is that of a multi-party system of democratic government to ensure
accountability, responsiveness and openness.758 The Constitution required candour on
the part of government. What was involved was not simply a matter of showing
courtesy to the public and to the courts, desirable though that always is. It was a
question of maintaining respect for the constitutional injunction that our democratic
government be accountable, responsive and open.759
In Makwickana v Ethekwini Municipality760 the Court found that respect by the
authorities for the rule of law is crucial for a defensible and sustainable democracy.
Malherbe and Van Eck state that it is evident that existing control mechanisms have not
prevented the state from acting outside the scope of the Constitution and have not
ensured state compliance with its constitutional and legal duties. They argue that –761
[i]t is essential in a democracy that the state shall comply with the provisions of the
Constitution and the law. The main objective of the Constitution is to structure the
state and the way in which the governing function is performed. The Constitution
regulates not only the authority of the state; it also controls the exercise of that
authority. It is the primary mechanism to prevent the state from abusing its authority.
State compliance with the Constitution goes a step further, as the Constitution also
ensures that the state remains true to the democratic principles enshrined in the
Constitution. Should the state act outside the boundaries of the constitution, the state
runs the risk of eroding the principles of democracy on which the Constitution is
755
Para 98.
756
Premier, KwaZulu-Natal v President of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (1) SA 769 (CC) para 47.
Section 1 provides as follows: ―The Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign, democratic state
founded on the following values: (a) Human dignity, the achievement of equality and the
advancement of human rights and freedoms. (b) Non-racialism and non-sexism. (c) Supremacy of
the Constitution and the rule of law. (d) Universal adult suffrage, a national common voter‘s roll,
regular elections and a multi-party system of democratic government, to ensure accountability,
responsiveness and openness.‖
Matatiele para 99.
Para 107.
2015 (3) SA 165 (KZD) C 2015 (3) SA para 78A.
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 214.
757
758
759
760
761
169
founded. To ensure the sustainability of democracy in South Africa, it is imperative that
the state acts in accordance with the Constitution and in doing so, upholds democracy
itself.
In Van Niekerk v Pretoria City Council,762 the Court discussed the effect of section 32 of
the Constitution, which deals with the right of access to information, on the right to
ethical, open litigation.763 The Court held the following:
In my view, section 23 entails that public authorities are no longer permitted to play
possum with members of the public where the rights of the latter are at stake.
Discovery procedures and common-law claims of privilege do not entitle them to roll
over and play dead when a right is at issue and a claim for information is consequently
made. The purpose of the Constitution as manifested in section 23, is to subordinate
the organs of the state, including municipal authorities, to a new regime of openness
and fair dealing with the public.
The Supreme Court of Appeal has similarly characterised problems the applicants
encountered with the Department of Social Development as reflecting ―a contempt for
people and processes‖ that is not in line with South Africa‘s constitutional order. The
Court declared that the Department‘s conduct ―misuses the mechanisms of the law,
which it is the responsibility of the courts to safeguard‖. 764 Amit states that in such
circumstances judicial intervention is essential in order to vindicate the rule of law by
making certain that exercises of power accord with the rights found in the
Constitution.765
Amit describes instances when the Department of Home Affairs (DHA) has acted in
blatant defiance of the court process.766 In Bakamundo v Minister of Home Affairs,767
Lawyers for Human Rights (LHR) brought legal proceedings against the DHA because
the detention of the applicant was unlawful. Two days before the Court hearing, while
the Department‘s attorneys were engaged in settlement negotiations with LHR, the DHA
deported the applicant. The Court later found that the applicant had been illegally
deported, in violation of the non-refoulement principle, and instituted constructive
762
763
764
765
766
767
1997 (3) SA 839 (T) para 850.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 5.
Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v Ngxuza
[2001] ZASCA 85 para 19.
Amit 2011 SAJHR 11.
Amit 2011 SAJHR 19.
(SGHC) unreported case no 17271/2009 (12 May 2009).
170
contempt proceedings against the DHA for interfering with the Court process. Amit
describes the tactic of the DHA as follows:768
Despite seemingly strong laws advancing asylum-seeker and refugee rights, DHA
officials have chosen to interpret the law in a manner that limits these rights. The
department‘s approach suggests that it does not feel bound by a strong legal
precedent that pre-determines and bounds its actions. Instead, it has offered various
legal interpretations developed to suit its needs in a particular case. Some of these
changing positions skirt the doctrine of estoppel, which, in general terms, precludes a
party from asserting a position that contradicts one it has previously put forth.
This indicated that the DHA did not feel bound by the law, but instead acted according
to what it deemed to be ―necessary and justifiable‖, irrespective of whether such
necessity accorded with the law.769
Officials of the DHA have even turned to spurious charges to justify the continued
detention of asylum seekers770 and persisted in lodging peripheral and unfounded
allegations in an effort to dismiss affidavits, responded to legal challenges by attacking
the lawyers who bring these cases, without addressing the legal arguments.771 Officials
even argued that LHR staff who depose to affidavits lack standing and may be acting
improperly or even illegally.772
Section 9(1) of the Constitution states that everyone is equal before the law and
everyone has the right to equal protection and benefit of the law. However, is there
equality before the law and equal protection and benefit of the law when the average
citizen engages in litigation against an organ of the state? Little examines the
circumstances where a state joins as a party to litigation in the United States of America
and describes it as follows:773
A state is a subsidised political plaintiff, driven by interest groups and ideology and its
officers' political ambitions; it can afford to bring a weak case and pursue it more
vigorously than could any private plaintiff. When the state takes over, the operation of
partisan interests and ideologies must be taken into account, as must indifference to
768
769
770
771
772
773
Amit 2011 SAJHR 21.
Amit 2011 SAJHR 24.
AS v Minister of Home Affairs (SGHC) unreported case no 101/2010 (12 January 2010).
Zimbabwe Exiles Forum v Minister of Home Affairs [2011] ZAGPPHV 29
Amit 2011 SAJHR 25.
Little 2001 Conn. L Rev. 1168.
171
the costs of litigation, a zealous plaintiff will be less inhibited than a risk-neutral
plaintiff and will act as if the odds of success are higher than an objective, risk neutral
appraisal would show them to be.
Little goes further and state that the remedies and enforcement powers available to the
state as litigant are simply not available to the private litigant. The same scenario is
playing out in South Africa. The state as litigant is in a more powerful position than the
average litigant finds him- or herself in. Organs of state usually have access to more
information and funds than their opponents do. This enables the state litigant to drag a
case through the court for years, indifferent to the cost incurred. After all, a cost order
against an organ of the state is paid for by the taxpaying public.
A case in point is President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Limited.774 In
this case, the respondents sought the release of Khampepe-Moseneke report on the
legality of the 2005 elections in Zimbabwe. It included two appearances in the High
Court, two appearances in the Supreme Court of Appeal and one appearance in the
Constitutional Court. The process dragged on for a period of twelve years despite the
courts holding that the arguments that the applicant relied on were disingenuous and
untrue. Lawyers for the respondent stated before the release of the report that a
concomitant risk is that state officials will be inclined to evade accountability simply by
refusing access to a record and then dragging the matter through the courts until the
issue becomes moot.775 Mootness in this context refers to the principle that a matter is
not justiciable by the court if it no longer presents an existing or live controversy or the
prejudice or threat thereof to the party no longer exists.776
The organ of state may therefore abuse the court process by dragging out the
proceedings until their adversary gives up, runs out of money or until the matter before
the court no longer presents an existing controversy or a threat or prejudice to the
other party, with the risk that the court may dismiss the matter as moot. When an
organ of state engages in such an obstructionist and cynical approach to litigation, it
774
775
776
2015 (1) SA 92 (SCA).
Legalbrief Today ‗Constitutional values threatened by Khampepe appeal – lawyer‘ No:3626 October
2014, available at http://legalbrief.co.za/story/constitutional-values-threatened-by-khampepeappeal-lawyer/ accessed May 2016.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 39.
172
does not do justice to the constitutional notion of equality before the law nor to the
notion of equal protection and benefit of the law. Furthermore, it prevents the
realisation of constitutional rights that is the object of the litigation in many cases. In
order to level the playing-field of litigation, it is important that government departments
be held to a stricter set of rules during court proceedings than their citizen opponents.
Du Plessis et al argue that sections 7(2)777 and 34778 of the Constitution oblige the
government litigant to respect the rights contained in them by ensuring that the matter
is adjudicated on the correct facts. The courts have put it beyond doubt that it is a duty
that the state should not take lightly, including by making adverse cost orders when the
state failed to comply with this duty.779
The state‘s failure to fulfil its constitutional duties is unacceptable in a constitutional
democracy such as South Africa. Such failure by the state challenges the bedrock of the
Constitution and endangers democracy itself. It follows from the great number of cited
cases and the displeasure the courts expressed with government litigants that the state
and state litigants persist in flouting constitutional duties. This strategy by state officials
constitutionally limits the positive application of strategic litigation and restrains the
realisation of constitutional rights. The state litigant then does not act as it is
constitutionally obligated to do; it is not the model litigant.
The current practice of curing vexatious proceedings with a punitive cost order is clearly
not effective when the state, ―clutching the unlimited public purse‖, is the offending
party.780 Adverse cost orders against the state punish the innocent taxpayer. Therefore,
there is a need in South African law of civil procedure for a set of guidelines or
principles with which the government litigant has to comply. The guidelines are
essential for two reasons. Firstly, the state has much more access to funds, information
and legal representation than the average litigant. This is contrary to the right to
equality contained in section 9 of the Constitution. Secondly, there is a pressing need
777
778
779
780
The state must respect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights.
Right to access to courts.
Van Niekerk v Pretoria City Council 1997 (3) SA 839 (T) and Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill
Constitutional Litigation 6.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 789 (CC) para 87.
173
for organs of state to comply with positive constitutional duties. Such principles or
guidelines must be aligned with section 1, read with section 195, of the Constitution.
This would allow the courts to test whether the litigants have complied with their
constitutional duties.
Levelling the litigation playing-field would lead to fairness in
litigation against state actors. It would also bring greater clarity for legal
representatives of the state about the legality of instructions taken from state
institutions. It is submitted that such guidelines would allow lawsuits to be settled more
quickly and fairly, and would give more clarity to government officials about the correct
way to conduct litigation when instructing state legal representatives. These guidelines
would assist the state litigant to be the model litigant. The guidelines are developed
and discussed in chapter 6 of this work.
2.9 Conclusion
The advent of the constitutional era brought significant changes to the South African
law of civil procedure by expanding the duties and powers of the courts. The
Constitution changed the structure and jurisdiction of the courts and granted more
power to the courts, including the power of judicial review. This brought about changes
to the traditional concept of litigation in South Africa. The pre-constitutional concept of
litigation is one of a lawsuit that is generic, retrospective and confined to the parties of
the case. Although such traditional litigation still reaches the courts, the postconstitutional concept of litigation has shifted from lawsuits enforcing private rights and
obligations to lawsuits challenging constitutional or statutory policy or orders. 781
Therefore, the harm alleged is often diffused and not limited to a clearly identifiable
right and the relief required is often forward-looking and general in application,
affecting a wide range of people.
The post-constitutional concept of litigation sets the tone for strategic litigation in which
litigants are able to enforce constitutional values, expose government corruption and
influence and shape government policy. Because of the far-reaching consequences of
the judgment in such a case, the litigation is often used this way to produce rapid and
781
Para 2.2.2 above.
174
comprehensive social transformation. The fact that litigants, lawyers and judges induce
social change in this way has often been criticised.782 The court, as the weakest branch
of government, has no power or ability to enforce the implementation of its orders.
Therefore, the courts often have their orders frustrated at the implementation stage.
The South African courts have stressed that the constitutional obligations imposed on
the state will be monitored by the courts. The court will therefore instruct the
government to comply with its constitutional obligations, but will leave the realisation of
these obligations to the state.783 These obligations are, however, not absolute or
unqualified. An obligation often rests on the state to take reasonable legislative and
other measures to achieve the progressive realisation of the right within the resources
available to it. Such measures will be evaluated by the courts on a case-by-case basis.
The judiciary is institutionally suited for the task of judicial review it assumes in
strategic litigation. The lack of political pressure from the electorate allows the courts to
make unpopular decisions that are based on constitutional interpretation, allowing
politicians to escape blame from the electorate.784 The structural and institutional
advantages of the judiciary to adjudicate on strategic litigation allow the courts to play
an important role in shaping social justice in South Africa. When a litigant approaches
the courts, various procedural hurdles can influence the success of the case. The
litigant must choose what cause of action to use and must determine if the case is
justiciable.
When bringing a lawsuit in South Africa, the plaintiff must set out the cause of action
on which he or she relies to prove his or her claim. A cause of action is a set of facts
giving rise to a claim recognised in law. In strategic litigation, the cause of action can
be derived from the common law, statutory law or the Constitution. The litigant may
often have more than one possible cause of action to rely on. If a right in the Bill of
Rights has been breached or threatened, the litigant can approach the court relying on
the constitutional guarantee of the protection of that right. In other words, the plaintiff
782
Para 2.2.3 above.
783
Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC).
S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC).
784
175
then relies on a constitutional cause of action. The breach may also give rise to a delict
in terms of the common law. The common law therefore also provides a remedy for the
plaintiff to use. The same occurs when the state has legislated to give effect to the
realisation of a right in the Bill of Rights.785 Therefore, there is more than one possible
cause of action available for the plaintiff to employ. The Constitutional Court has found,
however, that the availability of different remedies does not create a parallel system of
laws. The court held that, where possible, any case, civil or criminal, should be heard
without reaching a constitutional issue.786 The courts therefore subscribe to the principle
of subsidiarity, which means that if there is an adequate private-law remedy, whether in
common law or statute, that vindicates the right, it should be followed. The courts,
therefore, have stated clearly that there is no parallel system of laws in place in South
Africa.
The Constitution imposes positive duties on the state to respect, protect, fulfil and
promote the rights in the Bill of Rights.787 Organs of state must also assist and protect
the courts to ensure the independence and effectiveness of the courts. 788 This places a
positive obligation on the state to place all relevant and material evidence before the
court when the state is a party to litigation.789
There is a constitutional injunction on the government to be accountable, responsive
and open.790 The courts require candour from the government. Public administration
must be governed by the democratic values and principles enshrined in the
Constitution,791 including professional ethics, accountability, transparency and fairness.
This principle applies to the administration of every sphere of government, organ of
state and public enterprise.792 The Constitution implies a social contract between the
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
For example, the Promotion of Access to Information Act 2 of 2000, which gives effect to section 27
of the Constitution.
S v Mhlungu 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC).
Section 7(2) of the Constitution.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC).
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
Section 195(2) of the Constitution.
176
state and its citizens.793 It contracts, instructs and directs the state‘s powers and
prevents their abuse. It is therefore imperative that the state complies with its
constitutional duties. However, the state often fails to comply with constitutionally
imposed duties. The courts have frequently expressed their displeasure at the conduct
of the state, for instance saying it acted ―as though it is at war with its own citizens‖. 794
The courts have also held that remissness of the state to comply with constitutional
duties should not be tolerated.795 The Constitution contains fundamental values that set
positive standards with which all law and conduct by the state must comply, also when
the state engages in litigation. These fundamental values therefore set out how the
organ of state ought to behave before, during, and after litigation. It is vital that organs
of state should not be litigating with the intention of winning the case, no matter the
tactics employed. Organs of state should be acting in the public interest, according to
the Constitution. Organs of state should be model litigants.
It is evident that existing control mechanisms have not prevented the state from acting
outside the scope of the Constitution and have not ensured state compliance with the
Constitution and the legal duties conferred on it by the Constitution.796 It is furthermore
evident that the wide constitutional powers conferred on the courts do not prevail when
confronted with organs of state that are systematically ignoring court orders and
constitutionally imposed positive duties. The lack of effective control mechanisms to
ensure that organs of state comply with constitutionally imposed duties constitutionally
limits strategic litigation. Therefore, judicial intervention is essential in order to vindicate
the rule of law by making certain that state power is exercised in accordance with the
rights in the Constitution.797 Comprehensive guidelines that regulate the conduct of the
state litigant are urgently needed in South Africa. The state litigant must be held
constitutionally accountable when litigating. The state must be the model litigant. Such
guidelines are developed and discussed in the final chapter of this work.
793
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 210.
794
Permanent Secretary Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v Ngxuza 2001
795
Van Der Merwe v Taylor 2008 (1) SA 1 (CC).
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR 214.
Amit 2011 SAJHR 11.
(4) SA 1184 SCA.
796
797
177
Chapter 3:
Strategic litigation as an effective check to prevent
the abuse of powers in the context of the doctrine of the
separation of powers
3.1 Introduction
Debates about the proper role and limits of judicial authority in the state are unusually
heated, enduring and inconclusive. Talk about judicial review, the democratic deficit,
the counter-majoritarian difficulty and the separation of powers matters, because what
is at stake is the formal identification of the ultimate forum for political decision-making
in a constitutional democracy.1
The Supreme Court of South Africa was created as a direct result of the union between
the four colonies in Southern Africa: the Cape of Good Hope, Natal, the Orange River
Colony and Transvaal. The South Africa Act2 created a single Supreme Court with the
Appellate Division at its apex. This presented an excellent opportunity for judicial review
in South African legal history. The new Court was unencumbered by legal precedent
and the South Africa Act failed to lay down the limits of judicial authority.3 Judges were
therefore not bound to an uncritical disposition to governmental actions and legislation.
Judicial review was also known in South Africa. The Constitution of the Orange River
Colony entrenched several rights that required a large majority of the Volksraad to
amend,4 and the judges of the former South African Republic (Transvaal) attempted to
follow the lead of the American legal system by declaring invalid particular legislative
procedures used by the Volksraad. The Roman-Dutch legal tradition of South African
law also gave greater prominence to the concept of justice and less to the will of the
legislature.5
At its establishment, the South African Constitutional Court found itself in the same and
even more powerful position than the Appellate Division in 1910. The Court was
1
2
3
4
5
Corder Legal 2004 Studies 253.
South Africa Act, 1909.
Corder Judges at work 8.
Section 20 guaranteed the right to peaceful assembly, s 58 equality before the law and s 60 the
right to property.
Corder Judges at work 9-10.
176
unencumbered by legal precedent, and, in addition, the 1996 Constitution6 made special
provision for its powers of review.7 The Constitution has since its adoption laid the legal
foundation on which the social and political order in South Africa is founded. It lays
down the principles of democratic governance, and establishes and defines the powers
and functions of governmental institutions, as well as the values that underpin the
democracy.
Constitutional Principle VI, of the constitutional principles negotiated during the MultiParty Negotiating Process in 1993 and annexed to the Interim Constitution, provided
the following:
There shall be a separation of powers between the legislature, executive and judiciary,
with appropriate checks and balances to ensure accountability, responsiveness and
openness.
In the 1996 Constitution there is no express statement as to the separation of powers;
it is however implicit in the document itself.8 Although the Constitutional Court on
numerous occasions indicated a commitment to maintain the doctrine of the separation
of powers, it has not addressed the issue of dominant-party democracy or the
overconcentration of power in institutions.9
The dominance of the ruling party and the partial fusion of the legislature and executive
branches of government in South Africa have left the judiciary as the only effective
check on the abuse of power by the other branches of government. This gives rise to
tension between the courts constitutionally mandated to uphold the Constitution and a
government espousing the majoritarian principle of government.
6
7
8
9
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996.
Section 165(2) states that the courts are independent and subject only to the Constitution and the
law, which they must apply impartially and without fear, favour or prejudice; s 167(5) provides that
the Constitutional Court makes the final decision about the constitutionality of any Act or executive
decision.
Chapters 4 to 8 of the Constitution provide for a clear separation of powers between three spheres
of government. Section 43 vests the legislative authority of the Republic in the national sphere in
Parliament and in the provincial sphere in the provincial legislatures. Sections 85 and 125 vest the
executive authority of the Republic in the President and of the provinces in the Premiers,
respectively. Section 165 vests the judicial authority in the courts.
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 34.
177
Strategic litigation allows people, groups and political parties to influence and direct
government policy between elections. An executive-leaning judiciary stacks the odds
against the litigant challenging executive decisions in the courts, which compromises
the avenue for participatory democracy through strategic litigation. The bias or
perceived bias of judicial institutions may cause a ―chilling effect‖ on individuals and
organisations wishing to enforce constitutional rights.
This chapter analyses the nature of the doctrine of the separation of powers in South
Africa and the effect of the hybrid parliamentary form of government on this doctrine.
This analysis starts with an investigation into the historic development of the doctrine of
the separation of powers. A limited legal comparative element is employed to
investigate the application of the doctrine in South Africa, the United States of America
and some European countries. The tension between the different branches of
government is explored, attention being given to the standard of judicial review
employed by the courts and its effect on strategic litigation. The independence of the
judiciary and judicial institutions is investigated, especially with regard to adverse
executive influence on the judiciary and judicial institutions.
3.2 The development of the doctrine of the separation of powers and its
purpose
3.2.1 Historical development of the doctrine of the separation of powers
3.2.1.1
Early philosophers on the concept of the state
In ancient Greece, philosophers articulated different ideas about the ―ideal‖ state. 10 The
philosopher Herodotus of Halicarnassus specified in the fifth century BC that there are
three forms of state to counteract the absolute exercise of power. He categorised
monarchy, aristocracy and democracy as forms of government that counteract absolute
power.11 Aristotle laid down the division of the forms of state that is still regarded as
10
11
Guthrie The Greek Philosophers 81.
Labuschagne n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 23.
178
correct today.12 His theory rested on the premise of a supreme organ in which power is
concentrated and to which all other organs are subordinate. This division started from
the conception of the sovereign, rather than governmental authority. According to
Aristotle, democracy was the most acceptable form of government. Democracy
suggests a relationship between the citizens and the ruler and means that political
control is in the hands of the people, while arbitrary and absolute power is not
entrusted to the ruler alone. This meant that people had the right to exercise real
control over the government.13
According to Labuschagne, the city-states in ancient Greece represented the first model
of democracy and they are usually regarded as the purest. Greek philosophers based
their ideas of the state on human nature and maintained that only in the state can man
attain perfection and find true satisfaction.14 The state for them was the moral order of
the world in which human nature fulfils its end.15 Plato likened the workings of the state
to that of the human body, stating that if one organ of the state could not work
sufficiently, all other organs of the state would experience discomfort. Plato argued as
follows:16
The best state is that which approaches most nearly to the condition of the individual.
If a part of the body suffers, the whole body feels hurt and sympathises altogether
with the part affected.
Aristotle declared the state to be an association of clans and village communities in a
complete and self-sufficient life. Man is by nature a political animal and Aristotle
considered the state to be a product of human nature. According to Aristotle, ―the state
comes into being for the sake of mere life, but exists for the sake of the good life‖. The
individual therefore requires the state to give him legal existence; excluded from the
state, he has neither safety nor freedom.17
12
13
14
15
16
17
Bluntschli The Theory of the State Book VI.
Labuschagne ʼn Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 23.
Labuschagne ʼn Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 24.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 39.
Plato The Republic 462, quoted by Bluntschli The Theory of the State 39.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 40.
179
Labuschagne writes that in the Greek city-states decisions were taken by citizens
eligible for voting at mass meetings. This body of citizens or the ecclesia, took all
important decisions, including the election of officials. According to Labuschagne, public
officials were appointed by casting the lot and in such a way that it represented a broad
representation of the civil society. The executive functions were administered by a
committee of 500, of which the leader committee changed daily.18 Aristotle added a
further political and moral dimension by asking whether the ruler acts on his own behalf
or on the behalf of those he ruled. Labuschagne writes that these early checks and
balances against arbitrary authority were followed by the development of practical
mechanisms of mixed government aimed at creating a more balanced political system.
These mechanisms against arbitrary authority in the early philosophy sowed the seeds
for constitutional development that influenced Western political thinking and the
development of the modern constitutional state.19
Bluntschli posits that the term mixed government or mixed state may be understood as
indicating a state in which the monarchy, aristocracy or democracy may be limited by
the formation of an aristocratic senate and a primary representative assembly of the
people.20 Aristotle contributed to the concept of mixed government by arguing that, in a
healthy political system, there must be a balance between the different constituencies.
According to his theory, this balance would only be achieved if the middle class holds
the power, because they are numerically superior and they collectively hold more power
than the rich and the poor. This balance would have the effect of strengthening mixed
governments.21
3.2.1.2
Germanic influence on the development of the state
Montesquieu argued that the birthplace of parliamentary constitutions is to be found in
the forests of Germany.22 According to Bluntschli, the rudimentary beginning of free
18
19
20
21
22
Labuschagne ʼn Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 24.
Labuschagne n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 24.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 273.
Labuschagne n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 24.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 45; Labuschagne n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die
1993- en 1996-Grondwet 25.
180
representative government which later centuries produced can be found in the primitive
forms of government as described by Tacitus, where the Teutonic kings cooperated
with local princes and chiefs, on the one hand, and with the greater community of
freemen on the other. The Germanic law was not directly derived from the will of the
nation. Here the individual claims an inborn right which the state must protect, but
which the state did not create, and for which the individual is willing to fight, even
against the authority of his own government. Individual freedom was therefore the
supreme right, but the individual was required to sacrifice a part of that freedom to the
state in order to keep the rest more securely.23 Bluntschli writes that the Germanic idea
of the state respected the independence of private rights more decidedly than any
other system of government then in use. The freedom of the person and the family was
more assured and extended than in the Roman Empire. He states that the rights of the
state were therefore limited by the rights of the individual. Consequently, the Germanic
public law admitted no absolute power of the state, even in matters where the
community was affected. Bluntschli, on the Germanic people, stated: ―Before obeying
they wish to deliberate and vote‖. Their Stände were a political power with which the
king had to unite in order to make laws. However, the idea of the state as a collective
was unknown to them. The concept of state was embodied in a king, who was at the
head of the courts of justice and of the assembly of people, the Gau, the Zenf and the
Volksgemeinde. These sometimes strengthen and sometimes limit one another, thus
the whole community experience freedom. These ideas of the state did not show
themselves in the form of a philosophy or a theory, rather they could be found in
practice.24
According to Labuschagne, this development of state institutions in Germania is
important because it shows traces of state diversity, where power is distributed among
various actors. The composition of the tribal meetings (folk-moot) and the chosen
kingship already contain the basic elements of state diversity.25 Tacitus writes that the
king‘s power was neither unlimited nor arbitrary. Minor matters could be disposed of by
23
24
25
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 45.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 45.
Labuschagne n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 23.
181
the chiefs; important matters were deliberated before the assembly of people where
the popular vote settled the matter. He states that this assembly of people was held
regularly and on fixed days and not at the whim of the king or chief and it was before
the assembly of people that criminals were charged and tried. The king, chiefs and
generals might not execute, bind or even strike a delinquent. That power was reserved
for the priests after deliberation by the assembly of people.26 There was therefore a
subscription to the concept that political power had to be limited by established
institutions and prescribed procedures.27 In Tacitus‘s writing circa AD 98, we see the
basic conception of a legal state (Rechtsstaat) in Germania. This idea of a legal state
implies that individual rights could not be affected without a legal process and the
exercise of government power is constrained by law.28 It contained the first signs of
specialised government entities with some form of separate powers for these
institutions.
3.2.1.3
Separation of powers and the state
Montesquieu, the 18th century French social and political philosopher, argued that man
has a natural propensity to misuse political power entrusted to him. Because of man‘s
propensity to abuse power, every form of government will fall into despotism if there
are no restrictions placed on the state. Montesquieu‘s book, Spirit of the Laws, is
considered one of the great works in the history of political theory and jurisprudence,
and it inspired the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Constitution of the United
States.29 Montesquieu explained the division of power in states as follows:30
Republican government is that in which the people as a body, or only a part of the
people, have sovereign power; monarchical government is that in which one alone
governs, but by fixed and established laws; whereas, in despotic government, one
alone, without law and without rule, draws everything along by his will and his
caprices.
26
27
28
29
30
Tacitus Germania VII-XII.
Labuschagne ‘n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 24.
Schmitt The Concept of the Political Chapter 7.
Labuschagne ʼn Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 23.
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 25.
182
Montesquieu described the fundamental maxim of the republican form of government
―as government where officials are elected by the people‖. In order for the people to
trust the government, they must elect its members, either choosing the members
themselves as in Athens, or establishing some magistrate to elect them as was
occasionally the practice in Rome. Writing on the English system of government, he
states that there are three sorts of powers: legislative power, executive power over the
things depending on the right of nations, and executive power over the things
depending on civil right. He argues as follows on the principle of the separation of
powers:31
When legislative power is united with executive power in a single person or in a single
body of the magistracy, there is no liberty, because one can fear that the same
monarch or senate that makes tyrannical laws will execute them tyrannically. Nor is
there liberty if the power of judging is not separate from legislative power and from
executive power. If it were joined to legislative power, the power over the life and
liberty of the citizens would be arbitrary, for the judge would be the legislator. If it
were joined to executive power, the judge could have the force of an oppressor.
He maintained that to promote liberty, these three powers must be separate and acting
independently, and said:32
All would be lost if the same man or the same body of principal men, either of nobles,
or of the people, exercised these three powers: that of making the laws, that of
executing public resolutions, and that of judging the crimes or the disputes of
individuals.
Montesquieu further argues that judges must be elected from the population so that
the accused does not suppose that he has fallen into the hands of people inclined to do
him violence.33 There must be tribunals to arbitrate disputes and make decisions and:34
These decisions should be preserved; they should be learned, so that one judges there
today as one judged yesterday and so that the citizens' property and life are as secure
and fixed as the very Constitution of the state.
Montesquieu writes that it is a great drawback in a monarchy for the ministers or the
princes themselves to judge contested suits. He further makes it clear that it is the
31
32
33
34
Montesquieu
Montesquieu
Montesquieu
Montesquieu
The Spirit of the laws
The Spirit of the laws
The Spirit of the laws
The Spirit of the laws
174.
173-174.
158.
175.
183
prince as the executive who makes the law, but that others should enforce the law.
Political liberty is found to be present only when power is not abused, and so that one
cannot abuse power, power must check power by the arrangement of things.35 This can
be achieved if voting is done in public and the law comes from the people. A
constitution must be of such a nature that no one will be constrained to do the things
the law does not oblige him to do or be kept from doing the things the law permits him
to do.36 Abusive state power can thus be curbed by writing provisions into a constitution
with the aim of limiting or defining the power of the state.
John Calvin favoured a system of government that divided political power between
democracy and aristocracy (mixed government). In order to reduce the danger of the
misuse of political power, he suggested setting up several political institutions, which
should complement and control each other in a system of checks and balances. In this
way Calvin and his followers resisted political absolutism and furthered the growth of
democracy. Calvin's aim was to protect the rights and the well-being of ordinary
people.37
Mojapelo writes that Montesquieu‘s eighteenth-century thinking has served as a sound
and brilliant practical guideline for the prevention of the concentration of power and its
almost inevitable abuse in the hands of one individual or institution. He states that it is
inherently impossible to achieve an absolute separation of powers. This is where there
is room for legitimate variation in accordance with the peculiar circumstances of each
case.38 Montesquieu‘s work had wide political impact, exporting the principle of the
separation of powers to an international audience.39
Montesquieu‘s theory was influenced by an idealised but erroneous conception of the
style of government in England.40 The British system is founded on Acts of Parliament
and judicial decisions, on political practice and the common law. Thus, the executive,
35
36
37
38
39
40
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 155.
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 14.
Olmstead History of Religion in the United States 9-10.
Mojapelo The doctrine of separation of powers (a South African perspective) 45.
Labuschagne ‘n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 39.
Devenish Commentary on the South African Constitution 12.
184
judiciary and legislative branches were not completely independent of each other.41
According to Bluntschli, England was considered a mixed state in which rule is divided
between three supreme powers: the King, the House of Lords and the House of
Commons, and that this English state has been regarded as perfect, just because it is
the ideal representation of a mixed form of government. He further states that it is an
error to suppose that the English constitution has arisen from a division of the
governing power. Bluntschli argues that it was the gradual limitation of the monarchy
that gave the state its special form. This limitation was first enacted by a powerful
aristocracy and later by the admission of democratic elements.42
3.2.1.4
Development of the doctrine of the separation of powers in England
According to Wade and Bradley, the first attempt to introduce some form of devolution
of power in England was through the Magna Carta, enacted in 1215. It did not,
however, set out the doctrine of the separation of powers as it is known today. The
Magna Carta was a statement of grievances brought by a union of important classes
against the king.43 Wade and Bradley write that the Magna Carta set out the rights of
the various classes and the principle that the church was to be free from the state. It
also contained the famous clauses that no person should be punished except by the
judgment of his or her peers or the law of the land, and none should be denied justice.
The Magna Carta for the first time placed limitations on the absolute power of the
monarch. Henceforth the monarch who overstepped his or her powers would be
confronted with a constitutional document embodying the principle of the rule of law. 44
This constitutional development was the start of the supremacy of the law in England.
The supremacy of the law was an important development in combating the arbitrary
use of power by rulers. Carroll, on the importance of the rule of law, argues as
follows:45
41
42
43
44
45
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative law 5.
Bluntschli The Theory of the State 274.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative law 5.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative law 14.
Carroll Constitutional and Administrative law 40.
185
The rule of law is neither a rule nor a law. It is now generally understood as a doctrine
of political morality, which concentrates on the role of law in securing the correct
balance of rights and powers between individuals and the state in free and civilised
societies.
In 1620, a group of English separatist Congregationalists and Anglicans, who later
became known as the Pilgrim Fathers, founded Plymouth Colony in North America.
Enjoying self-rule, they established a bipartite democratic system of government. The
"freemen" elected the General Court, which functioned as legislature and judiciary and
which in turn elected a governor, who together with his seven "assistants" served in the
functional role of providing executive power.46
According to Wade and Bradley, the revolution of 1688 brought about the downfall of
James II (of England) and James VII (of Scotland). The English and Scottish
Parliaments restored the monarchy in the two kingdoms on terms laid down by the Bill
of Rights and Claim of Rights, respectively. This laid down the foundations for the
modern Constitution by disposing of the extravagant rights of the Stuarts to rule by
right. It contained the following important provisions:47
(a)
The power of suspending laws or the execution of laws by regal authority
without the consent of Parliament is illegal;
(b)
the free election of members of Parliament; and
(c)
freedom of speech in Parliament and proceedings in Parliament cannot be
impeached or questioned in a court of law.
The Bill of Rights limited the executive and legislative authority of the monarch and he
or she therefore could not decide, without permission of Parliament, which laws to
enforce or not. It also meant that the crown had to work more closely, and consult
more often, with Parliament. In 1689, John Locke penned the Second Treatise of Civil
46
47
Christopher Plymouth Colony Legal Structure Histarch.uiuc.edu.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative law 14.
186
Government in which he set out the theory of limited government, which justified the
constitutional developments that took place in England.48
The Act of Settlement passed in 1700 by the English Parliament contained the
provisions that judges‘ commissions should be made quamdiu se bene gesserint,49 their
salaries guaranteed and established, and that they may only be lawfully removed after
addressing both Houses of Parliament.50
According to Koopmans, the British form of government has shown a gradual evolution
into its present system. It slowly transformed the king-as-ruler into the king-inParliament; it put the absolute and central powers of the king into the hands of
Parliament.51 The British form of government, which would later become known as a
system of parliamentary sovereignty or the Westminster system, has had a huge effect
on the systems of government of especially British colonies. This leaves the question:
What is the purpose and limits of the doctrine of the separation of powers and how
does it relate to strategic litigation?
3.2.2 Purpose and limits of the doctrine of the separation of powers
The main objective of the doctrine of the separation of powers is to prevent the abuse
of power in the different spheres of government. According to Gildenhuys and Knipe,
government enjoys legislative, executive, judicial and administrative authority in the
modern state. The legislative function involves the enactment of general rules
determining the structure and power of public authorities and regulating the conduct of
citizens and private organisations. They write that the legislature is given the authority
to make laws pertaining to the common affairs of nations. The task of the executive is
to execute the orders of the legislature as contained in the laws made by the
legislature. Gildenhuys and Knipe continue that the mandate of the judiciary is the
interpretation of laws and adjudication on their execution and on the contravention of
48
49
50
51
Labuschagne ‗n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 23.
A clause found in grants of certain offices (as that of judge or recorder) to secure the office holders
in their posts so long as they are not guilty of abusing them.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative law 15.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 19.
187
such laws by the public. Under this model, the state is divided into branches, each with
separate and independent powers and areas of responsibility so that the powers of one
branch are not in conflict with the powers associated with the other branches.52
According to Montesquieu, it is the natural inclination of humanity to misuse authority
granted. ―Unlimited power will corrupt‖53 or, in the words of Lord Acton, ―Absolute
power corrupts absolutely‖.54 When there is no diversification of power between the
structures of the state, a concentration of political power will follow. Sir William
Blackstone referred to this phenomenon as follows: ―If the right of making and
enforcing laws is vested in the same man, and whenever these two powers are united,
there can be no public liberty.‖55
According to Wade and Bradley, the concept of the separation of powers may mean at
least three different things, namely:56
(a)
the same persons should not form part of more than one of the three
organs of government, for example ministers should not sit in Parliament;
(b)
one organ of government should not control or interfere with the work of
another, for example the legislature should be independent of the
executive; and
(c)
one organ of the government should not exercise the functions of another,
for example ministers should not have legislative powers.
Davis writes that the Bill of Rights is another area where the courts play a major role
and sometimes even intrude into the spheres of power of the other branches of
government. This requires the judiciary to examine both the procedural and substantive
52
53
54
55
56
Gildenhuys and Knipe The Organisation of Government 7.
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 133.
Figgis and Laurence Lord Acton 1990.
Blackstone Commentaries on the laws of England Chapter 1.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative Law 53.
188
elements of legislative and executive decisions and, where such decisions are in conflict
with the Bill of Rights, the judiciary has the authority to declare them unconstitutional.57
According to Wade and Bradley, the United States contributed to the doctrine of the
separation of powers with the principles of checks and balances. This requires that each
organ of state be entrusted with special powers designed to keep a check on the
exercise of functions by the others so that equilibrium in the distribution of powers may
be maintained, although a complete separation of powers is not possible in theory or in
practice.58 In modern legal systems, there will always be some overlap between the
different organs of state, but there must be effective checks and balances to prevent
the arbitrary exercise of power by the different branches of government.
It is not the exclusive aim of the doctrine of the separation of powers to create separate
institutions of government. A primary aim of the development of the doctrine is to
prevent the overconcentration of power in a single institution or individual.59 Machiavelli,
a strong exponent of central control in government, preached practical rules for
politicians to obtain and hold on to power. Machiavelli insisted that power was more
important than ethics and morality.60 Machiavelli produced his work during the period of
absolutism (1485-1789) when the classical ideas of mixed government and democracy
were frustrated.61
The doctrine of the separation of powers developed as a counterbalance to absolute
power and decries the concentration of power in one individual or institution. It is
important to note that a primary aim of the principle of the separation of powers is
therefore to prevent the overconcentration of power in a single individual or
57
58
59
60
61
Davis Fundamental Rights in the Constitution 3-4.
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative Law 53.
In Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa; Glenister v President of the
Republic of South Africa 2015 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) para 165, the Court stated that the dilution of power
possessed by any single person to appoint the head of a directorate (in casu, the Head of the
Hawks) he desires resonates with the separation of powers and attaches a significant counterweight
to the power of the executive and its members.
Labuschagne ‘n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 28.
Labuschagne ‘n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 28.
189
institution.62 As will be shown below, in the South African constitutional context, the lack
of effective checks and balances between the executive and legislative branches and
the resulting concentration of political power have opened the door to political activism
through strategic litigation to counterbalance the power of the executive. However,
unwarranted constitutional limitations on strategic litigation may erode the effectiveness
and purpose of the litigation.
3.3 The South African model of the separation of powers
3.3.1 Pre-constitutional parliamentary sovereignty
3.3.1.1
Introduction
The system of parliamentary sovereignty is known as a merger between the executive
and the legislative branches of government rather than a model based on the doctrine
of the separation of powers. Members of the executive are appointed from among the
representatives of the party with the majority in the legislature after a general election.
Members of the executive are therefore also represented in the legislative branch.
Labuschagne maintains that this has the effect that executive programmes can be
conducted effectively from Parliament, but it has the drawback of a fusion between the
legislative and executive branches. This places the executive in a very dominant
position.63 Lord Mustill defines the doctrine of the separation of powers in England as
follows:64
It is a feature of the peculiar British conception of the separation of powers that
Parliament, the executive and the courts have each their distinct and largely exclusive
domain. Parliament has a legally unchallengeable right to make whatever laws it thinks
right. The executive carries on the administration of the country in accordance with the
powers conferred on it by law. The courts interpret the laws, and see that they are
obeyed.
62
63
64
In In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 (4) SA 744 CC
para 112 the Court stated that the New Text (drawn up by the Constitutional Assembly relying on
the Constitutional Principles of the Interim Constitution) expressed concern for the overconcentration of power.
Labuschagne ‘n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 49.
R v Home Secretary, Ex Fire Brigades Union 1995 2 at 513 and 567.
190
According the Wade and Bradley, the legislative supremacy of Parliament means that
there are no legal limitations on the legislative competence of Parliament. This doctrine
consists essentially of a rule that governs the legal relationship between the courts and
the legislature, meaning that the courts are duty-bound to apply the legislation made
by Parliament and may not hold an Act of Parliament to be invalid or unconstitutional. 65
No court can therefore question the validity of a statute and every law-making body in
the country is subject to it.66 The British Westminster system of parliamentary
supremacy was transformed by the decision in 1973 to join the European Union and the
introduction of the Human Rights Act, 1998,67 that opened the door to judicial review in
Britain.
Dicey, writing on the British parliamentary system in 1885, explained the legislative
procedure by defining the collaboration between Parliament and the judiciary. He stated
that the sovereignty of Parliament means just this: Parliament under the English
Constitution has the right to make or unmake any legislation and no person or body is
recognised by the law in England as having the right to override or set aside the
legislation of Parliament.68 According to Koopmans, the success of the doctrine of the
sovereignty of Parliament in England is encouraged by English conceptions of
jurisprudence, legal theory and philosophy. The positive intellectual climate and the
unpopularity of natural law with English philosophers also encouraged the growth of a
centralist system of government. British constitutional law served as a model for other
countries, in particular when Great Britain was at the height of its powers.69 The
Westminster system of government that is prevalent in Britain was exported to most of
the British colonies and South Africa was no exception.
3.3.1.2
Pre-constitutional parliamentary sovereignty in South Africa
During the period 1910 to 1993, the South African government was marked
predominately by the dominance of a fused executive and legislature in a parliamentary
65
66
67
68
69
Wade and Bradley Constitutional and Administrative Law 65.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 15.
Para 3.4.2.2.
Dicey An Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution Chapter 1.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 15-19.
191
system of government, which survived the introduction of a republican state in 1961.70
This constitutional arrangement inhibited the separation of powers between the
legislature, the executive and the judiciary.71 The original intention of parliamentary
sovereignty as an effective check on the power of the executive was corrupted in South
Africa into a means of ensuring the retention of political power by the white inhabitants
of the country.72
The Union of South Africa was formed in 1910, shortly after the South Africa Act73 was
adopted in 1909. The Act had been drafted by the 1908 National Convention, which
met on 12 October 1908 and completed its work on 11 May 1909. This Convention
settled on the terms and Constitution of a governmental, legislative and economic
Union. These proposals were transmitted to the British government, which duly
prepared a Bill to give effect to these wishes. The Bill was passed by Parliament on 20
September 1909 and on that date King Edward VII of the United Kingdom proclaimed
that the Union of South Africa would be established on 31 May 1910. The Act
introduced government institutions of British design for the whole of South Africa and
provided for a bicameral Parliament consisting of a directly elected House of Assembly
and a partly elected and partly nominated Senate.74 The Cabinet had to enjoy the
support of the majority in the House of Assembly and all British conventions applicable
to the King, Prime Minister, Cabinet and lower and upper houses were followed more or
less unchanged in relation to the corresponding South African institutions.
In 1961 South Africa became a Republic in terms of the Republic of South Africa
Constitution Act.75 The most prominent change brought about by the 1961 Constitution
was the replacement of the British monarch by a ceremonial State President. The
70
71
72
73
74
75
Venter 2012 McGill Law Journal 723.
Labuschagne The doctrine of separation of powers 1.
Venter 2012 McGill Law Journal 723.
South Africa Act 1909.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 12.
32 of 1961.
192
existing institutions of the House of Assembly, the Senate and the Westminster system
of government were retained intact.76
Hoexter writes that during the time of the Westminster system of government in South
Africa, judicial review was the primary, and almost the only, significant control of
administrative power. The alternative was a set of administrative appeals; the only
safeguards in the administrative process were the Auditor-General, and (from 1979) an
Advocate-General, neither of which was very effective. The Supreme Court had the
inherent power to test delegated legislation and administrative decisions on grounds
established at common law.77 Innes CJ described this common-law jurisdiction as
follows:78
Whenever a public body has a duty imposed on it by statute, and disregards important
provisions of the statute, or is guilty of gross irregularity or clear illegality in the
performance of duty, this Court may be asked to review the proceedings complained of
and set aside or correct them. This is no special machinery created by the legislature;
it is inherent in the Court.
Hoexter writes that there are two distinctive models for judicial control of administrative
action. The first is the traditional system of parliamentary sovereignty as found in the
British government system. A feature of this system is that administrative bodies are
subject to supervision by the ordinary courts.79 The second system is found in French
law and other legal systems based on it. In this system, the administrative bodies are
subject to supervision by special administrative courts rather than the ordinary courts.
Hoexter says that the second system is generally informed by a strict conception of the
separation of powers. South Africa has always fitted clearly into the first model: the
supervision of the legality of administrative action falls under the jurisdiction of the
superior courts, while the task of assessing the merits rests on organs within the
executive or the legislature.80
76
77
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 12-14.
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 12-13.
78
Johannesburg Consolidated Investment Co Ltd v Johannesburg Town Council 1903 TS 111.
79
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 60.
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 60.
80
193
The doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty was a fundamental constraint on the powers
of the courts. Hoexter states that while the courts had the power to review
administrative conduct, Parliament was free to decide what was lawful and what was
not. It could simply authorise administrative officials to interfere with people‘s rights by
conferring such wide discretionary powers on the official that it was difficult for the
Court to fault the exercise of discretion.81 Dean described the South African
administrative law during this period as follows:82
Administrative law has developed within a system of government which concentrates
enormous power in the hands of the executive and the state administration and in
which law has been used not to check or structure these powers, but rather to
facilitate their exercise by giving those in whom they are vested as much freedom as
possible to exercise them in a way they see best. In this process the South African
courts have at times appeared to be all too willing partners displaying what virtually
amounts to a phobia of any judicial intervention in the exercise of powers by
administrative agencies.
Venter writes that during this period South Africa was internationally known as a human
rights offender. The public law of the country was devoid of any positive recognition of
human rights. This created a situation in which the doctrine of human rights was
reduced ―to either an instrument of oppositional social and political commentary and
mobilisation, or an abstract academic and philosophical theme with undertones of
wishful thinking about a better public law future‖.83
The advent of the democratic era has brought dramatic change to the South African
legal system, including a constitutional dispensation in which the doctrine of the
separation of powers is enshrined, a Constitutional Court at the apex of the legal order
with wide-ranging powers to review the actions of the legislature and the executive,
and a remodelling of the legal system around a dominant Bill of Rights.
81
82
83
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 13.
Dean 1986 SAJHR 164.
Venter 2012 McGill Law Journal 729.
194
3.3.2 Separation of powers in the Interim Constitution
3.3.2.1
Introduction
The constitutional principle of the separation of powers is an essential feature for
modern government. Klug explains that three sets of values in present-day modern
governments frame traditional notions of constitutionalism, namely –84
(a)
federalism, or the spatial divisions of power;
(b)
the separation of powers between the different branches of government;
and
(c)
the notion of constitutional rights.
These values allow different approaches to addressing the problem of limitations on
government. South Africa chose the option of a written Constitution with the doctrine of
the separation of powers entrenched in the document.
In 1993, during the multi-party negotiations, an agreement was reached on the
particulars of an interim constitution, the arrangements necessary to ensure free and
fair elections, and the establishment of a transitional executive council to supervise the
implementation of the Interim Constitution.85 The Interim Constitution86 was assented to
on 25 January 1994 and commenced on 27 April 1994. The Interim Constitution
acknowledged the need to create a new order in which all South Africans would be
entitled to a common South African citizenship in a sovereign and democratic
constitutional state in which there is equality between men and women and people of
all races so that all citizens are able to enjoy and exercise their fundamental rights and
freedoms.87
84
85
86
87
Klug Constituting democracy 24-25.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 16.
200 of 1993.
Preamble to the Interim Constitution.
195
The negotiating parties agreed that an interim government, established and functioning
under the Interim Constitution, would govern the country on a coalition basis while a
final Constitution was being drafted.88 A National Legislature, elected (directly and
indirectly) by universal adult suffrage, would double as the constitution-making body
and would draft the new Constitution within a given time. The new Constitution had to
comply with certain guidelines agreed upon in advance by the negotiating parties. An
independent arbiter, in the form of a Constitutional Court, had to ascertain and declare
whether the new Constitution indeed complied with the guidelines before it could be
put into operation.89 The Preamble to the Interim Constitution characterised the
Constitutional Principles as ―a solemn pact‖ in the following terms:
And whereas in order to secure the achievement of this goal, elected representatives
of all the people of South Africa should be mandated to adopt a new Constitution in
accordance with a solemn pact recorded as Constitutional Principles.
The Preamble of the Interim Constitution therefore acknowledged the Constitutional
Principles to be foundational to the new Constitution.
The Interim Constitution made express provision for the doctrine of the separation of
powers and the independence of the judiciary. Constitutional Principle VI, of the
constitutional principles negotiated at the multi-party negotiating process in the early
1990s and annexed to the Interim Constitution, provided as follows:
There shall be a separation of powers between the legislature, executive and judiciary,
with appropriate checks and balances to ensure accountability, responsiveness and
openness.
Constitutional Principle VII of the negotiated principles read as follows:
The judiciary shall be appropriately qualified, independent and impartial and shall have
the power and jurisdiction to safeguard and enforce the Constitution and all
fundamental rights.
88
89
In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 744 CC para 13.
Section 71(2) of the Interim Constitution reads as follows: ―The new constitutional text passed by
the Constitutional Assembly, or any provision thereof, shall not be of any force and effect unless the
Constitutional Court has certified that all the provisions of such text comply with the Constitutional
Principles referred to in subsection (1) (a).‖
196
The duty to certify whether the final Constitution complied with the negotiated
Constitutional Principles rested with the newly appointed judges of the Constitutional
Court.
3.3.2.2 Certification of the Constitution
In certifying the Constitution, the Court had to deal inter alia with objections regarding
the doctrine of the separation of powers, as was required by Constitutional Principle VI
of the Interim Constitution.90 This Constitutional Principle dealt with issues that directly
or indirectly affected the relationships between the judiciary, on the one hand, and the
legislature and executive, on the other. The Court‘s reasoning will be investigated, as
this forms the future basis of the application of the doctrine of the separation of powers
in the South African constitutional state.
3.3.2.2.1 Objections regarding the doctrine of the separation of powers
The principal objection was directed at the provisions of the section 47(1)(a) of the
Constitution,91 which provides that members of the executive may also be members of
the legislatures at all three levels of government. It was submitted that this failure to
effect full separation of powers enhanced the power of executive government
(particularly in the case of the President and provincial Premiers), thereby undercutting
the representative basis of the democratic order.92
The objection did not state that there had not been an adequate separation of the
judicial power from the legislative and executive power, or that there had not been an
adequate separation of the functions between the legislature, the executive and the
judiciary. The objection was directed at the fact that members of the Cabinet continued
to be members of the legislature and, by virtue of their positions, were able to exercise
a powerful influence over the decisions of the legislature. The objection was that this
90
91
92
In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa , 1996 (4) SA 744 CC.
Section 47(1)(a)(i), in terms of which only the President has to leave the National Assembly whereas
the Deputy President, Ministers and Deputy Ministers are entitled to remain members. The section
contains no provision requiring members of cabinet – other than the President - to resign from their
positions in the National Assembly.
Para 106.
197
was inconsistent with the separation of powers and cited as examples to be followed
the United States of America, France, Germany and the Netherlands.93 The Court
decided as follows:94
There is, however, no universal model of separation of powers, and in democratic
systems of government in which checks and balances result in the imposition of
restraints by one branch of government upon another, there is no separation that is
absolute. This is apparent from the objector‘s own examples. While in the USA, France
and the Netherlands members of the executive may not continue to be members of the
legislature, this is not a requirement of the German system of separation of powers.
Moreover, because of the different systems of checks and balances that exist in these
countries, the relationship between the different branches of government and the
power or influence that one branch of government has over another, differs from one
country to another.95 The principle of the separation of powers, on the one hand,
recognises the functional independence of branches of government, and –96
[o]n the other hand, the principle of checks and balances focuses on the desirability of
ensuring that the constitutional order, as a totality, prevents the branches of
government from usurping power from one another. In this sense it anticipates the
necessary or unavoidable intrusion of one branch on the terrain of another. No
constitutional scheme can reflect a complete separation of powers: the scheme is
always one of partial separation.
The Court stated that Constitutional Principle VI required that there should be a
separation of powers between the legislature, executive and judiciary. It did not
prescribe what form that separation should take. The Court found that constitutional
provisions must not be interpreted with technical rigidity. The language of
Constitutional Principle VI was sufficiently wide to cover the type of separation required
by the New Text.97 The Court accordingly rejected the objection.
The Court found support for its argument in Australian constitutional law.98 In the
Australian case of Victorian Stevedoring and General Contracting Co. Pty. Ltd. and
93
94
95
96
97
98
Para 107.
Para 108.
Para 108.
Para 109.
Para 113; New Text 89: The text drawn-up by the Constitutional Assembly in terms of the
Constitutional Principles of the Interim Constitution.
Para 113.
198
Meakes v Dignan.99 Dixon J, dealing with the Australian Constitution, which
distinguishes between legislative, executive and judicial powers in much the same
manner as does section 47, said: ―These provisions, both in substance and in
arrangement, closely follow the American model of separation of powers upon which
they were framed.‖
Later in Victorian Stevedoring, it was found that –
[t]he arrangement of the Constitution and the emphatic words in which the three
powers are vested by sections 1, 61 and 71 combine with the careful and elaborate
provisions constituting or defining the repositories of the respective powers to provide
evidence of the intention with which the powers were apportioned and the organs of
government separated and described.
The Australian Court thus held that a strict division between the executive and
legislature was not practical and re-affirmed that the Australian Constitution supported
this view.
It is debatable whether the Court followed the correct route by rejecting the objection
based on Australian constitutional law. In Australia, there is little separation between
the executive and the legislature, with the executive required to be drawn from, and
maintain the confidence of, the legislature.100 In the Certification judgment, the court
unfortunately subscribed to a future South African constitutional landscape where the
executive branch and Parliament are ―fused‖, with the result that Parliament is unable
to function as an effective check on the power of the executive.
In Executive Council, Western Cape Legislature v President of the Republic of South
Africa,101 the Constitutional Court was asked for the first time to adjudicate on the
principle of the separation of powers. In this case, the legislature delegated the
authority to amend a local government Act to the President. The President promulgated
the Local Government Transition Act102 transferring the power to appoint and dismiss
99
100
101
102
(1931) 46 CLR 73 at 89.
The Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act 1900 incorporates responsible government, in
which the legislature and the executive are effectively united. This incorporation is reflected in
sections 44, 62 and 64 of the Constitution.
1995 (4) SA 877 (CC).
209 of 1993.
199
Provincial Committee members (responsible for the demarcation and delimitation of the
Western Cape into areas of jurisdiction of transitional councils and transitional
metropolitan sub-structures for the purposes of the local government elections held on
1 November 1995) from the provincial to the national government. 103 This delegation
had the potential for negatively affecting the doctrine of the separation of powers. The
executive usurped the power of the provincial legislature.104
On appeal the Constitutional Court held that the legislature did not have the
competence to delegate its legislative authority to the executive. The Court found that
section 37 of the Interim Constitution placed legislative authority in the hands of
Parliament and that it did not make provision for this authority to be delegated to the
executive.105 The Court argued that this power could be used to introduce contentious
provisions into what was previously uncontentious legislation.106 The Court reasoned
that assuming this was done at a time party A had a majority in the Assembly, but not
in the Senate, it would be difficult for other parties to secure a resolution of Parliament,
which would be needed to invalidate the delegation. It is interesting to note that the
Court took into account the overconcentration of power in state institutions in the
judgment. Unfortunately, this reasoning was not extended to later cases. The judgment
of the Court highlighted the fact that the doctrine of the separation of powers was part
of the South African constitutional state and demonstrated that it was willing to hold
the executive to account should this principle be breached. The Court also affirmed the
supremacy of the Court in constitutional matters.
It is an essential deficit that the principle of the separation of powers was not clarified
to a greater degree in the Interim Constitution and that the partial fusion between the
legislative and executive was not averted. This oversight and the subsequent refusal of
the Constitutional Court to contemplate the danger of the overconcentration of powers
in state institutions led to the situation in which there still is a hybrid parliamentary
system in place with a corresponding concentration of power in the hands of the
103
104
105
106
Para
Para
Para
Para
12.
48.
64.
63.
200
executive.107 O‘Regan declares that a brief review of the South African Constitution
makes it plain that the various branches of government are not hermetically sealed
from one another. In particular, the Constitution opted for a model of the relationship
between the legislature and the executive modelled more closely on the Westminster
system than on the presidential system found in France and the United States. 108
Unfortunately, this weakens the ability of Parliament to function as an effective check
on the abuse of power by the executive.
3.3.2.2.2 Objection about the independence of the judiciary
The main objection with regard to the impartiality of the judiciary 109 was centred on110
the composition and independence of the Judicial Service Commission (hereafter the
JSC).111
Concerning the JSC, the Court stated that the JSC had a pivotal role in the appointment
and removal of judges. It consisted, at the time of the judgment, of the Chief Justice,
the President of the Constitutional Court, one Judge President, two practising attorneys,
two practising advocates, one teacher of law, six members of the National Assembly,
four permanent delegates to the National Council of Provinces, four members
designated by the President as head of the national executive, and the Minister of
Justice. The practising attorneys and advocates and the teacher of law are to be
designated by their respective professions; the Judge President serving on the
Commission is to be designated by the Judges President; at least three members of the
National Assembly must come from opposition parties; the four delegates of the
National Council of Provinces must be supported by the vote of at least six of the nine
provinces; and the four presidential appointments are to be made after consultation
with the leaders of all the parties in the National Assembly.112
107
108
109
110
111
112
Labuschagne ‗n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-Grondwet 218.
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ 125.
In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (4) SA 744 CC.
Para 119.
Section 178 of the Constitution.
Para 120; ss 174 and 178 of the Constitution.
201
The objection stated that Parliament and the executive were over-represented on the
JSC and that the President, who appoints the Minister of Justice, the Chief Justice, the
President of the Constitutional Court and four members of the JSC, and who selects the
Constitutional Court judges from the JSC list or lists, has been given too dominant a
role in the appointment of judges.113 The President is required to do this after consulting
the profession concerned and is required to consult the JSC before appointing the Chief
Justice.114 The President is also required to consult with the JSC and the leaders of
parties represented in the National Assembly before appointing the President of the
Constitutional Court.115
Constitutional Principle VI made provision for the separation of powers between the
legislature, executive and judiciary and Constitutional Principle VII required the judiciary
to be ―appropriately qualified, independent and impartial‖. Section 174(1) of the
Constitution requires that a person appointed to judicial office be ―appropriately
qualified‖ and a ―fit and proper person‖ for such office.116
The Court found that these are objective criteria subject to constitutional control by the
courts, and met the requirements of Constitutional Principle VII in that regard. The
Constitutional Principles did not require a JSC to be established and contained no
provision dealing specifically with the appointment of judges. The Court stated that an
essential part of the separation of powers is an independent judiciary.117 The Court
found that the fact that the executive makes, or participates in, the appointment of
judges was not inconsistent with the doctrine of the separation of powers or with the
judicial independence required by Constitutional Principle VII as Parliament and the
executive decide on judicial appointments in different jurisdictions where the principle
of separation of powers is well entrenched.
The Court argued that the crucial principle of the doctrine of the separation of powers
and the independence of the judiciary is that the judiciary should enforce the law
113
114
115
116
117
Para 121.
Section 174(4) of the Constitution.
Section 174(3) of the Constitution.
Para 122.
Para 123.
202
impartially and that it should function independently of the legislature and the
executive. Section 165 is intended to achieve this by vesting the judicial authority in the
courts and protecting the courts against any interference with its authority.
Constitutionally, therefore, all judges are independent. The JSC contains significant
representation from the judiciary, the legal professions and political parties of the
opposition. It participates in the appointment of the Chief Justice, the President of the
Constitutional Court and the Constitutional Court judges, and it selects the judges of all
other courts. The Court rejected the objection, stating that the JSC as an institution
provides a broad-based selection panel for appointments to the judiciary and provides
checks and balances on the power of the executive to make such appointments.118
It is unfortunate that the Court did not explore the effect of the ―fusion‖ between the
legislative and the executive branches, especially on the appointment of judges. Faure
and Lane predicted in 1996 that the effect would be the centralisation of power and
authority in the office of the President, the institutionalisation of executive power, the
decline of Parliament and the creation of informal systems of influence based upon
patronage to the leader. They wrote that despite the importance of the Bill of Rights
and the Constitutional Court, it was inevitable that the Constitution would give the
executive the foundation upon which to accumulate considerable power. 119 The
challenge is therefore how to balance this authority of the executive with the danger to
liberty that power always entails.120 The Constitutional Court, from its first judgment,
dismissed the notion of overconcentrated executive power in the JSC, thus ignoring one
of the basic tenets of the doctrine of the separation of powers, namely the prevention
of the overconcentration of power in public institutions. Although there is some
diversification in the composition of the JSC, it is not enough to prevent the
overconcentration of political power that Montesquieu cautioned against.121
118
119
120
121
Para 124.
Faure and Lane South Africa: Designing new political institutions 73.
Faure and Lane South Africa: Designing new political institutions 74.
Para 3.2.2 above.
203
3.3.3 Separation of powers in the South African constitutional state
3.3.3.1
Constitutional provisions
In the 1996 Constitution contains no express statement about the separation of
powers; it is, however, implicit in the document, and the structure and wording of the
Constitution embody a separation of powers.122 Chapters 4 to 8 of the Constitution
provide for a clear separation of powers between three spheres of government. Section
43 vests the legislative authority of the Republic in the national sphere in Parliament
and in the provincial sphere in the provincial legislatures. Sections 85 and 125 vest the
executive authority of the Republic in the President and of the provinces in the
premiers, respectively. Section 165 vests the judicial authority in the courts. Section 2
of the Constitution states unequivocally that the Constitution is the supreme law, that
law or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid and that the obligations imposed by it must
be fulfilled. The legislative authority is vested in Parliament (in the national sphere of
government), provincial legislatures (in the provincial sphere) and in municipal councils
(in the local sphere).123 In the national sphere, the executive authority is vested in the
President as head of the national executive and exercised together with other members
of the Cabinet.124 In the provincial sphere, the same applies to the premier and the
executive committee of every province.125
In terms of the Constitution –
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
(a)
the legislative authority at the national level is vested in Parliament;126
(b)
the executive authority is vested in the President; and127
(c)
judicial authority is vested in the courts.128
Van der Westhuizen 2008 AHRLJ 255.
Sections 43, 44, 104 and 156 of the Constitution.
Sections 83 and 85 of the Constitution.
Section 125 of the Constitution.
Section 43(a) of the Constitution.
Section 85(1) of the Constitution.
Section 165(1) of the Constitution.
204
The constitutional role of the courts are clearly defined in section 165(1) of the
Constitution, which provides that the judicial authority of the Republic is vested in the
courts – and only in the courts, not in the government, nor in any organ of civil
society.129
3.3.3.2 Constitutional role of the courts
The role of the Constitutional Court includes deciding disputes between organs of state,
deciding on the constitutionality of legislation and, under certain circumstances, Bills,
and on the constitutionality of any amendment to the Constitution, and deciding the
question whether Parliament or the President has failed to fulfil a constitutional
obligation.130 The Constitutional Court is the highest court in all constitutional matters
and thus decides appeals from other courts in disputes involving natural and juristic
persons and the state, including criminal matters, if the matter is a constitutional matter
or an issue connected with a decision on a constitutional matter.131 The Constitution
Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012 expanded the jurisdiction of the Court. The Court
may now hear any matter, if the Constitutional Court grants leave to appeal because
the matter raises an arguable point of law of general public importance that ought to be
considered by that court.
The Constitution makes it clear that the courts are independent and subject only to the
Constitution and the law.132 All persons to whom and organs of state to which a court
order or decision applies are bound by it.133 The courts must apply the Constitution and
the law impartially and without fear, favour or prejudice.134 When taking office, judges
swear or solemnly affirm to uphold and protect the Constitution and the human rights
entrenched in it and to administer justice to all persons alike, without fear, favour or
prejudice, in accordance with the Constitution and the law.135 The Constitution is
emphatic about the independence of the courts. Section 165(3) provides that no person
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
Van der Westhuizen 2008 AHRLJ 256.
Section 167 of the Constitution.
Section 167(3) of the Constitution.
Section 165(2) of the Constitution.
Section 165(5) of the Constitution.
Section 165(2) of the Constitution.
Item 6 of Schedule 2 of the Constitution.
205
or organ of state may interfere with the functioning of the courts. Nevertheless, the
overconcentration of executive power in judicial institutions begs the question: is the
judiciary truly independent?
In De Lange v Smuts,136 the Court had to deal with questions regarding the
independence of the judiciary. The applicant was convicted of the unlawful possession
of a firearm and ammunition and challenged the legality of the proceedings in the
regional court, contending that the magistrate‘s court lacked the institutional
independence as required by the Constitution. He subsequently sought to supplement
his appeal by review proceedings in which similar issues pertaining to the lack of
institutional independence of the regional court were raised. The case raised important
issues concerning the constitutionality of provisions of the Magistrates‘ Courts Act,137 the
Magistrates Act,138 and regulations made in terms of the Magistrates Act.139
The Constitutional Court found that the core of judicial independence is the complete
freedom of individual judicial officers to hear and decide the cases that come before
them, with no outside interference or attempt to interfere with the way in which judicial
officers‘ conduct their cases and make their decisions. Individually, judicial officers must
be free to act independently and impartially in dealing with the cases they hear and, at
an institutional level, there must be structures to protect courts and judicial officers
against external interference. These safeguards must include security of tenure and a
basic degree of financial security.140
In deciding whether a particular court lacks the institutional protection it requires to
function independently and impartially, it is relevant to have regard to the core
protection given to all courts by the Constitution, to the functions that the particular
court performs and to its place in the court hierarchy. Lower courts are, for instance,
entitled to protection by the higher courts should their independence be threatened.
136
137
138
139
140
1998 3 SA 785 (CC).
32 of 1944.
90 of 1993.
Regulations for Judicial Officers in the Lower Courts, 1994, published under GN R361 in Government
Gazette No 15524 of 11 March 1994 (as amended), and the Complaints Procedure Regulations,
1998, published under GN R1240 in Government Gazette No 19309 of 1 October 1998.
Para 70.
206
The greater the protection given to the higher courts, the greater is the protection that
all courts have. Judicial independence can be achieved in a variety of ways and the
mere fact that the legislation dealing with lower courts differs from the Constitution‘s
provision for higher courts is no reason for holding it to be unconstitutional.
The Court stated that the test for assessing whether the requirements for judicial
independence have been satisfied included an element of appearance or perception of
the court from the objective standpoint of a reasonable and informed person. Would
the court be perceived as enjoying the essential conditions of independence?141 The
Court found reasoning for this argument in the Canadian case of Valente v The Queen142
and stated:143
Both independence and impartiality are fundamental not only to the capacity to do
justice in a particular case but also to individual and public confidence in the
administration of justice. Without that confidence the system cannot command the
respect and acceptance that are essential to its effective operation. It is, therefore,
important that a tribunal should be perceived as independent, as well as impartial, and
that the test for independence should include that perception.
The constitutionality of many of the challenged provisions depends on whether the
Magistrates Commission is an independent body or subject to control by the Minister.
The Commission must be chaired by a High Court judge and must include magistrates,
lawyers in private practice and parliamentarians. The Commission‘s objectives include
ensuring that the appointment, promotion, transfer or discharge of, or disciplinary steps
against, magistrates take place without favour or prejudice and that no influencing or
victimisation of magistrates takes place. Therefore, although the executive influences
the selection of the Commission‘s members, this body is an important safeguard of
judicial independence. There is no reason to believe that its members will not discharge
their duties with integrity.144
The Court unfortunately overlooked the premise of the doctrine of the separation of
powers. One of the main objectives of the doctrine of the separation of powers is to
141
142
143
144
Para 32.
(1986) 24 DLR (4th) 161 (SCC).
Para 70.
Para 38.
207
prevent the abuse of power within different spheres of government.145 De Vries argues
that from a conceptual point of view, the doctrine of the separation of powers is
logically as much about the concept of power as it is about the concept of separation
between the branches of government.146 The main aim of the separation of powers of
government is therefore ―that of securing liberty by preventing the concentration of
power and by restraining its arbitrary deployment‖.147 The fact that the executive can
appoint the majority of members of the Magistrates Commission may lead to an
overconcentration of power in this institution and may result in the abuse of power.
Ellmann states that the composition of the JSC mixes considerations of professional
expertise and political choice. He acknowledges that political actors make up much of
the JSC‘s membership but leaves open the question of whether the system allows for
too much political influence.148 Mbazira examined the composition of the appointments
to the Constitutional Court and found that it has been dominated by persons who were
intricately involved in the ruling party.149 At the time of his research all judges of the
Constitutional Court have either been former ANC people or sympathetic to the ANC‘s
social policies. He argues that a political background may well be viewed as an asset
rather than a liability. In support of this argument, he quotes a passage from the JSC
interview with Sachs (before he was appointed to the Constitutional Court). Sachs was
asked about his political affiliation and how this history would influence his decisions as
a judge. He answered as follows:150
I might say that I do not think that it is a disadvantage to the court to have a member
who has had political experience and I say this with the confidence I got having been
to Germany. … The test is not whether or not you are being politically active and
involved, the test is do you have the independence and the credibility as a thinker and
as a person to work well. And the feeling there is that if you are going to have
somebody who is going to act as a brake on Parliament, a brake on the executive, it is
145
146
147
148
149
150
Mojapelo The doctrine of separation of powers 38.
De Vries 2006 Politeia 43.
Pennock and Smith Political science: An introduction 264.
Ellmann 2009 Constitutional Court Review 114.
Mbazira 2009 Constitutional Court Review 154; Faure and Lane Designing new political institutions
85.
Sachs‘s
response
to
interview
questions
at
the
JSC
http://www.constitutionalcourt.org.za/site/judges/transcripts/albertlouissachs.html
accessed
February 2015.
208
better to have people, at least some of the Judges who know the mechanisms and the
working and the thought process to be able to be most effective in that respect. … It is
not enough to be honourable and clever, you are working in a society and you are
relating to other institutions of Government and a good Constitutional Court functions
well within that context. And I think from that point of view a little bit of experience in
the world outside of the courts will not be at all damaging to the court and I will be
happy to contribute that.
Mbazira states that a short review of Sachs‘s judgments shows that in the main it has
been directed, not by black-letter law, but rather by what he conceptualises as an ideal
society shaped by the values to which he is committed and worked to bring into
existence.151
There can be no doubt that Sachs J brought a wealth of experience and knowledge to
the Constitutional Court bench. Indeed, it is not the intention of this work to impugn
the integrity of any of the past or serving judges of the Constitutional Court. It must,
however, be explored to what extent the influence of the executive on the appointment
of judges reflects on the credibility of the courts.
In Van Rooyen v The State,152 the Court again investigated the independence of the
magistrates‘ courts after the recomposition of the Magistrates Commission. The High
Court found that the control exercised over magistrates by the Minister of Justice does
indeed impermissibly limit their judicial independence and declared a number of
provisions of the Magistrates‘ Courts Act, the Magistrates Act and the Regulations for
Judicial Officers in Lower Courts inconsistent with the Constitution and invalid. On
appeal to the Constitutional Court, the Court found that the constitutionality of many of
the challenged provisions depended on whether the Magistrates Commission was an
independent body or subject to control by the Minister. The Court stated that, although
the executive influences the selection of the Commission‘s members, this body is an
important safeguard of judicial independence. The Court again cited with approval the
151
152
Mbazira 2009 Constitutional Court Review 157.
2002 (5) SA 246 CC.
209
―perceived independence‖ test from Valente v The Queen.153 The Court, in investigating
the issue of appearance, stated that –154
[t]he apprehension of bias must be a reasonable one, held by reasonable and rightminded persons, applying themselves to the question and obtaining thereon the
required information. In the words of the Court of Appeal: ―that test is what would an
informed person, viewing the matter realistically and practically, and having thought
the matter through conclude.‖
The Court agreed that an objective test properly contextualised is an appropriate test
for the determination of the issues raised about the separation of powers. The
perception that is relevant for such purposes is, however, a perception based on a
balanced view of all the material information.155 The Court construed it as follows:
Bearing in mind the diversity of our society this cautionary injunction is of particular
importance in assessing institutional independence. The well-informed, thoughtful and
objective observer must be sensitive to the country‘s complex social realities, in touch
with its evolving patterns of constitutional development, and guided by the
Constitution, its values and the differentiation it makes between different levels of
courts.
The Court then analysed the recomposition of the Magistrates Commission and found
that it has served a legitimate purpose to make it more representative of the South
African society, and continued that the changes made facilitated this, which would have
been understood by an objective observer taking a balanced view of all the relevant
circumstances.156 The Court again neglected to apply its mind to Montesquieu‘s warning
of the overconcentration of power in an institution and its effect on the doctrine of the
separation of powers.
When the same test of the objective observer is applied to the Constitutional Court, the
following question has to be asked: What would the objective observer conclude,
153
(1986) 24 DLR (4th) 161 (SCC).
154
Committee for Justice and Liberty v National Energy Board (1976) 68 DLR (3d) 716 at 735.
155
Para 34.
Para 61.
156
210
concerning the political affiliation of the appointees, about the independence of the
institution? The Court answered the question in the SARFU Recusal case157:
That a judge may have engaged in political activity prior to appointment to the bench
is not uncommon in most if not all democracies including our own. Nor should it
surprise anyone in this country. Upon appointment, judges are frequently obliged to
adjudicate disputes which have political consequences. It has never been seriously
suggested that judges do not have political preferences or views on law and society.
Indeed, a judge who is so remote from the world that she or he has no such views
would hardly be qualified to sit as a judge. What is required of judges is that they
should decide cases that come before them without fear or favour according to the
facts and the law, and not according to their subjective personal views. This is what
the Constitution requires.158
Venter states that it is accepted that politicians deal subjectively (politically) with policy
references in the making of laws and their execution and administration. He continues
that it is generally supposed that judges should maintain an attitude of objective
rationality in the adjudication of cases.159 Can the judiciary maintain such an attitude of
objective rationality when hearing matters, especially those where the executive is a
party? The call by the ANC‘s National Executive Committee in 2005 to bring "the
collective mind-set of the judiciary" into consonance with the vision and aspirations of
the millions who engaged in struggle to liberate our country from white minority
domination" is therefore ominous.160 Given this approach, the threat remains that the
executive might progressively try to ensure that executive-minded judges are appointed
to the bench.
The Constitutional Court have to date not squarely confronted a fundamental issue
relating to the doctrine of the separation of powers, namely that of the
overconcentration of powers in institutions. Malan writes about the JSC as follows:161
If the broad review powers of the South African courts with their actual and potential
political implications are taken into account, the composition of the JSC and its
decisions pertaining to recommendations of candidates, disciplining of judges –
provided for in the Constitution and other legal instruments referred to below – are
157
158
159
160
161
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
para 70.
Para 74.
Venter PELJ 130.
De Klerk 2010 PELJ 8.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1968.
211
obviously of political significance, rendering the JSC nothing less than an important
political body.
Although the JSC does not form part of the executive, its composition secures a
dominant position for the ruling party, at least twelve of its members being politicians
appointed by the ruling party.162 Labuschagne writes that the status of the JSC, as
independent judicial guard dog, has been politically tampered with. He states that the
cadre appointments and a series of controversial judiciary Bills that have been
proposed,163 shows an attempt to bring the judiciary more in line with the majority
sentiment and firmly under control of the executive.164 None of the proposed Bills has to
date been promulgated, but Malan makes the interesting observation that the
appointment of judges is excluded from the ambit of administrative actions reviewable
under the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act165 (hereafter PAJA). Malan argues that
the appointment of judges is political in nature and for that reason government has an
interest in not allowing these decisions to be subject to the strict requirements that
govern administrative actions.166
Devenish remarks that the executive's influence on the composition of the Standing
Committee on Public Accounts (Scopa) is a cause for concern and that this should be
considered unacceptable because it adversely affects the independence of Parliament. 167
This premise is also relevant to the executive‘s influence on the JSC as it adversely
affects the independence of the judiciary. A casual glance will show that there is a
prodigious concentration of powers friendly to the executive on the Magistrates
Commission, the JSC and the Constitutional Court. After adoption of the Interim
Constitution, the ruling party in practice controlled seven of the eleven appointments to
162
163
164
165
166
167
Malan 2014 PELJ 1968-1969.
During 2005, the government released five draft Bills, including a constitutional amendment
(Constitution Fourteenth Amendment Bill) that would have effectively placed and subjected the
Bench to the authority of the Minister of Justice (executive authority). This was followed by the
Superior Courts Bill, 2006, that echoed the sentiments of the Constitution Fourteenth Amendment
Bill, which also would have shifted court administration and budgeting to the Minister of Justice. At
the time of writing, none of these amendments happened. Indeed, the Superior Courts Act 10 of
2013 places the administration of the courts in the hands of the Chief Justice.
Labuschagne 2011 Politeia 20.
3 of 2000, s 1(gg) of the Act.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1969.
Devenish 2003 THRHR 89.
212
the Constitutional Court, including that of the President of the Court, and six judges
appointed from the JSC‘s list of nominations.168 The 1996 Constitution provides that
both the Chief Justice and the Deputy Chief Justice must be appointed by the President
after consultation with the JSC and the National Assembly.169 The rest of the judges are
appointed by the President, after consultation with the National Assembly, from a list
prepared by the JSC.170 The capacity to control judges therefore depends on the
capacity to control the JSC.171 With the ruling party in a position to appoint the majority
of the members of the JSC,172 there can be no other conclusion than that the JSC is
controlled by the ruling party and therefore the ruling party is controlling the
Constitutional
Court.
Such
executive-leaning
structures
are
worrisome
when
contemplating litigation against the state.
In Ferreira v Levin,173 the Constitutional Court recognised the potential danger of an
adverse cost order in constitutional litigation having a chilling effect on litigants‘
willingness to enforce their constitutional rights. The potential perception of an
executive-minded judiciary may lead to the same conclusion. It can have a ―chilling
effect‖ on litigants wishing to protect their constitutional rights against abuse by the
executive. This ―chilling effect‖ would place an unconstitutional limitation on strategic
litigation. This reflects negatively on the ―moral authority‖ of the courts to hear matters
impartially and independently. In S v Mamabolo174 Kriegler J said:
In our constitutional order the judiciary is an independent pillar of state,
constitutionally mandated to exercise the judicial authority of the state fearlessly and
impartially. Under the doctrine of separation of powers it stands on an equal footing
with the executive and the legislative pillars of state; but in terms of political, financial
or military power it cannot hope to compete. It is in these terms by far the weakest of
the three pillars; yet its manifest independence and authority are essential. Having no
constituency, no purse and no sword, the judiciary must rely on moral authority.175
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
Roux The politics of principle 167-168.
Section 174(3) of the Constitution.
Section 174(6) of the Constitution.
Roux The politics of principle 169.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1968-1969.
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) para 155.
2001 3 SA 409 (CC).
Para 16.
213
Although the Constitution clearly envisions a separation of powers between the different
branches of government, the application of the doctrine in South Africa is far from
settled. Ackerman J stated the following:176
I have no doubt that over time our courts will develop a distinctively South African
model of separation of powers, one that fits the particular system of government
provided for in the Constitution and that reflects a delicate balancing, informed both by
South Africa‘s history and its new dispensation, between the need, on the one hand, to
control government by separating powers and enforcing checks and balances, and, on
the other, to avoid diffusing power so completely that the government is unable to
take timely measures in the public interest.177
The fact that the executive is attempting to colonise independent institutions meant to
check its exercise of power leads to the question of how the South African constitutional
order and, in particular, the Constitutional Court will respond.178
The Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012179 provides explicitly that the
Chief Justice is the head of the judiciary and has responsibility to establish and monitor
norms and standards for all courts, which is undoubtedly an important step in
safeguarding the independence of the judiciary and must be lauded. However, until the
independence of the judiciary and its constitutional duty is fully understood and
accepted by the other branches of government, tension between the executive and the
judiciary will remain.
3.3.4 The rising tension between the executive and the judiciary
3.3.4.1
Introduction
The court process is often used by individuals, organisations and the state to advance
their own goals and objectives. The fact that the judiciary may change or modify official
government policy often leads to tension between the different organs of state.
Before the advent of the constitutional order in South Africa, Corder argued as follows:
176
177
178
179
De Lange v Smuts NO Case CCT 26/97 1998 CC para 60.
Para 60.
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 3.
The Act came into operation on 23 August 2013.
214
It seems to me that we should rapidly become aware of the extent of the impact the
presence of a Bill of Rights will have on the appointment and accountability of the
judiciary and the way in which legal challenges are argued and decided. In addition,
we should harbour few illusions that the law, through a Bill of Rights, will fashion some
miraculous breakthrough which will render further struggles for political democracy
redundant.
Corder pleads for a sober understanding of such a Bill's inherent limitations, including
the difficulty of enforcing it.180
3.3.4.2
International position
3.3.4.2.1 Position in the United States of America
In Marbury v Madison,181 the American Supreme Court announced for the first time the
principle that a court may declare an Act of Congress void if it is inconsistent with the
Constitution. Marshall CJ formulated this opinion by declaring how the American
Constitution defines and limits the powers of the legislature. It does this by attributing
certain powers to the federal Congress and leaving others to the state legislature, and
by forbidding Congress from making certain laws.182 The authorities from whom these
rules proceed are supreme because they have been established by the people
themselves. The people thus have an original right to establish the rules applicable to
future government and they exercise this right by assigning to different institutions their
respective powers. The Chief Justice concluded with the following statement:183
The Constitution is either a superior paramount law, unchangeable by any ordinary
means, or it is on a level with ordinary legislative acts and, like any other act, is
alterable when the legislature shall please to alter it. If the former part of the
alternative be true, then written constitutions are absurd attempts, on the part of the
people, to limit a power in its own nature illimitable.
Since Marbury v Madison the American Supreme Court has been the final arbiter of the
constitutionality of congressional legislation. This does not mean that there is not an
on-going debate about the validity of judicial review in the United State of America.
180
181
182
183
Corder 1992 SALJ 206.
5 US 1 Cranch 137 1803.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 37.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 37.
215
Professor Corder, in analysing the arguments of Robert Bork on the separation of
powers in the United States of America,184 comments that Bork is concerned with the
judicial role in government under the American Constitution. His basic argument is that
the law, through the judgments of the Supreme Court, has become ―seduced‖ into
playing a political role to which it is unsuited and which the Constitution did not intend
it to assume.185 Bork remarks that ―politics‖ has seduced institutions; he reasons as
follows:
In the past few decades American institutions have struggled with the temptations of
politics. Professions and academic disciplines that once possessed a life and structure
of their own have steadily succumbed to the belief that nothing matters beyond
politically desirable results, however achieved. In this quest, politics invariably tries to
dominate another discipline, to capture and use it for politics' own purposes, while the
second subject – law, religion, literature, economics, science, journalism, or whatever –
struggles to maintain its independence. It is coming to be denied that anything counts,
not logic, not objectivity, not even intellectual honesty, that stands in the way of the
"correct" political outcome.
Bork concludes with the following:186
There are heavy costs for the legal system, heavy costs for our liberty to govern
ourselves, when the Court decides it is the instrument of the general will and the
keeper of the national conscience. Then there is no law; there are only the moral
imperatives and self-righteousness of the hour.
Bork argues that the spectacular efflorescence of modern constitutional theory is not a
sign of vigour and health but in reality is the brilliant flower of decay. He states,
however, that constitutional theory is necessary for attempts to resolve what he calls
the ―Madisonian dilemma‖, which is one of the central problems for any constitutional
court: the conflict between the principle of self-government by the majority and that of
protection of the individual or a minority against the tyranny of the majority.187
Koopmans comparatively analysed the current and past decisions of the American
Supreme Court and noticed a difference in emphasis. The current Supreme Court
prefers to limit the scope of cases before it and is more concerned with formal elements
184
185
186
187
Corder 1992 SALJ 207.
Bork The Tempting of America 209.
Bork The Tempting of America 210.
Bork The Tempting of America 211.
216
such as admissibility.188 In Arizonians for Official English v Arizona,189 the Court stated
that a more ―cautious approach‖ to judicial review was in order. Koopmans refers to the
deeply divided political landscape of the American society and states that the choices
made by the Court may again come under the political spotlight. He observes that the
volatile character of American politics does not rest easy with the consistency that the
American Supreme Court strives to achieve in its constitutional interpretation.190
3.3.4.2.2 Position in European countries
During the nineteenth century, judicial review of legislation remained an American
phenomenon. Judicial review of legislation was part of a specifically American
conception of democracy that was completely at odds with the dawning democratic
government in Europe.191 Koopmans states that the European perception started to
change as faith in the reliability of political institutions, even when democratically
elected, began to shrink after Europe experienced dictatorship and world wars. Judicial
review was also being considered as an expression of the idea that protection of civil
liberties might not be safe in the hands of, if wholly entrusted to, political institutions. 192
Austria was the first European country to introduce judicial review of legislation. The
Republican Constitution of 1920 reinforced the protection of civil liberties by setting up
a specialised court to which issues of the compatibility of legislation with provisions of
the Constitution could be referred. Ireland followed with the 1937 Constitution, which
explicitly provided for judicial review of legislation.193
After the Second World War, both Italy and Germany followed suit and adopted
constitutions that entrusted judicial review to specialised courts. In France, one
enduring legacy of the French Revolution was the prohibition of judicial review. The
purpose of the prohibition was to seal off the "political function" (law-making) from the
"judicial function" (dispute resolution), thereby securing the supremacy of statute within
188
189
190
191
192
193
Koopmans Courts
520 US 43 1997.
Koopmans Courts
Koopmans Courts
Koopmans Courts
Koopmans Courts
and Political Institutions 61-62.
and Political Institutions
and Political Institutions
and Political Institutions
and Political Institutions
62.
40.
41.
42.
217
the legal order.194 The French Constitution of 1958 introduced judicial scrutiny of the
compatibility of statutes with the Constitution before the statute is officially
promulgated and published. The Constitution introduced the Conseil Constitutionnel, or
Constitutional Council, as the highest constitutional authority in France. Strictly
speaking, the French Constitutional Court could not exercise judicial review because it
could only look into questions of constitutionality between the passing of the bill and
the promulgation of the statute: it ―previews‖ rather than reviews.195 Its main activity
was to rule on whether proposed statutes conformed to the Constitution, after they had
been approved by Parliament and before they were signed into law by the President of
the Republic. However, the position was changed by the French constitutional law of 23
July 2008,196 which amended article 61 of the French Constitution. Courts may now
submit questions of unconstitutionality of laws to the Constitutional Council.197 The
Court of Cassation (Supreme Court over civil and criminal courts) and the Council of
State (Supreme Court over administrative courts) filter the requests coming from the
courts below them.
The principle of judicial review and the issue of the doctrine of the separation of powers
are settled in most European countries. In terms of the European Convention for the
Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, all member countries of the
European Union must abide by the provisions of the Convention.198 The European Court
of Human Rights is jurisdictionally empowered to review matters relating to human
rights in member countries. The purpose is to ensure that the standards of the
Convention and its protocols are observed by the governments, authorities, executives,
judiciaries and citizens of the states concerned.199 The Convention places an obligation
on all members to respect human rights and to secure the rights and freedoms defined
in the Convention for all within their jurisdictions.200 This obligation puts pressure on the
traditional view of sovereignty in the English legal system, the primacy of the European
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
Sweet 2003 Faculty Scholarship Series 2746.
Koopmans Courts and Political Institutions 43.
Loi constitutionnelle de modernisation des institutions de la Ve République.
Article 61: Constitutional recourse.
Preamble to the Convention.
Brownlie Basic Documents in International Law 244.
Article 1 of the Convention.
218
Convention having been confirmed in jurisprudence.201 The British Westminster system
of parliamentary supremacy was transformed by the decision to join the European
Union in 1973 and the introduction of the Human Rights Act, 1998,202 which opened the
door to judicial review in Britain.
Sweet writes that European constitutions written after World War II placed considerable
constraints on government, including restrictions on legislative and executive authority
in the form of human rights, which go far beyond the American Bill of Rights. Most
constitutions provide for constitutional review by a constitutional court, but unlike the
United States‘ Supreme Court, the European Constitutional Court is a specialised
jurisdiction, with institutions independent from the judiciary hearing constitutional
matters. Sweet states that in European constitutionalism –
(a)
state institutions are established by, and derive their authority exclusively
from, a written constitution;
(b)
such constitution assigns ultimate power to the people by way of elections;
(c)
the use of public authority, including legislative authority, is lawful only
insofar as it conforms with the tenets of the European Convention for the
Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms; and
(d)
the law will include constitutional rights and a system of constitutional
justice to defend those rights.
The American system of judicial review is diffuse. Any court, at any time, at the behest
of any litigating party, has the power to declare a law unconstitutional. 203 As such,
judicial review remains a judicial matter because it is necessary to resolve specific
cases. Sweet states that American judicial review is activated by a claim that the
enforcement of an unconstitutional law caused damages to one of the litigants. This has
201
202
203
Jowell and Oliver The Changing Constitution 92.
Para 3.4.2.2 below.
Sweet 2003 Faculty Scholarship Series 2770.
219
the effect of American courts‘ denying standing to parties that fail to show some degree
of direct interest in the review of impugned legislation.
In contrast to the American system, European constitutional review is concentrated,
being exclusively located in a specialised organ of state. European judicial review is also
more abstract and can proceed in the absence of litigation: the judge reads the
legislation against the constitutional law of the member state concerned and the
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and then
decides on its constitutionality.204
3.3.4.3
Position in South Africa
3.3.4.3.1 Introduction
Section 2 of the 1996 Constitution provides that the Constitution is the supreme law of
the Republic and that any law or conduct inconsistent with it is of no force and effect.
Section 172(2)(a) provides that the Supreme Court of Appeal, the High Court or a court
of similar status may make an order concerning the constitutional validity of an Act of
Parliament, a provincial Act or any conduct of the President, but an order of
constitutional invalidity has no force unless it is confirmed by the Constitutional Court.
Section 167(4)(e) provides that only the Constitutional Court may decide that
Parliament or the President has failed to comply with a constitutional duty.
The principle of judicial review of legislative and executive action is therefore firmly
entrenched in the South African Constitution. The review powers of the courts, although
firmly entrenched in the Constitution, often leads to tension between the courts and the
other two branches of government.
Labuschagne states that –205
[i]n South Africa, the first detectable signs of state instability have largely emanated
from a disturbance of the desired harmonious intra-relationship between the fused
executive/legislature and the judiciary, within the constitutional state.
204
205
Sweet 2003 Faculty Scholarship Series 2771.
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 2.
220
Labuschagne goes on to say that the balance of power within a state – between the
legislature, executive and judiciary (separation of powers and internal checks and
balances) – is of paramount importance to guard against the arbitrary use of power or
other factors which might disturb the balance. Currently, however, the ruling party‘s
dominance is institutionalised in a fused legislature/executive that is ―hostile‖ towards
the judiciary, which is seen as restrictive and hampering the majority will. The logical
and inevitable result of this development, if taken to the extreme, will be an overcentralised state, a degraded rule of law and, ultimately, the destabilisation of the
state.206 The tension between the judiciary and the executive branch is not new to
South Africa. An analysis of South African legal history shows that it has occurred
before.
3.3.4.3.2 Historical clashes between the judiciary and executive in South Africa
The earliest example of a clash between the executive and the judiciary occurred in
1898 when the President of the South African Republic, President Paul Kruger, clashed
with Chief Justice Kotzé.
In the last third of the 1880s, the Volksraad, the legislative body of the South African
Republic, developed a practice of legislating by means of informal resolutions
(besluiten) that were in complete disregard of the procedure laid down by the 1858
Constitution (Grondwet).207 The Court, however, upheld the validity of resolutions in
Nabal v Bok208 and in Executors of McCorkindale v Bok209. In these decisions, the
executive was vested with sovereign powers and the Constitution was seen to have the
same status as an ordinary Act of the Volksraad. The reasoning of the Court started to
change in Trustees in the Insolvent Estate of Theodore Doms v Bok.210 Kotzé CJ, for the
majority, stated that it was desirable that the Constitution be revised and a provision
inserted into it, as in the Constitution of the United States, in terms of which the High
Court was granted the power of deciding on the constitutionality of laws and
206
207
208
209
210
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 6.
Barry 2014 TSAR 817.
1883 1 SAR 60.
1884 1 SAR 202.
(1885-1888) 2 SAR TS 189.
221
resolutions, and applying to these the test of the Constitution.211 The Chief Justice found
that ―[t]he duty of the judge is merely to interpret and enforce the laws, as laid out by
the Legislator‖.212
Jorissen J, in a minority dissenting opinion, was of the opinion that the Constitution
bound the Volksraad and that informal besluiten could not constitute legislative acts. He
held that the formal procedure for legislation set out in the Constitution had to be
followed by the legislature, arguing that the Volksraad, as representatives of the
people, possessed sovereign powers by virtue of the Constitution and thus in
accordance with its provisions.213 Jorissen then asked the following questions:
What is the meaning of a constitution, if the body or power for which it is prescribed
raises itself above it?" Whatever may be the grounds on which the Volksraad possesses
the power of altering the constitution, a second question is in what way must it be
done? By the law? Or by resolution?
In Brown v Leyds,214 Kotzé CJ, having been swayed by the minority opinion in the
Theodore Doms case, stated that the question of judicial review should be explored
again.215 The Chief Justice found that the Volksraad, consisting of representatives or
delegates of the people, had been assigned the power of exercising, under certain
limitations, the legislative power and of making the laws of the country under the
Constitution.216 Therefore, although the Volksraad was designated the highest or
supreme authority –217
[w]e are not, however, justified in concluding from this that the Volksraad, as the
highest authority, is, in the sense of the absolute power, above the Constitution, but
rather, and indeed, that the portion of the sovereign power entrusted to the Volksraad
by the people shall be exercised under and in accordance with the terms of the
authority or mandate as expressed in the Constitution. Were this not so, the agent or
mandatory would have greater power than the principal, a position which cannot for a
moment be maintained.
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
Page 192.
Page 191.
Page 196-197.
(1897) 4 Off Rep 17.
Page 24.
Page 25.
Page 26-27.
222
The people, who have declared their independent existence in the Constitution, and
who possess the sovereign power in this Republic, have entrusted this power, in
various measure, to the Volksraad, the executive, and the judiciary. Each of these
bodies derives its authority from the Constitution, and must regulate itself, each within
its own sphere and scope, in accordance with the terms thereof. None of these powers
is above or independent of the Constitution. That the Volksraad is declared to be the
highest authority in the land is quite consistent with this view, for there is nothing
contradictory in the fact that the highest authority in a state must conform to the
terms of the Constitution, which created it, and is not at liberty to exceed the
prescribed limitations. What would otherwise be the use of a Constitution, if it is not to
be observed by the various departments of state, to which it has been appointed as a
guide?
The Chief Justice found that the Court had to determine and decide upon both the facts
and the law as applicable to those facts. This right and this duty belonged exclusively to
the Court. In exercising this function the Court did not by any means raise itself above
the Legislature, but remained within its province, by inquiring whether what had been
submitted to it was in reality a law.218
The Court ruled that the besluiten were invalid as to form (procedure). It was further
held that Act 4 of 1890, to the extent that it decreed to the contrary, was
unconstitutional and invalid. The effect of the Court‘s decision was dramatic. It meant
that all the besluiten on the statute book could have been declared invalid as well as
other laws passed by the Volksraad that were in conflict with the Constitution.219
Landman states that the decision of the Court did not go down well with the Volksraad
and the Volksraad empowered President Kruger to put to the judges the question, inter
alia, whether they renounced their claim to a testing right. The President was charged
with the duty of dismissing any judge who gave a negative or an insufficient answer or
no answer. The judges provided answers that were linked to legislative amendments
and were considered satisfactory, but President Kruger regarded a communication on
the subject by Kotze CJ as a renunciation of his undertaking and dismissed him, even
though the Chief Justice objected that he had been appointed for life.220 The first
attempt by the judiciary to defy the executive did not end well for the judiciary; the
218
219
220
Page 27.
Barry 2014 TSAR 817.
Landman 2000 Judge‘s Forum 44.
223
High Court subsequently became subject to a form of control, which constituted a
dangerous intrusion on its independence and created an ―uncontrolled legislature‖.221
Another infamous example of a clash between the judiciary and the executive occurred
during the 1950s in the Union of South Africa. Here the Appellate Division of the
Supreme Court clashed with the National Party government over the power of
Parliament to amend an entrenched provision in the South Africa Act (the constitution)
and the power of the Appellate Division to overturn the amendment as unconstitutional.
In the case of Harris v Minister of the Interior,222 the government attempted to remove
the coloured voters of the Cape Province from the common voter‘s role. The
government argued that Parliament could adopt any procedure it saw fit and the courts
had no power to question the validity of its acts.
The resulting order of the Appellate Division was that the Separate Representation of
Voters Act 46 of 1951 was invalid and of no legal force and effect. The ruling, authored
by Centlivres CJ and handed down on 20 March 1952, was unanimous. The government
responded that it found the ruling unacceptable, that the government refused to abide
by it, and that steps would be taken to have it overturned. The government ended the
controversy by enlarging the Senate and altered its method of election, allowing the
amendment to be successfully enacted.
Both of these cases are examples of clashes between the judiciary and the executive,
resulting in defeat for the judiciary.
3.3.4.3.3 Current position in South Africa
The negotiated constitutional settlement in South Africa during the early 1990s has
resulted in a new constitutional dispensation after years of parliamentary supremacy.
The judiciary is protected by the Constitution, which establishes the courts as guardians
of the Constitution, with the resulting duty to intervene should the Constitution be
221
222
Barry 2014 TSAR 824.
1952 (4) SA 769 (A).
224
violated.223 It did, however, give rise to the ―Madisonian dilemma‖ as described by Bork.
Labuschagne describes the South African Madisonian dilemma as follows:224
The fused legislative/executive systems, which present the subjective aspirations,
needs and desires of the people, was set up against an unelected body (judiciary) that
represented objective, universal human rights and values. This scenario set the stage
for a collision somewhere in the future, and was compounded by the prior experience
of the frustration of the majority will in South Africa by undemocratic pre-1994
governments. After the attainment of democracy, it seemed to the majority of people
that their needs and aspirations would be frustrated again, sometimes in favour of
their former oppressors.
The Madisonian dilemma is compounded in the South African constitutional state
because, while South Africa's Constitution and Bill of Rights can certainly be described
as ―truly modern‖,225 the reality is that the majority of South African individuals are not
so ―modern‖ in their political values.226 Many of the rights embraced by the Constitution
and the Bill of Rights do not reflect majoritarian sentiments; instead, they are based on
international human rights norms.227 Therefore, while the Constitution is representative
in its nature,228 which in principle espouses the majoritarian sentiment, it and Bill of
Rights are not universally embraced in South Africa. Labuschagne, after examining the
public speeches of political leaders, writes as follows:229
However, it seems that this ―outlandish‖ Constitution has little appeal for the majority
of the citizens, who visualise it as a compromise between the country‘s elites, and not
as representative of the will of the people.
As a result, some of the rights guaranteed (and particularly some of the subsequent
decisions of South African courts enforcing and defining those rights) run contrary to
public concerns and desires.230 The South African Constitutional Court therefore finds
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
Section 2 of the Constitution provides that the Constitution is the supreme law of the Republic; law
or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid, and obligations imposed by it must be fulfilled. Section
165(2) reads: ―The courts are independent and subject only to the Constitution and the law, which
they must apply impartially and without fear, favour or prejudice.‖
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 26.
Kende 2003 CHAP. L. REV 160.
Goodsell 2007 BYU J. Pub. L 111.
Van der Vyver 2000 Emory Int'l L. Rev. 788.
Currie and De Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook at 14.
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 19.
Goodsell 2007 BYU J. Pub. L. 111.
225
itself embroiled in the same political quagmire as the American Supreme Court as
described by Bork. Labuschagne sums up the position as follows:231
The political community also clearly displays strong material populist tendencies,
favouring majoritarianism that aligns strongly with the characteristics of an organic
state. This creates systemic stress within the restrictive nature of a constitutional state,
because the logical response is to attack the restrictions that hamper the realisation of
the majority will. This also explains why politicians of the ruling majority party have
started an undeclared war on the judiciary, and in effect on the constitutional state.
This political ―attack‖ on the constitutional state follows a two-prong strategy: firstly to
erode the material status of the judiciary, and secondly to use their numerical
advantage to oppose constitutional restrictions in the way of unbridled majority will.
Hulme and Pete write that South African lawyers and academics experience a deep
sense of unease at the prospect of a possible clash between the executive and the
judiciary on an issue that goes to the heart of South Africa's post-apartheid
constitutional democracy. That issue is the nature and extent of the powers of the
judiciary vis-à-vis the legislature and the executive, which concerns the doctrine of the
separation of powers.232 What is also worrying is the lack of acceptance the executive
displays regarding the doctrine of the separation of powers and the part of the judiciary
in the doctrine. Hulme and Pete state that –
[t]he present South African executive seems to be struggling with the idea that the
power conferred upon it by the electorate can be limited by an unelected judiciary
which acts in terms of a Constitution as the final source of authority. Of course, this
view is predicated upon a simple ―majoritarian‖ as opposed to a ―liberal‖ (or
―constitutional‖) concept of democracy.
Hulme and Pete further state that in situations in which there is conflict between the
branches relating to the doctrine of the separation of powers compromise on such
foundational issues are often impossible. The conflict must be resolved in favour of one
side or the other, with profound implications for the society in question. History has
shown that such conflicts have dire implications for the societies where they occurred.233
One of the earliest examples of a clash between the executive and the judiciary on the
question of the separation of powers took place in the 17th century between King
231
232
233
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 19.
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 16.
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 35.
226
James I of England and his Chief Justice, Edward Coke, which ultimately resulted in a
bloody civil war and the formation of an absolutist dictatorship.234
Hulme and Pete compare the Proclamations del Roy of 17th-century England with the
current South African position. They state that both James I and President Jacob Zuma
regard the source of their authority to be self-evident and irrefutable. James, working
from the premise of the divine right of kings, believed that he was duly anointed by
God. President Zuma, working from the premise of a simple majoritarian concept of
democracy, believes his authority to be derived directly from ―the people‖. Hulme and
Pete state that each of these claims to authority is potent in their respective contexts.
King James challenged the authority of parliament with his claim of divine sponsorship.
President Zuma235 challenges the bedrock of the Constitution with his claim of speaking
with the ―voice of the people‖.236
Former South African Chief Justice Arthur Chaskalson, in a speech at a workshop held
at the University of Cape Town, pointed out that a degree of tension between
politicians and judges was inevitable in a constitutional democracy characterised by the
rule of law with an independent judiciary tasked with the judicial review of legislative
and executive action.237 According to him, such tension is inherent in all systems that
respect the doctrine of the separation of powers. He continued:238
The executive has no doubt been frustrated by a number of high-profile cases that it
has lost before the courts, and this may be the reason for complaints by political
leaders about the judiciary. Unsuccessful litigants are inclined to blame the court rather
than themselves and politicians are no exception to this. Such attacks, coming from
senior politicians, undermine the constitutional order and pose a threat to our
democracy.
234
235
236
237
238
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 36.
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 54. Zuma is reported (direct quotes) to have said, inter alia, the
following: ―The powers conferred on the courts cannot be regarded as superior to the powers
resulting from a mandate given by the people in a popular vote. We must not get a sense that there
are those who wish to co-govern the country through the courts, when they have not won the
popular vote during elections. We also wish to reiterate our view that there is a need to distinguish
the areas of responsibility between the judiciary and the elected branches of the state, especially
with regards [sic] to policy formulation. Our view is that the executive, as elected officials, has the
sole discretion to decide policies for government.‖
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 55.
Chaskalson www.timeslive.co.za.
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ 26.
227
This statement made by the former Chief Justice is undeniably true. Tension between
the different branches of government will ebb and flow as different ideas and
personalities take up posts in government institutions, including the judiciary. The
tension will also depend on the strength of will of the actors in both the executive and
the judiciary. Both the executive and the judiciary will at times push for more autonomy
and attempt to broaden the influence of the different branches of government. What is
worrying is that the undue influence of the executive on judicial institutions may
weaken the judiciary to such an extent that judges will not have the necessary will to
implement the Constitution as it was intended. A weakened judiciary without the will to
hold the executive to account for the abuse of power will result in the redundancy of
strategic litigation. This will constitutionally limit strategic litigation against a state party.
Furthermore, the tension between the judiciary and the executive is exacerbated by the
failure of the executive, and indeed a number of other organs of state, to always
comply with constitutionally imposed positive duties. The failure of organs of state to
comply with constitutional duties often leads to the situation where the state does not
always act in the public interest. This can be readily adduced in situations where the
organ of state abuses the court process to protect politically connected individuals or
organisations from being held constitutionally accountable. Constitutional obligations
require a high standard of professional ethics from organs of state. 239 This requires that
the state litigant must be ethical in its approach to litigation. The organ of state must
be the model litigant.
The Constitution, however, contains checks and balances to restrict branches of
government in their exercise of power.
3.4 Checks and balances on the separation of powers in the South African
constitutional state
239
Section 195(1)(a) of the Constitution.
228
3.4.1 Introduction
It is universally accepted that government authority can never be exercised by a single
government body in a democratic state.240 In modern states, government authority is
distributed among various government bodies, branches and levels of government. The
doctrine of the separation of powers entails that the freedom of citizens of a state can
be ensured only if a concentration of power, which can lead to abuse, is prevented by a
division of government authority into legislative, executive and judicial authority.241
To prevent one branch from becoming supreme and to protect the minority from the
majority, and to induce the branches to cooperate, constitutional orders that employ
the doctrine of the separation of powers need a way to balance each of the branches.
This is typically accomplished through a system of ―checks and balances‖, the origin of
which, like the separation of powers itself, is specifically credited to Montesquieu.
Checks and balances allow for a system-based regulation that allows one branch to limit
another, such as the power of the United States Congress to alter the composition and
jurisdiction of the federal courts.242
3.4.2 Checks and balances: the legislature
3.4.2.1 Participatory democracy
Section 57(1)(b) of the Constitution provides that the National Assembly may make
rules and orders concerning its business, with due regard to representative and
participatory democracy, accountability, transparency and public involvement. Similar
provisions provide for public participation in respect of the National Council of Provinces
and the provincial legislatures (sections 70(1)(b) and 116(1)(b) of the Constitution).
The concept of participatory democracy was addressed in Merafong Demarcation Forum
v President of the Republic of South Africa.243 The question before the court was to
what extent the legislator should take into account the views raised by concerned
240
241
242
243
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 66.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 68.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 66.
2008 (5) SA 171 (CC).
229
citizens. In the Merafong case, the legislature used the Constitution Twelfth
Amendment Act of 2005 to change provincial boundaries, including the boundary
between the provinces of Gauteng and North West, with the result that one part of the
Merafong City Local Municipality was relocated from Gauteng to North West, which was
where the other part of the same municipality was located prior to the enactment of the
amendment.244 A public hearing on the issue was publicised and held, and the views
expressed at the meeting indicated that the overwhelming majority of people were
opposed to the relocation.245 The Portfolio Committee of the Gauteng Provincial
Legislature then adopted a ―negotiating mandate‖ to support the Constitution Twelfth
Amendment Act of 2005 ―on condition that the municipal area of Merafong was
included in the Gauteng Province‖, that is, it undertook to propose an amendment to
the Amendment Act in the National Council of Provinces (NCOP) in order to locate
Merafong in Gauteng.246 Subsequently, however, the Portfolio Committee established
that the amendment was not possible in law,247 and after deliberation changed its
position, adopting a final voting mandate providing that Gauteng would support the Bill
in the NCOP.248 The Gauteng Provincial Legislature adopted the final voting mandate
and voted in support of the Bill, which was passed. Thereafter the whole of Merafong
was incorporated into North West.
The first applicant was an organisation which, according to its founding document,
campaigned ―for democracy to prevail in Merafong‖. It consisted of members of the
community drawn from political organisations, taxi associations, a women's movement,
students, trade unions, churches, businesses and professionals, including teachers,
nurses and lawyers. Its primary purpose was ―to fight and defeat the undemocratic
move by government to transfer Merafong from Gauteng to North West‖.
The applicants applied for direct access to the Constitutional Court, seeking an order –
244
245
246
247
248
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
1 of the judgment.
31-33.
34.
36.
37.
230
(a)
declaring that the Gauteng Provincial Legislature did not comply with its
constitutional obligation to facilitate public involvement in its processes
leading up to the approval of the Constitution Twelfth Amendment Bill by
the NCOP;249 alternatively,
(b)
declaring that the Gauteng Provincial Legislature did not exercise its
legislative powers rationally when it voted in support of the relevant parts
of the Constitution Twelfth Amendment Bill.250
The applicants' argument regarding (a) was that the process of public involvement was
not meaningful because the Portfolio Committee changed its position after the
negotiating mandate and before the final voting mandate without further consultation
with the community and that this was unreasonable. Their argument regarding (b) was
based on the contentions (1) that the change of position was irrational, and (2) that the
decision to relocate Merafong lacked merit.251
The current discussion focuses on the first argument raised by the applicants only,
which related to the question of meaningful public involvement in the decisions of the
legislature. The Court found that when provincial boundaries are at stake (which is a
constitutional matter), national and regional needs and perceptions must often be
balanced against each other. Government must be open and responsive to the wishes
of communities, which may not necessarily be adequately represented in national
elections and could therefore find expression in localised resistance. However, it also
must act in the national interest, be loyal to those who voted it into office and strive to
realise the constitutional ideal of achieving the equitable distribution of resources across
the country and between provinces.
The Court stated that the requirement to facilitate public involvement is in line with the
contemplation in the Constitution of elements of participatory democracy, in addition to
representative democracy. Participatory and representative democracy must be seen as
249
250
251
The Constitution Twelfth Amendment Act of 2005 changed provincial boundaries. As this is a
provincial matter, the Bill had to be adopted by the province in terms of s 114 of the Constitution.
Para 40.
Para 41.
231
mutually supportive. According to the Court, such public involvement also enhances
responsible citizenship and legitimate government. It furthermore accords with the
constitutional principle of cooperation and communication between national and
provincial legislatures, as institutionalised in the National Council of Provinces.
The Court found that legislatures have discretion to determine how to fulfil the
obligation and that it is open to innovation. It was emphasised, however, that citizens
must have a meaningful opportunity to be heard. The applicants contended in part that
the consultations were not meaningful because the outcome was always a done deal;
they also submitted that the Portfolio Committee's change of position between the
negotiating mandate and the final voting mandate, without further consultation with the
community, was unreasonable.252 In support of the first submission, the applicants
relied on the majority judgment of Ngcobo J in Doctors for Life,253 emphasising the need
for citizens to be involved in public affairs, to identify with institutions of government,
and to become familiar with laws.254 Ngcobo J found255 that public participation
strengthens the legitimacy of legislation in the eyes of the people and that it is an
important counterweight to secret lobbying and influence-peddling.256
The applicants also relied on the concurring judgment of Sachs J in the same case, 257
which highlights the assurance that people or groups who have been the victims of
historical silencing will be listened to, and the need for people to feel that they have
been given a real opportunity to have their say and that they are taken seriously.258
252
Para 47.
253
Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others 2006 (6) SA 416 (CC).
Merafong Demarcation Forum para 44.
254
255
256
257
258
Para 44.
The particular passage reads as follows: ―If the will of the Parliamentary majority will in the end
mostly prevail in any event, and all that is required is to ‗involve‘ the public by, for example,
mechanically holding public hearings for every piece of legislation — or to make sure that hearings
are not promised as in this case — participatory democracy would appear to be quite cosmetic and
empty, in spite of any idealistic and romantic motivation for promoting it.‖
Para 45.
They relied on the following passage: ―All parties interested in legislation should feel that they have
been given a real opportunity to have their say, that they are taken seriously as citizens and their
views will receive due consideration at the moments when they could possibly influence decisions in
a meaningful fashion.‖
232
The question for a court to determine, therefore, is whether the legislature has done
what is reasonable in all the circumstances.259 In determining whether the legislature
acted reasonably, the Court will take into consideration what the legislature decided to
be the appropriate method.260 The method and degree of public participation that are
reasonable in a given case depends on a number of factors, including the nature and
importance of the legislation and the intensity of its impact on the public. The Court
found that, from the perspective of respectful dialogue and the accountability of
political representatives, it might well have been desirable to report to the people of
Merafong that it was impossible to adhere to the position taken by the Portfolio
Committee in the negotiating mandate.261 To the extent that the community was given
the impression that the Committee agreed with them and that an understandable
expectation was created that their views would prevail, 262 it was possibly disrespectful
not to return to inform them of subsequent events.263 The Court said that the question,
though, was whether the omission to consult again after the alteration of the Portfolio
Committee's negotiating mandate amounted to a failure to facilitate public involvement
in the processes of the Gauteng Provincial Legislature. The Court judged that the failure
to report to the Merafong community did not rise to the level of unreasonableness,
which would have resulted in the invalidity of the Constitution Twelfth Amendment Act
that was otherwise properly passed by Parliament.264
The process of the demarcation of Merafong was accompanied by protests, including
disruption of schools, petrol-bombing the homes of ANC councillors, blocking roads and
destruction of municipal property. Residents also boycotted the 2006 municipal
elections, which saw only 130 people casting votes in that voting district. 265 The
municipality was part of the North West Province from 2005 to 2009, when it was
reincorporated into the Gauteng Province by another amendment to the Constitution,
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
Para 57.
Para 114.
Para 115.
Para 52.
Para 55.
Para 55.
Mail & Guardian ANC meets forum over Merafong demarcation 25 Jun 2008.
233
following the often violent protests in the area.266 Ultimately, therefore, the residents
were successful in their efforts to keep the Merafong district part of the Gauteng
Province, not through following the legitimate legal channels by approaching the courts,
but through violent protest. Merafong serves as an example of public mass mobilisation
influencing state action when officials refuse to acknowledge the public will and
strategic litigation fails.
3.4.2.2
General elections
Section 1(d) of the Constitution provides that regular elections under a system of
universal adult suffrage be held. The Constitution further provides that the National
Assembly is elected to represent the people and to ensure government by the people
under the Constitution.267
The legislature is ultimately accountable to the voters, who can use the power of their
vote to show their displeasure with the legislature. In most democracies, the legislature
will always judge the public mood and desire, lest they be voted out in the next general
elections. This serves as the main check on the power of the legislature and its exercise
of power.
3.4.3 Checks and balances: the executive
3.4.3.1
Public control
Public control over the executive branch of government is exercised by a variety of
means. Rautenbach and Malherbe state that an important form of control over the
executive is exercised through the press, public conferences, debates and a large
variety of interest groups in the community, such as consumer groups, churches and
cultural institutions.268 This involvement of citizens in public life between elections leads
266
267
268
The Local Government Handbook http://www.localgovernment.co.za/locals/view/63/merafong-citylocal-municipality accessed December 2015.
Section 42(3) of the Constitution.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 209.
234
to the opening of social and political spaces for ordinary people to participate in
decision-making processes and their own development.269
The Constitution does not provide for direct public participation in the decision-making
process of the executive branch of government; public control therefore is effected
indirectly. The Constitution provides the necessary tools for civil-society engagement
with the executive. The so-called ―expressive‖ rights contained in sections 15 to 19 of
the Constitution are important in this respect. Section 15 provides that everyone has
the right to freedom of conscience, religion, thought, belief and opinion. Section 16
provides that everyone has the right to freedom of expression, including freedom of the
press and other media and the freedom to receive or impart information or ideas, while
section 17 provides that everyone has the right to assemble, to demonstrate, to picket
and to present petitions. Section 18 provides that everyone has the right to freedom of
association, and in terms of section 19 everyone is free to make political choices,
including the right to form, to participate in the activities of, or to campaign for, political
parties. Section 19 also guarantees every citizen the right to free and fair elections in
which they have the right to vote for a political party of their choice or to stand for
election. These constitutionally guaranteed rights offer avenues for individuals,
organisations and minorities to make their opinions heard.
In South Africa, a variety of civil-society groups attempts to influence the executive to
some extent. The most active civil organisations are unions and political organisations,
which exercise far-reaching lobbying powers over the executive. These civil-society
groups use a variety of strategies to influence government policy and to advance the
rights of their members. Thus organisations and their members play a watchdog role
over state actions, state spending and legislation. These organisations also lobby and
make demands on the state for various public goods.270
Ranchod posits that, in part, the watchdog role of such organisations is a way of forcing
the government to remain accountable to citizens in general and their own membership
269
270
African Human Security Review: African Commitments to civil society engagement: A review of eight
Nepad countries http://www.africanreview.org/docs/papers/civsoc.pdf accessed August 2015.
Ranchod 2007 Policy: Issues & Actors 3.
235
in particular. This civil-society engagement with the state can be viewed as part of
political pluralism;271 this implies tolerance and accommodation of diverse views,
passions, interests and demands in the public sphere. According to Ranchod, the
engagements by civil society with the state between elections is a form of public
political participation, which ranges from mobilisation of public opinion to action on the
streets and includes both non-confrontational and confrontational methods of
engagement. Methods include litigation, petitions, media campaigns, mass marches,
strikes and civil disobedience. As part of this political participation, organisations and
individuals often disregard or distrust the political process and approach the courts to
advance their own interest and to protect their own rights.272 Schokman states that the
organisation or individual takes on the legal case as part of a strategy to achieve
broader systemic change. The case may bring about change either through the success
of the action and its impact on law, policy or practice, or by publicly exposing injustice,
raising awareness and generating broader change.273
Around the world, litigation or judicial review has become immensely popular as a
treatment for the pains of modern governance.274 South Africa is no exception to this
phenomenon.275 This activism by litigation consists of efforts to promote, impede, or
direct social, political, economic or environmental change, or stasis.276 However, for
litigational activism to be effective it requires the organ of state to abide by
constitutional obligations compelling it to assist the courts by placing all relevant
material in its possession before the courts when engaging in litigation. It further
271
272
273
274
275
276
The view that in liberal democracies power is (or should be) dispersed among a variety of economic
and ideological pressure groups and is not (or should not be) held by a single elite or group of elites.
Pluralism assumes that diversity is beneficial to society and that autonomy should be enjoyed by
disparate functional or cultural groups within a society, including religious groups, trade unions,
professional organizations, and ethnic minorities. www.britannica.com/EBchecked/.../pluralism
Ranchod 2007 Policy: Issues & Actors 3.
Schokman 2012 Advocates for International Development 3.
Hertogh and Halliday Judicial review and bureaucratic impact in future research 15.
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 104.
Schokman 2012 Advocates for International Development 3.
236
requires the state litigant to behave ethically when litigating and to respect and comply
with the court‘s decision. The state litigant must be the model litigant.277
3.4.3.2 Parliamentary control over the executive
In South Africa, the executive president is elected by the National Assembly. While this
violates the strict doctrine of the separation of powers, it has the advantage of ensuring
that the executive does not get too powerful and is ultimately answerable to
Parliament. The National Assembly, as the elected representatives of the voters, is
mandated to control the actions of the executive on behalf of the electorate. 278 The
National Assembly must also provide for mechanisms to ensure that all executive
organs of state in the national sphere of government are accountable to it and to
maintain oversight of the exercise of national executive authority, including the
implementation of legislation.279
The National Assembly exercises constitutionally mandated control over the executive in
the following ways:280
(a)
Question time in the houses of Parliament, during which time members
may ask questions of ministers on any aspect of the exercise of their
powers and functions.
(b)
Interpellations, which are used to obtain explanations from ministers with
regard to their actions.
(c)
Parliamentary committees that investigate and report on activities of the
executive.
277
278
279
280
The model litigant obligation that is placed on the state litigant is discussed in the final chapter of
this work.
In terms of s 42(3) of the Constitution the National Assembly is elected to represent the people and
to ensure government by the people under the Constitution. It does this by choosing the President,
by providing a national forum for public consideration of issues, by passing legislation and by
scrutinizing and overseeing executive actions.
Section 55(2) of the Constitution.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 210.
237
(d)
The tabling of subordinate legislation and of reports by the executive in
order to keep Parliament informed.
(e)
Approval of the budget, which in general comprise an evaluation of the
actions by the executive and individual ministers.
(f)
Consideration of the reports by the Auditor-General on the accounts,
financial statements and financial management of executive organs.281
The Public Protector, has the power to investigate any conduct in state affairs, or in the
public administration in any sphere of government, that is alleged or suspected to be
improper or to result in any impropriety or prejudice.282
Parliamentary control over the executive is however stymied by the heavy influence the
executive exerts over the parliamentary committees, which act rather as a rubber
stamp of approval for executive actions and decisions.283 Choudhry states that the
dominant status of the ruling ANC has undermined those procedures and mechanisms
that should operate through political means to check its power. An early casualty of the
ANC‘s dominance was legislative oversight of the executive in Parliament, stymied by
the ANC‘s strict enforcement of party discipline against its own members. Therefore,
although legislative authority formally vests in Parliament, its role has been reduced to
approving bills drafted by the executive.284 Giliomee writes:285
Ostensible authority resides in the Constitution, Parliament and the Cabinet, but real
authority resides in the party (ANC). Real decision-making occurs outside of formal
constitutional structures such as Parliament and is instead conducted behind the closed
doors of party forums.
According to documents of the ruling party, transformation of the state entails,
primarily –286
281
282
283
284
285
286
Section 188 of the Constitution.
Section 182 of the Constitution.
Devenish 2003 THRHR 89.
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 11.
Giliomee, Myburgh and Schlemmer 2001 Democratization 44-45.
The State, Property Relations and Social Transformation, Umrabulo No.5, 3rd Quarter 1998.
238
[e]xtending the power of the National Liberation Movement (NLM) over all levers of
power: the army, the police, the bureaucracy, intelligence structures, the judiciary,
parastatals, and agencies such as regulatory bodies, the public broadcaster, the central
bank and so on.
Choudhry raises the question whether there are effective external checks that operate
outside the constitutional system on the ANC that can serve as functional substitutes for
the internal institutional checks provided by the formal institutions for parliamentary
democracy that the ANC‘s dominance has eroded.287 It is suggested that strategic
litigation, through judicial control over the executive, provides for such an ―external
check‖ by keeping executive power contained within the parameters set by the
Constitution.
In National Director of Public Prosecution v Zuma,288 the Court had no difficulty in
defining and restricting executive power in relation to the National Director of Public
Prosecutions (hereafter the NDPP). The Court held that the Minister may not instruct
the NDPP to prosecute or to decline to prosecute or to terminate a pending
prosecution.289 The Court found that ministerial responsibility entails only that the
Minister is entitled to be kept informed in respect of all prosecutions initiated or to be
initiated which may arouse public interest or involve important aspects of legal or
prosecutorial authority.290
The judgment severely curtails the power of the executive and protects the
independence of the prosecution authority. Section 179 of the Constitution does not
clearly define the position of the Minister vis-à-vis the prosecution authority, so the real
basis of the judgment can be found in the proposition that ―any prosecution authority
ought to be free from executive or political control‖.291 The same proposition can be
made for all independent public institutions, including the JSC and Magistrates
Commission,
which
would
allow
the
courts
overconcentration of powers in such institutions.
287
288
289
290
291
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 12.
2009 2 SA 277 SCA.
Para 28.
Para 30.
Choudbry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 56.
239
to
test
whether
there
is
an
3.4.3.3 Judicial control over the executive
Although the Constitution does not provide for direct public participation in executive
decision-making, section 33 of the Constitution requires administrators to act lawfully,
reasonably and procedurally fair and to be able to give reason for their actions. The
Constitution further guarantees the right to have any dispute that can be resolved by
the application of law decided in a court or, where appropriate, another independent
tribunal.292
The principle of legality, as enshrined in section 33, goes beyond administrative
decisions. It is a broad constitutional principle that governs the use of all public power
rather than the narrower realm of administrative power.293 The principle of legality is an
aspect of the rule of law, a founding value of the Constitution.294
The fundamental idea the principle of legality expresses is that the exercise of all public
power is only legitimate when lawful.295 In the Fedsure Life Assurance case,296 the Court
found that when a legislature, whether national, provincial or local, exercises the power
to raise taxes or rates, or determines appropriations to be made out of public funds, it
is exercising a power that under our Constitution is a power peculiar to elected
legislative bodies. This power is exercised by democratically elected representatives
after due deliberation. The Court clearly stated that in this instance the power exercised
by the legislature did not constitute an administrative decision.297 The Court found that
the question that had to be considered was the extent of the constitutional controls on
the exercise of the powers of local government legislatures. The Court held that a local
government might only act within the powers lawfully conferred upon it and found –298
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
Section 34 of the Constitution.
Adelman 1994 Journal of Law and Society 317.
Section 1(c) of the Constitution.
Fedsure Life Assurance v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council 1999 (1) SA 374.
Fedsure Life Assurance v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council 1999 (1) SA 374.
Para 45.
Paras 55-56.
240
[t]here is nothing startling in this proposition – it is a fundamental principle of the rule
of law,299 recognised widely, that the exercise of public power is only legitimate where
lawful. The rule of law – to the extent at least that it expresses this principle of legality
– is generally understood to be a fundamental principle of constitutional law.
According to the Court, it was central to the conception of our constitutional order that
the legislature and executive in every sphere were constrained by the principle that
they may exercise no power and perform no function beyond that conferred upon them
by law.300
In Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa,301 the Court had to deal
with the issue of the role of the courts in controlling public power. It raised the question
whether a court has the power to review and set aside a decision by the President to
bring an Act of Parliament into force.302 The matter arose when the Transvaal High
Court was requested to review and set aside the President‘s decision to put the South
African Medicines and Medical Devices Regulatory Authority Act, 1998, into operation.
The Court held that the exercise of all public power must comply with the Constitution,
which is the supreme law, and the doctrine of legality, which is part of that law. 303 The
Court further held that ultimately all public power, whether exercised by the legislative,
executive or judiciary, is controlled by the Constitution.304
The Court noted the ―reluctance‖ of courts in other countries to review decisions of this
nature because of the political nature of the judgment required and its closeness to
legislative powers.305 The Court held that the power was not ―administrative action‖ as
contemplated in the administrative justice provision in the Bill of Rights, and therefore
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
The Court referred to Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution 193, in which
Dicey refers to this aspect of the rule of law as follows: ―We mean in the second place, when we
speak of the ‗rule of law‘ as a characteristic of our country, not only that with us no man is above
the law, but (what is a different thing) that here every man, whatever be his rank or condition, is
subject to the ordinary law of the realm and amenable to the jurisdiction of the ordinary tribunals.‖
Para 58.
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA in Re: The Ex Parte Application of the President of
the Republic of South Africa 2000 (2) SA 674.
Para
Para
Para
Para
1.
19.
20.
70.
241
did not fall within the controls of public power set out in that provision.306 Rather, it was
a power of a special nature, the character of which is neither legislative nor
administrative, although it is more closely linked to the legislative than the
administrative function. However, the exercise of such a power is not beyond the reach
of judicial review, because the exercise of all power must conform with the Constitution,
and, in particular, the requirements of the rule of law: a foundational principle in the
Constitution.307
The Court held that this includes the requirement that a decision, viewed objectively,
must be rationally related to the purpose for which the power was given.308 Therefore,
even if the President acts in good faith, his decision may be invalid if it does not meet
this objective requirement.309 This does not mean that a court can interfere with a
decision simply because it disagrees with it or considers that the power was exercised
inappropriately. The Court may find, however, that the decision taken by the President
was objectively irrational and therefore unlawful.
In Democratic Alliance v President of the Republic of South Africa,310 the question was
asked whether the appointment of the Director of Public Prosecutions by the President
was lawful. The matter was first heard by the High Court, which found that, while the
appointment of Mr Simelane as the National Director raised some concerns, it could not
be said that the conduct of the President fell afoul of the Constitution.311 The Supreme
Court of Appeal reversed the High Court‘s decision, finding that the appointment was
inconsistent with the Constitution and invalid. The matter was then referred to the
Constitutional Court in terms of section 172(2)(a) for confirmation. The Court found
that it was common cause that the decision of the President was an executive decision
306
307
308
309
310
311
Para 45.
Para 79.
Para 85.
Para 90.
2013 (1) SA 248 (CC).
Democratic Alliance v President of the Republic of South Africa (263/11) 2011 ZASCA 241.
242
and that the decision had to be rational.312 The issues before the Court were defined as
follows:
(a)
The question whether the requirement that the National Director must be a
fit and proper person to be appointed to that position is an objective
jurisdictional fact antecedent to appointment.
(b)
The requirements of rationality concerned in particular with –
(i)
the distinction between reasonableness and rationality and the
relationship between means and ends;
(ii)
whether the process as well as the ultimate decision must be
rational;
(c)
(iii)
the consequences for rationality if relevant factors are ignored; and
(iv)
rationality and the separation of powers.
An investigation into whether the decision of the President to appoint Mr
Simelane was rational and, in particular, whether the President‘s failure to
take into account the finding in relation to and evidence of Mr Simelane in
the Ginwala Commission was rationally related to the purpose for which the
power to appoint a National Director was conferred.
(d)
If the decision is found to be rational in this sense then the Court must
evaluate whether –
(i)
the evidence shows that Mr Simelane is a fit and proper person to be
appointed the National Director; and
(ii)
the President had an ulterior purpose in making the appointment.
In their argument, the executive placed considerable emphasis on the fact that the role
of the prosecuting authority was policy-driven and that the National Director was what
312
Para 12.
243
was referred to in argument as ―a political appointee‖. The Court stated that while it is
true that the National Director is appointed by the President, it does not follow that this
renders the incumbent of that office ―a political appointee‖.313 The Court approvingly
quoted the following:314
The most important change brought about by section 179 … is that a single national
prosecuting post was created. Previously there was a direct link between the Minister
of Justice and the various attorneys-general, whose activities such Minister coordinated
and to whom they reported. What section 179 did was to slot the NDPP in between the
political head of the Department of Justice and the officers at the head of the
provincial prosecutorial divisions. The effect of the change was to gather the strands of
the country‘s prosecutorial services in the hands of one non-political chief executive
officer directly appointed by the President.
In terms of the qualification of the appointee, the Court held that the Constitution does
not leave the determination of appropriate qualification to the President. It obliges the
legislature to ensure that the National Director is appropriately qualified.315 On the
premise of whether the appointee was a ―fit and proper person‖, the Court ruled that
the Act316 itself does not say that the candidate for appointment as National Director
should be fit and proper ―in the President‘s view‖. The legislature could easily have
done so if the purpose was to leave it in the complete discretion of the President.
Crucially, the section is couched in imperative terms. The appointee ―must‖ be a fit and
proper person.317
The Court argued as follows on the question as to whether the President exercises a
value judgment in the appointment process:318
It is correct that the determination whether a candidate does fulfil the fit and proper
requirement stipulated by the Act involves a value judgment. But it does not follow
from this that the decision and evaluation lies within the sole and subjective preserve
of the President. Value judgments are involved in virtually every decision any member
of the executive might make where objective requirements are stipulated. It is true
that there may be differences of opinion in relation to whether or not objective criteria
313
Para 16.
314
Minister of Defence v Potsane and Another; Legal Soldier (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Defence 2002 (1) SA
315
1 (CC).
Para 21.
316
National Prosecuting Authority Act 32 of 1998.
317
Para 22.
Para 23.
318
244
have been established or are present. This does not mean that the decision becomes
one of subjective determination, immune from objective scrutiny.
The courts have shown that executive and legislative actions will be evaluated in terms
of the Constitution and, if such are found wanting, the courts will not hesitate to
declare such actions unlawful. The danger of executive influence on the judiciary as
highlighted above remains, and the overconcentration of executive power in judicial
institutions can negatively affect the independence of these institutions, which runs
contrary to the doctrine of the separation of powers. The lack of independence of the
judiciary, perceived or otherwise, might limit the effectiveness of strategic litigation.
However, although the judiciary is centrally placed as a check on the abuse of power by
Parliament and the executive, the question remains whether there are any checks and
balances on the power of the judiciary. Quis custodiet ipsos custodes?319
3.4.4 Checks and balances: the judiciary
In most democratic countries, judicial control is the most effective way to ensure that
the legislative and executive branches comply with the law.320 This raises the question
of whether there is any control by the other branches of government over the judiciary.
A problem exists in reconciling any control over the judiciary with the principle of
judicial independence.321 The Constitution vests the judicial authority of the Republic in
the courts and the independence of the courts is guaranteed and subject only to the
Constitution and the law, which they must apply impartially and without fear, favour or
prejudice.322
The following are examples of control over the judiciary:
(a)
Few modern constitutions provide for the direct election of judges and
magistrates. They are usually appointed, subject to safeguards to ensure
319
320
321
322
Juvenal Satires VI lines 347–348: "Who will guard the guards themselves?"
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 234.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 235.
Section 165(2) of the Constitution.
245
their independence, by the executive or the legislative branch, or by both
branches.323
(b)
For the sake of an independent judiciary, the right of freedom of expression
and the right of the media to report on the judiciary are curtailed by the
offence of contempt of court,324 but this does not exclude all criticism of the
court.325 Analysis and academic criticism of court judgments is a form of
public control over the judiciary.
(c)
The system of appeal and review of the decisions of lower courts by higher
courts amounts to an extensive form of judicial control.326
(d)
International Law and institutions such as the African Court on Human and
Peoples‘ Rights and the United Nations Human Rights Council can be
approached to enforce international human rights law. This can apply as a
form of oversight of the Constitutional Court, whose decisions, as apex
court in South Africa, cannot be appealed.
Judicial officers are not immune to civil actions, which may result from their decisions.
Immunity will only apply if the officer acted bona fide. If the officer acted mala fide, he
or she will be held liable.327
A judge may be removed from office if the JSC finds that the judge suffers from
incapacity, is crossly incompetent or is guilty of gross misconduct, and the National
Assembly, by a resolution adopted by at least a two-third majority of its members, calls
for the judge to be removed.328
323
324
325
326
327
328
Sections 174, 175 and 178 of the Constitution.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 235.
S v Van Niekerk 1972 3 SA 706 (A) 720-721.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 235.
Rautenbach and Malherbe Constitutional Law 235.
Section 177 of the Constitution.
246
A judge who is the subject of investigation by the JSC may be suspended by the
President on the advice of the JSC.329
Although there is some oversight over the judiciary by other branches of government,
any further attempts at oversight will negatively influence the independence of the
judiciary. The independence of the judiciary as the ―weakest‖ of the branches of
government is of paramount importance. This means that the judiciary should approach
the question of judicial review cautiously with due regard to the doctrine of the
separation of powers and the independence of the legislative and the executive
branches.
3.5 Judicial review and strategic litigation
3.5.1 Introduction
In Glenister v President of the RSA,330 the Court found the following:
In our constitutional democracy, the courts are the ultimate guardians of the
Constitution. They not only have the right to intervene in order to prevent the violation
of the Constitution, they also have the duty to do so. It is in the performance of this
role that courts are more likely to confront the question of whether to venture into the
domain of other branches of government and the extent of such intervention. … But
even in these circumstances, courts must observe the limits of their power.
When this statement is analysed it becomes clear that it raises a number of issues.
Firstly, courts have the right and duty to intervene to prevent the violation of the
Constitution. This forms the bedrock on which strategic litigation is brought before the
courts. Secondly, courts will not automatically venture into the domain of other
branches of government; some qualification is needed before a court will take that step.
Thirdly, after a court has made the decision to intervene, the scope of such intervention
will have to be determined. The second and third issues will for the most part depend
on the standard of judicial review that the courts subscribe to. The South African courts
subscribe to a standard of judicial review based on deference to the other branches of
329
330
Section 177(3) of the Constitution.
2009 1 SA 287 CC par 33.
247
government.331 The standard for judicial review is of critical importance in strategic
litigation. It is imperative for litigants and activists to know when the court will
intervene in the sphere of other state institutions and when the court will defer to such
institutions. Lastly, the courts would constantly have to observe the limits of their
power. The courts will not make a ruling if the ruling cannot be complied with or
implemented.332
Strategic
litigation
should
therefore
focus
on
attainable
and
implementable orders that fall within the powers of the court. The standard for judicial
review is of critical importance when contemplating strategic litigation against the
executive or legislature. Bias or perceived bias by the courts in favouring the executive
or legislature may intimidate individuals or organisations from pursuing litigation to right
wrongs and expose corruption.
3.5.2 Determination of the ―proper standard‖ for judicial review
O‘Regan argues that an important aspect of the South African doctrine of the
separation of powers is that the separation between judicial, legislative and executive
contains a structural and functional distinction between the arms of government which,
in order to preserve their institutional integrity and their democratic function, needs to
be preserved from intrusion.333 It is however not only the judiciary that must be
protected from intrusion by the other branches of government. The doctrine of the
separation of power (and therefore the principle of good governance) will be breached
when the judiciary unconstitutionally interferes in the area of responsibility of the other
branches of government.
Mureinik wrote: ―The principles of judicial review represent the core of the judicial
conception of justice.‖334 Dyzenhaus lists the following principles, which were articulated
by Mureinik and are considered fundamental for judicial review:335
331
332
333
334
335
Para 5.2 below.
Chapter 5.
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ 131.
Mureinik 1994 SALJ 617.
Dyzenhaus 1998 SAJHR 18.
248
(a)
The principle that policy should be implemented in a reasonable or nondiscriminatory fashion.
(b)
The principle that someone whose rights will be affected by an official
decision has a right to be heard before that decision is made.
(c)
The principle that, when a statute says an official should have reason to
believe that x is the case before he or she acts, the court should require
that the reasons produced are sufficient to justify that belief.
(d)
The principle that no executive decision can encroach on a fundamental
right
unless
the
empowering
statute
specifically
authorises
that
encroachment.
(e)
The principle that regulations made under discretionary powers (for
example, the power to make regulations declaring and dealing with a state
of emergency) must be capable of being defended in a court of law by a
demonstration that there are genuine circumstances of the kind which
justifies invoking the power and that the powers actually invoked are
demonstrably related to the purpose of the empowering statute.
If the above-mentioned principles are analysed, it becomes clear that Dyzenhaus
argues for a policy of non-discrimination, openness, justification, accountability and
participation. A person whose rights are affected must be given an opportunity to be
heard, reasons must be given for decisions and the decisions must be based on and
related to an empowering statute.
Dyzenhaus proposes three separate approaches to the problem of the judicial role in
reviewing decisions of the administration:336
(a)
Law as authority: the law reflects the preferences of the majority of society
as developed through the medium of a democratically elected legislature.
336
Dyzenhaus 1998 SAJHR 11.
249
(b)
Law as a culture of neutrality, which seeks to protect a range of individual
rights from interference by the state. Statutes that infringe on the
individual‘s right to decide how to live, for example, are illegitimate; they
offend against public reason, the custodians of which are the judges.337
(c)
Law as a culture of justification, which seeks to promote the idea that
parties are entitled to participate in decisions which affect them, that is,
decisions which determine their rights, and further, that the decisions of
organs of state must be justified by the decision-maker within the public
discourse fashioned by the Constitution, thereby rendering the decisionmaker accountable to the public he serves.
The third approach proposed by Dyzenhaus corresponds with the fundamental
principles articulated by Mureinik. Law as a culture of justification also resonates with
the constitutional values of accountability, participation, justification and openness.
In Speaker of the National Assembly v De Lille,338 the Court noted that the constitutional
order requires courts to intervene to protect rights and that, accordingly, the principle
of non-interference with the affairs of another branch of government, an important
aspect of the doctrine of the separation of powers, must give way to the need to
provide protection for individual rights which lie at the heart of our democratic order.
O‘Regan states that it is clear from the court‘s jurisprudence that the principle of nonintrusion, although not unqualified, is an important aspect of our doctrine of the
separation of powers.339
In Premier of Mpumalanga v Executive Committee of State-aided Schools, Eastern
Transvaal,340 the Court held that –341
[i]n determining what constitutes procedural fairness in a given case, a court should be
slow to impose obligations upon government which will inhibit its ability to make and
337
338
339
340
341
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 29.
(297/98) [1999] ZASCA 50; [1999] 4 All SA 241 (A).
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ 132.
1999 (2) BCLR 151 (CC); 1999 (2) SA 91 (CC).
Para 41.
250
implement policy effectively (a principle well recognised in the common law and that of
other countries). As a young democracy facing immense challenges of transformation,
we cannot deny the importance of the need to ensure the ability of the executive to
act efficiently and promptly.
The Court thus recognised the importance of allowing the executive to carry out its
functions without undue hindrance. The Court reasoned as follows:342
In treating the decisions of administrative agencies with the appropriate respect, a
court is recognising the proper role of the executive within the Constitution. In doing
so a court should be careful not to attribute to itself superior wisdom in relation to
matters entrusted to other branches of government. A court should thus give due
weight to findings of fact and policy decisions made by those with special expertise and
experience in the field. The extent to which a court should give weight to these
considerations will depend upon the character of the decision itself, as well as on the
identity of the decision-maker. A decision that requires an equilibrium to be struck
between a range of competing interests or considerations and which is to be taken by
a person or institution with specific expertise in that area must be shown respect by
the courts. … This does not mean however that where the decision is one which a will
not reasonably result in the achievement of the goal, or which is not reasonably
supported on the facts or not reasonable in the light of the reasons given for it, a court
may not review that decision. A court should not rubber-stamp an unreasonable
decision simply because of the complexity of the decision or the identity of the
decision-maker.
The Court thus subscribes to a vision of the doctrine of the separation of powers which
recognises the need to protect the institutional character of each of the three branches
of government in a manner that will prevent their ability to discharge their
constitutional role being undermined.343 O‘Regan frames this vision as follows:344
The role of the courts under our Constitution is to protect the Constitution, and in
particular individual fundamental rights. At times, in asserting this function, courts will
have to intrude to some extent on the terrain of the legislature and the executive. In
doing so, however, it is clear from the jurisprudence that is emerging that courts must
remain sensible to the legitimate constitutional interests of the other arms of
government and seek to ensure that the manner of their intrusion, while protecting
fundamental rights, intrudes as little as possible in the terrain of the executive and
legislature.
O‘Regan stated that the courts, when they intrude into the domain of other branches,
should be circumspect and intrude as little as possible. The key question, then,
concerns the function of the judge in mediating between the law and legislative and
342
343
344
Bato Star Fishing para 48.
South African Association of Personal Injury Lawyers v Heath 2001 (1) SA 883 (CC).
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ 132.
251
executive politics.345 In other words, what should be the proper standard of judicial
review that the courts subscribe to?
3.5.3 The direction of the Constitutional Court
The principle of judicial review is well established in the South African constitutional
state. The Constitution clearly mandates the courts to review legislation or conduct that
is inconsistent with constitutional provisions.346
Hoexter, in seeking to develop an appropriate response to judicial review in a
constitutional dispensation, contends that the judiciary must display –347
[a] willingness to appreciate the legitimate and constitutionally-ordained province of
administrative agencies; to admit the expertise of those agencies in policy-laden or
polycentric issues; to accord their interpretations of fact and law due respect and to be
sensitive in general to the interests legitimately pursued by administrative bodies and
the practical and financial constraints under which they operate.
Hoexter contends that these considerations permit the adoption of a concept of
deference which is consistent with the concern for individual rights and a refusal to
tolerate corruption and maladministration. She states that because of the wide powers
conferred on the courts to review executive and legislative actions, it is essential that
courts justify their intervention or non-intervention. It is also important that this be
done candidly and consciously rather than in a formalistic or coded style.348 The culture
of deference has been increasingly employed by South African courts.349
Given the fusion between the executive and the legislature in South Africa, and the
overconcentration of executive power in the legislature and judicial institutions, the
concept of deference in judicial review falls short of finding the correct balance between
345
346
347
348
349
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ 132.
Section 2 of the Constitution which reads: ―The Constitution is the supreme law of the Republic; law
or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid, and the obligations imposed by it must be fulfilled.‖
Hoexter 2000 SALJ 501.
Hoexter Administrative Law in South Africa 138.
Logbro Properties CC v Bedderson 2003 (2) SA 460 (SCA) paras 20–21; Minister of Environmental
Affairs and Tourism v Phambili Fisheries (Pty) Ltd 2003 (6) SA 407 (SCA).
252
the constitutional values of participation, openness, justification and accountability, and
the doctrine of the separation of powers. Pieterse argues:350
Given the executive‘s stranglehold over the legislature, citizens increasingly look to the
judiciary to ensure accountability and for the protection of their basic interest. Today,
the judiciary acts both as watchdog over the other branches‘ adherence to the doctrine
of separation of powers and as primary protector of citizens‘ rights within its confines.
In South Africa, as elsewhere, this reality has been underscored by the introduction of
a justiciable Bill of Rights, which ―fundamentally changed the place of the judiciary in
South Africa‘s constitutional and political order‖.
Although there should be a culture of mutual co-operation and respect between the
different branches of government,351 the courts are mandated by constitutional
provisions to ensure that the executive and legislature operate within the boundaries of
the Constitution. Davis writes that the concept of deference is employed by the courts
to promote certain basic principles, namely:352
(a)
South Africa is committed to transformation and to meeting the needs of
the poor, hence government and its administrations are of critical
importance;
(b)
often, the substance of decisions made by government agencies is not
appropriate to judicial decision-making, particularly because of the polycentricity of task and consequence; and
(c)
the government official/agency is an expert or at least more of an expert
than the court deciding the issue in question.
When the principles promoted by the Court‘s reliance on the notion of deference are
analysed, there is no provision for the realisation of the values and objectives enshrined
in the Constitution. Furthermore, the notion of deference falls short of holding the state
litigant constitutionally accountable for the high standard of professional ethical
350
351
352
Pieterse 2004 SAJHR 383.
Chapter 3 of the Constitution.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 26.
253
behaviour required from it.353 It brings the state litigant no closer to the model litigant
that the Constitution requires it to be.
The principles listed by Davis were clearly illustrated by the finding of the Court in Bato
Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Environmental Affairs.354 The question was raised of
the extent to which an executive decision is susceptible to review under the
constitutional order. The Court employed the following test to determine whether the
decision was reviewable:355
If we are satisfied that the Chief Director did take into account all the factors, struck a
reasonable equilibrium between them and selected reasonable means to pursue the
identified legislative goal in the light of the facts before him, the applicant cannot
succeed. The task of allocation of fishing quotas is a difficult one, intimately connected
with complex policy decisions and requires on-going supervision and management of
that process by the departmental decision-makers who are experts in the field.
Ngcobo J formulated a different approach by way of the constitutional framework within
which all decisions of state organs need to be assessed. He commenced his judgment
by referring to the transformative objectives of the Marine Living Resources Act.356 He
then emphasised that a foundational principle of the Act is the transformation of the
fishing industry. Ngcobo J concluded that, if the Minister were to fail to heed the
transformative considerations enshrined in the Act, ―he would be acting unlawfully and
his decision would be open to attack‖.357 The duty of the courts, however, does not
extend to telling the functionaries how to implement transformation. That must be left
to the functionaries concerned.358 Therefore, although Ngobo J sets a standard to which
the executive must aspire – the attainment of the transformation of the fishing industry
– the Court deferred to the executive on how to achieve this goal. It is submitted that
this culture of deference fails to satisfy the foundational values of the Constitution.
353
354
355
356
357
358
Section 195 of the Constitution.
2004 (4) SA 490 (CC) para 48.
18 of 1998, para 50.
Para 69.
Para 85.
Para 104.
254
O‘Regan J, in ascribing to the deference of the courts to other branches of government,
stated as follows:359
In treating the decisions of administrative agencies with the appropriate respect, a
court is recognising the proper role of the executive within the Constitution. In doing
so, a court should be careful not to attribute to itself superior wisdom in relation to
matters entrusted to other branches of government.
Davis criticises this dictum:360
This dictum appears to be more concerned with judicial restraint than with the
construction of a coherent concept of deference that might serve as a guide to a court,
which seeks to mediate between law and the implementation of legislative and
executive politics.
He continues by citing from paragraph 48 of the Bato Star Fishing case, where the court
argues as follows:
This does not mean however that where the decision is one which will not reasonably
result in the achievement of the goal, or which is not supported on the facts or not
reasonable in the light of the reasons given for it, a court may not review that decision.
A court should not rubber-stamp an unreasonable decision simply because of the
complexity of the decision or the identity of the decision-maker.
According to Davis, this illustrates an ―absence of a coherent theory of review in a
constitutional context‖.361 While O‘Regan J‘s judgment turns on the deference owed to
the expertise of the department charged with the decision to allocate fishing quotas,
Ngcobo J bowed to transformational prominence and the fact that ―functionaries should
be given the scope to implement these objectives‖.
Davis is rightly critical of both judgments and states that it is bizarre that the full bench
concurred with both judgments:362
One judgment is, at best, committed to respect for the principle of separation of
powers. The other judgment appears to nudge the legal community to accept that an
interrogation of constitutional values rather than a conflation of a contested concept of
institutional competence with the principle of separation of powers must be the key
guideline for review of administrative decisions. But, as it is about to take the
conclusive step, it falters into line with the judgment of O‘Regan J. The coherent
359
360
361
362
Para 48.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 26
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 26.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 28.
255
theory of review in the constitutional era appears as much an illusion as the
respondent department‘s commitment to transformation!
Davis proposes a culture of justification for judicial review that takes into account the
democratic prerogative of the elected branches of government to fashion and
implement public policy within the framework of the Constitution. This culture accepts
that the role of judicial review is to foster a culture of democracy, and that the judiciary
must commence from a standpoint that it operates within a governmental system that
is based upon a doctrine of the separation of powers.363 Davis rightly states that the
Constitution does not contain a programme which judges can ―download‖ on to their
computers and which would then provide them with the exact boundaries within which
they must operate in each case of review that comes before them. They have to
interpret their own role in a constitutional democracy, not only about unlocking the big
constitutional conundrums, but also about the manner that they go about the business
of review of the administration.364 He argues that –
[i]f the model of government is based on the idea of participation by citizens in
decisions which affect them, the right to express views about any decision which an
administrative agency is about to take which may determine a right of a citizen needs
to be robustly protected, as would the right to reasons for any such decision and the
corollary thereto, the provision of all reasonable means to participate in the decisionmaking process. The principle of separation of powers should not be allowed to
undermine these rights of participation; in other words, deference should usually not
play a significant role in the formulation of the scope and content of these procedural
rights.
The culture of justification ensures that the government justifies its decisions to the
governed and that the principles of participation and accountability are fostered.
Although deference may have been the correct approach for the Constitutional Court at
its inception, the Court and the Constitution are now a permanent feature of the South
African state. Therefore –365
[a] group of judges collectively committed to the ideal of adjudication according to the
law might disregard the political constraints impacting on their decisions without any
conscious appreciation of their decisions on their court‘s capacity to withstand political
attack.
363
364
365
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 8.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 30.
Roux The politics of principle 95.
256
The Constitution sets the values against which executive and legislative action must be
tested. The inherent values of openness, justification, participation and accountability,
which form the basis of the South African Constitution, are not realised when the courts
subscribe to a policy of deference. Furthermore, it does not encourage the ethical
behaviour constitutionally required of the state litigant. In its role as the reviewer of
policy, the judiciary must commence from a standpoint that it operates within a
governmental system that is based upon the doctrine of the separation of powers. 366
The culture of justification allows the courts to test executive and legislative action
against the foundational values of the Constitution and finds the correct balance in the
application of the principle of the separation of powers. It is suggested that it is time for
a change of direction by the Constitutional Court, as the Court cannot be said to have
achieved the degree of institutional independence characteristic of a court in a mature
democracy.367 Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng accused the executive of interfering in
the judiciary‘s independence and said that the judiciary needed to take collective
responsibility and do things differently.368 He said the following:
We ought to be worried when there is instability or a measure of instability in the
executive and in the legislative arm of government. But we ought to be terrified and
deeply concerned when the judiciary does not appear to be what it was established to
be. When there is a possibility, no matter how remote, that the judiciary might be
manipulated then we have to be vigilant. Without an independent judiciary democracy
is doomed.
Dworkin rejects judicial restraint because judicial review exists to protect minorities
against the oppression of the majority, and judges should not defer to the will of the
legislature but should instead interpret constitutional rights according to the demands
of precedent and integrity. Dworkin is also sceptical about the seriousness with which
the legislature takes its responsibility to interpret the Constitution faithfully and to act in
accordance with that interpretation. He distrusts elected officials, believing that they are
366
367
368
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 31.
Roux The politics of principle 391.
Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng addressing the Association of Regional Magistrates of Southern
Africa Litigator https://litigator.co.za/hands-off-judiciary-warns-chief-justice.
257
likely, because of electoral pressure, to ignore the Constitution and to take the side of
the majority against the minority.369
Dworkin‘s view is relevant in the South African constitutional state for two reasons, the
first being the ―fused‖ nature of the South African legislature and executive and the
overconcentration of ANC power in state institutions. The second reason relates to the
ANC‘s subscription to majoritarianism. Moreover, the demands of precedent and
integrity, as argued by Dworkin, can be met by relying on the inherent values of
openness, justification, participation and accountability that form the basis of the South
African Constitution. This makes the principle of judicial deference particularly unsuited
to South Africa.
Owing to the influence of Dicey, parliamentary systems have a deep distrust for any
supervisory role of the courts over the administration. For Dicey, all exercise of public
power was to be channelled through parliament, as parliament reflects the will of the
people and hence is the appropriate mechanism in a democratic state to exercise such
an oversight role.370 This distrust is still evident in South Africa with its hybrid
parliamentary form of government. Davis states that in a constitutional democracy the
principle of accountability means that decisions of the administrative agencies must be
accountable to constitutional provisions and values and must mean more than the right
to be informed about decisions. This principle must be true to a concept of ―public
interest‖, which is defined by constitutional values.371 Davis‘s principle of accountability
can be strengthened by the notion that when litigating, the state litigant must display
the ethical characteristics that the Constitution demands from it. A constitutionally
accountable litigant would be a model litigant. The strength of the executive means that
it increasingly displays an unwillingness to engage with the courts through judicial
proceedings372 by ignoring the process373 or by questioning the final judgment.374
369
370
371
372
373
Dworkin Is Democracy Possible Here? 134.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 24.
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 31.
McLean 2009 PULP 208.
Khosa v Minister of Social Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social Development 2004 6 SA 505
(CC) where the executive failed to respond to the court‘s direction.
258
In Minister of Home Affairs v Somali Association of South Africa Eastern Cape, 375 the
Minister failed to adhere to a court order instructing the state to reopen a refugee
reception office. The Court stated that it is a most dangerous thing for a litigant,
particularly a State department and senior officials in its employ, wilfully to ignore an
order of court.376 The Court found that:377
The cornerstone of democracy and the rule of law is the uncompromising duty and
obligation upon all persons, more especially State departments, to obey and comply
with court orders. There are processes in place for those who disagree with court
orders. But they are not free to simply turn a blind eye to the order nor do they have
any discretion to not obey the order.
The Court found that no democracy could survive if court orders were shunned and
trampled on as happened in this matter and if there was a likelihood of a future
repetition of similar conduct on the part of the relevant authorities
378
Lenta writes that the political majority enjoyed by the ANC may tempt the government
not always to act in a way that furthers the common good, but rather in a way that
prioritises the government‘s and its supporters‘ interests over considerations of
justice.379 It is imperative that judicial review is structured in such a manner that state
action is kept within the bounds of the Constitution. Venter posits that the justification
for constitutional review should rather be sought in the need for the qualification of
blind popular majoritarianism with rational judicial argument.380 The principle of
deference is not an effective qualification of the concept of majoritarianism. In fact, the
principle of deference subscribes to a majoritarian vision of democracy by
countenancing a ―superior role‖ for the legislature and executive vis-à-vis the courts.
Venter argues as follows:381
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
The Minister of Health stated that she would ignore the court order handed down in Minister of
Health v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 5 SA 721 (CC).
(831/2013) [2015] ZASCA 35 (25 March 2015).
Para 35.
Para 33.
Paras 35-36.
Lenta 2004 SAJHR 30.
Venter 2005 ZaöRV 145.
Venter 2005 ZaöRV 158-159.
259
Where the Court orders the state ―to take measures to meet its constitutional
obligations‖ and subjects the reasonableness of government conduct to evaluation, it
can by definition not be a meek and inhibited role. The Court has made it patently
clear that, in terms of the powers granted it by the Constitution, it primarily lies within
its domain to determine what is consistent with the Constitution and what not.
Although this statement was made concerning judgments relating to socio-economic
rights, there is no reason why a more expansive, uniform theory of constitutional
review cannot be implemented by the courts. Davis argues: ―The courts should ascribe
to a more expansive theory of judicial review which would embrace the values and
objectives which are quarried from the constitutional text.‖382
The dominance of the executive over Parliament means that at all three levels of
government there are few effective checks and balances on the abuse of power by the
executive. The deployment policy of the ANC uses language that is unapologetically
Leninist, calling for the placement of ―cadres‖ in key positions in national, provincial and
local government and the public sector, even the independent Chapter 9 institutions,
with the aim of bringing these institutions under its control.383 According to documents
of the ruling party, transformation of the state entails, primarily –384
[e]xtending the power of the National Liberation Movement (NLM) over all levers of
power: the army, the police, the bureaucracy, intelligence structures, the judiciary,
parastatals, and agencies such as regulatory bodies, the public broadcaster, the central
bank and so on.
McLean states that this means that the traditional separation of powers between the
three branches of government is effectively found only between the courts on the one
hand and the executive and legislature on the other. In the absence of robust checks
and balances elsewhere, courts should respond, not by adopting a deferential position,
but by ensuring that the other branches of government are held accountable to it and
the Constitution.385
The ―culture of participation‖ approach, as proposed by Davis, finds the correct balance
for judicial review in both an objective interpretation of constitutional provisions and the
382
383
384
385
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica 31.
Roux The politics of principle 181.
The State, Property Relations and Social Transformation, Umrabulo No. 5, 3rd Quarter 1998.
McLean 2009 PULP 209.
260
values inherent to the Constitution and the doctrine of the separation of powers. South
Africa subscribes to a democratic style of government based on accountability,
responsiveness and openness.386 When government action is tested against the culture
of participation, it allows these values to be explored and realised. Furthermore, it
allows for the ethical principles constitutionally required from the state litigant to be
realised. The circumstances in which the South African constitutional state currently
operates, where multiparty democracy comes under pressure, non-majoritarian
constitutional review is essential for the survival of constitutionalism.387 Venter words
this need as follows: ―Strong and fearless judicial consistency is needed as a corrective
to majoritarian arrogance rather than judicial echoes of government policy and
ideology.‖388
3.6 Conclusion
An analysis of the historical development of the doctrine of the separation of powers
shows that unrestrained government power will be corrupted. Such uncontained power
without effective checks and balances will result in despotism. In order to prevent
absolutism and despotism, institutions should be set up in a system that complement
and control each other with checks and balances.389 A complete separation of powers is
possible neither in theory nor in practice. In modern legal systems, there will be some
form of overlap between the different organs of state. However, although there will
invariably be an overlap between the organs of state, there should be checks and
balances to check the arbitrary exercise of powers by the branches of government.
The doctrine of the separation of powers was developed not only to create separate
institutions of government; a primary aim of the development of the doctrine was to
prevent the overconcentration of power in a single institution or individual. From a
conceptual point of view, the doctrine of the separation of powers is logically as much
386
387
388
389
Hugh Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa CCT 07/14 and CCT 09/14 2014 ZACC 32
para 165, in which the Court states our Constitution pointedly regards as a fundamental value not
only universal adult suffrage but also ―accountability, responsiveness and openness‖ of government.
Venter 2005 ZaöRV 165.
Venter 2005 ZaöRV 165.
Para 3.4.3 above.
261
about the concept of power as it is about the concept of separation between the
branches of government. The main aim of the separation of powers of government is
therefore ―that of securing liberty by preventing the concentration of power and by
restraining its arbitrary deployment‖. 390
During the multi-party constitutional negotiations, an agreement was reached in 1993
on the particulars of an Interim Constitution, which came into operation in 1994. The
Constitutional Principles of 1993 expressly provided for the doctrine of the separation of
powers. The Constitution of 1996 does not expressly provide for the doctrine of
separation, but the doctrine is implicit in the document itself. It is an crucial deficiency
that the concept of the separation of powers was not clarified to a greater degree in the
Interim Constitution. This allowed a hybrid parliamentary system of government to be
put in place in South Africa with a partial fusion between the executive and legislative
branches of government. This ―hybrid‖ Westminster form of government weakens the
ability of Parliament to act as an effective check on the misuse of power by the
executive and allows the executive, through a system of political appointees and cadre
deployment, to dominate state institutions. This left in place a form of separation of
powers with the judiciary on the one hand, and the executive and legislature on the
other, with few effective checks and balances on the power of the executive.391
The courts have ignored this fusion between the legislative and executive branches and
its corresponding effect on the doctrine of the separation of powers. Roux argues that
the Constitutional Court has failed to work out a convincing institutional role for itself.
The Court relies on a thin conception of democracy that is inadequate to the task of
ensuring that the ruling party does not abuse its dominant position. Roux argues
convincingly that the Constitutional Court‘s deferential review policy misconstrues the
contribution a robust political jurisprudence might have made to the Court‘s long-term
independence.392
390
391
392
Para 3.3.3 above.
Para 3.2.2.2 above.
Roux The politics of principle 10.
262
Choudhry argues that one of the pathologies of a dominant-party democracy (such as
South Africa) is the colonisation of independent institutions meant to check the exercise
of political power by the dominant party (such as the ANC).393
Labuschagne writes that the status of the JSC, as independent judicial guard dog, was
politically tampered with. He states that the ruling party, through cadre deployment to
the JSC, attempts to bring the judiciary more in line with the majority sentiment and
firmly under control of the executive.394 Devenish remarks that the executive's influence
on the composition of Parliament‘s Standing Committee on Public Accounts (Scopa) is
cause for concern and that this should be considered unacceptable because it adversely
affects the independence of Parliament.395 This premise is also relevant to the
executive‘s influence on the JSC, as it adversely affects the independence of the
judiciary. Machiavelli, the primary exponent of central control in government, preached
practical rules for politicians to obtain and hold on to power. Machiavelli insisted that
power was more important than ethics and morality.396 The ruling party seems to
subscribe to the philosophy of Machiavelli, namely exercising power over all public
institutions despite the constitutional provisions enshrining the doctrine of the
separation of powers.
The courts have found that the requirements for judicial independence lie in the
complete freedom of individual judicial officers to hear and decide cases with no outside
influence or interference. In De Lange v Smuts and Van Rooyen v The State, the Court
approvingly referred to the ―perceived-independence‖ test as formulated in Canadian
jurisprudence.397 The Court stated that a prerequisite of judicial independence includes
an element of the appearance or perception of the independence of the judiciary from
the objective standpoint of a reasonable and informed person. If this test is applied in
the South African constitutional context, it cannot fail to show that there is a prodigious
393
394
395
396
397
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review 3.
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia 20.
Devenish 2003 THRHR 89.
Para 3.2.1.3 above.
Para 3.3.2.2 above.
263
concentration of powers friendly to the executive on the Magistrates Commission and
the JSC.
The method of appointing Constitutional Court judges has been lamented because one
branch of government – the executive, and specifically the majority party and its leader,
the President – dominates this process.398 In 1996, Faure and Lane said that the
Constitutional Court was unlikely to enjoy the independence it needed to be an effective
guarantor of the Constitution. This has not happened. The Constitutional Court has on
some occasions ruled against the executive, the President and the ruling party.
Nevertheless, the perception of bias is not healthy for the Constitutional Court or the
South African constitutional landscape. There is a danger that the entire legal system
and the law will become discredited and delegitimised by an excessively politicised
Constitutional Court.399 The perception that the judiciary may eventually be dominated
by the executive is worrisome for anyone contemplating litigation against the state. It
can place a ―chilling effect‖ on litigants wishing to protect their constitutional rights
against abuse by the executive. This reflects negatively on the ―moral authority‖ of the
courts to hear matters impartially and independently.400
The hybrid parliamentary system of government in South Africa has led to tension
between the judiciary and the other branches of government, with the judiciary as the
only check on the abuse of power by the legislature and the executive. Although
constitutional provisions clearly define the role and duty of the judiciary to enforce the
Constitution, the populist predisposition of the executive challenges the bedrock of the
Constitution and fuels this tension. The history of South Africa is replete with examples
of infamous clashes between the executive and the judiciary, with the judiciary
ultimately losing out to executive power.401 In the current constitutional dispensation,
where the courts are constitutionally mandated to review executive and legislative
398
399
400
401
Faure and Lane Designing new political institutions 86.
Faure and Lane Designing new political institutions 86.
Para 3.3.2.2 above.
Para 3.3.4.3.2 above.
264
action,402 the courts must ensure that this mandate is not eroded by the executive
through the overconcentration of powers friendly to the executive in judicial institutions.
Public control over the executive in the form of strategic litigation remains a viable
option to curb the abuse of power when executive and legislative action is placed
before the courts for review. Strategic litigation against the state by individuals, civilsociety groups and political parties fosters a culture of accountability by publicly
exposing injustice and corruption.403 The Constitutional Court practices a system of
judicial review based on principles of non-intrusion and deference. This culture of nonintrusion and deference that the courts adhere to fails to find the correct balance
between the constitutional duty of review and the right of the other branches of
government to function effectively without undue interference. Owing to the fused
nature of the executive and legislative branches and the dominance of the executive in
public institutions, there are no effective checks and balances on the powers of the
executive. The fact that the courts do not address the issue of overconcentration of
executive power in public institutions sufficiently holds grave danger to the principle of
separation of powers in South Africa.
Montesquieu is relevant here: ―Political liberty is found to be present only when power
is not abused, and so that one cannot abuse power, power must check power by the
arrangement of things.‖404 Any government, despite its form, will therefore turn despotic
if there are no checks and balances placed on it: ―Unlimited power will corrupt.‖405 The
doctrine of the separation of powers aims to curb absolute power and decries the
overconcentration of power in one individual or institution. This subscribes to a system
of different levels of government with the power of each branch clearly defined and
checks and balances to limit the power of each branch. The deference policy of judicial
review employed by the courts does not function effectively as a check on the power of
the executive and further fails to satisfy the constitutional values fundamental to the
South African Constitution.
402
403
404
405
Sections 2 and 165 of the Constitution.
Chapter 2 par 2.2.3.2 above.
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 155.
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws 133.
265
Mureinik argues for a policy of judicial review based on non-discrimination, openness,
justification, accountability and participation. Dyzenhaus suggests an approach to
judicial review based on law as a culture of justification, which promotes Mureinik‘s
approach.
Both
these
approaches
satisfy
a
value-based
assessment
of
the
Constitution.406 The executive‘s stranglehold on the legislature and state institutions
leads to citizens looking to the judiciary to ensure accountability and the protection of
their basic interests.407 Davis argues for a culture of justification in judicial review that
will take into account the prerogative of the elected arms of government to fashion and
implement public policy within the framework of the Constitution.408 Such a culture
accepts that the role of judicial review is to foster a culture of democracy, including
strengthening the principle of the separation of powers. This culture of justification
meets the tenets of judicial review as set out by both Mureinik and Dyzenhaus and finds
application in an objective interpretation of constitutional provisions and values.
When government action is tested by strategic litigation, a culture of justification would
allow the values of accountability, responsiveness and openness to be explored and
realised. This will allow the courts to review executive and legislative action within the
framework of the Constitution and thus fashion a system of the doctrine of the
separation of powers that will survive the fused nature of the legislative and the
executive. This will further allow the ethical component, constitutionally required of the
state litigant, to be tested. The culture of justification can then assist in forcing the
state litigant to conduct itself as the model litigant.
Although it is imperative that the courts recognise the need to protect the institutional
character of each of the branches of government in a manner which will not prevent
their ability to discharge their constitutional role, the courts are mandated to uphold
constitutional provisions, including the doctrine of the separation of powers. The
doctrine of the separation of powers is as much about power 409 as it is about separate
406
407
408
409
Para 4.5.3 above and 5.2 below.
Para 4.5.3 above and 5.3 below.
Para 4.5.3 above and 5.3 below.
De Vries 2006 Politeia 43.
266
and
independent
public
institutions.410
It
is
therefore
imperative
that
the
overconcentration of executive power in public institutions be addressed, something the
courts seem unwilling to do. As the only check on executive power, a strong and
fearless judiciary is needed as a corrective to executive power, rather than judicial
deference and respect.411 The overconcentration of executive power in public
institutions such as the JSC might result in manipulation of the process of appointing
judges. This can lead to an executive-leaning judiciary, which could place constitutional
limitations on strategic litigation against the state.
410
411
Para 3.2.1.3 above. In Hugh Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa CCT 07/14 and
CCT 09/14 2014 ZACC 32 para 165, the Court stated that the dilution of power possessed by any
single person to appoint the head of an institution ( in casu, the Head of the Hawks) he desires
resonates with the separation of powers and attaches a significant counterweight to the power of
the executive and its members. In In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South
Africa 1996 (4) SA 744 CC para 112, the Court stated that the New Text (drawn-up by the
Constitutional Assembly relying on the Constitutional Principles of the Interim Constitution)
expresses concern for the over-concentration of power.
Para 4.5.3 above and 5.3 below.
267
Chapter 4:
The role of the judge in strategic litigation
4.1 Introduction
The traditional function of a judge in civil litigation is to resolve disputes between
litigants. However, under a supreme constitution, courts, and the Constitutional Court in
particular, have to –1
pronounce on the validity of legislation and executive conduct and to guard over our
Constitution, its democratic structures, and the values and rights in it, build a
constitutional jurisprudence and human rights culture, protect the weak against abuse
of power, facilitate access to justice for those who most need it and often cannot
afford it and generally strive to further our constitutional project.
Therefore, while the judge must resolve disputes, this must be done in a culture that
promotes justice and fairness.
Chapter 2 discussed the way strategic litigation serves as an effective check to prevent
the abuse of powers in the context of the doctrine of the separation of powers. Public
control over the executive in the form of strategic litigation remains a viable option to
curb the abuse of power when executive and legislative action is placed before the
courts for review. Strategic litigation against the state by individuals, civil-society groups
and political parties fosters a culture of accountability by publicly exposing injustice and
corruption. However, strategic litigation against the state would be meaningless without
an independent and impartial judiciary.
In Chapter 3, it was shown that the South African law of civil procedure underwent
great changes since the advent of the Constitution. The Constitution changed the
structure of the judiciary, defined the jurisdictional powers of courts regarding
constitutional issues and requires of the courts to develop the common law. The
changes to the common-law concepts of civil procedure set in place by the Constitution
profoundly affected litigation in South Africa as well. Chapter 3 also focused on the
changes to the traditional role of the courts. In strategic litigation, the judge may stay
involved in the proceedings after the final order has been granted. The judge is active,
1
Van der Westhuizen 2008 AHRLJ 260.
266
with the responsibility not only for credible fact assessment but also for organising and
shaping the litigation to ensure a just and viable outcome. Therefore, the advent of a
supreme Constitution also changed the traditional adjudicative role of judges. However,
although South Africa has a constitution as supreme law or guiding principle for
adjudication, there still is uncertainty about the role of the judge in litigation. The
constitutional function of the courts is undeniably political in nature and so is the role of
the judge when adjudicating. The political role of judges brings a new dynamic to
adjudication, with the court‘s decision in some instances reaching well beyond the
parties to the litigation and affecting a wider range of people. Changes made to the
political and constitutional landscape by a court‘s decision are difficult if not impossible
to alter, as the Constitutional Court is the final arbiter in constitutional matters.
This chapter investigates the constitutional landscape in which judges adjudicate.
Section 2 explores the judicial appointment process in South Africa and analyses how
political considerations and transformation issues can affect the independence of
judges.
In Section 3, the judicial independence and impartiality as a requirement for a fair trial
is discussed. Judicial independence is explored by highlighting the objective
prerequisites for judicial independence in South Africa. The impartiality of judges is
investigated by focusing on the recusal of judges and judicial impartiality in South
Africa.
Section 4 explores the interpretation of constitutional rights and values by focusing on
the sources for constitutional interpretation and the effect of so-called ―hard cases‖ on
interpretation. The section further explores the interpretation of constitutional rights
and values by the courts by examining relevant case law.
In Section 5, the concepts of rationality and justness in adjudication are investigated.
The focus is placed on so-called ―hard cases‖ in which objective legal interpretation is
problematic. However, the concepts of rationality and justness require that the court
reach a just decision that is correct from a legal point of view. The methods and
267
sources of constitutional interpretation used by the Constitutional Court are analysed by
reference to case law and the possibility of a legitimate theory of constitutional
interpretation is explored.
4.2 The judicial appointment process
4.2.1 The importance of the judicial appointment process
With the advent of the constitutional era, South Africans opted to accomplish a
significant portion of law making through adjudication. According to Klare, this is a
decision fraught with institutional consequences. At the most superficial level, South
Africans have chosen to limit the supremacy of Parliament and to increase the power of
judges, each to an unknowable extent.2
Viewing the Constitutional Court strictly as a legal institution is to underrate its
significance in the South African political system and its constitutional function. It is also
a political institution, often judging on controversial issues of national policy in which
the ―setting‖ of the case is political.3 Venter points out that the Constitutional Court
considers it unavoidable that its judgments in certain critical political areas within its
jurisdiction will have political consequences.4
Chief Justice Langa unapologetically stated that there is no longer place for assertions
that the law can be kept isolated from politics. He reasoned as follows:5
While they are not the same, they are inherently and necessarily linked. At the same
time, transformative adjudication requires judges to acknowledge the effect of what
has been referred to elsewhere as the personal, intellectual, moral or intellectual
preconceptions on their decision-making. We all enter any decision with our own
baggage, both on technical legal issues and on broader social issues. While the policy
under apartheid legal culture was to deny these influences on decision-making, our
constitutional legal culture requires that we expressly accept and embrace the role that
our own beliefs, opinions and ideas play in our decisions.
2
3
4
5
Klare 1998 SAJHR 147.
Dahl 1957 J. Pub. L. 279. The phrase was adopted from Dahl into a South African setting.
Venter 2003 PELJ 173.
Langa 2006 Stell LR 353.
268
The possible political repercussions of Constitutional Court judgments cannot be denied.
However, the acceptance of the political essence of court judgments raises the question
of judicial activism. If the judgments of the Constitutional Court are political in nature,
to what extent are the political leanings of judges allowed to shape court decisions and
how can such decisions be rationally justified? Finally, is the political predisposition of
the judge a criterion in the political appointment process?
The judiciary fulfils an important function in a democratic society, preserving the rule of
law. Therefore, judges must interpret the law fairly and consistently and remain free
from undue political influence. Because of the primacy of having competent and
impartial judges, the process for selecting judges is of critical importance for strategic
litigation. The goal of the selection process can best be articulated by the words of
Chief Justice Arthur T. Vanderbilt:6
An essential of a sound judicial system is, of course, a corps of judges, each of them
utterly independent and beholden only to the law and to the Constitution, thoroughly
grounded in his knowledge of the law and of human nature, including its political
manifestations, experienced at the bar in either trial or appellate work and preferably
in both, of such a temperament that he can hear both sides of a case before making
up his mind, devoted to the law and justice, industrious, and, above all, honest and
believed to be honest.
Akkas describes the judicial appointment process as follows:7
Mechanisms for judicial appointment are important factors in appointing judges. In any
society, the appointment of judges involves some formal and informal practices. The
whole system depends largely on the political culture and social values of a society.
Consequently, mechanisms for judicial appointment differ between jurisdictions. There
are no standardised systems of appointment. Whatever mechanism is used in any
particular country, it should be transparent and open to public scrutiny. Transparency
and public scrutiny in the mechanisms for judicial appointment are of paramount
importance to ensure appointment of the best available persons to judicial office and to
enhance public confidence in the judiciary.
When these statements are analysed, two conclusions are reached. Firstly, the focus is
on the judge himself, calling for the appointment of persons of fitness of character that
6
7
Vanderbilt 1953 Nw. U.L. Rev. 3.
Akkas 2004 Bond Law Review 201.
269
are suitably qualified and experienced. Secondly, the focus is on the mechanisms and
institutions responsible for judicial appointments.
4.2.2 Appointment of judges in South Africa
The procedure for the appointment and removal of judges embodied in the South
African Constitution provides for security of tenure and for safeguarding judicial
independence. The appointment of judges is regulated by section 174(3) and (4) of the
Constitution. The Constitution provides for the establishment of the Judicial Service
Commission (JSC) and the JSC is entrusted with a key role in making all judicial
appointments.8
The powers and functions of the JSC are assigned to it in terms of the Constitution and
national legislation and the JSC may advise the national government on any matter
relating to the judiciary or the administration of justice.9 The functions of the JSC are to
recommend suitable persons to the President for appointment as judges and to provide
oversight over judicial conduct and the accountability of judicial officers.10 The
composition of the JSC is therefore of vital importance for judicial independence in
South Africa.
The Constitution regulates the composition of the JSC, which consists of the following
persons:11
The Chief Justice, who presides at meetings of the Commission.
The President of the Supreme Court of Appeal.
One Judge President designated by the Judges President.
The Cabinet member responsible for the administration of justice, or an alternate
designated by that Cabinet member.
8
9
10
11
Section 178 of the Constitution.
Section 178(4) and 178(5) of the Constitution.
Chapter 2 of the Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994.
Section 178(1)(a)-(k) of the Constitution.
270
Two practising advocates nominated from within the advocates' profession to
represent the profession as a whole, and appointed by the President.
Two practising attorneys nominated from within the attorneys' profession to
represent the profession as a whole, and appointed by the President.
One teacher of law designated by teachers of law at South African universities.
Six persons designated by the National Assembly from among its members, at
least three of whom must be members of opposition parties represented in the
Assembly.
Four permanent delegates to the National Council of Provinces designated
together by the Council with a supporting vote of at least six provinces.
Four persons designated by the President as head of the national executive, after
consulting the leaders of all the parties in the National Assembly.
When considering matters relating to a specific Division of the High Court of
South Africa, the Judge President of that Division and the Premier of the
province concerned, or an alternate designated by each of them.
Members of the JSC hold office for a term not exceeding five years, but12the President
must remove any such member from office at any time if the designator who or which
designated such member, so requests, or a member may resign from office by giving at
least one month‘s written notice thereof to the chairperson.
The composition of the JSC at first glance seeks to ensure that persons from diverse
political, social and cultural backgrounds, representing varying interest groups, would
participate in its deliberations.13 The fact that legal practitioners, judges and members
of opposition parties are included in the decision-making process makes the process
inclusive and therefore legitimate. Such legitimacy is, however, of no value if there is an
12
13
Section 2(1) Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994, (as amended by the Judicial Service
Commission Amendment Act 20 of 2008.
Judicial Service Commission v Cape Bar Council 2012 (11) BCLR 1239 (SCA) para 35.
271
overconcentration of one group in the composition of the JSC which allows that group
to dominate.
4.2.3 Politics and the judicial appointment process
Malan states that, in the light of the broad review powers assigned to the courts and
the political implication thereof, the composition of the JSC and its decisions are of
political significance. Therefore, the JSC is an important political body.14 The JSC is
independent of the executive, although its composition could secure a dominant
position for the executive. At least twelve of the twenty-three members of the JSC will
be politicians appointed by the President from the ranks of the majority party in the
national legislature.15
Van Zyl also regards the JSC as politically loaded, fifteen out of the twenty-three
members being politicians. Van Zyl recommends a new approach, in which the
Constitution is amended to provide for a JSC consisting substantially, if not exclusively,
of judges, practising advocates and attorneys, and legal academics that are better
suited to decide on the appointment of judges.16 Van Zyl‘s approach may well lead to
the merit-based appointment of judges; however, such an appointment process may be
seen as elitist if lawyers only have the power to appoint judges. Nevertheless, it is clear
that a more balanced and inclusive judicial appointment process is called for. This
process should include politicians, but without the overconcentration of a parliamentary
majority of a single political party on the JSC as is the current situation.
Currently, the appointment of judges invites arbitrariness because it allows executive
interference in judicial process. According to Venter, in certain areas the Constitutional
Court invariably chooses to adopt the stance of the current political majority by, for
example, giving in its interpretation the constitutional provisions on equality an
extensive ideological meaning, which is unique in the world.17 Although the
Constitutional Court is mandated to give voice to the inherent values and principles of
14
15
16
17
Malan 2014 PELJ 1968.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1969.
Van Zyl 2009 PELJ 10.
Venter mentions equality and the ownership of land as significant.
272
the Constitution, ―as final interpreter of the Constitution it cannot rely on one method of
interpretation of those values and principles‖. The danger exists that emphasis on the
supremacy of the Constitution can become a ―sub-conscious stratagem behind which
the unexpressed political and moral presuppositions of a judge are concealed‖.18
The danger inherent in such a stratagem is that judges may substantively try to correct
perceived injustices in the law using any number of extra-constitutional sources. Extraconstitutional sources in this context include the ideology of political parties. Although
Venter emphasises that this kind of judicial choice should be distinguished from
executive-mindedness, the Constitutional Court cannot be bound to the ideological
stance of a political party. It would of course not be a problem if the ideological
discourse of the party were clearly aligned with the Constitution. However, the court
cannot in its interpretation of the values and principles seek meaning in the ideological
reasoning of any political party. Such constitutional interpretation would make a
mockery of the notion of the separation of powers, judicial independence and judicial
impartiality and integrity.
4.2.4
Transformation and the judicial appointment process
The JSC's criteria for judicial appointments were adopted in 1998 and published in
2010.19 In terms of the criteria, the following questions are asked:
(a)
Is the particular applicant an appropriately qualified person?
(b)
Is he or she a fit and proper person?
(c)
Would his or her appointment help to reflect the racial and gender
composition of South Africa?
Other criteria reflect the need for appointees to show commitment to the values and
principles of the Constitution:
18
19
Venter 2007 Speculum Juris 63.
JSC Criteria for Judicial Appointment 2010 http://www.justice.gov.za/saiawj/saiawj-jsc-criteria.pdf
accessed October 2015.
273
Is the proposed appointee a person of integrity?
Is the proposed appointee a person with the necessary energy and motivation?
Is the proposed appointee a competent person?
(i)
Technically competent
(ii)
Capacity to give expression to the values of the Constitution
Is the proposed appointee an experienced person?
(i)
Technically experienced
(ii)
Experienced concerning the values and needs of the community
Does the proposed appointee possess appropriate potential?
Symbolism. What message is given to the community at large by a particular
appointment?
The first criteria are a repeat of section 174(1) and (2) of the Constitution. The precise
meaning of section 174(2) is unclear. According to Hoexter and Olivier, two possible
meanings could be attributed to the section: firstly, that it advocates a thick notion of
diversity, or, secondly, a thinner idea of representativeness. Therefore, the Constitution
may require the appointment of more female and black judges or it could demand
something deeper, a judiciary that is more sensitive to the multiple values of the
Constitution, one that delivers a better and different quality of justice, promotes the
values of the Constitution and helps to create a more egalitarian society.20
This viewpoint is echoed by Malan, albeit in a different context. According to Malan,
there are the transformationists whose supporters are insisting on the preference of
transformation and representativeness as deciding criteria for judicial appointments.
The opposing view is held by the liberals, who reproach the JSC for its alleged
20
Hoexter and Olivier The judiciary in South Africa 247.
274
preference for recommending less competent and pliant pro-government candidates.
The liberals have misgivings about the JSC's bias against liberal and independentminded candidates, who are regarded as the foremost subscribers to the values
underpinning the South African Constitution.21
It is submitted that, as in the Constitution, the criteria of merit and fitness of person are
qualified by the criteria of representativeness. As such, merit and fitness of person
should be the primary criteria for judicial appointment, tempered by representativeness.
Fitness of person has been described by the Constitutional Court as follows:22
The overarching requirement for suitability is ―fit and proper‖ which, broadly speaking,
means that the candidate must have the capacity to do the job well and the character
to match the importance of the office. Experience, integrity and conscientiousness are
all intended to help determine a possible appointee‘s suitability ―to be entrusted with
the responsibilities of the office concerned‖. Similarly, laziness, dishonesty and general
disorderliness must of necessity disqualify a candidate.
Should the appointed person not display the kind of experience, the work ethic and the
disposition to the truth that are required, a successful legal challenge may be mounted
against that appointment. The appointment criteria of the JSC address the potential
appointee‘s commitment to constitutional values and principles as well as judicial
competence. It has given rise, however, to tension among the members of the JSC.
In Judicial Service Commission v Cape Bar Council,23 the JSC decided to recommend
only one candidate from a shortlist of candidates, with the result that two positions on
the bench remained vacant.24 The Cape Bar Council (CBC) brought an application in the
High Court seeking an order declaring the proceedings of the JSC to be inconsistent
with the Constitution, unlawful and consequently invalid and declaring the failure by the
JSC to fill two judicial vacancies on the bench of the WCHC25 to be unconstitutional and
unlawful.26 The Court held that the decisions of the JSC are reviewable under the
21
22
23
24
25
26
Malan 2014 PELJ 1970-1971.
Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa; Glenister v President of the
Republic of South Africa 2015 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) para 63.
2012 (11) BCLR 1239 (SCA).
Para 2.
Western Cape High Court.
Para 3.
275
doctrine of legality.27 The power to advise the President on the appointment of judges
of the High Court is derived from section 174(6)28 of the Constitution and, as such, it is
undoubtedly a public power.29
The CBC argued that the JSC‘s failure to recommend any of the unsuccessful candidates
for appointment to the two remaining vacancies was irrational and therefore invalid. 30
The CBC relied on the provisions of section 174(1) and (2)31 of the Constitution. Three
of the shortlisted candidates were supported by the CBC on the basis that they met the
requirements in section 174(1).32 The CBC requested reasons from the JSC for its
decision to leave two vacancies instead of recommending any one of these candidates.
The JSC‘s only response was that none of these candidates received a majority vote.
The JSC did not deny that the three candidates proposed by the CBC were
appropriately qualified persons who were fit and proper for judicial appointment as
contemplated by section 174(1),33 nor did the JSC profess to have been influenced by
considerations of racial and gender representativeness contemplated in section 174(2)
when it decided not to recommend any of the unsuccessful candidates. The only reason
it gave why none of these candidates were nonetheless recommended to fill the two
vacancies, was that no one secured sufficient votes for recommendation.
The JSC answered the charge that it had failed in its duty to provide reasons for not
recommending any of the unsuccessful candidates at three levels:34
(a)
That there is no duty imposed upon it, either by the Constitution or by any
other legislative enactment, to give reasons for that decision.
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
Para 20.
This section provides that the President must appoint judges of all courts on the advice of the JSC.
Para 22.
Para 37.
Section 174(1) provides that any appropriately qualified woman or man who is a fit and proper
person may be appointed as a judicial officer. In terms of s 174(2), the need for the judiciary to
reflect broadly the racial and gender composition of South Africa must be considered when judicial
officers are appointed.
Para 38.
Para 39.
Para 42.
276
(b)
That it has in any event given a reason for not selecting any of the
unsuccessful candidates, namely that none of them received enough
votes.
(c)
That because of its secret voting procedure it was not possible to provide
better reasons than the one it gave.
The Court firstly held that the JSC is under a constitutional duty to exercise its powers
in a way that is not irrational or arbitrary.35 Secondly, because the JSC is an organ of
state it is bound by section 195 of the Constitution36 to the values of transparency and
accountability. The JSC is therefore obliged to give reasons for its decision not to
recommend a particular candidate if properly called upon to do so.37
The Court therefore held that, since the JSC is under a constitutional obligation to act
rationally and transparently in deciding whether or not to recommend candidates for
judicial appointment, it follows that, as a matter of general principle, it is obliged to give
reasons for its decision not to do so.38 The response that the particular candidate did
not garner enough votes, does not meet that general obligation, because it amounts to
no reason at all. The Court continued by stating that, in a case such as this, where the
undisputed facts gave rise to a prima facie inference that the decision not to
recommend any of the suitable candidates was irrational, the failure by the JSC to
adhere to its general duty to give reasons inevitably leads to confirmation of that prima
facie inference.
The decision of the Court to rebuke the JSC for not recommending two suitable white
candidates for the bench as irrational and therefore incompatible with the principle of
legality and the rule of law seems to strengthen the argument of the liberal-leaning
writers. It is clear from the judgment that should the JSC decide not to recommend
suitable and qualified candidates based on race, the decision should be rationally
justified to escape scrutiny by the courts. The judgment of the Court supports the
35
36
37
38
Paras 43 and 44.
Basic values and principles governing public administration.
Para 45.
Para 51.
277
notion that the primary criteria for judicial appointment are merit and fitness of
character and that the issue of transformation plays a secondary role. The judgment
also confirms the aim to promote the transformative justice of the Constitution
premised on the fact that the principle of legality must be observed.39
Section 174(1) of the Constitution provides that any appropriately qualified woman or
man who is a fit and proper person is eligible for an appointment as a judge. However,
the need for the judiciary broadly to reflect the racial and gender composition of South
Africa must be considered in the appointment process of judges.40 According to
Andrews –41
[t]his project of constitutional transformation has not occurred without rancour, as the
sometimes competing challenges of racial and gender transformation and
representation, on the one hand, and integrity, competence, skill, and merit, on the
other hand, are evaluated and balanced.
The statement by Andrews encapsulates the tension between the liberals and the
transformationists in the judicial appointment process. It is also argued that
transformation is used as an excuse for creating a more compliant judiciary. Therefore,
―the government‘s assertions that judicial appointments are based on the need to
increase diversity and promote a more rights-oriented judiciary are really pretexts for
appointing individuals
who are less likely to challenge official policies and
programmes‖.42 Such individuals would also be less likely to hold the state litigant
constitutionally accountable.
When the independence of the judiciary is questioned, it reflects negatively on the
legitimacy of the judiciary. Legitimacy in this sense refers to the possibility of the
governed recognising and accepting the exercise of power as the exercise of authorised
power.43 The judiciary is not supposed to have an interest in the outcome of its
decisions; they do not represent the people‘s will or interest but administer the existing
39
40
41
42
43
South African Police Service v Solidarity OBO Barnard 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC) para 38.
Section 174(2) of the Constitution.
Andrews 2006 Osgoode Hall Law Journal 567.
Gordon and Bruce Transformation and the independence of the judiciary in South Africa Centre for
the Study of Violence and Reconciliation: Project on Justice and Transition 2007 www.csvr.org.za 48
accessed August 2015.
Bax and Van der Tang Theses on control in Constitutional Law 92.
278
law with due consideration of the Constitution. Therefore, ―judicial decisions are
provided with legitimacy in so far as they present themselves as applications of the law
in concrete controversies by an independent and impartial institution‖.44
The appointment of judges oriented towards the ideology of a political party leaves the
possibility that judges will have an interest in the outcome of the case when that party
was part of the proceedings. In the words of Malan,45
[j]udicial impartiality would not be possible, especially where the state is a party to
litigation, for example, unless the court is independent from the legislature and the
executive; that is, insulated from external interference in conducting its judicial
responsibilities.
If a judge then found for the political party, the decision, even when correctly arrived
at, could be suspect in the eyes of the public because of potential bias. An impartial
system of judicial selection offers the best option. No judicial ruling should be
questioned because of a cloud of suspected partisanship hanging over the judge.
According to the Burgh House Principles on the Independence of the International
Judiciary (hereafter the Burgh Principles),46 the following criteria are important when
considering judicial appointments:
Judges should be chosen from among persons of high moral character, integrity and
conscientiousness who possess the appropriate professional qualifications, competence
and experience required.
Criteria to ensure the fair representation of people in an area are acceptable, but
appropriate
personal
and
professional
qualifications
must
be
the
overriding
consideration in the nomination, election and appointment of judges.
Although the Burgh Principles were drafted as guidelines for the appointment of judges
in international forums, they provide helpful and acceptable criteria for the appointment
44
45
46
Bax and Van der Tang Theses on control in Constitutional Law 95.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1983.
Study Group of the International Law Association on the Practice and Procedure of International
Courts and Tribunals, in association with the Project on International Courts and Tribunals : Burgh
House Principles http://www.ucl.ac.uk/laws/cict/docs/burgh_final_21204.pdf. accessed October
2015.
279
of judges in national jurisdictions.47 The criteria to ensure representativeness are of the
utmost importance for the appointment of judges in South Africa. However, the
Principles clearly state that although representativeness in the judiciary is important,
appropriate
personal
and
professional
qualifications
must
be
the
overriding
consideration in the nomination, election and appointment of judges.
Further confirmation of this argument can be found in the Basic Principles on the
Independence of the Judiciary,48 according to which persons selected for judicial office
should be individuals of integrity and ability with appropriate training or qualifications in
law.49 The rest of the section states that –
[a]ny method of judicial selection shall safeguard against judicial appointments for
improper motives. In the selection of judges, there shall be no discrimination against a
person on the grounds of race, colour, sex, religion, political or other opinion, national
or social origin, property, birth or status, except that a requirement, that a candidate
for judicial office must be a national of the country concerned, shall not be considered
discriminatory.
It is clear from this section that rejecting a suitable candidate for judicial appointment
because of his or her race would be considered discriminatory and therefore
unacceptable and illegal.
The appointment of judges oriented towards the ideology of a political party leaves the
possibility that judges may have an interest in the outcome of the case if that party
takes part in the proceedings. This relates directly to strategic litigation because judicial
impartiality would not be possible when the state is a party to the litigation. As is shown
in section 4.4 below, subjective inclinations in the process of constitutional adjudication
are an inescapable part of the constitutional landscape. This may lead to a situation
where the courts are ―functionally associated with the executive and consequently
47
48
49
The Code of Judicial Conduct, adopted in terms of section 12 of the Judicial Service Commission Act
9 of 1994, published in Government Gazette No. 35802 of 18 October 2012, refers approvingly to
the Principles.
Adopted by the Seventh United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of
Offenders held at Milan from 26 August to 6 September 1985 and endorsed by General Assembly
resolutions 40/32 of 29 November 1985 and 40/146 of 13 December 1985.
Section 10.
280
unable to control the executive‘s power with the detachment and independence
required by the Constitution‖.50
A situation in which the courts are functionally associated with the judiciary holds an
inherent danger for the independence of the judiciary. Oseko writes that, in Kenya, the
president had sole powers to appoint the chief justice.51 Therefore, the president made
an important executive decision affecting the judiciary, but that decision was unchecked
by either the judiciary or the legislature. This unchecked power resulted in the
following:
The President took over all appointments with no fettered discretion. The
concentration of powers in the executive was evident. That the executive powers had
been expanded at the expense of the judiciary is visible. The folly of this arrangement
is that it exposed the judiciary to abuse by the subsequent executives, thus
compromising the independence of the judiciary. The Chief Justice could influence the
decisional independence of judges and magistrates over whom he held enormous
administrative authority.
According to Oseko, public confidence in the office of the chief justice was very low as a
result and he was perceived to be a puppet of the president. Oseko accordingly called
for urgent amendments to the Constitution, providing for a more stringent appointment
process, comprising checks by the legislature.52
The 2010 Constitution of Kenya,53 currently in force, replaced the 1969 Constitution.
The 2010 Constitution now reads that the president may only appoint the chief justice
in accordance with recommendations made by the Judicial Service Commission and
subject to the approval of the National Assembly.54 The unfettered power of the
president to appoint the chief justice in Kenya has been curtailed. However, the same
danger of executive interference in the judicial appointment process, and partisan
judges consequently, remains in South Africa.
50
51
52
53
54
Gordon and Bruce Transformation and the independence of the judiciary in South Africa Centre for
the Study of Violence and Reconciliation Project on Justice and Transition 2007 www.csvr.org.za 28
accessed August 2015.
Section 61(1) of the Constitution of Kenya, 1969.
Oseko Judicial independence in Kenya 139.
Constitution of Kenya, 2010.
Section 166(1) of the Constitution of Kenya, 2010.
281
The South African courts recognise the danger a perception of partisan judges may
cause, stating that nothing is more likely to impair confidence in judicial proceedings
than actual bias or the appearance of bias in the officials who have the power to
adjudicate on disputes.55 Should the public lose their trust in the courts, something that
will surely happen if the courts are perceived to be biased, other ways will be sought to
settle disputes, including means such as self-help and violence.56
Van Zyl writes that struggle credentials appears to have been elevated to a
qualification, if not a prerequisite, for judicial appointment, with the subsequent loss of
qualified candidates for appointment to the various courts in South Africa.57 The
Constitutional Court has held that pre-1994 involvement in struggle politics does not
reflect on the ability of a judge to hear matters independently.58 However, this surely
cannot mean that struggle credentials are a prerequisite for judicial appointment. In
strategic litigation, the primary litigant is the state. The Constitutional Court is entrusted
with the final jurisdiction in constitutional cases. The availability of law-based dispute
resolution between the state and other parties, especially concerning the exercise of
public power, is of paramount importance. If this approach is compromised, it will
undermine the supremacy of law in the South African constitutional structure. No sitting
judge should operate with the realisation that his or her career depends on the extent
his or her rulings in the lower court pleased or displeased the primary litigant.
What is needed is the appointment of non-partisan, non-political and appropriately
qualified judges. If the JSC rose above political ideology, the judicial appointment
process could be balanced, inclusive and open to participation. Such a balanced
approach would lead to creating and sustaining an intellectually and legally
distinguished and a politically independent and representative judiciary. Gordon and
Bruce says that if appointments were based on merit as opposed to party allegiance or
other inappropriate factors, judges would be less likely to feel that they need to favour
55
56
57
58
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
para 35.
Malan 2014 PELJ 2024.
Van Zyl 2009 PELJ 9 also Venter 2007 Speculum Juris 68-69.
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
para 72.
282
the people who appointed them. Such judges would also be more likely hold the state
litigant constitutionally accountable. Merit-based appointments would also ensure that
judges have the necessary legal education and experience, both of which help foster
and reinforce the importance of judicial independence.59
It is undeniable that the interpretation of indeterminate constitutional values requires a
diverse judiciary. In R v S (R.D.),60 the Court held as follows:
It is obvious that good judges will have a wealth of personal and professional
experience, that they will apply with sensitivity and compassion to the cases that they
must hear. The sound belief behind the encouragement of greater diversity in judicial
appointments was that women and visible minorities would bring an important
perspective to the difficult task of judging.
In the Constitutional Court, the differences in interpretation of constitutional rights and
values by the judges are readily discernible. The analysis in section 4.4 below shows
the different approaches of judges in reasoning, interpreting the Constitution and
selective sourcing. This sets the background for a liberal democratic and social
democratic culture of constitutional interpretation premised on justification.
The differences of opinion and interpretation of the Constitution provide plurality and
give meaning to the rights and values imbedded in the Constitution. The judicial
appointment process must provide judges who have the necessary skills and
qualifications and who can contribute different opinions to constitutional interpretation.
This articulates the thick version of diversity described by Hoexter and Olivier that
strives for a multiple intersectional difference of race, gender, culture and sexual
orientation, for diverse judicial attitudes and values, and for diverse values and modes
of adjudication.61
Should the plurality necessary for constitutional interpretation be stifled by the
appointment of judges of similar political orientation, the integrity of the courts as well
as the principle of participation as articulated by the Constitution would be
59
60
61
Gordon and Bruce Transformation and the independence of the judiciary in South Africa Centre for
the Study of Violence and Reconciliation Project on Justice and Transition 2007 www.csvr.org.za
accessed August 2015.
(1997) 118 CCC (3d) 353 para 119.
Hoexter and Olivier The judiciary in South Africa 247.
283
compromised and might lead to a monopoly on constitutional interpretation or
interpretive consensus. Interpretive consensus might limit the extent of constitutional
interpretation and force consensus, but not because the Constitution itself compels
agreement. This might lead to an attempt by similarly minded judges to force
conformity or their version of the truth on all. Interpretive consensus would then not be
based on constitutional principles and values, but on political ideology.
The Constitutional Court inevitably and frequently makes decisions that have political
implications. Therefore, constitutional adjudication is necessarily political, because it is
guided by the values and principles of the Constitution, which have to be interpreted
and applied within a specific socio-political reality.62 Constitutional interpretation
therefore cannot be driven by any brand of political ideology.
4.3 Judicial independence and impartiality
4.3.1 International law and the independence and impartiality of the judiciary
According to Lummis, ―the moment a decision is controlled or affected by the opinions
of others or by any form of external influence or pressure, that moment the judge
ceases to exist‖.63 Judicial impartiality requires that the judge reach a decision based on
the acceptable current law, free from outside interference.
The Burgh Principles,64 noting that each court has its own characteristics and functions,
consider the following principles of international law to be of general application to
ensure the independence and impartiality of the judiciary:65
(a)
Judges must enjoy independence from the parties to cases before them,
their own states of nationality or residence, the host countries in which they
62
63
64
65
Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa; Glenister v President of the
Republic of South Africa 2015 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) para 205.
Lummis The trial judge 10, quoted by Volcansek 2007 Fordham Urban Law Journal 383.
Study Group of the International Law Association on the Practice and Procedure of International
Courts and Tribunals, in association with the Project on International Courts and Tribunals: Burgh
House Principles http://www.ucl.ac.uk/laws/cict/docs/burgh_final_21204.pdf.
Preamble of the Report.
284
serve, and the international organisations under the auspices of which the
court or tribunal is established.
(b)
Judges must be free from undue influence from any source.
(c)
Judges must decide cases impartially, based on the facts of the case and
the applicable law.
(d)
Judges must avoid any conflict of interest, as well as being placed in a
situation which might reasonably be perceived as giving rise to any conflict
of interests.
(e)
Judges must refrain from impropriety in their judicial and related activities.
These Principles set the minimum standard required for the impartiality of the judiciary.
Internationally, the independence and impartiality of courts are required for any
democracy. The international standards, endorsed by the resolutions of the General
Assembly of the United Nations,66 include two principles: Firstly, the independence of
the judiciary must be guaranteed by the state and enshrined in the Constitution or the
law of the country. It is the duty of all governmental and other institutions to respect
and observe the independence of the judiciary. Secondly, the judiciary must decide
matters before them impartially, based on facts and in accordance with the law, without
any restrictions, improper influence, inducements, pressures, threats or interference,
direct or indirect, from any quarter or for any reason.
The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights67 guarantees that all persons are
equal before the courts and that in the determination of any criminal charge or of rights
66
67
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, adopted by the Seventh United Nations
Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders held at Milan from 26 August
to 6 September 1985 and endorsed by General Assembly resolutions 40/32 of 29 November 1985
and 40/146 of 13 December 1985.
Signed by South Africa in October 1994 but not ratified.
285
and obligations in a suit at law, everyone is entitled, without undue delay, to a fair and
public hearing by a competent, independent and impartial tribunal established by law.68
In the Bangalore Code of Judicial Conduct 200169 (hereafter the Bangalore Code), chief
justices of a number of countries laid down the premises for judicial integrity:
A judge shall exercise the judicial function independently on the basis of the judge's
assessment of the facts and in accordance with a conscientious understanding of the
law, free of any extraneous influences, inducements, pressures, threats or
interference, direct or indirect, from any quarter or for any reason. Judges shall be
independent in relation to society in general and in relation to the particular parties to
a dispute which the judge has to adjudicate. A judge shall not only be free from
inappropriate connections with, and influence by, the executive and legislative
branches of government, but must also appear to a reasonable observer to be free
therefrom. In performing judicial duties, a judge shall be independent of judicial
colleagues in respect of decisions which the judge is obliged to make independently.
Under the Bangalore Code, impartiality is essential for the proper discharge of the
judicial office. It applies not only to the decision itself but also to the process by which
the decision is made.
Another principle laid down in the Bangalore Code is equal treatment of all before a
court. In the application of the equality treatment, the Bangalore Code provides as
follows:
A judge shall be aware of, and understand, diversity in society and differences
arising from various sources, including but not limited to race, colour, sex, religion,
national origin, caste, disability, age, marital status, sexual orientation, social and
economic status and other like causes ("irrelevant grounds").
A judge shall not, in the performance of judicial duties, by words or conduct,
manifest bias or prejudice towards any person or group on irrelevant grounds.
A judge shall carry out judicial duties with appropriate consideration for all persons,
such as the parties, witnesses, lawyers, court staff and judicial colleagues, without
68
69
Article 14(1) of the Covenant.
The Bangalore Draft Code of Judicial Conduct 2001 adopted by the Judicial Group on Strengthening
Judicial Integrity, as revised at the Round Table Meeting of Chief Justices held at the Peace Palace,
The Hague, November 25-26, 2002.
286
differentiation on any irrelevant ground, immaterial to the proper performance of
such duties.
A judge shall not knowingly permit court staff or others subject to the judge's
influence, direction or control to differentiate between persons concerned in a
matter before the judge, on any irrelevant ground.
A judge shall require lawyers in proceedings before the court to refrain from
manifesting, by words or conduct, bias or prejudice based on irrelevant grounds,
except such as are legally relevant to an issue in proceedings and may be the
subject of legitimate advocacy.
The Bangalore Code is instrumental in testing the conduct of judges. The Constitution,
in particular, and strategic litigation, by necessity, require an independent judiciary with
structures and constitutional principles guaranteeing such independence. Strategic
litigation also calls for judges who are fair and impartial, non-partisan and averse to
promoting a particular political ideology.
4.3.2 Judicial independence in South Africa
The chief characteristic distinguishing the courts from political institutions is judicial
independence:
independence
from
government
and
from
political
leadership,
independence from political parties and political fashion, independence from popular
feelings.70 According to Malan, as its basic tenet, judicial independence –71
implies that the courts must stand in an independent relationship to the legislature and
the executive, and that judges must be in a position to discharge their functions free
from interference of whatever nature and from whatever source.
However, he continues that it would be ―unrealistic and incorrect to portray the
judiciary as the supreme power centre in the constitutional system which the weak
political branches must obey‖. Ultimately, the power of the courts rests on the
70
71
Koopmans Courts and political institutions 250.
Malan 2014 PELJ 1984.
287
willingness of the public, and the political actors accountable to it, to respect the
independence and the decrees of the court.72
Judicial independence in South Africa is regulated by the Constitution, the Judicial
Service Commission Act 9 of 1994 and a Code of Judicial Conduct.73
In terms of the Constitution, the judicial authority in South Africa is vested in the
courts.74 The courts are independent and subject only to the Constitution and the law,
which they must apply impartially without fear, favour or prejudice.75 No person or
organ of state may interfere with the functioning of the courts.76 Organs of state,
through legislative and other measures, must assist and protect the courts to ensure
the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.77
The Constitution provides a blueprint for a judiciary that is insulated from interference
from the other branches of government. The Constitution78 requires national legislation
to be enacted to ensure the independence of the judiciary.
In terms section 12 of the Judicial Service Commission Act, a code of judicial conduct
was adopted that serves as the prevailing standard for judicial conduct, to which judges
must adhere.79 The Code of Judicial Conduct (hereafter the Code)80 was compiled by the
Chief Justice, acting in consultation with the Minister, and tabled by the Minister in
Parliament for approval.81
Any wilful or grossly negligent breach of the Code constitutes misconduct, which will
lead to disciplinary action in terms of section 14 of the Act. The preamble to the Code
states that it is necessary for public acceptance of the authority and integrity of the
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
Friedman 2006 New York University Law and Economics Working Papers 261.
Adopted in terms of section 12 of the Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994, published in
Government Gazette No. 35802 of 18 October 2012.
Section 165(1) of the Constitution.
Section 165(2) of the Constitution.
Section 165(3) of the Constitution.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Section 179(6) of the Constitution.
Section 12(5) of the Act.
Code of Judicial Conduct, adopted in terms of Section 12 of the Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of
1994, published in Government Gazette no. 35802, 18 October 2012.
Section 12(1) of the Act.
288
judiciary in order to fulfil its constitutional obligations that the judiciary should conform
to ethical standards that are internationally accepted, in particular as set out in the
Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct (2001) as revised at The Hague (2002).
Article 4 of the Code highlights the importance of judicial independence in South Africa.
Therefore, a judge must –
(a)
uphold the independence and integrity of the judiciary and the authority of
the courts;
(b)
maintain an independence of mind in the performance of judicial duties;
(c)
take all reasonable steps to ensure that no person or organ of state
interferes with the functioning of the courts; and
(d)
not ask for nor accept any special favour or dispensation from the executive
or any interest group.
Note 4 requires the following:82
A judge acts fearlessly and according to his or her conscience because a judge is
only accountable to the law.83
Judges do not pay any heed to political parties or pressure groups and perform
all professional duties free from outside influence.84
Judges should not appear at public hearings or otherwise consult with an
executive or legislative body or official except on matters concerning the law, the
legal system or the administration of justice.85
82
83
84
85
Explanatory footnotes for each Article.
Note 4(i).
Note 4(ii).
Note 4(iii).
289
Judicial independence is not a private right or a principle for the benefit of
judges. It denotes freedom of conscience for judges and non-interference in the
performance of their decision-making.
The Code further requires that judges act honourably,86 comply with the law,87 ensure
equality at all times,88 and take reasonable steps to enhance transparency.89 Judges
must be fair in resolving disputes90 and perform judicial duties diligently.91 Judges
should not comment on the merits of a case and not enter into public debate about a
case irrespective of criticism levelled against the judgment. 92 The right to association of
judges is curtailed, as they are not allowed to belong to any political party or secret
organisation and must sever all professional links to such organisations upon
appointment.93
Each judge and acting judge must also take an oath or solemnly affirm to be faithful to
the Republic of South Africa and to uphold and protect the Constitution and the human
rights entrenched in it and administer justice to all persons alike without fear, favour or
prejudice, in accordance with the Constitution and the law.94
The Constitutional Court relied95 on Canadian jurisprudence96 when it defined judicial
independence:
Historically, the generally accepted core of the principle of judicial independence has
been the complete liberty of individual judges to hear and decide the cases that come
before them: no outsider — be it government, pressure groups, individuals or even
another judge — should interfere in fact, or attempt to interfere, with the way in which
a judge conducts his or her case and makes his or her decision. This core continues to
be central to the principle of judicial independence.
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
Article 5 of the Code.
Article 6 of the Code.
Article 7 of the Code.
Article 8 of the Code.
Article 9 of the Code.
Article 10 of the Code.
Article 11 of the Code.
Article 12 of the Code.
Item 6 of Schedule 2 of the Constitution.
De Lange v Smuts 1998 3 SA 785 (CC) para 70; Van Rooyen v S 2002 5 SA 246 (CC) para 19.
The Queen in Right of Canada v Beauregard (1986) 30 DLR (4th) 481 (SCC) 491.
290
According to Van der Westhuizen, independence of the courts places a huge
responsibility on the judiciary. Firstly, the courts have to value, assert and protect their
own independence. This means that the judiciary must resist all attempts at
interference in the form of corruption or instructions or requests from the politically
powerful. Van der Westhuizen further states that the judiciary should reject fear of
rejection or a desire for popularity.97 This would allow the courts to build institutional
legitimacy and play an effective role in democratic politics. The rejection of fear or a
desire for popularity would allow the judge to hold the state litigant to account for the
constitutional violations. This could assist in creating a culture of accountability. Such a
culture would insist that the state litigant is ethical and fair when appearing in court. In
other words, it would require the state litigant to be the model litigant.
When the state is a party to litigation, the relationship between the parties and
between the court and the parties may affect proceedings. Dyzenhaus puts it as
follows:98
At the moment that a court accepts jurisdiction over a controversy between
government and an individual, government is demoted — it loses its claim to be the
exclusive representative of the state. At the same time, the individual is promoted to a
public role, to one with an equal claim to represent the state. The court, then, in
deciding between these claims, articulates a vision of what the state is and publicly
draws the line between law and politics. In order to articulate this vision, the court
needs to be independent.
This statement by Dyzenhaus encapsulates a basic tenet of strategic litigation and
indeed the law in general. When involved in litigation, it is a principal element of the
law and the court to level the playing field and to ensure that parties to the litigation
are equal in the eyes of the law and the court. Therefore, the state party, for the
purpose of the litigation, loses its public representative mandate. The state is placed on
equal constitutional footing with the litigant who challenged the policy. The court, as
objective arbiter of the dispute, relies on principles and values articulated by the
Constitution to ensure that the matter reaches a fair and just conclusion. However, to
reach the level of fairness and justness as required by the Constitution, it may be
97
98
Van der Westhuizen 2008 AHRLJ 259.
Dyzenhaus 1998 SAJHR 172.
291
necessary for the court to hold the state litigant to a different standard than the private
litigant. Constitutional obligations require this from the courts. After all, there is
sometimes a meaningful imbalance of power in litigation against the government with
its access to substantial resources.99
There is ample constitutional protection for the independence of the judiciary in South
Africa. However, it is essential that both the executive and the legislature respect and
promote the independence of the courts. In 2015, Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng
accused the executive of interfering in the judiciary‘s independence and said that the
judiciary needed to take collective responsibility and do things differently.100 He said that
–
[w]e ought to be worried when there is instability or a measure of instability in the
executive and in the legislative arm of government. But we ought to be terrified and
deeply concerned when the judiciary does not appear to be what it was established to
be. When there is a possibility, no matter how remote, that the judiciary might be
manipulated then we have to be vigilant. Without an independent judiciary democracy
is doomed.
Ultimately, the responsibility for maintaining the independence of the judiciary rests
with the judiciary itself; this independence can be achieved by holding the executive
and Parliament to account whenever judicial independence is threatened.
4.3.3 Judicial impartiality in South Africa
4.3.3.1
Recusal of judges
The issue of recusal of judges was heard by the Constitutional Court in President of the
Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union.101 The respondent in the
case stated that he had reasonable apprehension that every member of the Court
would be biased against him and that, as a result, he might not get a fair trial. 102 The
Court firstly held that if that apprehension was reasonable, all its members would have
99
100
101
102
This argument is further explored in section 6 of this work.
Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng addressing the Association of Regional Magistrates of Southern
Africa Litigator https://litigator.co.za/hands-off-judiciary-warns-chief-justice accessed October 2015.
1999 (7) BCLR 725 (CC).
Para 6.
292
been under a duty to recuse themselves, despite the fact that no formal application for
such relief was made.
The Court stated that a judge who sits in a case in which he is disqualified from sitting
because there is a reasonable apprehension that such judge might be biased would act
in a manner that is inconsistent with section 34 of the Constitution.103 Such a judge
would also be in breach of the requirements of section 165(2)104 of the Constitution and
the prescribed oath of office.105 A judge who incorrectly refuses to recuse himself could
fatally contaminate the ultimate decision of the Court.106
The Court reasoned that there are two possible tests to determine bias. The first is to
ask whether there is a real likelihood of bias and the second is whether there is a
reasonable suspicion or apprehension of bias.107 The Court held that the preferred test
is that of reasonable apprehension of bias.108
The Court stated that the test for apprehension of bias is objective and that the onus of
establishing it rests on the applicant. Furthermore, the apprehension of bias must be
reasonable and held by reasonable and right-minded persons, applying themselves to
the question and obtaining all the required information.109
The question that a court will ask when a recusal application is made is therefore –110
whether a reasonable, objective and informed person would on the correct facts
reasonably apprehend that the judge has not or will not bring an impartial mind to
bear on the adjudication of the case, that is a mind open to persuasion by the evidence
and the submissions of counsel.
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
Everyone has the right to have any dispute that can be resolved by the application of law decided in
a fair public hearing before a court.
Courts are independent and subject only to the Constitution and the law, which they must apply
impartially and without fear, favour or prejudice.
Item 6 of Schedule 2 of the Constitution.
SARFU case para 32.
Para 36.
Para 38.
Para 45.
Para 48.
293
Should the answer to this question be in the affirmative, the judge would have to
recuse him- or herself. Failure to recuse him- or herself would lead to the invalidity of
the decision of the judge.
In practice, the judges recuse themselves where one of the parties to the litigation is a
close family member. However, this does not always relate to the situation where the
family member appears as counsel before the judge. The son of Chief Justice
Chaskalson on occasion appeared before him in the Constitutional Court, as did the
daughter of Justice Yacoob. Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng‘s wife appeared before
him in the High Court. None of these judges recused themselves. Justice O‘Regan did
recuse herself when her husband appeared before her in the Constitutional Court. 111
The fact that the judges failed to recuse themselves does not mean they were biased.
There is a presumption that judges will be impartial in adjudication.112 However,
absolute neutrality on the part of a judicial officer can hardly, if ever, be achieved. 113
Therefore, previous political positions held by a judge cannot be regarded as proof that
the judge will be biased. Indeed, it is appropriate for judges to utilise their life
experiences in the adjudication process.
4.3.3.2
Judicial impartiality in South Africa
Impartiality is that ―quality of open-minded readiness to persuasion without unfitting
adherence to either party, or to the judge‘s own predilections, preconceptions and
personal views that is the keystone of a civilised system of adjudication‖. 114 Impartiality,
in short, requires a mind open to persuasion by the evidence, facts and the legal
arguments placed before the court by the parties to the litigation. However, this does
not mean absolute neutrality; judges are human and there is no human being who is
111
Hoexter and Olivier The judiciary in South Africa 229.
112
Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of the Republic of South Africa 2011 (5) SA 388 (CC) para
113
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Ltd 2012 (2) SA 50 (CC) para 42.
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
40.
114
705 (CC) para 14.
294
not the product of his or her own social experience, process of education and human
contact. What is possible and desirable is impartiality:115
The wisdom required of a judge is to recognize, consciously allow for, and perhaps to
question, all the baggage of past attitudes and sympathies that fellow citizens are free
to carry, untested, to the grave. True impartiality does not require that the judge have
no sympathies or opinions; it requires that the judge nevertheless be free to entertain
and act upon different points of view with an open mind.
Another core element of impartiality is that the judge has not let media pressure, public
opinion or any other outside influence, including social, political, ideological or religious
pressure, dictate the hearing and the decision in the case. The trial judge‘s primary
concern should be that the parties before him be afforded a fair trial.116
When adjudicating, judges are realising legal and social order. The individual should
have the real and tangible opportunity of pursuing his rights through the courts with
the expectation that the court will adjudicate on the matter impartially and fairly and
that the court will come to a reasoned and just decision. This requires impartial judges
that operate with skill, efficiency and professionalism, and asks of judges to deliver
judgments that are just, lawful, reasonable and well argued, all principles that are
requirements for a fair trial.
According to Gordon and Bruce, the independence of the judiciary is objective and
protected by constitutional and other legal guarantees, while the impartiality of the
judiciary is subjective and refers to a judge‘s state of mind. 117 Therefore, judges
themselves carry the burden of remaining impartial. The question of impartiality is
significant when judges are asked to interpret the often vague and undefined
constitutional provisions. When a judge is confronted with these broad formulations and
imprecise notions –118
115
116
117
118
Canadian Judicial Council: Commentaries on Judicial Conduct (1991) https://www.cjcccm.gc.ca/cmslib/general/news_pub_judicialconduct_Principles_en.pdf 12 accessed December 2015.
Botein Trial judge 132.
Gordon and Bruce Transformation and the independence of the judiciary in South Africa Centre for
the Study of Violence and Reconciliation: Project on Justice and Transition 2007 www.csvr.org.za
para 2.3 accessed October 2015.
Venter 2003 PELJ 25.
295
[t]his may inspire unwarranted reactions, such as the rejection of the law of the
Constitution as "real" or "black letter" law, or it may seem like a justification of the idea
that the Constitution means what the judges wish it to mean.
Judges come onto the bench with their own ideological views and may apply them in
resolving cases. In the American Supreme Court, attitudinalists are able to predict with
an enormous degree of success119 how the American Supreme Court Justices‘ vote
based on ideology.120 Although precedent carries substantial weight to constrain judges,
empirical evidence in the United States shows that even if the judges are deciding cases
in good faith based on their best understanding of the law, they still are voting
according to their own values.
There is no comparable empirical study in South Africa relating to the judgments of the
Constitutional Court. However, public statements by judges and court dicta shed light
on whether the personal views of judges may affect judgment.
Sachs J had this to say about the impartiality of the judges of the Constitutional
Court:121
Our function is to interpret the text of the Constitution as it stands. Accordingly,
whatever our personal views on this fraught subject might be, our response must be a
purely legal one.
According to Sachs, judges are not supposed to have their personal views interfere
when they adjudicate on the bench. Kentridge AJ articulated this in another way:122
While we must always be conscious of the values underlying the Constitution, it is
nonetheless our task to interpret a written instrument. I am well aware of the fallacy of
supposing that general language must have a single ―objective‖ meaning. Nor is it easy
to avoid the influence of one's personal intellectual and moral preconceptions. But it
cannot be too strongly stressed that the Constitution does not mean whatever we
might wish it to mean.
In S v Zuma,123 the Court held that while it may not be easy to avoid the influence of
one‘s personal intellectual and moral preconceptions, the Court has from its very
119
120
121
122
Quoted by Friedman: There are legal commentators who predict with 70% accuracy how judges will
vote based on their ideology.
Friedman 2006 New York University Law and Economics Working Papers 272-273.
S v Makwanyane 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC) para 349.
S v Zuma 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (CC) para. 17.
296
inception stressed the fact that ―the Constitution does not mean whatever we might
wish it to mean‖. Therefore, cases fall to be decided on a principled basis.
Each case that is decided adds to the body of South African constitutional law, and
establishes principles relevant to the decision of cases that may arise in the future.
Where principles have not yet been established, courts may draw on the international
jurisprudence on constitutional rights. It is therefore the duty of the courts to develop
constitutional jurisprudence based on principle and to decide cases in the light of
established precedent.
In President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union ,124 the
Court held as follows:
By the same token a judicial officer is required to adjudicate a case in accordance with
the facts and the law and not according to his or her personal views or opinions. In
this regard a pragmatic approach appears from the SARFU case: The nature of the
judicial function involves the performance of difficult and at times unpleasant tasks.
Judicial officers are nonetheless required to administer justice to all persons alike
without fear, favour or prejudice, in accordance with the Constitution and the law. To
this end they must resist all manner of pressure, regardless of where it comes from.
This is the constitutional duty common to all judicial officers. If they deviate, the
independence of the judiciary would be undermined, and in turn, the Constitution
itself.
Therefore, whatever the personal beliefs of the judge, justice must be administered to
all persons alike without fear, favour or prejudice. This includes holding the state
litigant accountable to the Constitution, even where such litigant is a high-ranking
member of government. However, the Court also found that given that all people have
emotions, experiences and beliefs, it is virtually impossible for judges to be absolutely
neutral and that it is appropriate for judges to draw on their own life experiences,
thereby adding diversity of perspectives when adjudicating cases.125 Judges are
123
124
125
1995 (2) SA 642 (CC) para 17.
1999 4 SA 147 (CC) para 104.
Para 42.
297
unavoidably the product of their own life experiences, and this perspective informs each
judge‘s performance of his or her judicial duties.126
Justice Langa, lecturing on the transformative nature of the Constitution, said the
following on the transformation of the legal culture:127
It is no longer sufficient for judges to rely on the say-so of parliament or technical
readings of legislation as providing justifications for their decisions. Under a
transformative Constitution, judges bear the ultimate responsibility to justify their
decisions not only by reference to authority, but also by reference to ideas and values.
This approach to adjudication requires an acceptance of the politics of law. There is no
longer place for assertions that the law can be kept isolated from politics. While they
are not the same, they are inherently and necessarily linked. At the same time,
transformative adjudication requires judges to acknowledge the effect of what has
been referred to elsewhere as the ‗‗personal, intellectual, moral or intellectual
preconceptions‘‘ on their decision-making. We all enter any decision with our own
baggage, both on technical legal issues and on broader social issues. While the policy
under apartheid legal culture was to deny these influences on decision-making, our
constitutional legal culture requires that we expressly accept and embrace the role that
our own beliefs, opinions and ideas play in our decisions. This is vital if respect for
court decisions is to flow from the honesty and cogency of the reasons given for them
rather than the authority with which they are given.
In embracing the role of own ―beliefs, opinion and ideas‖ on decision-making, it is clear
that the Chief Justice envisioned a greater degree of judicial activism in the judiciary
and judicial decision-making. The statement by the judge shows more acceptance of
the role of a judge‘s own beliefs in adjudication. However, judges still have to justify
their decisions not only by reference to authority, but also by reference to constitutional
ideas and values.
The concept of subjective constitutional interpretation rests uneasy with the principle of
justification, especially in the form of a court order. After all, the power and influence of
judges rest to a large degree "on the confidence reposed in the soundness of their
decisions and the purity of their motives‖.128 Therefore, should a judgment not clearly
reflect the rational application of existing law, including adherence to constitutional
126
127
128
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
705 (CC) para 14.
Langa 2006 Stell LR 353.
United States v Lee 106 US 196 223 (1882).
298
values, the purity of the motive of the judge might be questioned. A judge whose
motives are questioned undermines public confidence in the law and the Constitution.
Although an objective approach to adjudication is preferred, the values ingrained in the
Constitution lend themselves to a degree of subjective interpretation. It is inescapable
that substantive reasoning will accompany the interpretation of the values of the
Constitution. Nevertheless, it is important that substantive reasoning is not based on
the concealed and capricious pre-conceived political, moral or religious notions of the
adjudicator. What is needed is an acceptable and legitimate theory of interpretation of
the values embedded in the Constitution. Such a constitutional theory of interpretation
would not necessarily establish a generic content of the values of the Constitution
which is neither desirable nor possible. Developing a theory, which calls for the
establishing of generic content of the values of the Constitution, falls beyond the scope
of the present study. Constitutional interpretation based on the values imbedded in the
Constitution would provide legitimacy to such interpretation.
4.4 Interpretation of constitutional values and rights
4.4.1 Sources for constitutional interpretation
According to Fuller and Winston –129
[c]ourts can be counted on to make a reasoned disposition of controversies, either by
the application of statutes or treaties, or in the absence of these sources, by the
development of rules appropriate to the cases before them and derived from general
principles of fairness and equity.
The rule of law therefore places a restriction on the arbitrary exercise of power by
subordinating it to well-defined and established legal norms. In South Africa, the first
source for judicial decision-making will be the Constitution, followed by the accepted
current law in the form of statutory law, common law and customary law as well as
court precedent.130
129
130
Fuller and Winston 1978 Harvard Law Review 372.
Hereafter, any reference to ―current law‖ includes these sources.
299
In most cases commonly before the courts, the legal sources point to a clearly defined
outcome after the facts and legal arguments have been heard. The sources of law that
the judge must interpret to arrive at a just and fair conclusion are obvious. If the
plaintiff in a delictual claim for damages proved, by fact and legal argument, that he
has been assaulted intentionally and unlawfully by the defendant, he is entitled to the
damages that he can prove. The legal sources point in one direction: a delict was
committed and the plaintiff is entitled to damages. Therefore, there is conformity in the
objective legal interpretation of the sources. However, adjudication is also sought in
matters where the accepted sources of law are not always clear, may contradict one
another, or may offer no clear and acceptable legal sources for the resolution of the
dispute. These are referred to as ―hard cases‖, in which an objective way of reaching a
judgment based on the accepted sources of law is problematic. Therefore, there is a
lack of clear consensus on the interpretation of the applicable current law.
4.4.2 Constitutional interpretation in hard cases
Posner states the following regarding hard cases:131
If a case is difficult in the sense that there is no precedent or other text that is
authoritative, the judge has to fall back on whatever resources he has to come up with
a decision that is reasonable, that other judges would also find reasonable, and ideally
that he could explain to a layperson so that the latter would also think it a reasonable
policy choice. To do this, the judge may fall back on some strong moral or even
religious feeling. Of course, some judges fool themselves into thinking there is a
correct answer, generated by a precedent or other authoritative text, to every legal
question.
Therefore, in hard cases, where the court is asked to resolve an issue fairly, the court is
asked to decide something about which the parties themselves could not agree and for
the determination of which no standard exists.132 This sometimes requires subjective
interpretation from the judge, imposing on him- or her, his or her own moral, religious
or political belief. The judge then is the ―interpreter for the community of its sense of
131
132
Segall The Court: A talk with Judge Richard Posner The New York Review of Books
http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2011/sep/29/court-talk-judge-richard-posner/
2011
accessed November 2015.
Fuller and Winston 1978 Harvard Law Review 373.
300
law and order and must supply omissions, correct uncertainties, and harmonise results
with justice through a method of free decision‖.133
According to Dworkin, a hard case is a situation in law that gives rise to genuine
arguments about the truth of a proposition of law that cannot be resolved by recourse
to a set of plain facts determinative of the issue.134 If objective analysis is problematic
when adjudicating on hard cases, what consistent legal method can be used to reach a
conclusion of what the law is and what verdict should be reached?
In terms of the Constitution, courts are constrained in their decision-making by the
supremacy of the Constitution and the rule of law.135 However, the courts are further
constrained by legislation, the common law, precedent and procedural rules in order to
arrive at the outcome that is the most correct, both on the factual basis of the case and
the application of the law to the matter. Examples of these include the exclusionary
rules of evidence, the audi alteram partem rule and the right to legal representation.
In the South African constitutional setting, established legislation, prevailing precedents
and other accepted sources of law can be used by the courts in the adjudication
process. The judgment of the court serves as the basis on which the legality of the trial
is weighed.
In Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission,,136 the Court described the
duty to give reasoned decisions:
In the first place, a duty to give reasons entails a duty to rationalise the decision.
Reasons therefore help to structure the exercise of discretion, and the necessity of
explaining why a decision is reached requires one to address one's mind to the
decisional referents which ought to be taken into account. Secondly, furnishing reasons
satisfies an important desire on the part of the affected individual to know why a
decision was reached. This is not only fair: it is also conducive to public confidence in
the administrative decision-making process. Thirdly — and probably a major reason for
the reluctance to give reasons — rational criticism of a decision may only be made
when the reasons for it are known. This subjects the administration to public scrutiny
and it also provides an important basis for appeal or review. Finally, reasons may serve
133
134
135
136
Cardozo The nature of the judicial process 16.
Guest Ronald Dworkin 136.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
2015 (2) SA 498 (WCC) para 14.
301
a genuine educative purpose, for example where an applicant has been refused on
grounds which he is able to correct for the purpose of future applications.
The decision maker therefore has to deliberate before reaching a decision and justify
the decision made. In this way the duty to give reasons tempers the exercise of
discretion present in decision-making. Furthermore, the furnishing of reasons allows an
aggrieved party to evaluate and argue the rationality, lawfulness, reasonableness and
justness of the impugned decision.137 This means the decision of the court should be
based on fact and sound reason and it must be well founded in the prevailing law. It
must present a just appraisal of the facts, evidence and arguments placed before the
courts. However, this leaves open the questions whether the decision arrived at is
equitable and just.
4.4.3 The interpretation of constitutional values and rights by the courts
Venter describes constitutional values as follows:138
As an abstract concept, it indicates a standard or a measure of good. A constitutional
value may therefore be deemed to set requirements for the appropriate or desired
interpretation, application and operationalization of the Constitution and everything
dependent thereupon.
In Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention,139 Chaskalson CJ
described the values in section 1 of the Constitution as follows:140
The values enunciated in section 1 of the Constitution are of fundamental importance.
They inform and give substance to all the provisions of the Constitution. They do not,
however, give rise to discrete and enforceable rights in themselves. This is clear not
only from the language of section 1 itself, but also from the way the Constitution is
structured and in particular the provisions of Chapter 2 which contains the Bill of
Rights.
Although abstract, the constitutional values form the standard for constitutional
interpretation. The values are abstract because they do not spell out the impact they
are intended to have on any actual situation or how these values are to be
compromised against other values or rights. However, the values are fundamental to
137
Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission 2015 (2) SA 498 (WCC) para 16.
138
Venter 2001 PELJ 25.
2005 (3) SA 280 (CC).
Para 21.
139
140
302
the Constitution, establishing its character and structure. The core values of the
Constitution are not enforceable on their own but the authority of the state should be
employed to enable it to secure and effect the realisation of these values.
Interpretation of the Constitution is governed by its section 39. When interpreting the
Constitution courts must promote the values that underlie a democratic society based
on human dignity, equality and freedom. The courts must consider international law
and may consider foreign law. South African courts readily consider foreign law when
interpreting constitutional rights and values.
In S v Zuma,141 the Court explored the principles on which a constitutional Bill of Rights
should be interpreted. The Court stated that it was the task of the courts to interpret a
written instrument, acknowledging the fallacy of supposing that general language must
have a single "objective" meaning.142
The Court further acknowledged the difficulty of avoiding the influence of personal
intellectual and moral preconceptions in interpreting the Constitution, but stressed that
the Constitution does not mean whatever one might wish it to mean. The Court stated
that the language employed in the drafting of the Constitution must be respected,
holding that, if the language used by the lawgiver is ignored in favour of a general
resort to "values‖, the result is not interpretation but divination. 143 Therefore,
embodying fundamental rights should as far as its language permits be given a broad
construction.
The Court, in exploring the burden of proof in criminal matters, interpreted
constitutional provisions by taking into account the historical background of the rules
and comparable foreign case law.144 The Court also argued that the interpretation
promoted the values underlying an open and democratic society.
141
142
143
144
1995 (2) SA 642 (CC).
Para 17.
Para 18.
Para 33.
303
In Qozeleni v Minister of Law and Order,145 the Court found that, because the
Constitution is the supreme law against which all law is to be tested, it must be
examined with a view to extracting from it those principles or values against which law
can be measured and that the Constitution must be interpreted to give clear expression
to the values it seeks to nurture for a future South Africa. Interpretation of the
Constitution should therefore be forward-looking.
In S v Makwanyane,146 the Court had to deal with the undefined rights and values
articulated by the Interim Constitution. The Court held that because there is no
definition of what is to be regarded as cruel, inhuman or degrading punishment,147 the
Court had to give meaning to these word itself.
Makwanyane is an example of a ―hard case‖ for its extremely difficult interpretive
choices. The drafters of the Constitution left the resolution of the question of the
constitutionality of the death penalty up to the courts. The text of the Interim
Constitution offered no guidance, and section 11 was unqualified, stating that everyone
has the right to life. The general limitation provisions of section 36 stated that rights
could be limited but there were no previous precedent or comparable South African
jurisprudence to guide the adjudication.
The Court held that provisions of the Constitution should not be construed in isolation,
but in their context, which includes the history and background of the adoption of the
Constitution together with the other provisions of the Constitution itself and, in
particular, the provisions of the Bill of Rights.148 Provisions must also be construed in a
way that secures for "individuals the full measure" of its protection.
The Court further held that it was permissible in interpreting a statute (in this case the
Constitution) to have regard to the purpose and background of the legislation in
145
146
147
148
1994(1) BCLC 75(E) paras 80 and 81.
1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 8.
Section 11(2) of the Interim Constitution.
Para 10.
304
question.149 The Court referred approvingly to the dictum in Jaga v Dönges,150 where the
Court stated:
Certainly no less important than the oft repeated statement that the words and
expressions used in a statute must be interpreted according to their ordinary meaning
is the statement that they must be interpreted in the light of their context. But it may
be useful to stress two points in relation to the application of this principle. The first is
that "the context", as here used, is not limited to the language of the rest of the
statute regarded as throwing light of a dictionary kind on the part to be interpreted.
Often of more importance is the matter of the statute, its apparent scope and purpose,
and, within limits, its background.
The Court further found that, when interpreting a statute, it might be permissible to
take into account debates of Parliament, statements by the Minister responsible for the
legislation, explanatory memoranda providing reasons for new bills and the report of a
judicial commission of enquiry on the object of the legislation.151 Background material in
the form of reports by technical committees assisting the multi-party negotiating
process can provide a context for the interpretation of the Constitution.152
Chaskalson CJ, pronouncing on whether the death penalty constituted cruel and
unusual punishment, referred to reports by the South African Law Commission,153 press
statements by the Minister of Justice154 and international and foreign comparative law. 155
The Chief Justice stated that public international law would include non-binding as well
as binding law to be used as tools of interpretation. Furthermore, international
agreements and customary international law provided a framework within which the
Human Rights Charter of the Interim Constitution could be evaluated and understood.
Therefore, decisions of tribunals dealing with comparable instruments, such as the
United Nations Committee on Human Rights, could be sourced in constitutional
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
Para 13.
1950 (4) SA 653 (A) 662G-H.
Makwanyane para 14.
Para 17.
Para 22.
Para 23.
Para 33.
305
interpretation.156 However, in relation to interpreting the Constitution by sourcing
comparative international and foreign law, he said:157
In dealing with comparative law, we must bear in mind that we are required to
construe the South African Constitution, and not an international instrument or the
Constitution of some foreign country, and that this has to be done with due regard to
our legal system, our history and circumstances, and the structure and language of our
own Constitution. We can derive assistance from public international law and foreign
case law, but we are in no way bound to follow it.
The Court acknowledged that the majority of South Africans favour the retention of the
death penalty but stated that public opinion could not sway the Court. The question
that had to be answered was whether the Constitution allowed the sentence.158
The Court therefore listed appropriate sources for the interpretation of constitutional
rights and values. However, the judges were not consistent in the method of
interpretation and sources used in their individual interpretation of the constitutional
values.
Although the judgment of the Court was unanimous, the judges based their reasoning
and decisions on different aspects of constitutional interpretation and different rights,
values and sources of law.
Chaskalson CJ stated that the core argument against the death penalty is based on
section 11(2), which prohibits cruel and inhuman punishment.159 From this right flow
other constitutional rights such as the right to life, equality and dignity. Because of the
arbitrariness of the death penalty, these rights would be breached.
Ackerman J also based his decision on the prohibition of cruel and inhuman
punishment, but added that the constitutional right to life cannot be qualified.160 He
further relied on the fact that the arbitrariness of the death penalty results in unequal
treatment of persons, therefore violating the right to equality. The judge argued that
156
157
158
159
160
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
35.
39.
87.
8.
155.
306
when deciding on whether to impose the death penalty, the decision maker had to
make a subjective decision. This involved weighing up mitigating and aggravating
factors and, subsequently, a value judgement as to whether the death sentence was
appropriate. This left wide latitude for difference of individual assessment, evaluation
and normative judgment that are inescapably prejudiced.
Didcott J emphasised the constitutional right to life.161 He argued that the imposition of
the death penalty called for a value judgment that could be influenced by one‘s own
moral attitude and feeling. He acknowledged, however, that the courts‘ experience and
training warned against the trap of undue subjectivity.
Kentridge J argued that the imposition of the death penalty was not a question of the
right to life, but whether the imposition of the death penalty constituted cruel and
inhuman punishment.162 He found that the imposition of the death penalty was cruel and
inhuman because it infringed on the right to life, dignity and equality.
Kriegler J argued that the question called for legal and not moral or philosophical
reasoning.163 However, value judgements in the answering of the question were
inescapable. The judge stated that law does not operate in a vacuum and calls for value
judgements in which extra-legal considerations may loom large. The judge
unfortunately did not specify what extra-legal considerations would be deemed
acceptable. The judge found that the right to life was unqualified and therefore it was
unnecessary to consider further inconsistencies with other constitutional rights.
Langa J emphasised the right to life and used the principle of ubuntu as a source to
define the right to life and human dignity.164
Madala J also looked to the principle of ubuntu as a source to define the constitutional
values. Central to this was the ideas of humaneness, social justice and rehabilitation. 165
161
162
163
164
165
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
177.
194.
207.
215.
235.
307
Because the death penalty offered no chance for rehabilitation, it was cruel and
inhumane.
Mahomed J argued that the Constitution articulated the shared aspirations of a nation
and defined the values which bind its people, and were the basic premises upon which
judicial, legislative and executive power was to be wielded.166 The judge was rational in
his interpretational approach, reasoning that there was no rational justification for the
death penalty. Facts and argument for the retention of the death penalty did not justify
a rational and judicious judgment for its retention.
Mokgoro J referred to indigenous South African values that had to be recognised in
promoting the underlying values found in an open and democratic society. 167 The
concept of ubuntu embodied these values. According to the judge, constitutional
interpretation
involved
making
constitutional
choices
by
balancing
competing
fundamental rights and freedoms. This could only be done by reference to a system of
values extraneous to the Constitution. These principles constituted the historical context
in which the text was adopted and which explained the meaning of the text. However,
the courts would have to make the necessary value choices.
The judge argued that balancing opposing rights required value judgements, which
form the nature of constitutional interpretation. However, because the Constitution
allows the courts to seek guidance in international norms and foreign judicial precedent
reflective of the values which underlie an open and democratic society based on
freedom and equality, and by articulating rather than suppressing values which underlie
the judgment, the court was not being subjective. Because the courts set out the
foundations for their interpretations in a transparent and objective way and made their
decisions available for criticism, the courts were objective in their reasoning.
O‘Regan J argued that the right to life encapsulated all other rights in the
Constitution.168 Therefore, the right to life could not be qualified. The Justice referred to
166
167
168
Para 261.
Para 300.
Para 318.
308
acceptable common-law principles as sources for values to provide guidance for
constitutional interpretation.
Sachs J did not agree with the reliance placed on the prohibition against cruel and
inhuman punishment.169 He argued that the right to life was unqualified. He further
argued that whatever one‘s personal view might be, the response had to be a purely
legal one. The judge took a rational interpretational approach by arguing that based on
rationality and proportionality the death penalty could not be justified. The judge was
also more formalistic in his interpretation, stating that section 9 should be read to mean
exactly what it says: every person shall have the right to life. Because it was not
qualified in any way, the drafters of the Constitution did not intend to allow the state to
take the life of its citizens. He also referred to customary law as a source to interpret
constitutional values.
The analysis of the Makwanyane case shows that although the judgment was
unanimous, the judges reached their decisions by relying on different constitutional
values and rights, different methods of constitutional interpretation and different
sources for their interpretation. They were faced with an inescapable normative choice
in deciding which constitutional values and rights should be prevalent. The argument of
each judge presented an interpretive choice between the constitutional values or sets of
values. Six of the judges premised their arguments on the right to life, with two
reasoning that this right could not be qualified. Three based their findings on the fact
that the death penalty constituted cruel and inhuman punishment,170 while two said that
the death penalty violated the right to dignity and equality and as such was arbitrary
and unconstitutional.
169
170
Para 345.
Kentridge J went so far as to state that the matter before the court was not a question of the right
to life. Makwanyane para 194.
309
The Makwanyane judgment illustrates four methods of interpretation based on an
adapted version of the Savignian model171 described by Du Plessis:172
(a)
Grammatical
interpretation:
concentrating
on
ways
in
which
the
conventions of natural language can assist legal interpretation and can help
to limit the many possible meanings of a provision. The Court quoted
approvingly from Jaga v Dönges NO,173 where the Court held that words
and expressions used in legislation must be interpreted according to their
ordinary meaning.174
(b)
Systematic interpretation: as a manifestation of contextualism, calling for
an understanding of a specific provision in the light of the text or
instrument as a whole and of extra-textual indicia. The Court held that
constitutional provisions should not be construed in isolation but in their
context, which includes the history and background of the provisions.175
(c)
Purposive interpretation: that sheds light on the possible meanings of a
provision with reference to its purpose. The Court must have regard to the
purpose of the constitutional provisions.176
(d)
Historical situating: a provision in the tradition from which it emerged and
allowing qualified recourse to information concerning the genesis of the text
in which the provision occurs and concerning the provision itself. The Court
held that the history and background of the adoption of the Constitution
together with the other provisions of the Constitution itself and, in
171
172
173
174
175
176
Le Roux ―Six (individually-named) notes‖ 73: The traditional continental model of interpretation in
which various common-law canons of statutory interpretation must be classified into grammatical,
systematic, purposive, historical and comparative reading strategies.
Du Plessis 2005 PELJ 86.
1950 (4) SA 653 (A) para 662g-h.
Makwanyane para 13.
Para 10.
Para 13.
310
particular, the provisions of the Bill of Rights must be taken into account
when interpreting constitutional provisions.177
However, the analysis also shows that the judges acknowledged that subjective
constitutional interpretation is unavoidable in constitutional jurisprudence. Mokgoro J
argued that, because judgments of the courts are articulated and available for criticism
and are based on acceptable sources in the form of applicable international and foreign
precedent, the interpretation is not subjective.
This argument is not entirely correct. Although the Court considered applicable
international law and foreign law, it did not consider sources that argued that the death
penalty was an appropriate penalty.178 This reflects the critical role of interpretive choice
in adjudication.179 Interpretive choice is still a measure of subjective interpretation,
choosing the sources of law that will support your own subjective view of constitutional
interpretation. However, this does not make the decision of the Court arbitrary or
unrestricted.
The Court was transparent in its analysis of the inherent fundamental values of the
Constitution. However, the judges did not explain their reliance on the particular case
law of the countries in question. This leaves the possibility that the subjective
disposition of the judges was a deciding factor in choosing these sources.
The Makwanyane case laid the foundation for a particular style of constitutional
interpretation. The opinions of the judges were the product of a human rights text
setting forth a liberal culture of rights founded upon human rights and values and
premised on justification. The Court turned to these human rights and values for
guidance in their constitutional interpretation. According to Harcourt, the judges were
strongly optimistic and idealistic in the realisation of these rights and values. The Court
177
178
179
Para 10.
The Court relied heavily on jurisprudence of the United States of America and India that argued
against the death penalty, although the death penalty was considered a competent sentence in both
of these countries. The Court also referred to African countries (Namibia, Mozambique and Angola),
where the death penalty was abolished, but it did not refer to Botswana, a constitutional democracy,
where the death penalty was a competent verdict. Makwanyane para 33.
Harcourt 1996 Harvard Human Rights Journal 256.
311
was able to articulate forcefully and transparently the fundamental changes that have
taken place in South Africa, thereby setting forth a culture of rights and justification.180
The Makwanyane case also shows the conundrum of constitutional interpretation.
Judges work in a liberal constitutional context based on human rights and values and
premised on justification. It is in in this context that judges will have to interpret the
Constitution. Makwanyane further stands as an example of the state litigant litigating
fairly and honestly. The organs of state involved in the matter provided the court with
all available information, allowing the court to formulate a just and fair conclusion to
the death penalty in South Africa. In this case the state litigant was a model litigant.
4.4.4 The transformative nature of the South African Constitution
Chief Justice Langa referred to the transformative nature of the Constitution as a
permanent ideal.181 He stated:
Transformation is a permanent ideal, a way of looking at the world that creates a
space in which dialogue and contestation are truly possible, in which new ways of
being are constantly explored and created, accepted and rejected and in which change
is unpredictable but the idea of change is constant. This is perhaps the ultimate vision
of a transformative, rather than a transitional Constitution. This is a perspective that
sees the Constitution as not transformative because of its peculiar historical position or
its particular socio-economic goals but because it envisions a society that will always
be open to change and contestation, a society that will always be defined by
transformation.
Therefore, the transformative nature of the Constitution calls for a society that will
always be in flux, consistently changing to best realise constitutional values and goals.
This suggests that constitutional interpretation would also have to be consistently
changing, evolving and adapting.
Andrews states that the Constitution provides the basis for a fundamental restructuring
of the entire legal system. Its purpose is to render the system representative,
180
181
Harcourt 1996 Harvard Human Rights Journal 267.
Langa 2006 Stell LR 351-360.
312
accountable and accessible, and to allow the system to provide justice to all South
Africans, irrespective of race, gender and ethnicity.182
The transformative nature of the Constitution has been acknowledged by the courts. In
S v Makwanyane,183 the Court held that ‗‗[w]hat the Constitution expressly aspires to do
is to provide a transition from these grossly unacceptable features of the past to a
conspicuously contrasting future‖. In Du Plessis v De Klerk,184 the Court stated that ‗‗the
Constitution is a document that seeks to transform the status quo ante into a new
order‘‘. In Rates Action Group v City of Cape Town,185 the Court described the
Constitution as transformative and a mandate, a framework and a blueprint for the
transformation of society.
In City of Johannesburg v Rand Properties (Pty) Ltd,186 the Court described the
Constitution as follows:
Our Constitution encompasses a transformative provision. As such, the State cannot be
a passive bystander in shaping the society in which individuals can fully enjoy their
rights. The full transformative power of the rights in the Bill of Rights will only be
realised when they are interpreted with reference to the specific social and economic
context prevalent in the country as a whole, and the social and economic context
within which the applicant now finds itself in particular.
Langa said that the ideal of the transformation of the South African society is the
creation of a new society, based on the values and provisions expressed in the
Constitution. This new society is one based on substantive equality, a social and
economic revolution with the objective of a truly equal society. According to Langa,
under this new envisioned society –187
[t]he Constitution demands that all decisions be capable of being substantively
defended in terms of the rights and values that it enshrines. It is no longer sufficient
for judges to rely on the say-so of parliament or technical readings of legislation as
providing justifications for their decisions. Under a transformative Constitution, judges
182
183
184
185
186
187
Andrews 2006 Osgoode Hall Law Journal 565-566.
1995 3 SA 391 (CC) para 262.
1996 3 SA 850 (CC) para 157.
2004 12 BCLR 1328 (C) para 100.
2006 6 BCLR 728 (W) paras 51-52.
Langa 2006 Stell LR 351-360.
313
bear the ultimate responsibility to justify their decisions not only by reference to
authority, but also by reference to ideas and values.
Interpretation of the Constitution based on its transformative nature requires two value
assessments. Firstly, economic transformation to achieve substantive equality and
realise socio-economic rights is a necessity. Secondly, a changed legal culture and
society based on the values and provisions expressed in the Constitution and premised
by justification must be achieved. In realising a premise of justification, it could be
helpful to develop a set of rules to assist the state litigant in observing the positive
constitutional obligations placed upon it. When the state litigant is able to justify its
decision to litigate and its conduct during the trial, the state litigant could be the model
litigant.
The Constitution must be interpreted with reference to the specific social and economic
context prevalent in the country as a whole. However, such interpretation must be
lawful and nuanced.188 The interpretation must be reactive and transformative through
the determination not to repeat the abuses of the past.189
It is clear that the notion of transformation has played and will play a vital role in
interpreting the Constitution. Such interpretation must be achieved by ―reconciling the
compelling need for transformative justice with the core function of the Constitution to
integrate, in a fair and proportional manner, the diversity of rights and interests at
stake‖.190 The courts will have to achieve this with due regard to the need not only to
uphold the Constitution‘s democratic values and fundamental human rights, but also to
promote social justice.191 The aim to promote the transformative justice of the
Constitution is further premised on the fact that the principle of legality must be
observed and the human dignity of those affected may not be unduly compromised.192
4.5 Rationality and justness in constitutional adjudication
188
189
190
191
192
SA Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association v Minister of Justice and Constitutional
Development 2015 (2) SA 430 (WCC) para 223(e).
Ackermann 2004 New Zealand LR 643.
Pretorius 2010 SAJHR 569.
Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education v Hoërskool Ermelo 2010 (2) SA 415
(CC) para 61; Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 95.
South African Police Service v Solidarity OBO Barnard 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC) paras 30 and 38.
314
4.5.1 Rationality in constitutional adjudication
The purpose of the rule of law is to protect basic individual rights by requiring the
government to act in accordance with pre-announced, clear and general rules that are
enforced by impartial courts in accordance with a fair procedure.193 The principle of
legality, an offshoot of the rule of law, requires that the court reach a decision that is
correct from a legal point of view. Fuller and Winston describe the adjudication process
as follows:194
Adjudication is, then, a device which gives formal and institutional expression to the
influence of reasoned argument in human affairs. As such it assumes a burden of
rationality not borne by any other form of social ordering. A decision which is the
product of reasoned argument must be prepared itself to meet the test of reason. We
demand of an adjudicative decision a kind of rationality we do not expect of the results
of contract or of voting.
Rationality is therefore a measure of the lawfulness of the court‘s decision. In
Wednesbury195 the Court explored the relation between reasonableness, rationality and
justness. The Court held as follows:
It is true the discretion must be exercised reasonably. Now what does that mean? It
has frequently been used and is frequently used as a general description of the things
that must not be done. For instance, a person entrusted with a discretion must, so to
speak, direct himself properly in law. He must call his own attention to the matters
which he is bound to consider. He must exclude from his consideration matters which
are irrelevant to what he has to consider. If he does not obey those rules, he may truly
be said, and often is said, to be acting ‗unreasonably‘. Similarly, there may be
something so absurd that no sensible person could ever dream that it lay within the
powers of the authority. Warrington LJ in Short v Poole Corporation gave the example
of the red-haired teacher, dismissed because she had red hair. That is unreasonable in
one sense. In another sense it is taking into consideration extraneous matters. It is so
unreasonable that it might almost be described as being done in bad faith; and in fact,
all these things run into one another.
According to Black's Law Dictionary Online Legal Dictionary,196 reasonableness is defined
as agreeable to reason; just; proper and ordinary or usual. There is therefore a
correlation between reasonableness, rationality and justness in legal adjudication. In
adjudication, rationality means that the decision of the court must be based on facts
193
194
195
196
Dicey An introduction to the study of the law of the Constitution xcvi-xcvii.
Fuller and Winston Harvard Law Review 366-367.
[1948] 1 KB 223 para 229.
http://thelawdictionary.org/reasonable/ accessed February 2017.
315
and reason. Therefore, the court‘s judgment must be agreeable to reason, show itself
exercising reason and this reason must be based on acceptable principles. Judges
therefore must form judgments logically and objectively, based on facts, evidence or
reasoned legal argument and provide the reasons on which the decisions are founded.
This argument conforms to the principle of Begriffsjurisprudenz, a brand of legal
positivism.
The principled legal thinking of Begriffsjurisprudenz is in general assigned to three
interrelated elementary positions:197
(a)
That the given law contains no gaps.
(b)
That the given law can be traced back to a logically organised system of
concepts.
(c)
That new law can be logically deduced from superordinate legal concepts,
which themselves are found inductively.
According to Du Plessis, in terms of Begriffsjurisprudenz, legal problems are solved
when, through deductive reasoning, a concrete situation is subsumed under a norm
relevant to the exigencies of that type of situation. Therefore:
The state is the source of law and law, in its turn, allegedly rests on an independent
foundation of reason and logic. Courts are autonomous institutions that apply the law
in a systematic (even mechanistic) way as if it were a system of fixed (and predictable)
rules. The ―is‖ and the ―ought‖ of law are markedly distinct, as are ―law‖ and ―morality‖
as well as ―law‖ and ―politics‖.
Du Plessis is critical of the paradigm described above. According to him, the Basic Law
perceives fundamental rights as antecedent to the state and the state‘s law and
therefore as subject to the objective order of values enshrined in the Basic Law. Law
and morality can therefore not be neatly separated.198 Reason and logic alone cannot
form the basis for judicial interpretation; some measure of morality must be injected to
assure justice is achieved.
197
198
Haferkamp Enzyklopädie zur Rechtsphilosophie IVR (Deutsche Sektion) und Deutsche Gesellschaft
für Philosophie http://www.enzyklopaedie-rechtsphilosophie.net/inhalts accessed January 2016.
Du Plessis 2005 PELJ 85.
316
By relying on rationality alone to justify a decision by the court, one may find that the
decision was reached by applying the facts and evidence of the court case to the
relevant and current law in question. Reason and logic were employed. However, was
the outcome just? Has justice been served? How can one measure the ethical and
moral impact of the outcome of a trial? After all, the court judgment must be fair and
just within the context of the particular dispute before the court.199 Furthermore, section
172(1)(b) of the Constitution provides that when deciding a constitutional matter, a
court may make any order that is just and equitable. This means that the test for the
effectiveness of the court‘s order is whether the remedy is appropriate, just and
equitable. Therefore, the order of the court should be based on what is morally right
and fair and the order should be fair and impartial.200
4.5.2 The concept of justice in adjudication
With rationality one can answer the question of whether a court decision conforms to
the accepted current law and is correctly based on the facts of the case. In other
words, one can answer as to the lawfulness of the decision. However, as is submitted in
section 4.5.1, by relying on rationality alone to provide justification for the decision of
the court, the question of whether the outcome was just is left open. Has justice been
served? Rationality alone as a yardstick for justification of the court‘s decision does not
measure the ethical and moral impact of the decision.
Justice as a principle in adjudication plays a prominent part in the social ordering of a
community and consists of two aspects: formal and substantive justice.201 Formal justice
is the impartial and consistent application of established rules or laws. This aspect of
justice is clearly capable of being reinforced by the concept of rationality in
adjudication. Substantive justice, on the other hand, offers interpretation of the specific
delivery of corrective actions in response to a violation of the rights of another.
199
200
201
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC) para 42.
Based on the accepted legal definition of the words ―just‖ and ―equitable‖; Hiemstra Trilingual Legal
Dictionary 46 and 68.
Bosman en Hosten Inleiding tot die Suid-Afrikaanse reg en regsleer 21.
317
Substantive justice therefore focuses on the content of the legal norm itself, while
formal justice focuses on the procedural aspect of the trial.
According to Radbruch, law is the will to do justice and justice involves judging the
individual without bias and measuring each person by the same standard. 202 This
concept is reinforced in South Africa by the predominance of the values of dignity and
equality in the Constitution. Section 1(a) of the Constitution acknowledges human
dignity, the achievement of equality and the advancement of human rights and
freedoms as the founding values of the Republic of South Africa. Further reference to
human dignity can also be found in the Bill of Rights.203 Section 7(1) of the Constitution
provides that the Bill of Rights affirms the democratic values of human dignity, equality
and freedom.
In section 36,204 the Constitution requires any limitation of rights entrenched in the Bill
of Rights to meet the threshold of the extent to which the proposed limitation is
reasonable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and
freedom. In section 39(1)(a), judicial authorities interpreting the Bill of Rights are
required to promote the values that underlie an open and democratic society based on
human dignity, equality and freedom. The principle of dignity and equality therefore lies
at the heart of the Constitution.
Venter writes that the prime goal of the enlightened state must be securing and
preserving optimal fairness and justice for all.205 If this is accepted as valid, fairness and
justice can be regarded as fundamental principles of law that are greater than any legal
decree, and then any law that defies these fundamental principles loses its validity. This
view is echoed by the courts as well. The court judgment must be fair and just in the
context of the particular dispute before the court.206
202
203
204
205
206
Gustav ―Five minutes of legal philosophy‖ 233.
Chapter 2 of the Constitution.
The limitation section.
Venter Constitutionalism and religion 2.
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC) para 42.
318
The courts, therefore, should attempt to synchronise the real world with the ideal
construct of a constitutional world207 premised on fairness and justice for all.
Furthermore, the courts have a duty to mould an order that will provide effective relief
to those affected by a constitutional violation.208 The remedy issued by the courts
should instil humility without humiliation, and should bear the message that respect for
the Constitution protects and enhances the rights of all.209 These statements again
reflect the reliance placed on the concepts of dignity and self-worth in constitutional
interpretation.
According to Venter, the potential of these principles to be generally accepted lies in the
ethical norm of reciprocity: treat others as you want them to treat you. The essential
values of a constitutional state, namely the inherent dignity of a person and the need
for fair non-arbitrary government, flow from reciprocity. The principle of reciprocity
therefore manifests itself as a major truth equal to the acceptance of murder, theft and
dishonesty as constituting reprehensible conduct.210
This means that there is an underlying value system in a community that should inform
the legal norms in that community. This concept is not new. Hart stated: ―Moral and
legal rules of obligation and duty have certain striking similarities, enough to show that
their common vocabulary is no accident.‖211 The common vocabulary found between
morals and legal rules can be explained in terms of common normative development.
This means that certain morals, indicating how the majority would act in certain
circumstances, attained the property of what to do or how to act in such
circumstances.212 This does not mean, however, that the law and moral convictions are
the same. Although the moral code of a community may provide an overriding and
supreme principle that lends validity to legal norms, the morals of the community and
the legal norms differ in terms of content and practical application. Not all the moral
convictions of the community find expression in the law. The law may also change as
207
208
209
210
211
212
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 94.
Fose para 102.
Marlboro Crisis Committee v City of Johannesburg 2012 ZAGPJHC 187 para 101.
Venter Constitutionalism and religion 83.
Hart The concept of law 168.
Bosman en Hosten Inleiding tot die Suid-Afrikaanse reg en regsleer 2.
319
the boni mores of a community adapt to changing circumstances. Adultery, for
instance, may be socially unacceptable but it is not a crime, at least not in South Africa.
This principle was confirmed in Thebus v S,213 where it was held that –
[t]he superior courts have always had an inherent power to refashion and develop the
common law in order to reflect the changing social, moral and economic make-up of
society. That power is now constitutionally authorised and must be exercised within the
prescripts and ethos of the Constitution.
In Executors of Mc Cordindale v Bok,214 Kotzé CJ stated: ―Our notions of morality may
differ, but the simple question for a court of justice is ‗what is the law?‘‖. This concept
that morality is irrelevant to the idea of law is not consistent with the Constitution. The
South African state is founded upon values.215 These values lend moral conviction and
validity to legal norms.216
The Constitutional Court recognises the importance of self-worth in the lives of
individuals.217 Therefore, the value of human dignity in the Constitution is not only
concerned with an individual‘s sense of self-worth, but constitutes an affirmation of the
worth of human beings in our society.218 The concept of self-worth and dignity requires
individuals to display respect for other people‘s identities that differ from their own,
which is in turn reciprocated by others. This reciprocity requires mutual respect and
that no individual attempt to impose his or her vision on others.219
In terms of section 172(1)(b) of the Constitution, courts have the power to order any
just and equitable remedy that would place substance above mere form by identifying
213
Thebus v S 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC) para 31.
214
(1884) 1 SAR 202 para 216.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
Section 2 of the Constitution, which provides, inter alia, that any law inconsistent with the
Constitution is invalid.
In Le Roux v Dey 2011 (3) SA 274 (CC) para 138, the Court held that the concept of dignity
embraces the self-worth of an individual.
Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC) para 27.
Bilchitz and Williams 2012 SAJHR 168.
215
216
217
218
219
320
the actual underlying dispute between the parties.220 Justice and fairness are therefore
critical components in the legal reasoning of the courts.
It is submitted that this concept of reciprocity can form the foundation of the quest for
justice in strategic litigation. As was shown, constitutional interpretation is of necessity
influenced by the personal history, views, convictions, etc. of the judge. The concepts
of dignity, mutual respect and reciprocity as fundamental principles in constitutional
interpretation and adjudication set the basis for the realisation of justice at a
fundamental level.
4.5.3 Building an acceptable theory of constitutional interpretation
Klare is of the opinion that judges will always be confronted with conflicting pulls and
tensions of freedom and constraint. He articulated this tension between judicial
constraint and judicial freedom as follows:221
On the one hand, there is a grand constitutional text replete with broad phrases and
redolent with magnificent hopes to overcome past injustice and move toward a
democratic and caring society. Yet, on the other, just about everyone takes for granted
that adjudication is not and cannot be infinitely plastic and open-ended, that judges
and lawyers are not completely at large to say and do as they please by the lights of
whatever personal vision of freedom they hold.
Klare‘s point of view is undoubtedly true of the rights and values contained in the South
African Constitution. These rights and values are often vague and undefined. What
encapsulates dignity for one reader of the Constitution will not necessarily mean the
same for another. As such, substantive interpretation is an integral ingredient of
constitutional adjudication in South Africa. While this does not mean that judges are not
impartial, absolute neutrality in adjudication is impossible.222 The culture of substantive
adjudication must, however, be balanced by justification in the form of the court‘s
decision.
220
221
222
Head of Department of Education: Free State Province v Welkom High School 2014 (12) SA (CC)
para 107.
Klare 1998 SAJHR 149.
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
705 (CC) para 14.
321
The value concepts of the Constitution are clearly based on Western liberal-democratic
principles, with dignity, equality and freedom prominent. As these values are not
defined, their interpretation will depend on the subjective value set of the interpreter.
In a constitutional democracy, set in a multi-cultural community, this is certainly a
necessity:223
Judges will certainly have been shaped by, and have gained insight from, their
different experiences, and cannot be expected to divorce themselves from these
experiences on the occasion of their appointment to the bench. The reasonable person
does not expect that judges will function as neutral ciphers; however, the reasonable
person does demand that judges achieve impartiality in their judging.
Nevertheless, interpreters of the values of the Constitution, including and especially
judges, should be aware of their own preconceived notions.224
In the M & G Media Ltd case,225 the Supreme Court of Appeal acknowledged that
discretion plays an important part in decision-making and that discretion ―permits
abstract and general rules to be applied to specific and particular circumstances in a fair
manner‖. The scope of these discretionary powers may vary.226
Where broad discretionary powers are conferred, there must be some constraints on
the exercise of those powers so that those who are affected by the exercise of the
powers will know what is relevant to the exercise of those powers or in what
circumstances they are entitled to seek relief from an adverse decision.227
An example of broad discretionary powers conferred on the courts can be obtained
from the power of the courts to ascertain what constitutes a reasonable member of the
public, and what their views would be. This is not done in a vacuum; it is contextspecific. Judges often rely on their own experience as members of society to determine
223
224
225
226
227
R v S (RD) (1997) 118 CCC (3d) 353 para 38.
Venter 2007 Speculum Juris 74.
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Ltd 2011 (2) SA 1 (SCA) para 1.
Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) para 53.
Affordable Medicines Trust v Minister of Health 2006 (3) SA 247 (CC) para 34.
322
this.228 The same principle holds true for the often vague and undefined constitutional
rights and values.
In adjudication, the judge engages in a fact-finding exercise. The court attempts to give
a meaningful interpretation of a set of events, so fact-finding seems unavoidable.
According to conventional understanding, fact-finding involves establishing congruence
between statements made about the world and the world itself.229 However, most facts
litigants seek to establish in adjudication, and in particular strategic litigation, are social
facts rather than phenomena intrinsic to nature.230 When adjudicating on matters
relating to social facts, divergent viewpoints can cause problems for the administration
of justice. This is especially likely in a deeply split society, like South Africa, where
normative standards are uncertain. The undefined rights and values fundamental to
constitutional interpretation may aggravate this uncertainty.
Does this mean that constitutional legal discourse has been reduced to a system of
contradictory discourse that is never conclusive because there is no prevailing standard
method of interpretation of constitutional values and no supreme principle determining
which value should prevail? Judges are human and therefore absolute neutrality in
judicial officers is not possible.231 Cardozo describes this as follows:232
There is in each of us a stream of tendency, whether you choose to call it philosophy
or not, which gives coherence and direction to thought and action. Judges cannot
escape that current any more than other mortals can. All their lives, forces which they
do not recognize and cannot name, have been tugging at them, inherited instincts,
traditional beliefs, acquired convictions; and the resultant is an outlook on life, a
conception of social needs, the total push and pressure of the cosmos, which, when
reasons are nicely balanced, must determine where choice shall fall.
Therefore, ―[w]e may try to see things as objectively as we please. None the less, we
can never see them with any eyes except our own.‖233 However, constitutional
228
229
230
231
232
233
Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa; Glenister v President of the
Republic of South Africa 2015 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) para 207.
Damaska 1998 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series 291.
Damaska 1998 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series 293.
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
705 (CC) para 14.
Cardozo The nature of the judicial process 12.
Cardozo The nature of the judicial process 13.
323
adjudication requires that judicial officers interpret the Constitution in ways which will
give effect to its fundamental values. When the constitutionality of legislation is in
issue, judges are under a duty to examine the objects and purport of an Act and to
read the provisions of the legislation, so far as is possible, in conformity with the
Constitution.234
Proponents of the Critical Legal Studies Movement highlight the role of ideology in law
by claiming that the legal reasoning and justifications of courts are only argumentative
techniques. There can never be a ―correct legal solution‖ that differs from the correct
ethical and political solution to a legal problem. The Movement claims that legal text
does not constrain the judge‘s interpretation in any significant way. 235 Therefore,
adjudication cannot be separated from subjective interpretation or ideological influence.
This statement is supported at a fundamental level by the notion that when assigning
meaning to the values of the Constitution, each person seeking interpretation will face
the danger that what is sought will be a construction of the ―search‖ instituted to find it.
This means that each individual‘s search for constitutional value interpretation will be a
construct of his or her own making. Such construct will in turn depend on the subjective
disposition of the individual him- or herself. Therefore, when giving meaning to
constitutional rights and values, the judge‘s search is an extension of his or her own
beliefs.
The interpretation by the courts of the Constitution, including its undefined rights and
values, is critically important in strategic litigation. The rights and values are
fundamental to, and entrenched in, the Constitution, establishing its character and
structure. Judges of the South African Constitutional Court recognise the danger of
unrestrained subjective interpretation of the Constitution. Therefore, the Constitutional
Court seeks to implement the moral vision of the Constitution, as articulated by the
imbedded values, while justifying its decisions in terms acceptable to the legal
community. Furthermore, the process of interpreting the Constitution must ―recognise
234
235
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd 2001
(1) SA 545 (CC) para 22.
Kennedy 1986 Journal of Legal Education 518.
324
the context in which we find ourselves and the Constitution‘s goal of a society based on
democratic values, social justice and fundamental human rights‖.236 However, these
democratic values are again open to a degree of subjective interpretation.
The courts recognise that legal training and experience prepare judges for the difficult
task of fairly determining where the truth may lie in a welter of contradictory
evidence.237 Legal tradition, in the form of community expectations, the legal training of
the judge and the traditions of the bench, the advocates' bars and the different law
societies also condition a judge to be fair and just in adjudication. 238 Furthermore,
judicial conditions of service and codes of conduct provide valuable guidelines for
ensuring a fair trial. Therefore, judges are assumed to be people of conscience and
intellectual discipline, capable of judging a particular controversy fairly based on its own
circumstances.239 This will show in instances where the judge may differ from the
political, religious or traditional ideology of a party, or may have sympathy with a party,
but still adjudicate the case on the strength of constitutional principles to reach a just
and lawful conclusion. Furthermore, it is appropriate for judges to bring their own life
experience to the adjudication process.240 Nevertheless, Cardozo asks the following
questions:241
If I am seeking logical consistency, the symmetry of the legal structure, how far shall I
seek it? At what point shall the quest be halted by some discrepant custom, by some
consideration of the social welfare, by my own or the common standards of justice and
morals?
When adjudicating, a judge must recognise the internal view that comes into play when
hearing a case. The judge should look to his or her conscience, consider his or her own
moral position, the facts and evidence of the case, the litigants and the constitutional
rights and values at stake, and conclude that his or her own moral presumptions do not
236
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd 2001
237
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
(1) SA 545 (CC) para 21.
238
239
para 40.
Boten Trial judge 291.
240
United States v Morgan 313 U.S. 409 (1941) para 421.
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
241
para 42.
Cardozo The nature of the judicial process 10.
325
cloud the judgment. The internal view acknowledges that inherent personal views may
influence the judgment of the court. This introspective view gives rise to a theory of
acknowledgement, which allows judges to frame subjective predispositions into the
court‘s reasoning.
In articulating the theory of acknowledgment, the argument of Mokgoro J in S v
Makwanyane242 may useful. The judge argued that, because judgments of the courts are
articulated and available for criticism and are based on acceptable sources in the form
of applicable international and foreign precedent, the interpretation is not subjective.
This is true to a certain extent. However, in the quest for objectivity, judges should
acknowledge and address the extent of their own predisposition on the case before
them. Should the introspection show that the judge‘s own moral predisposition might
be in play, this must be articulated in the court‘s decision.
The Mogoeng CJ‘s ambivalence over gay rights was put in the spotlight when he
dissented from a judgment of the Constitutional Court that said it was not defamatory
to call someone gay.243 The Chief Justice provided no reasons for his dissent. While it is
not possible to determine the reason behind the dissent, it seems likely that it was
based on his personal moral convictions. If that was indeed the case, for the sake of
legal clarity and objectivity it would have been preferable if this was articulated in the
judgment. Although it might have opened the decision of the Chief Justice to criticism,
it would certainly have been more preferable than a bland denial of subjective
predispositions and an absence of justification.
In Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of the Republic of South Africa,244 the
Court had to decide whether the Chief Justice might continue to serve after the expiry
of the non-renewable term of twelve years.245 The Court held that any attempt to
extend the term of the Chief Justice would be unconstitutional. However, three
242
243
244
245
1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 300.
Le Roux v Dey 2011 (3) SA 274 (CC).
2011 (5) SA 388 (CC).
Section 176 of the Constitution.
326
members of the Court did not agree with the decision of the Court.246 Neither the names
of the dissenting judges nor their reasons for dissent were given. This again raised the
spectre of possible subjective predispositions that should have been acknowledged and
articulated in the judgment.
The theory of acknowledgment provides legitimacy and objectivity to the judgment by
exposing the subjective interpretational element to criticism. Political judging, then, is
not the problem; it becomes a problem when it is not recognised and acknowledged as
such. The theory of acknowledgement allows for a process through which subjective
interpretation becomes objectively verifiable and provides acceptable grounds for
interpretation and justification. If subjective adjudication is influenced by the moral
presumptions of our judges, it is their duty to articulate and make public such
influences for insight and possible criticism.
The theory of recognition also allows for the realisation of the words of Chief Justice
Langa:247
Articulating the subjective interpretational element in adjudication allows the realisation
of our constitutional legal culture, which requires that we expressly accept and
embrace the role that our own beliefs, opinions and ideas play in our decisions.
4.6 Conclusion
The adoption of the Constitution changed the civil role of the courts. Their preconstitutional mandate in civil matters was primarily to adjudicate disputes between
parties. This is still the case, but under a constitutional dispensation, the courts, and in
particular the Constitutional Court, may be called upon to pronounce on the validity of
legislation and executive conduct and thus to guard over the Constitution. As was
shown in Chapter 2, strategic litigation is often prompted by the desire to ―shape‖
societal values and to influence or change laws or executive conduct accordingly.
Societal values are, in turn, regulated by the often vague and undefined constitutional
values.
246
247
Para 95.
Langa 2006 Stell LR 353.
327
The analysis done in section 4.3 above shows the different approaches to reasoning,
constitutional interpretation and selective sourcing by the judges of the Constitutional
Court. Because of the ambiguity inherent in language, the constitutional text has no
static meaning. Meaning is in the eye of the interpreter. Therefore, plurality of
constitutional interpretation is essential to give effect to a liberal and social democratic
culture of constitutional interpretation that is premised on justification.
Through manipulation of the judicial appointment procedure, training or hierarchy,
some like-thinking groups may obtain a monopoly on constitutional interpretation,
which may lead to interpretive consensus. This interpretive consensus may limit the
extent of constitutional interpretation and force consensus, thus providing for a
monopoly on constitutional interpretation. Consensus among judges would then not be
based on constitutional values and principles but rather on shared political ideology or
similar like-minded thinking. Different moral views are needed in constitutional
interpretation to give legitimacy to the courts and the Constitution and to ensure
judicial independence.
The responsibility for judicial independence rests on the courts themselves when they
are faced by the executive or Parliament as a party to the litigation. In litigation, it is
the duty of the court and the purpose of the law to level the playing field and to ensure
that parties to the litigation are equal in the eyes of the law and the court. 248 When the
controversy before the court is a matter traditionally falling in the sphere of the
executive or Parliament, it becomes more problematic. After all, the executive and
Parliament are democratically and constitutionally mandated to shape policy. However,
when such a policy is challenged on constitutional grounds, the executive and
Parliament cannot claim political considerations to trump constitutional imperatives. As
such, political ideology is not at issue in the adjudication process. The state as litigant is
placed on an equal constitutional footing with the litigant challenging the policy. The
court as impartial arbiter of the dispute is bound to and must be guided by the
principles and values articulated by the Constitution to ensure that the matter reaches a
248
Section 3.2 above.
328
just and fair conclusion. Furthermore, when the court is guided by constitutional
principles such as justification, openness and accountability, the court is able to hold
the state litigant to the constitutional promise that the state litigant would display a
high standard of professional ethics.249 The court can then ensure that the state litigant
is a model litigant.
A cornerstone of any fair and just legal system is the impartial adjudication of disputes
brought before the courts.250 This calls for judgments that are well reasoned and
correct, are within the confines of the law and are marked by impartiality and the equal
treatment of all parties. In South Africa, the benchmark for a fair trial is set by
constitutional values. Human dignity, equality, freedom, democracy, supremacy of the
Constitution, the rule of law, non-racialism and non-sexism constitute the norm.251
Rationality is an important but not exclusive measure of the lawfulness of
adjudication.252 However, although rationality can be used as a measure of the
lawfulness of a court's decision, it does not adequately answer questions relating to the
justness of the decision. In terms of rationality, judges must form decisions logically
and objectively, based on the facts, evidence and reasoned legal argument produced
during the trial, and provide the reasons on which the decision of the court is founded.
The reasons provided by the court must conform to the applicable law. Therefore,
rationality can show whether the decision of the court was lawful and, furthermore,
whether formal justice has been achieved, in other words, whether an impartial and
consistent application of established rules or norms took place. However, rationality is
not sufficient in itself as a measurement of the substantive justice of the court‘s
decision.
Law is the will to do justice and justice involves judging the individual without bias and
measuring each person by the same standard.253 This statement articulates the values
249
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
250
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4 SA 147 (CC)
251
252
253
para 35.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
Section 5.1 below.
Radbruch 2006 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 233.
329
of dignity and equality that lie at the heart of the Constitution. Venter believes that the
prime goal of the enlightened state must be securing and preserving optimal fairness
and justice for all.254 If that is so, dignity, equality, fairness and justice can be viewed as
fundamental principles of law that are greater than any legal decree.
The South African state is founded on values.255 These values lend moral conviction and
validity to legal norms.256 Therefore, the values of dignity, equality, fairness and justice
should be the norm in constitutional interpretation and adjudication.
In section 4.5.2, it was shown that there is an underlying moral value system in the
Constitution that should inform all legal norms, as well as the Constitution itself. This
includes the interpretation of the undefined constitutional values. This moral value
system is based on the principles of fairness and justice, which can be realised by
subscribing to the ethical norm of reciprocity: treating others as you want them to treat
you.257 Reciprocity is therefore integrated in the very core of the text of the Constitution
and underlines the concepts of dignity and equality articulated in the Constitution.
The Constitutional Court recognises the importance of dignity and self-worth in the lives
of individuals. Therefore, the value of human dignity in the Constitution is not only
concerned with an individual‘s sense of self-worth, but constitutes an affirmation of the
worth of human beings in our society.258 The concept of self-worth and dignity requires
individuals to show respect for other people‘s identities that differ from their own and
this is reciprocated by the other. Reciprocity is based on mutual respect and requires
that no individual seek to impose his vision on others.259 All parties must respect and
benefit from this relationship. Should reciprocity not be practiced, in other words,
should one of the parties disrespect the dignity and self-worth of the other by imposing
his or her own vision on the other, it would lead to resentfulness and anger. Therefore,
should the judge expect the litigant to abide by the Constitution but fail to keep
254
255
256
257
258
259
Venter Constitutionalism and religion 2.
Section 1 of the Constitution.
Section 2 of the Constitution, which provides, inter alia, that any law inconsistent with the
Constitution is invalid.
Venter Constitutionalism and religion 83.
Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC) para 27.
Bilchitz and Williams 2012 SAJHR 168.
330
reciprocity in mind by ensuring justice and fairness to the litigant and arbitrarily
imposing his own vision on the litigant, the litigant might justifiably feel aggrieved.
Judges have to interpret the Constitution and consider and adjudicate the ―hard cases‖.
The power that the Constitution puts into their hands is great and may, like all power,
be open to abuse. However, the legal system, legal traditions and legal training prepare
judges for the need for principled adjudication. There is no guarantee for justice except
the honest, principled, independent and competent judge. Reciprocity is the basis of the
trust in the judges and the basis for the legitimate power of the courts. However, as
has been shown in section 4.3, judges enter a decision under the effect of their own
personal history, both on technical legal issues and on broader social issues.
Furthermore, transformative adjudication requires judges to acknowledge the effect of
what has been referred to as their personal, intellectual, moral or intellectual
preconceptions on their decision-making.260
It is accepted that the often vague and undefined rights and values imbedded in the
Constitution lend themselves to a degree of subjective interpretation. Subjective
interpretation might be influenced by the moral, religious or political predisposition of
the judge. After all, absolute neutrality in adjudication is impossible.261 Judges should be
aware of this and look inward when adjudicating. This introspection recognises that
inherent personal background might influence the judgment of the court. This allows
judges to acknowledge the possibility of subjective personal views influencing the
adjudication process.
The rule of acknowledgement allows a judge to articulate the possible influence of
moral, religious or political predispositions on the decision of the court.262 This provides
rationality and objectivity by justifying the court‘s decision and opening the decision for
public scrutiny and rational criticism. In the end, the theory allows judges to accept
expressly and embrace the role that their own beliefs, opinions and ideas play in
260
Langa 2006 Stell LR 353.
261
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd 2000 (3) SA
262
705 (CC) para 14.
Section 4.5.3 above and Section 5.3.
331
judgments. However, when embracing and acknowledging the effect that subjective
views may have on the decision of the court, the judge should also ensure that
substantive justice is served by the decision of the court.
In section 3.5.2 and 3.5.3 above, it was argued that a guiding principle in the South
African constitutional state is the premise that citizens are allowed to participate in
decisions that may affect them. This calls for a more expansive and uniform theory of
constitutional review that fosters a culture of participation and justification. The culture
of justification satisfies a value-based assessment of the Constitution. This culture of
justification and the principle of reciprocity are mutually supportive.
The principle of reciprocity facilitates the right to participation by preventing the
arbitrary imposition of the personal view of the judge. This means that when meaning
is assigned to undefined constitutional values, the judge must acknowledge the inner
self and articulate the reasoning process that gave rise to the decision of the court for
public scrutiny. Reciprocity then allows the judge to adhere to the constitutional
commitment to justice, including treating litigants equally, thereby bestowing dignity
and self-worth on the litigant and fostering a culture of justice, openness, justification
and participation in adjudication. In strategic litigation this means that, whatever the
outcome of the litigation, justice as a concept is realised by the way the litigants are
treated by the court and eventually by its judgment. Furthermore, the constitutional
promise of ethical and professional behaviour required of the state litigant can be
realised. The principles of justice, openness and justification allow the courts to demand
from the state litigant to behave as the model litigant.
332
Chapter 5:
Constitutional limitations on strategic litigation
5.1 Introduction
In chapter 2, it was argued that the strategic litigant seeks to regulate executive and
legislative action in accordance with the Constitution. The relief claimed aims at
restructuring the public organisation or conduct by the legislature and/or executive to
eliminate a threat to the principles and values enshrined in the Constitution or to align
unconstitutional conduct of the executive or the legislature with the Constitution. It was
further shown that the Constitution contains fundamental values that set positive
standards with which all law and conduct of the state must comply, including when it
engages in litigation. From chapter 2 it is evident that the existing control mechanisms
have not prevented the state from acting outside the scope of the Constitution and
have not ensured state compliance with the legal duties constitutionally conferred upon
it. It is furthermore evident that the wide constitutional powers conferred upon the
courts are not always adequate when they are confronted with organs of state that,
when litigating, are sometimes ignoring court orders and constitutionally imposed
positive duties. The Constitution requires that the organ of state must be held to a
different standard than the private litigant. Constitutional obligations demand that the
state litigant display a high standard of professional ethics when litigating. 1 The state
litigant must also assist the courts and ensure the effectiveness of the courts.2 This can
be achieved when the state litigant places all relevant information in its possession
before the court to allow the court to come to a just and correct decision. Therefore,
the state must conduct itself as the model litigant.
Chapter 3, indicated that the doctrine of deference to which the courts subscribe does
not function as an effective check on the misuse of power by state organs. It was
further argued that the doctrine of deference does not satisfy the constitutional values
fundamental to the South African Constitution. Instead, a policy of judicial review that is
based on non-discrimination, openness, justification, accountability and participation
1
2
Section 195 of the Constitution.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
332
was suggested. Such a value-based assessment of the Constitution supported by a
culture of justification allows for the values of accountability, responsiveness and
openness to be explored and realised. This will allow the courts to review executive and
legislative action within the framework of the Constitution and thus fashion a model of
the doctrine of the separation of powers that will survive the fused nature of the
legislative and the executive in South Africa.
In chapter 4, it was submitted that there is an underlying moral value system in the
Constitution that should inform all legal norms, as well as the Constitution itself,
including the interpretation of the undefined constitutional values. This moral value
system is based on the principles of fairness and justice, which can be realised by
subscribing to the ethical norm of reciprocity. Reciprocity underlies the concepts of
dignity and equality articulated in the Constitution and can be used to ensure justice
and fairness.
This chapter uses three case studies to illustrate, with reference to the conclusions
drawn from the previous chapters, the constitutional limitations of strategic litigation
against a state party. The case studies fall into the following broad categories: firstly,
that of strategic litigants who attempt to ―shape‖ societal norms and values by seeking
to change the common or statutory law; secondly, that of strategic litigants who
attempt to influence or change executive policy; and, thirdly, that of strategic litigants
who attempt to hold individuals or organs of state accountable to the Constitution. In
practice, these categories may overlap.
In section 5.2 an example is discussed of a strategic litigant who attempted to ―shape‖
societal norms and values by endeavouring to change the common-law definition of
rape to include male-on-male rape. The difference between the majority and minority
opinions of the court is examined, highlighting the contrasting approaches to
constitutional interpretation. In this matter, the minority decision sought to use a wider
approach to constitutional interpretation not recognised by the majority of judges. The
minority opinion embraced a more expansive theory of judicial review in an attempt to
give the fullest effect to constitutional values.
333
Section 5.3 deals with an example of a strategic litigant attempting to influence or
shape executive policy. This section examines the tension between rationality and
formal and substantive justice in the context of the value system inherent in the
Constitution and whether the moral value system underlying the Constitution can shape
the decisions of the courts and promote substantive justice.
Section 5.4 scrutinises the attempt by a strategic litigant to hold an organ of state – in
this instance the executive – accountable to the Constitution. This section analyses the
legal battle for the release of the Khampepe-Moseneke Report. The case was heard
twice in the High Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal, and once in the
Constitutional Court. The state persisted in its efforts to justify its refusal to release the
report despite its failure to establish an evidential basis for the refusal and multiple
orders for costs granted against it. This case study highlights the occasional failure of
organs of state to comply with their constitutional obligations and further illustrates how
punitive cost orders do not necessarily deter organs of state from abusing the court
system.
5.2 Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions
In Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions,3 the case revolved around the constitutional
validity of the gender-specific, common-law definition of rape.4 The issues raised in this
matter involve the protection of the rights to dignity,5 equality,6 freedom and security of
the person,7 and children‘s rights,8 as well as the applicant‘s rights to fair trial.9
3
4
5
6
7
8
2007 (5) SA 30 (CC).
Para 1.
Section 10 of the Constitution provides that everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have their
dignity respected and protected.
Section 9(1) provides that everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and
benefit of the law.
Section 12 provides, inter alia: ―(1) Everyone has the right to freedom and security of the person,
which includes the right (a) not to be deprived of freedom arbitrarily or without just cause; … (c) to
be free from all forms of violence from either public or private sources; … (2) Everyone has the right
to bodily and psychological integrity, which includes the right … (b) to security in and control over
their body; …‖.
Section 28(1)(d) provides that every child has the right to be protected from maltreatment, neglect,
abuse or degradation.
334
5.2.1 Majority decision
The Court found that the current definition of rape criminalises unacceptable social
conduct that is in violation of constitutional rights.10 The definition ensures that the
constitutional right to be free from all forms of violence, whether public or private, and
the right to dignity and equality are protected. What is therefore required is that the
definition be extended instead of eliminated to promote the spirit, purport and objects
of the Bill of Rights.11
However, the Court found it not necessary to consider whether the definition should be
extended to include rape of males. The Court stressed that it is not desirable that a
case be dealt with because of what the facts might be rather than what they are. 12 The
development of the common law is a power that has always vested in the courts. It is
exercised in an incremental fashion, as the facts of each case require. 13 The Court
therefore refused to amend the common-law definition of rape to include male-on-male
rape, and instead left the amendment of the common law to the legislature.14
5.2.2 Minority decision
Langa CJ and Sachs J dissented from the judgment penned by Nkabinde J, reasoning
that there was no reason why the issue of male rape could not be included in the
development of the common law.15 They held that refusing to give equal protection to
both sexes failed to give full effect to the constitutional values of dignity, equality and
freedom: dignity through recognition of a violation; equality through equal recognition
of that violation; and freedom because rape negates not only dignity, but also bodily
autonomy. All these concerns applied equally to men and women and necessitated a
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
Section 35(3) provides, inter alia: ―Every accused person has a right to a fair trial, which includes the
right … (l) not to be convicted for an act or omission that was not an offence under either national
or international law at the time it was committed or omitted; … (n) to the benefit of the least severe
of the prescribed punishments if the prescribed punishment for the offence has been changed
between the time that the offence was committed and the time of sentencing; …‖.
Para 25.
Para 27.
Para 29.
Para 31.
Para 30.
Para 84.
335
definition that was gender-neutral concerning victims; the criminalisation of rape was
about protecting the ―dignity, sexual autonomy and privacy‖ of all people, irrespective
of their sex or gender.16
5.2.3 Similar examples of strategic litigation
In Van Deventer v National Director of Public Prosecutions NO,17 the applicant sought
an order directing the respondent to consider the applicant‘s representations for the
diversion of a criminal case and to take such steps as necessary to ensure that the
application for diversion be reconsidered. In the alternative, the applicant sought an
order directing the respondent to determine a proper policy and/or guidelines for
diversion cases, alternatively specific guidelines for diversion of specific crimes. The
applicant contended that the decision of the respondent to proceed with the
prosecution was arbitrary, irrational, capricious and in a manner inconsistent with the
provisions of section 179(2) of the Constitution.18 The Court held that the respondent
considered the available evidence and the circumstances under which the offence was
committed, the personal circumstances of the applicant and the interest of society in
exercising its discretion. The court further held that the respondent‘s exercising its
discretion not to divert the case could not be faulted. The application was dismissed
with costs.
In Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security,19 the applicant instituted proceedings
for damages against the respondents, claiming that members of the South African
Police Service and public prosecutors had negligently failed to comply with the legal
duty they owed her to take steps to prevent an assailant from causing her harm. The
applicant sought to bring the common-law delictual duty to act in line with the
Constitution.
16
17
18
19
Para 80.
(64268/2013) [2015] ZAGPPHC 550 (7 August 2015).
Section 179(2) provides that the prosecuting authority has the power to institute criminal
proceedings on behalf of the state and to carry out any necessary functions incidental to instituting
criminal proceedings.
2001 (4) SA 938 (CC).
336
The Court held that the Constitution is the supreme law and that section 173 of the
Constitution gives to all higher courts the inherent power to develop the common law,
taking into account the interests of justice.20 Where the common law deviates from the
spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights, the courts have an obligation to develop
it by removing that deviation. Therefore, the courts should remain vigilant and should
not hesitate to ensure that the common law is developed to reflect the spirit, purport
and objects of the Bill of Rights. The Court held that it was implicit in the applicant‘s
case that the common law had to be developed beyond existing precedent. The Court
was satisfied that the case for the applicant had sufficient merit to require careful
consideration to be given to the complex legal issues it raised. The Court therefore
referred the matter back to the court a quo to deal with the matter based on the facts
as determined by it.
In K v Minister of Safety and Security,21 the applicant sought damages in delict from the
respondent, on the basis that she was raped by three uniformed and on-duty police
officers after she had accepted a lift home from them when she found herself
effectively stranded in the early hours of the morning. The Court held that the question
of the protection of the applicant‘s rights to security of the person, dignity, privacy and
substantive equality is of profound constitutional importance. Furthermore, it was part
of the three policemen‘s work to ensure the safety and security of all South Africans
and to prevent crime. The Court held that the rape was clearly a deviation from their
duties. Furthermore, when
committing the rape, the three policemen were
simultaneously omitting to perform their duties as policemen. The policemen all bore a
statutory and constitutional duty to prevent crime and protect the members of the
public. That duty was a duty which also rested on their employer and they were
employed by their employer to perform that obligation. As such, the employer was
vicariously liable for the delict they committed. The case successfully widened the scope
of the vicarious liability of the Minister of Safety and Security under South African law.
20
21
Section 173 reads: ―The Constitutional Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal and the High Court of
South Africa each has the inherent power to protect and regulate their own process, and to develop
the common law, taking into account the interests of justice.‖
2005 (6) SA 419 (CC).
337
In Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa, Matiso v Commanding Officer
Port Elizabeth Prison,22 the foundation of the applications was that the statutory
authority of the orders committing the particular debtors to prison had been vitiated by
sections 11(1)23 and 25(3)24 of the Interim Constitution. Those subsections, it was
argued, made imprisonment without a fair trial unconstitutional. The Court held that to
put someone in prison is a limitation of that person‘s right to freedom. To do so without
any criminal charge being levelled or any trial being held is manifestly a radical
encroachment upon such right. The Court therefore held that the statutory authority of
the orders committing a debtor to prison was incompatible with constitutional
provisions.
In Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa; Glenister v
President of the Republic of South Africa,25 the applicant unsuccessfully argued that the
legislative scheme that created the Directorate for Priority Crime Investigation was
defective and therefore constitutionally invalid.26 The majority opinion held that the
applicant (Glenister), in pursuit of an otherwise legitimate constitutional cause of
ensuring that there was an adequately independent corruption-fighting agency, chose
to be careless and to overburden the court record with an ocean of irrelevancies, and
ordered cost against him. Furthermore, the majority held that legislative scheme that
created the Directorate for Priority Crime Investigation was constitutionally valid.
In Makwickana v Ethekwini Municipality,27 the Court scrutinised the eThekwini
Municipality: Informal Trading By-law, 2014, pertaining to the removal and
impoundment of the trading goods of informal or street traders by the municipal police.
The applicant contended that the removal and impoundment of the trading goods of a
trader who failed to produce a licence to trade were ultra vires and invalid. The Court
held that the By-law was an unjustifiable limitation on constitutional rights that led to
22
23
24
25
26
27
1995 (4) SA 631 (22 September 1995).
―Every person shall have the right to freedom and security of the person, which shall include the
right not to be detained without trial.‖
―Every accused person shall have the right to a fair trial …‖
2015 (1) BCLR 1 (CC).
Amendments to the National Prosecuting Authority Act 32 of 1998.
2015 (3) SA 165 (KZD) C 2015 (3) SA.
338
self-help and abuse of power by officials of the respondent. Therefore, the Court
amended the By-law to curtail the power of officials to impound and confiscate
property.
5.2.4 Conceptual analysis of the decision
The Masiya judgment shows the different approaches to constitutional interpretation,
which give rise to minority opinions and divided judgments. The majority opinion sets
forth the decision of the court and explains the rationale behind the court's decision;
however, judges may give different reasons for reaching the same conclusion. A
minority or dissenting opinion will be the opinion of a judge or judges who express
disagreement with the majority opinion. The dissenting judge(s) may disagree with the
majority for a number of reasons: different interpretation of the current law, the
application of different principles or values, or a different interpretation of the facts of
the case.28
In the Masiya judgment, the minority judgment sought a wider approach to
constitutional interpretation not recognised by the majority. The fact that the majority
of the Court refused to entertain a broad constitutional interpretation is problematic,
given the Constitutional Court‘s previous finding that the Constitution should be
generously interpreted to give individuals the full benefit of the fundamental rights in
the Constitution.29 The refusal by the majority to entertain a broad constitutional
interpretation was not convincingly explained, with the Court preferring to defer to the
legislature for the necessary amendment.
The courts should attempt to synchronise the real world with the ideal construct of a
constitutional world,30 premised on fairness and justice for all. This the minority opinion
attempted, by an interpretation of the constitutional values that is functional and lends
to the substantive meaning of the values a functional and not symbolic effect.
Furthermore, courts have a duty to mould an order that will provide effective relief to
28
29
30
Taken from Oxford Dictionaries Online https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/OED accessed January 2016.
S v Zuma 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC) paras 8-9.
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 94.
339
those affected by a constitutional breach.31 Interpretation should therefore view the
Constitution as a resource for coping with present as well as future constitutional
violations.
In chapter 2, a more expansive theory of judicial review was called for.32 This theory of
judicial review embraces the values and objectives quarried from the constitutional text,
and strives for the correct balance between the constitutional values of participation,
openness, justification and accountability, and the doctrine of the separation of powers.
The minority judgment of Langa CJ and Sachs J subscribes to such a broad theory of
judicial review.33
The minority opinion stressed the necessity of giving full effect to the constitutional
values of dignity, equality and freedom. The judges preferred a wider approach to
constitutional interpretation not echoed by the majority. This embodied a more
generous interpretation of the Constitution and attempted to give individuals the full
measure of protection that the fundamental constitutional rights offer.
The majority argued that in the South African constitutional democracy the legislative
branch has the major responsibility for law reform and that this should be recognised
and respected by the courts.34 The Court therefore based its refusal to extend the
definition of rape to male non-consensual intercourse on the issue of the separation of
powers and the principle of deference in judicial review. This argument is fallacious, to
say the least; the development of the common law has traditionally resided in the
powers of the courts, as acknowledged by the majority in the next paragraph of the
judgment.35
The majority opinion was that the common-law definition of rape was not
unconstitutional when it excluded male-on-male rape,36 but the majority also argued
that the common-law definition of rape had to be adapted appropriately to
31
32
33
34
35
36
Fose para 102.
Section 5.3 above.
Section 3.2 above.
Masiya para 30.
Para 31.
Para 32.
340
acknowledge male-on-male rape. The majority did not clarify why the definition had be
adapted if it was not unconstitutional, and in conformity with what norm, if not the
Constitution, the definition had to be adapted.
Section 8(3) of the Constitution requires the courts to give effect to the Bill of Rights by
developing the common law to ensure the realisation of those rights. Furthermore, the
majority‘s reliance on the principle of deference resulted in a situation where the
constitutional values of dignity, equality and freedom were apparently not entertained
by the court in reaching its decision.
In the Masiya case, the applicant was ultimately not successful in shaping the prevalent
norm. However, the wider approach to constitutional interpretation exercised by the
judges in the minority opinion vindicated the Constitution by taking into account
constitutional values in adjudication. The other examples of strategic litigation
mentioned above show that, in some of the cases, the strategic litigant was successful
in attempting to shape societal norms.
The Van Deventer case attempted to change prosecutorial considerations relating to a
charge of driving under the influence of alcohol. However, from the facts of the case it
appeared that the applicant challenged the impugned policy entirely for his own benefit.
He was unable to show a wider impact of the presumed constitutional violations. The
Helen Suzman Foundation case also was unsuccessful in attempting to change the
structure of the investigation of priority crime in South Africa.
Both cases against the Minister of Safety and Security (Carmichael and K) were
successful in broadening the scope of vicarious liability against the Minister of Safety
and Security. In both these cases the courts used a broad approach to constitutional
interpretation by focusing on fundamental constitutional rights and values, such as the
rights to personal safety, bodily integrity, freedom from violence and dignity.
The Coetzee case changed the common law as well as the societal norm of putting
debtors in prison. The decision changed not only the way debt is collected in South
Africa but also the way credit is provided.
341
The Makwickana case was successful in changing the practice of removing and
impounding the trading goods of a trader who failed to produce a licence.
It is clear that the courts will follow a broader approach to constitutional interpretation
and adjudication when the affected parties are regarded as vulnerable.
5.3 Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria37
5.3.1 Background to the case
The respondent, a local authority, had sued the appellant in a magistrate's court for
arrear rates and levies imposed by it on the appellant's property, which was situated in
a formerly white area of the respondent's jurisdiction.38 The appellant had refused to
pay his accounts in full because the respondent had assessed him at a user-based tariff
(as measured by meters installed at his home), while the residents of two neighbouring,
formerly black, townships under the respondent's jurisdiction were being charged a flat
rate for the same services. Residents of these areas who had paid a metered rate were
refunded their moneys and no legal action was taken against delinquent ratepayers
residing there, while several thousand summonses were issued in the formerly white
areas. The appellant contended that this amounted to unfair discrimination against him.
The trial court (magistrate‘s court) held that, although the respondent had
discriminated between the two formerly black townships, on the one hand, and the
area in which appellant resided, on the other, the discrimination had not been based on
race but on area of residence. Therefore, the appellant had not been able to show that
the discrimination was unfair in terms of section 8 of the Interim Constitution.39
37
38
39
1997 (4) SA 189 (T).
Page 197(a)-(g).
The right to equality. All references in this discussion to the Constitution are to the Constitution of
the Republic of South Africa 200 of 1993.
342
5.3.2 Decision of the High Court40
The High Court held that when conduct was tested against section 8(2),41 it had to be
determined, in the first place, whether there had been differentiation between the
complainant and others and, in the second place, whether such differentiation had been
unfair.42 The question of whether there had been unequal treatment was a question of
fact, and the question of whether the unequal treatment had been unfair required a
value judgement that had to be made based on society's norms.43 There was no onus
on a party to convince the Court that the conduct or measures in question were fair or
unfair; the Court had to make a decision once all the relevant facts had been
determined.
Furthermore, the Court held that there was no indication in section 8 that discrimination
had to be limited to the specifically stated grounds.44 The built-in limitation was to be
found in the word ―unfair‖ and not in the word ―discrimination‖ or in the specifically
stated grounds.
The Court held, as to the question of whether the discrimination practised by the
respondent had been unfair, that the imposition of a flat rate on some ratepayers and a
metered rate on others was not inherently unfair.45 It would have been different if the
flat rate did not reflect the fair value of the services rendered. Therefore, if the services
were equivalent but the payment charged not, the discrimination was unfair.
The Court held that unfair discrimination was clarified by section 178(2) of the
Constitution,46 which provided that municipal levies and the recovery thereof had to be
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria 1997 (4) SA 189 (T).
―No person shall be unfairly discriminated against, directly or indirectly, and, without derogating
from the generality of this provision, on one or more of the following grounds in particular: race,
gender, sex, ethnic or social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience,
belief, culture or language.‖
Page 206(c).
Page 206(g)-(i).
Page 207(g)-(h).
Page 207(i)-(j) and para 208(a)-(b).
―A local government shall, subject to such conditions as may be prescribed by law of a competent
legislature after taking into consideration any recommendations of the Financial and Fiscal
Commission, be competent to levy and recover such property rates, levies, fees, taxes and tariffs as
343
based on a uniform structure for the local authority's area of jurisdiction. Therefore, the
section did not allow for any exceptions to the requirement of uniformity, not even on
grounds of efficiency.47
The Court held that the appellant had prima facie clearly been unfairly discriminated
against because of his area of residence.48 The Court argued that to distinguish
between white and black residential areas in so far as the levying and recovery of
service charges was concerned was not justifiable. Therefore, there was a burden of
rebuttal on the respondent to justify its prima facie unfair conduct.
The respondents contended that it could not read the installed meters in the black
areas as this would have led to the destruction of its installations and the intimidation of
its staff members.49 However, the Court found that this argument lacked conviction
because there was no evidence of intimidation of its staff members or threats to its
property placed before the Court. Furthermore, the ability of the new consumers in the
black areas to pay for their services was never questioned, nor was any convincing
reason given for the cross-subsidisation of services or the refunding of paid moneys to
customers in the predominantly black areas.
The Court stated that the grounds of justification offered by the respondent were not
convincing; it was clear that administrative red tape was the reason for the delay in
installing meters in the black areas, and the respondent was not entitled to hide behind
its own negligence.50 Furthermore, the indications were that the moratorium on the
payment for services provided in the predominantly black areas was instituted under
pressure and for the sake of political expediency and not based on sound business
principles.
47
48
49
50
may be necessary to exercise its powers and perform its functions: Provided that within each local
government such rates, levies, fees, taxes and tariffs shall be based on a uniform structure for its
area of jurisdiction.‖
Page 208(d)-(f).
Page 209(f)-(g).
Page 209(g).
Page 210(b).
344
The Court held that the imposition of the flat rate amounting to cross-subsidisation, the
selective summonsing of residents based on historically race-defined geographical
divisions, and the imposition of different tariffs on residents of two different areas when
both sets of residents had meters was unconstitutional.51
The applicant had raised unfair discrimination as an absolute defence.52 The Court
therefore had to be innovative in providing the appellant with a remedy. The
appropriate remedy for the applicant was absolution from the instance with costs.
5.3.3 Decision of the Constitutional Court53
5.3.3.1
Majority decision
The applicant (City Council of Pretoria) appealed to the Constitutional Court. The Court
held that the following background issues were raised:54
(a)
Electricity and water charges in the council‘s area were levied on a
differential basis.
(b)
The residents of old Pretoria, including the respondent, were levied on a
tariff based on actual consumption measured by means of meters installed
on each property. This had been the position long before the
amalgamation.
(c)
Residents of the former black areas, in the absence of meters, were levied
based on a uniform rate for every household.
The respondent‘s objections to the council‘s conduct were based on the following
grounds:55
51
52
Page 211(a)-(b).
Page 211(d)-(e).
53
City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (17 February 1998) (CC).
54
Para 5.
Para 6.
55
345
(a)
The flat rate in former black areas was lower than the metered rate and
this therefore meant that the residents of old Pretoria subsidised those of
the two townships.
(b)
The differentiation in the tariffs continued even after meters had been
installed on some properties in the former black areas.
(c)
Only residents of old Pretoria were singled out by the council for legal
action to recover arrears whilst a policy of non-enforcement was being
followed in respect of the former black areas.
(d)
The imposition of differential rates was a contravention of section 178(2) of
the Interim Constitution.
(e)
The applicant did not take the residents of old Pretoria into its confidence
when the target dates for the implementation of a consumption-based tariff
were not met. Instead, misleading information was given to old Pretoria
residents, leaving them under the impression that the metered rate was
being uniformly applied at a time when it was not.
The respondent‘s complaint was that the council‘s conduct amounted to unfair
discrimination and was therefore in breach of section 8 of the Interim Constitution.
The Court stated that the dispute should be seen in the light of changes which have
come about because of the adoption of a new constitutional order. 56 Therefore, it would
be surprising if the process of bringing together, in a constitutional sense, people and
communities who were kept apart for many years did not result in difficulties and
tensions. These difficulties were the result of disparities and imbalances inherent in the
South African society, which resulted from policies of the past.
The Court referred to the glaring disparities between the two black townships and old
Pretoria, in property values, delivery of services and infrastructure.57 The inferiority of
56
57
Para 17.
Para 19.
346
the infrastructure in the black townships included no meters for water and electricity.
The residents were levied a flat rate for such services as they received and this
situation had been carried over after the amalgamation of the different areas.
Therefore, from the outset, the council faced a challenge to provide services and to
treat all the residents within its jurisdiction equally.58 The council announced in 1995 a
consumption-based tariff for its entire area (including the former black areas). 59 At that
time, meters had already been installed on some of the properties in the townships.
The consumption-based tariff was, however, not applied to those properties; they
continued instead to be charged according to the flat rate. The decision was taken not
to implement the consumption rate until meters had been installed on all the properties.
The respondent belonged to a group that called itself Besorgde Belastingbetalersgroep
(the BBG), whose members refused to pay the full amount for electricity, instead paying
a lower amount which was equivalent to the flat rate applicable in the former black
areas.60
The Court held that it was clear that the council treated the respondent, together with
the other residents of old Pretoria, in a manner different to the treatment accorded to
the residents of the black areas by –61
(a)
operating a flat rate in the former black areas while a consumption-based
tariff, which was higher, was used in old Pretoria;
(b)
differentiating between old Pretoria and those parts of the black areas
where meters had already been installed; and
(c)
taking legal steps to recover arrears from the residents of old Pretoria only
and failing to take similar action against defaulters in the former black
areas.
58
59
60
61
Para
Para
Para
Para
20.
21.
22.
23.
347
The Court noted that this differentiation was, at least partly, an inherited one. 62 The flat
rate in the historically black areas was a convenient practical expedient because of the
poor infrastructure. This differentiation was not initiated by the new council; however, it
became the council‘s responsibility to end it.
The Court held that the question whether there had been a violation of section 8 of the
Interim Constitution had to be assessed against the background of the case.63 The
respondent argued that ―[t]he conduct of the council could not be said to have been
authorised by section 8(3)(a) of the Interim Constitution inasmuch as the discriminatory
measures had not been ‗designed to achieve the adequate protection and advancement
of persons or groups or categories of persons disadvantaged by unfair discrimination‘‖. 64
The position of the applicant was, however, that the differentiation was rationally
connected to the legitimate objective of dealing with the period of transition by phasing
in the required changes in order to achieve equality between the residents of the
different areas.
The Court held that when dealing with issues relating to equality before the law or
equal protection of the law, the dictum articulated by the Court in S v Ntuli65 should be
followed. This entails that the right to equality before the law is concerned more
particularly with entitling everybody, at the very least, to equal treatment by our courts
of law. Furthermore, no one is above or beneath the law and all persons are subject to
law applied and administered impartially. This rationality criterion is equally applicable
whether we are dealing with equality before the law or equal protection of the law.
The Court therefore held that the differentiation in the present matter was rationally
connected to legitimate governmental objectives. The measures were of a temporary
nature and designed to provide continuity in the rendering of services by the council
while phasing in equality in terms of facilities and resources during a difficult period of
62
63
64
65
Para 24.
Para 26.
Para 27.
1996 (1) BCLR 141 (CC) para 18.
348
transition. However, this left the question of whether the differentiation complained of
constituted discrimination and, if it did, whether that discrimination was unfair.
The Court found that the impact of the applicant‘s policy was clearly one that
differentiated in substance between black residents and white residents.66 Therefore,
the impact of the policy that was adopted by the council was to require the white
residents to comply with the legal tariff and to pay the charges made in terms of that
tariff on pain of having their services suspended or legal action taken against them. 67 In
contrast, the black residents were not held to the tariff, were called upon to pay only a
flat rate, which was lower than the tariff, and were not subjected to having their
services suspended or legal action taken against them.
The Court stated that differentiation on one of the specified grounds referred to in
section 8(2) gives rise to a presumption of unfair discrimination.68 Therefore, the
applicant bears the burden of rebutting the presumption of unfair discrimination. 69 This
requires an examination of the impact of the discrimination on the respondent.70 The
Court held that intention to discriminate is regarded as an essential element of unfair
discrimination.71 Furthermore, there was nothing in the language of section 8(2) that
called for the section to be interpreted as requiring proof of intention to discriminate as
a threshold requirement for either direct or indirect discrimination.72 Therefore, the
elements of discrimination and unfairness must be determined objectively in the light of
the facts of each particular case.
The Court stated that the respondent belonged to a group that had not been
disadvantaged by the racial policies of the past.73 The respondent‘s group is neither
disadvantaged nor vulnerable, having been benefited rather than adversely affected by
discrimination in the past. The Court highlighted that generalisations are invidious but
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
32 of Walker.
33.
35.
36.
37.
39.
43.
47.
349
that courts must be astute to distinguish between genuine attempts to promote and
protect equality, on the one hand, and actions calculated to protect pockets of privilege
at a price, which amounts to the perpetuation of inequality and disadvantage to others,
on the other.74
The Court pointed out that the applicant had a responsibility to deliver services to all
residents in its area.75 This task had to be performed in a manner which did not unfairly
discriminate against any one of the residents. The applicant was also entitled to be paid
for the delivery of services. Therefore, the applicant was required to put in place
effective measures for the collection of municipal charges.
The Court held that there was no reasonable alternative to a flat charge.76 Meters had
not been installed in residential premises in the former black areas and without them
there was no way of measuring the consumption of individual users. Therefore, the
method used by the applicant was dictated by the circumstances with which it was
confronted.77
The Court held that the view of the High Court that cross-subsidisation was
discriminatory and that the levying of different rates for the same services was always
unfair was incorrect, stating that it looked to formal rather than substantive equality.78
The Court investigated the complaint of selective enforcement by referring to historical
factors such as the culture of payment in the former white areas against the culture of
non-payment in the black areas.79 The applicant adopted a policy to address this
problem by enforcing payment of arrear charges in the white areas, if necessary by
means of suspension of services or legal action, and by encouraging payment of arrears
74
75
76
77
78
79
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
48.
49.
52.
53.
62.
70.
350
by residents in the black areas, but not taking legal action against them while the
installation of meters was still in progress.80
The Court held that section 8 of the Constitution guaranteed that at least at the level of
law-making and executive action hurtful discrimination would no longer be a feature of
South African life.81 Equality is one of the core values of the Constitution and section 8
calls for more than formal equality. However, the Constitution requires that the
applicant‘s debt-collection policy be rational and not constitute unfair discrimination.
The Court argued that the reasons given for the policy of the applicant were pragmatic,
hoping to avoid anything that might provoke a hostile reaction from the residents of the
former black areas at a time when the contractors were engaged in the installation of
meters in the two townships.82 Furthermore, the policy was implemented not only
without public notice but also in secrecy and after untrue and misleading public
statements had been made by the officials concerned with regard to that policy. 83 For
the Court, this painted a picture of confusion and uncertainty, with officials being pulled
in different directions by different pressure groups, and of the truth being concealed
and false information being disseminated.84
The Court held that no members of a racial group should be made to feel that they are
not deserving of equal concern, respect and consideration and that the law is likely to
be used against them more harshly than others who belong to another race group.85
Therefore, the impact of the policy of selective enforcement on the respondent and
other persons similarly placed, viewed objectively in the light of the evidence on record,
affected them in a manner which is ―at least comparably serious to an invasion of their
dignity‖. This was exacerbated by the fact that they had been misled and misinformed
by the council.
80
81
82
83
84
85
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
72.
73.
74.
76.
79.
81.
351
The Court found that the policy of selective enforcement amounted to unfair
discrimination within the meaning of section 8(2). The Constitution was infringed by the
manner in which the tariff was applied and enforced.86
In ascertaining what appropriate relief for the respondent would be, the Court took into
consideration the particulars of the case. The Court decried the self-help the respondent
resorted to, stating that local government is functioning for the common good, but it
cannot do so efficiently and effectively if every person who has a grievance about the
conduct of a public official or a governmental structure were to take the matter to
court.87 The Court stated that the kind of society envisaged in the Constitution implied
also the exercise of responsibility towards the systems and structures of society. The
Court, therefore, refused to countenance the respondent‘s refusal to pay for services
received.
5.3.3.2
Minority decision
Sachs J was unable to agree with the majority that the selective enforcement of debt
recovery by the applicant amounted to unfair discrimination against the respondent.88
The judge articulated his concern with the finding of unfair discrimination as follows:89
I find it jurisprudentially incongruous to regard the complainant as a victim of unfair
discrimination as a result of such a process. He was disturbed in no way in his
enjoyment of residence in a neighbourhood which had been made affluent by stateenforced advantage in the past. The group with which he identified himself continued
to get the benefit of regular municipal services at all material times. He was not called
upon to do any more than to pay what he owed for services he had always received.
He was not being singled out or targeted in any way, neither because of his race nor
even because he lived in a comfortable neighbourhood. In my view, although treated
differently, he was not discriminated against in any manner whatsoever; alternatively,
if the council‘s conduct can correctly be classed as discriminatory against him, it was by
no means unfair.
The judge argued that section 8 provided two major principles to guide programmes
aimed at achieving substantive equality through the application of differential treatment
86
87
88
89
Para
Para
Para
Para
87.
93.
100.
103.
352
for those who start off in unequal situations.90 Firstly, once duly adopted, laws must be
administered in an impartial and even-handed way. Secondly, such programmes must
be designed to achieve the adequate protection and advancement of persons or groups
or categories of persons disadvantaged by unfair discrimination, in order to enable their
full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms.
The judge disagreed that the issue raised was one of discrimination at all, direct or
indirect.91 Thus, there was no direct discrimination on the grounds of race, nor was
there indirect discrimination on the grounds of race simply because whites lived in one
area and blacks in another.
Sachs J further stated that –
[t]here is overwhelming evidence to show that the complainant has in fact benefited
from accumulated discrimination and that he continues to enjoy structured advantage
of a massive kind. I find nothing in the papers, on the other hand, to prove that he has
been prejudiced by discrimination, whether direct or indirect, or whether in the past or
at present. The mere coincidence in practice of differentiation and race, without some
actual negative impact associated with race, is not, in my view, enough to constitute
indirect discrimination on the grounds of race.
He defined the ―impact‖ required as follows:92
Indeed, the very word ―impact‖ which is usually contrasted with ―intention‖,
presupposes an element of forceful contact or collision that in some way disturbs the
existing equilibrium of the contacted object. Implicit in it is the notion of adverse effect
equivalent in outcome to that of an intended blow. Thus absent some additional
contextual element, a one-off caress to A is not a blow to B, especially when A is in
need of tender care and B is in good health. There is simply no impact on B. The
action does not reach B. If, on the other hand, there has been a history of systematic
favouritism to A and neglect of B, then, of course, there would be symbolical impact of
a prejudicial kind, since even a slight gesture would track and reinforce structured
disadvantage and maintain internal disequilibrium.
The core of the judge‘s argument was therefore that the respondent had not made out
a case of having suffered prima facie discrimination at all. In order to invoke the
presumption of unfairness contained in section 8(4), some element of actual or
90
91
92
Para 104.
Para 105.
Para 105, footnote 10.
353
potential prejudice must be immanent in the differentiation, otherwise there is no
discrimination to be evaluated.93
The judge acknowledged, however, that, in the light of our history of institutionalised
racism and sexism, there might be sound reasons for treating direct differentiation on
the grounds specified in section 8(2) as prima facie proof of discrimination without
further evidence of prejudice being required, thereby triggering the presumption of
unfairness contained in section 8(4). In the case of differential impact of an indirect
nature, the judge held that there was no scope for any such per se assumption of
discrimination, and that some element of prejudice, whether of a material kind or to
self-esteem, had to be established.94
The judge interpreted section 8 in a historical setting. He argued that the text made it
clear that equality was not to be regarded as being based on a neutral and given state
of affairs from which all departures had to be justified.95 Rather, equality was envisaged
as something to be achieved through the dismantling of structures and practices that
unfairly obstructed or unduly attenuated its enjoyment. He held that the presumption of
unfairness as provided for by section 8(4) then made perfectly good sense when there
was either overt or direct differentiation on one of the specified grounds, such as race
or sex, or where patterns of disadvantage based on such grounds were being
reinforced without express reference but as a matter of reality. However, the
presumption made no sense at all when invoked to shield continuing advantage gained
because of past discrimination from the side-winds of remedial social programmes
designed to reduce the effect of such structured advantage.
Sachs continued by stating that the complainant was being deprived of nothing by the
measure that he attacks.96 His objection was simply that he was being left out of a
programme that relieves other persons from obligations whose objective circumstances
are markedly different from and inferior to his.
93
94
95
96
Para
Para
Para
Para
106.
107.
109.
110.
354
According to the judge, for a question of indirect unfair discrimination under section
8(2) to be raised, something more had to be shown than differential impact on persons
belonging to groups specified in section 8(2).97 Therefore, to establish that the impact
of the indirect differentiation was prima facie discriminatory on grounds specified in
section 8(2), the measure had at least to impose identifiable disabilities, burdens or
inconveniences, or threaten to touch on or reinforce patterns of disadvantage, or in
some proximate and concrete manner threaten the dignity or equal concern or worth of
the persons affected. The judge concluded that the decision not to issue summonses
against persons in black areas did not in any way threaten or was in any way capable of
imposing burdens or reinforcing disadvantage for the respondent. It was not
withholding benefits from him or undermining his dignity or sense of self-worth.
Expanding on the concept of indirect discrimination, Sachs J argued that he was
unaware of the concept being expanded to favour the beneficiaries of overt and
systematic advantage.98 He further held that, because of the history and legacy of the
country, almost every piece of legislation, and virtually every kind of governmental
action, would affect the groups specified in section 8(2) of the Constitution differently.99
For the judge, then, section 8 would be spread too thinly to achieve its purpose if each
measure of such kind were to be regarded as effecting indirect discrimination, which
was presumptively suspect.100
In articulating the principle of fairness, the judge said the following:101
The doors of the courts must, of course, be equally open to all South Africans,
independently of whether historically they have been privileged or oppressed. Indeed,
minorities of any kind are always potentially vulnerable. Processes of differential
treatment which have the legitimate purpose of bringing about real equality should not
be undertaken in a manner which gratuitously and insensitively offends and
marginalises persons identified as belonging to groups who previously enjoyed
advantage.
97
98
99
100
101
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
113.
115.
116.
118.
123.
355
However, the place of a complainant in the structures of advantage and disadvantage
will always be one of the central elements in the determination of how fair or unfair the
challenged discrimination is. Coupled with this is the fact that the societal objective
pursued by the issuing of the summonses was the unproblematic one of recovering a
debt, thereby enabling the applicant to meet its obligations towards the inhabitants in
its area.102 The soft approach to non-payment the applicant preferred towards the
people living in the black areas was to overcome rather than to perpetuate inequality. 103
The judge further stated:104
I simply cannot see how the complainant‘s rights were affected or his fundamental
human dignity impaired by his receiving a summons to pay for something that was
due. Nor do I discern any other injury of comparable gravity that he may have
suffered.
The judge relied on the work of Dworkin105 to state ―the right to equality means the
right to be treated as equals, which does not always mean the right to receive equal
treatment‖.106 Sachs acknowledged that, even in the absence of concrete disadvantage,
the symbolic effect of a measure could impair dignity in a way which constitutes unfair
discrimination.107 However, the more manifestly justifiable the public purpose in the light
of the objectives of the Constitution, the less scope for a legitimate feeling of having
been badly done by.
The judge argued that what was fair or unfair had to be viewed simultaneously from
the diverse points of view of all the inhabitants of the whole of Pretoria, bearing in mind
the values enshrined in the Constitution.108 All were entitled to equal respect, and all
had the right to have their concerns and sensitivities taken account of in an equal
manner. However, this did not require the same treatment for all.
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
Para 125.
Para 126.
Para 127.
Dworkin Taking Rights Seriously 226.
Para 128.
Para 129.
Para 130.
356
The judge held that, ultimately, the case was not about money but about the rights and
responsibilities of citizenship.109 In attempting to eliminate the inequalities of the past,
the applicant adopted a path of negotiations, which was correct under the
circumstances.110
5.3.4 Similar examples of strategic litigation
In City of Cape Town v South African National Roads Authority Limited,111 the applicant
applied for the judicial review and setting aside of the declaration of parts of the N1 and
N2 national roads to be toll roads in terms of section 27112 of the South African National
Roads Agency Limited and National Roads Act (hereafter SANRAL Act).113 The
applicant‘s challenge to the declaration rested on the allegation that the decision to
declare the roads toll roads was irrational because the Minister of Transport approved
the declaration of the affected portions of the N1 and N2 to be toll roads without
knowing what the cost of the project or the toll fees would be, and, furthermore, that
the Minister failed to consider whether the toll fees would be affordable, or whether
tolling would afford a financially sustainable or socio-economically appropriate means of
undertaking the work needed on the roads in issue. The Court dismissed the application
for interdictory relief. However, the Court held that the decision taken by the Minister
was not remotely compliant with the requirements of the SANRAL Act. Therefore, the
decision was reviewed and set aside.
In Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom,114 the applicant applied to
court to change the housing policy of the three tiers of government, requiring that
government provide them with adequate basic shelter or housing until they obtained
permanent accommodation and were granted certain relief. The Court ordered the
applicant to comply with its constitutional duties. Therefore, the applicant had to
develop a housing programme that had to include reasonable measures to provide relief
109
110
111
112
113
114
Para 133.
Para 134.
(20786/2014) [2015] ZASCA 58.
Levying of toll by the Agency.
7 of 1998.
2001 (1) SA 46 (CC).
357
for people who have no access to land, have no roof over their heads, and are living in
intolerable conditions or crisis situations. Unfortunately, the Court did not structurally
interdict the applicant to provide a time frame for the implementation of the
programme.
In Soobramoney v Minister of Health (Kwazulu-Natal),115 the applicant attempted to
change the policy set in place by the respondent owing to a shortage of resources. The
guidelines or policy provided that the applicant was not eligible for treatment. The
applicant claimed that in terms of the Constitution, 1996, the respondent was obliged to
make treatment available to him. The Court held that the positive obligations imposed
on the state in terms of various provisions of the Bill of Rights must be construed to
allow the state to fulfil its primary obligations to provide health care services within its
available resources. The Court argued that the applicant‘s case was not an emergency
which called for immediate remedial treatment. It was an on-going state of affairs
resulting from a deterioration of the applicant‘s renal function, which was incurable. In
the Court‘s view, section 27(3)116 of the Constitution did not apply to these facts.
Therefore, the Court held that the state‘s resources were limited and that the appellant
did not meet the criteria for admission to the renal dialysis programme.
In Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign,117 the respondent challenged the
applicant‘s HIV policy because of perceived shortcomings in its response to aspect of
the HIV/AIDS challenge. More specifically, the respondent argued that the applicant
had acted unreasonably in (a) refusing to make an antiretroviral drug called
Nevirapine 3 available in the public health sector where the attending doctor considered
it medically indicated and (b) not setting out a time frame for a national programme to
prevent mother-to-child transmission of HIV. The Court held that section 27(1) and
(2)118 of the Constitution required the government to devise and implement, within its
115
116
117
118
1998 (1) SA 765 (CC).
―No one may be refused emergency medical treatment.‖
(No. 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC).
Section 27(1) and (2) of the Constitution reads: ―(1) Everyone has the right to have access to (a)
health care services, including reproductive health care; (b) sufficient food and water; and (c) social
security, including, if they are unable to support themselves and their dependants, appropriate social
358
available resources, a comprehensive and coordinated programme to realise
progressively the rights of pregnant women and their newborn children to have access
to health services to combat mother-to-child transmission of HIV.
In Minister of Health v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd,119 new measures to introduce
control in the production, distribution and pricing of medicine provoked strong
opposition from within the pharmaceutical industry, including litigation challenging the
validity of certain provisions of amending legislation. The litigation challenged the policy
of the applicant aimed at giving effect to a pricing system for the sale of medicines. The
respondents were partially successful with their application, the Court holding that
certain of the regulations issues by the applicant were not authorised by the Medicines
and Related Substances Control Amendment Act
120
and were accordingly invalid.
In Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development v The Southern Africa Litigation
Centre,121 the applicant appealed an order by the court for the arrest of President Bashir
of the Sudan on an international warrant of arrest issued by International Criminal
Court. South Africa was under obligation to arrest President Bashir under the
Implementation of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court Act 27 of 2002
during his visit to South Africa. The respondent challenged executive policy, which held
that a visiting head of state was immune from arrest even when an international
warrant of arrest had been issued. Of interest here is that the state legal
representatives requested postponement on more than one occasion while refuting
media reports that President Bashir was in the process of leaving South Africa. The
Court was repeatedly reassured during the entire hearing that President Bashir was still
in the country. It was later established that he had left the country even before
proceedings commenced. The Court held that this was a violation of the interim order
issued by the Court ordering the state to prevent President Bashir from leaving the
country until the proceedings were finalised. The Court felt it necessary to rebuke the
119
120
121
assistance. (2) The state must take reasonable legislative and other measures, within its available
resources, to achieve the progressive realisation of each of these rights.‖
2006 (8) BCLR 872 (CC).
90 of 1997.
2016 (1) SACR 161 (GP).
359
executive for ignoring the interim order issued, stating that ―a democratic State based
on the rule of law cannot exist or function if the government ignores its constitutional
obligations and fails to abide by court orders. A court is the guardian of justice, the
corner-stone of the rule of law. If the State, an organ of State or State official does not
abide by court orders, the democratic edifice will crumble stone-by-stone until it
collapses and chaos ensues‖. The Court invited the National Director of Public
Prosecutions to consider whether criminal proceedings against the respondents were
appropriate.
5.3.5 Conceptual analysis of the decision
The Walker case is a clear example of strategic litigation in which the applicant desired
to influence or change the legal norms and executive action. It also highlights the
different approaches to constitutional interpretation the court followed to draw different
inferences from the Constitution. Although the case relates to a matter which falls
under the traditional powers of the executive – the implementation of policy – neither
the majority nor the minority opinion referred to the principle of deference so eminent
in later decisions of the Constitutional Court.
The majority decision of the Court relied on an interpretational approach based on
rationality, whereby all persons are subject to the law and the law is applied and
administered impartially.122
The Court acknowledged, however, that the rationality principle only gives rise to
formal and not substantive equality.123 Therefore, the levying of different rates for the
same services for different groups of people would not always be unfair. The Court
therefore acknowledged that rationality by itself could not give rise to substantive
justice, but when the Court investigated the complaint of the selective enforcement of
non-payment of rates, it reverted to relying on the rationality principle.124 The Court
held that although section 8 of the Constitution called for more than formal equality,
122
123
124
Para 27.
Para 62.
Para 73.
360
the selective enforcement of non-payment could not be justified by relying on
substantive equality.
The minority decision argued that section 8 catered for substantive equality that might
necessitate the differential treatment of those who start in unequal situations. 125
Therefore, programmes (and laws) must be designed to achieve the adequate
protection and advancement of people disadvantaged by previous unfair discrimination.
The selective enforcement policy of the applicant therefore did not discriminate either
directly or indirectly against the respondent, as it was aimed at achieving substantive
justice. This argument appears at first glance to be correct; however, the judge also
argued that a person relying on section 8 had to prove an element of actual or potential
prejudice when arguing discrimination.126 Therefore, actual or potential prejudice had to
be shown when persons belonging to different groups were treated unequally.127 This
argument of the judge favours substantive justice but does not take into consideration
the aspects of rationality and formal justice. In section 5.2 above, it has been shown
that there is an moral value system underlying the Constitution that should inform all
legal norms, as well as the Constitution itself. By subscribing to this moral value system,
the courts could allow for the values of dignity, equality, fairness and justice to be
realised. The decision in the High Court recognised this by stating that when a question
of whether the unequal treatment of persons or groups was unfair had to be answered,
it required a value judgement based on society‘s norms.128 Societal norms in South
Africa are, of course, derived from the Constitution.
In such a scenario, the moral value system first enquires whether the principles of
rationality and formal justice have been realised. This requires an impartial and
consistent application of legal norms. When there is differentiation in applying the law
to subsections of the community by an organ of state, such differentiation means that
the principles of rationality and formal justice have not been realised. No proof of
prejudice is needed. However, should the organ of state show that the differentiation is
125
126
127
128
Para 104.
Para 106.
Para 113.
Walker (High Court) para 206(g)-(i).
361
required to realise substantive justice or equality, the courts can test the fairness of the
differentiation.
The second question that should be addressed in terms of the moral value system
underlying the Constitution is whether substantive justice is advanced by focusing on
the content of the legal norm in question. In identifying whether the content of the
legal norm in question advances substantive justice when differentiating between
different groups, the process of judicial review based on a culture of justification as
argued in Chapter 3 can greatly assist the courts. Then, even though the impugned
legal norm differentiates between members of the community, such differentiation is
essential to establish substantive equality or justice for the disadvantaged, who need to
be protected or advanced.
This is where the moral value system underlying the Constitution comes into play. The
moral presumption inherent in the Constitution allows for what Mureinik called
conscientious argument by conscientious advocates to reach conscientious judges.129 In
this instance, a conscientious judge would look to the Constitution to promote the
fundamental values of equality, dignity, openness and justification. However, the
Constitution also calls for conscientious litigants. The values of the Constitution are
applicable to all people in South Africa. Reciprocity in this context does not apply to the
judge only, but also to the litigants involved in the controversy. After all, the
Constitution does have some measure of horizontal application.130 The principle of
reciprocity allows for the realisation of substantive as well as formal justice by allowing
differentiation when it is constitutionally justifiable to promote the fundamental values
inherent to the Constitution.
The Walker case was partially successful in changing or influencing executive policy. In
the similar examples of strategic litigation mentioned above, all but one was successful.
The case of Soobramoney v Minister of Health shows that, in some instances,
budgetary constraints on organs of state would prevent the courts from vindicating
129
130
Mureinik 1988 ―Dworkin and Apartheid‖ 182.
Section 8(2) of the Constitution.
362
constitutional rights and values. However, the successful cases show that where the
executive policy is far reaching and affecting the vulnerable or poor, the courts will not
hesitate to invoke the question of substantive justice. The Grootboom and the
Treatment Action cases show that the court would intrude on official executive policy
and influence or change the legal norms and executive action accordingly. These cases
further show that where the people affected by the impugned executive policy are
deemed vulnerable or poor by the court, the court will be much more inclined to follow
a wider approach to constitutional interpretation in order to give the maximum effect to
constitutional rights and values. The conduct of the state litigant cannot be faulted in
any of the discussed cases. The state placed all relevant information in its possession
before the courts to assist the courts in reaching just and fair decisions. The
constitutional values and rights at stake during the litigation were not clearly defined,
nor was the role that the organs of state had to play in fulfilling its duty to respect and
promote these rights and values. The litigation was therefore in the public interest as it
allowed the courts to define the state‘s role in promoting and respecting constitutional
rights and values.
5.4 President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Limited
The history of the case is as follows:131 President Mugabe of Zimbabwe faced a critical
presidential election in 2002. Concerns over the conduct of the election in Zimbabwe
prompted debate in the Commonwealth and led to the difficult decision to suspend
Zimbabwe from the organisation. The then President Mbeki supported President
Mugabe during this period.
In 2002, President Mbeki appointed two senior South African judges 132 to assess the
constitutional and legal issues relating to the national elections in Zimbabwe. The two
judges were sent to ascertain whether the election held in the country was free and
fair.
131
132
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Limited Case CCT 03/11 [2011] ZACC 32
para 1.
Judges Sisi Khampepe and Dikgang Moseneke.
363
After the conclusion of the election in Zimbabwe, the judges returned to South Africa
and prepared a report that was submitted to President Mbeki.133 The report was never
released to the public. M & G Media Limited (M & G), the publisher of a weekly
newspaper, the Mail & Guardian, requested access to the report relying on section 11134
of the Promotion of Access to Information Act (hereafter PAIA).135 The Presidency
refused the request on two grounds:136 firstly, that disclosure of the report would reveal
information supplied in confidence by or on behalf of another state or an international
organisation, contrary to section 41(1)(b)(i) of PAIA,137 and, secondly, that the report
had been prepared for the President to assist him in formulating executive policy on
Zimbabwe, as contemplated in section 44(1)(a) of PAIA.138
5.4.1 First hearing in the High Court
The applicant pursued the matter in terms of section 78 of PAIA139 in the North Gauteng
High Court, Pretoria.140 The applicant argued that the respondent had provided no
factual basis in support of the grounds relied upon to refuse the release of the report
and that any confidential information contained in the report could be redacted, while
the rest of the report was released as envisaged in PAIA. The High Court found for the
applicant and ordered the respondent to make the entire report available. The order of
the High Court included an order as to costs.
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
The Khampepe-Moseneke Report.
The right of access to records of public bodies.
2 of 2000.
M & G case para 2.
A public body may refuse a request for access to a record of the body if its disclosure would reveal
information supplied in confidence by or on behalf of another state or an international organisation.
A public body may refuse a request for access to a record of the body if the record contains an
opinion, advice, report or recommendation obtained or prepared for the purpose of assisting to
formulate a policy or take a decision in the exercise of a power or performance of a duty conferred
or imposed by law.
Applications to court: Applications regarding decisions of information officers or relevant authorities
of public bodies or heads of private bodies.
M & G Limited v President of the Republic of South Africa [2010] ZAGPPHC 43 Case No 1242/09, 4
June 2010 (unreported) para 13.
364
5.4.2 First appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal
The state took the matter on appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal.141 The case was
heard by a full bench of five judges. The Court held that open and transparent
government and a free flow of information concerning the affairs of the state are the
lifeblood of democracy.142 Central to the Bill of Rights is the constitutional guarantee to
everyone of the right of access to any information that is held by the state.
The Court referred to a culture of justification that permeates the Constitution and
PAIA. Any request for information held by a public body may only be refused by the
information officer when he or she can justify withholding the information by advancing
adequate reasons for the refusal; the public body bears the burden of proving that the
secrecy is justified.143 Therefore, an evidential burden is cast on the public body to
allege sufficient facts to justify the refusal.144
The Court found that the affidavits that had been filed by the applicant (the executive)
asserted conclusions reached by the deponents of the affidavits, with no evidential
basis to support the conclusions in the apparent expectation that their assumptions put
an end to the matter.145 However, the Court held that the Constitution and PAIA require
a court to be satisfied that secrecy was justified and that a proper evidential basis to
justify the secrecy was laid.
Furthermore, the three people who had direct knowledge of the mandate that was
given to the judges, Mr Mbeki and the two judges, had not deposed affidavits.146 The
applicant‘s case amounted to no more than rote recitation of the relevant sections and
bald assertions that the report fell within the realm of secrecy. The Court therefore held
that there was no evidential basis for refusing to release the report and consequently
dismissed the appeal with costs.
141
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Ltd 2011 (2) SA 1 (SCA).
142
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
143
144
145
146
1.
11.
14.
19.
20.
365
5.4.3 Referral to the Constitutional Court
The state then appealed to the Constitutional Court.147 The important issue raised in the
matter was how the state discharged the burden, in terms of section 81(3) of PAIA,148
of establishing that its refusal to grant access to a record was justified. 149 The Court
referred to PAIA and held that, in South African law, the disclosure of information is the
rule and exemption from disclosure is the exception.150 The constitutional guarantee of
the right of access to information held by the state gives effect to accountability,
responsiveness and openness as founding values of the South African constitutional
democracy.151 However, there are reasonable and justifiable limitations on the right of
access to information as articulated by PAIA.152
The Court said that at stake was the constitutional and statutory framework within
which claims for exemption from disclosure must be considered and evaluated.153 The
Court turned to foreign jurisprudence in formulating the standard to assess whether the
state had properly discharged its evidentiary burden in refusing to disclose.154
The Court first turned to the United States with its well-developed jurisprudence
concerning access to information.155 As in South Africa, the agency claiming the
exemption can discharge its burden only by presenting the court with evidence that the
information withheld falls within the exemption claimed. In presenting evidence, the
state may not rely on affidavits that are conclusory, merely repeat the language of the
statute, or are founded on sweeping and vague claims. Affidavits filed by the state must
also describe the justification for nondisclosure with reasonably specific detail for the
requester of information to be able to mount an effective case against the claim for
exemption.
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
President of the Republic of South Africa v M & G Media Ltd 2012 (2) SA 50 (CC).
The burden of establishing that the refusal of a request for access complies with the provisions of
this Act rests on the party claiming that it so complies.
Para 5.
Para 9.
Section 1(d) of the Constitution.
The exemptions from disclosure contained in Chapter 4 of PAIA.
Para 12.
Para 16.
Para 17.
366
In Canadian jurisprudence, the evidentiary burden of establishing that a challenged
refusal is authorised rests with the state institution refusing access to the information. 156
The Canadian courts, however, limit their review to whether or not the refusal was
reasonable, but the state must provide evidence that the record falls within the
description contemplated by the statutory exemption invoked. Therefore, the state
must provide actual, direct evidence of the confidential nature of the information at
issue, which must disclose a reasonable explanation for exempting the record.
In Australian jurisprudence, the test for determining whether a refusal was justified is a
reasonableness test, and the state‗s burden is not discharged merely by showing that
the refusal was not irrational, absurd or ridiculous.157 The state must show that, in the
light of the public interest, there are reasonable grounds for the refusal. Even where a
government minister has certified refusal on the grounds of public interest, the court
still has to ask itself whether, in the light of countervailing factors in the public interest,
there were reasonable grounds for the refusal.
The Court deduced from the comparative analysis of the standards applied by courts in
other jurisdictions with legislation comparable to PAIA that the state might discharge its
evidentiary burden only when it has shown that the record withheld falls within the
exemptions claimed.158 Furthermore, exemptions are construed narrowly, and neither
the mere ipse dixit of the information officer nor his or her recitation of the words of
the statute is sufficient to discharge the burden borne by the state. At the least, the
refusal of access to information held by the state must be reasonable. Therefore, the
question that a court must answer is whether the state has put forward sufficient
evidence for a court to hold that, on the probabilities, the information withheld falls
within the exemption claimed.159
The Court stated that –160
156
157
158
159
160
Para
Para
Para
Para
Para
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
367
(a)
the recitation of the statutory language of the exemptions claimed is not
sufficient for the state to show that the record in question falls within the
exemptions claimed; and
(b)
mere ipse dixit affidavits cannot be offered by the state; the affidavits for
the state must provide sufficient information to bring the record within the
exemption claimed.
The question, then, was not whether the best evidence to justify refusal had been
provided, but whether the information provided was sufficient for a court to conclude,
on the probabilities, that the record fell within the exemption claimed. If it did, then the
state has discharged its burden under section 81(3) and the refusal to provide
information would be justified.161
The Court held that a deponent‘s assertion that information was within his or her
personal knowledge was of little value without some indication, in the context of the
case, of how that knowledge had been acquired.162 Knowledge may emerge from the
duties of the deponent and the office he occupies, as well as the seniority of the
deponent in the office and his prior experience with similar activities or procedures in
the office.163
According to the Court, proceedings under PAIA differ from ordinary civil proceedings in
a number of aspects:164
(a)
Firstly, PAIA disputes involve a constitutional right of access to information.
(b)
Secondly, access-to-information disputes are not purely private disputes;
requesters of information often act in the public interest and the outcome
of these disputes therefore affects the general health of our democratic
polity.
161
162
163
164
Para
Para
Para
Para
25.
28.
31.
33.
368
(c)
Thirdly, parties to these disputes may be constrained by factors beyond
their control in presenting and challenging evidence.
(d)
Finally, courts are empowered to call for additional evidence in the form of
the contested record.165
The Court said that the ―judicial peek‖ allowed by section 80 of PAIA empowers courts
to review independently the record in order to assess the validity of the exemptions
claimed, and provides legislative recognition that, through no fault of their own, the
parties may be constrained in their ability to present and refute evidence.166 The
purpose of section 80 is to test the argument for non-disclosure by using the record in
question to decide the merits of the exemption claimed and the legality of the refusal to
disclose the record.167
The Court held that the argument of the applicant – that the report contained
information that was received in confidence – had not been established by acceptable
evidence and therefore it would have been in the interests of justice if section 80 had
been invoked.168
Cameron J, in a minority judgment, held that the applicant had failed to justify its
refusal of access to the report under PAIA. The judge held that the applicant‘s plea
―fails to meet even a baseline standard to warrant further probing‖.169
The judge based his reasoning on two facts. Firstly, the ―hands-tied‖ argument of the
applicant was only raised in its opposing affidavits, creating the appearance of having
been added as an afterthought.170 There was no mention of such difficulty when the
state first refused the M & G‘s request for the report in terms of PAIA. The second
reason related to the applicant‘s failure to explain why evidence that seemed to have
165
166
167
168
169
170
Section 80 of PAIA.
Para 42.
Para 52.
Para 55.
Para 113.
Para 114.
369
been readily available was not produced.171 Not one of the presidents172 who dealt with
the report during their time in office supplied evidence to support the allegations of the
applicant in the case.173 What was also telling was the absence of evidence by the
judges who were asked to report on the election in Zimbabwe.174 They were living and
seemingly available to depose affidavits. The judge pointed out that an affidavit by
either of them could have quickly shed light on the matter before the courts.
The majority of the Court, however, held that the case should be remitted to the High
Court to examine the report in terms of section 80 of PAIA and to determine its release
or otherwise.175
5.4.4 Second hearing in the High Court
In terms of the referral from the Constitutional Court, the North Gauteng High Court
examined the report in terms of section 80 of PAIA.176 Most of the argument of the case
were centred on the question of how the procedural aspects of section 80 of PAIA
should be construed by the Court.177 An interesting aspect of this hearing was that the
applicant attempted to introduce new evidence in the form of an affidavit by former
President Thabo Mbeki. Both the court of first instance and the Supreme Court of
Appeal lamented the fact that the original conveyor of the mission did not explain, by
way of affidavit, why the report should be kept secret. The Court refused the
application to have new evidence admitted, because the applicant could not justify the
late filing of the evidence.178
After a section 80 ―judicial peek‖ at the report, the Court held that its contents did not
support the argument that disclosure of the report would reveal information supplied in
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
Para 115.
Presidents Mbeki, Motlanthe and Zuma held office during the time that M & G requested access to
the report.
Para 116.
Para 117.
Para 72(3).
M & G Media Ltd v President of the Republic of South Africa 2013 (3) SA 591 (GNP).
Paras 8-24.
Paras 25-56. The Court refused leave to file new evidence on the basis that the affidavits were filed
more than three years after the first hearing of the application by the court.
370
confidence by another state or organisation.179 There was also no indication that the
report had been prepared for assisting the President in formulating executive policy on
another country. What the report did was to give a balanced reflection of the events
prior to, during and after the elections.
The Court reiterated that the disclosure of information held by the state is the rule in
South African law. Exemption from disclosure of information is the exception.180 The
Court held that most of the information in the report was common knowledge. 181
Furthermore, the information was supplied by people who did not qualify as members
of another state.
The Court held that the report contained information about whether the legal
requirements for the elections in Zimbabwe had been met. Furthermore, the report
could never be reasonably construed as information supplied in confidence by another
state. The Court quoted from jurisprudence of the European Union, stating:182
The mere fact that certain documents contain information or negative statements
about the political situation or the protection of human rights in a third country does
not necessarily mean that access to them may be denied on the basis that there is a
risk that public interest may be undermined.
The Court held that the report disclosed evidence of a substantial contravention of and
failure to comply with the law.183 Therefore, public interest superseded the harm that
may ensue from releasing the report. The Court held that the entire report should be
made available to the applicants within ten days.184 The Court again awarded costs
against the respondent, including the costs of two counsel.
Of further interest in the case was the Court‘s description of what had transpired
previously.185 The Court stated that the matter had travelled a vicious circle, starting in
the High Court with an appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal and finally to the
179
180
181
Para 59.
Para 61.
Para 62.
182
Kuljer v EU Council (no 2) [2002] 1 WLR 1941.
183
Para 67.
Para 69(2).
Para 32.
184
185
371
Constitutional Court and then back again to the High Court. Illuminating is the manner
in which the Court debunked the arguments of the respondent. From the judgment, it is
clear that none of the reasons advanced by the respondent to refuse disclosure had any
merit. The fact that the respondent tried to file new evidence, which should have been
filed to oppose the original application, also showed the respondent‘s disregard for the
court procedure. No attempt was made to justify the late filing of evidence.
Furthermore, the respondent relied on a bare denial of the M & G‘s argument
throughout the case. The respondent claimed it was hamstrung by the provisions of
PAIA itself, which prevented it to present evidence relating to its arguments. However,
the Court reiterated that the arguments set forth by the respondent were simply not
correct.
It can be construed that the respondent used the bare denial in its arguments to
prevent the disclosure of a report that might have been politically embarrassing to the
state or individuals connected with the state.
5.4.5 Second appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal
The executive persisted with its efforts to halt the release of the report. It appealed the
decision of the High Court and the matter was again heard in the Supreme Court of
Appeal.186
The Court held that it was common cause that the requester (M & G) met the
procedural requirements in terms of PAIA, therefore M & G did not have to justify its
request for access to the report.187 The onus rested on the appellants (hereafter jointly
the Presidency) to justify their refusal. The Presidency again argued that it was
hamstrung by PAIA itself to give reasonable grounds for the refusal to disclose the
report and, as a result, it was unable to give ―adequate reasons for the refusal‖.188
186
President of the RSA v M & G Media Ltd 2015 (1) SA 92 (SCA).
187
Para 5.
Para 8.
188
372
The Supreme Court of Appeal then analysed the evidence the Presidency relied on in
the previous cases.189 The Presidency relied on three affidavits containing the grounds
for the refusal to allow the release of the report. The three affidavits consisted of a
recital of the provisions of PAIA allowing the refusal to release the report,190 followed by
the reassurance that the report is covered by the stated provisions. Two of the
affidavits contained assurances by the deponents that the report contained information
provided by representatives of the Zimbabwean Government in confidence.
The Court then referred to the previous findings of the courts relating to the evidence
tendered by the Presidency.191 This was summarised as follows: None of the deponents
were privy to the appointment of the judges. Therefore, the deponents could not
describe the judges‘ mandate or their terms of reference from their own knowledge, nor
could they, on their own account, testify as to what took place in Zimbabwe and as to
how, from whom and on what basis the information reflected in the report had been
obtained. Therefore, the applicant established no proper evidential basis for refusing
access to the report. Not one of the three deponents on behalf of the Presidency could
have had any direct knowledge of facts essential for the grounds on which the refusal
relied.
The Constitutional Court also concluded that the evidence put forward by the
Presidency in its answering papers was insufficient to discharge the onus resting on it in
terms of PAIA192 to establish that the report fell within the scope of the exemptions
claimed. However, the Constitutional Court acknowledged that parties might be
constrained by factors beyond their control in presenting and challenging evidence. The
Constitutional Court then referred the matter back to the High Court for a ―judicial
peek‖ at the report.
189
190
191
192
Para 10.
Sections 41(1)(b)(i) and 44(1)(a) of PAIA.
Para 11.
Section 81(3).
373
The Court then dealt with the second hearing in the High Court.193 The Court initially
focused on the attempt by the state to submit further evidence in the form of an
affidavit by former President Mbeki, which was submitted by the Presidency in an effort
to stop the Court from having a ―judicial peek‖ at the report. The Court held that this
was in clear contravention to the guidelines the Constitutional Court had issued. The
affidavit tried to plug some of the holes in the case of the Presidency that were pointed
out in the judgments of the courts in the previous round of litigation and particularly in
the minority judgment of Cameron J in the Constitutional Court. However, Raulinga J
held that the Constitutional Court had directed him to take a judicial peek at the report
and that he proposed to do so.
The second appeal to the Supreme Court raised two issues: firstly, whether the High
Court should have allowed the Presidency to tender further evidence,194 and, secondly,
whether the two affidavits, in combination with the judicial peek at the report, should
have had the effect that refusal of access to the report was justified.
The Court held that this was an attempt by the Presidency to introduce evidence
through the backdoor. The affidavits should have been introduced in its original
answering papers.195 The Court referred approvingly to the minority judgment of
Cameron J when the matter was heard in the Constitutional Court, holding that the
judge rightly suspected that the state‘s failure to make out a case had nothing to do
with being hamstrung at all.196 The Court was critical of the attempt by the Presidency
to introduce the new evidence stating that, at the time it filed the affidavit, it knew
what was in the report. The Presidency must have realised that the lifeline the majority
of the Constitutional Court had thrown it could not save its case, since the contents of
the report did not support the grounds of refusal upon which it relied. Therefore –
[w]hat it then tried was to head off the consequence of a judicial peek by tendering
evidence which should have been adduced at the outset during the first round of
193
194
195
196
Para
Para
Para
Para
16.
22(a)-(b).
24.
25.
374
litigation. It clearly did so in the hope that this would persuade the court to refuse M &
G‘s application on a basis which had nothing to do with the contents of the report.
The Presidency therefore attempted to use the referral back to the High Court for a
purpose that was the exact opposite of what the Constitutional Court had in mind.
According to the Supreme Court of Appeal, this conduct amounted to an abuse of
process that could not be tolerated. The Court also described the applicant‘s reliance on
arguments that the judges on the mission to Zimbabwe were diplomatic envoys as bald
and unlikely propositions that bordered on the cynical.197 For the Court it was clear that
the two judges were not on a diplomatic mission but were deputed to focus on matters
of law.
The Court held that the appeal could not succeed, as there was nothing in the report to
support the grounds on which the state refused access to the report. 198 The Court
accordingly dismissed the appeal with costs, including the costs of three counsel.199
5.4.6 Content of the Khampepe-Moseneke Report
200
When analysing the report, the following becomes clear: In the introduction and terms
of reference of the report, the mission is described as a Judicial Observer Mission (JOM)
to the Zimbabwe presidential elections.201 There is no mention of the diplomatic status
of the mission as had been consistently claimed by the executive. The terms of
reference of the JOM are given as to observe and report on whether in the period
before, during and after the election –202
(a)
the Constitution and electoral and other laws of Zimbabwe could ensure
free and fair elections; and
(b)
the elections were conducted in substantial compliance within this
legislative framework.
197
198
199
200
201
202
Para 29.
Para 27.
Para 32.
The report is available at https://eisa.org.za/pdf/zim2002KhampepeReport.pdf accessed December
2015.
Para 1 of the Report.
Para 2 of the Report.
375
The report referred to the Electoral Act (Modification) Notice, 2002, issued by President
Mugabe, which had the effect that an estimated 96 000 voters could not participate in
the elections.203 Previously, this class of voters had full status to vote in the elections in
Zimbabwe. This legislation was passed of few days before the elections.
The Report also referred to the General Laws Amendment Act,204 which inserted a
residential qualification for a voter to register for the election.205 The amendment
allowed the Registrar-General to remove from the voters‘ roll voters who had failed to
reside for a continuous period of twelve months in the constituency. Furthermore, the
Registrar-General had the power to demand proof of residency from any registered
voter. The Report mentioned that this disfranchised voters who resided outside
Zimbabwe, voters who were unable to prove continuous residence for a period of
twelve months in the constituency of voting and any voters who might have been
displaced by violence, including pre-election violence.206
The voters affected by the residential qualifications were estimated to be anything from
half a million to two million voters.207 The Amendment Act was held to be unlawful in its
enactment by the Zimbabwe Supreme Court.208 However, Zimbabwean citizens could
still only vote within their constituency of residence. The Report questioned how many
voters were disfranchised by the legislation and its last-minute recall.209
Another cause for concern was the enactment of the Electoral (Amendment)
Regulations, 2002, which limited the appointment of electoral observers to members of
the Zimbabwean public service.210 The Report raised concern over this amendment,
pointing out that monitors should be drawn from the broad citizenry since the
impartiality of members of the public service was at best suspect.
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
Para 15 of the Report.
2 of 2002 (Zimbabwe).
Para 16 of the Report.
Para 17 of the Report.
Para 18 of the Report.
Para 19 of the Report.
Para 20 of the Report.
Para 25 of the Report.
376
The Zimbabwean Electoral Act211 was also amended so that no person other than the
Electoral Commission or a person authorised by it may provide voter education. This
excluded opposition political parties from providing voter education.212
The Report also mentioned wide-spread disruptions and cancellation of opposition
rallies by the police,213 pre-election violence, intimidation and harassment principally
perpetrated by the supporters of the government.214 These perpetrators of violence
consisted of militias of unemployed youths who received military training from the
state. The number of opposition members killed was estimated at 107. Many rural areas
were also sealed off from the opposition as no-go areas.215 As a result, many opposition
party members had to flee their homes and sought refuge elsewhere. It was also
alleged that the police were complicit in this violence by either actively participating in
the violence or turning a blind eye towards the activities of the youth militias.
The Report highlighted a particular example where the JOM was on an observation visit
to a polling station before the elections.216 Members of the opposition reported that
militias were camping in a school in the area to intimidate opposition members not to
vote. The JOM intervened and reported the matter to the police, who took steps to
remove the militia from the school.
The Report also highlighted the arrest of members of the opposition, including the
leader of the main opposition.217 These arrests were conducted just two weeks before
the election but the charges against the arrested persons dated from years back.
The Report further noted that partisan coverage by the state media broadcaster, 218 and
the invitation of electoral observers only from countries considered friendly by the
government cast a bad light on the elections.219 The Report also referred to the decision
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
1992. Section 14(d) of the Act.
Para 27 of the Report.
Para 47 of the Report.
Para 51 of the Report.
Para 52 of the Report.
Para 54 of the Report.
Paras 55-57 of the Report.
Paras 58-63 of the Report.
Para 70 of the Report.
377
of the state to reduce the number of polling stations in areas where the opposition had
majority support, while increasing the number of polling stations in areas where the
state found support.220
The Report reached the following conclusions:221
(a)
The majority of people killed in the run-up to the elections were opposition
party members.
(b)
The youth militia trained by the government were the main perpetrators of
violence.
(c)
The violence and intimidation engendered fear in connection with the
electoral process, which compromised freedom of choice, movement,
speech, assembly and association of voters.
(d)
There was no equal access to publicly owned and funded media.
The state disregarded the rule of law by either failing to give effect to court orders or
by introducing statutory instruments or regulations that altered, reversed or
undermined court decisions.
The Report concluded by stating that, having regard to all the circumstances, and in
particular the cumulative substantial departures from international standards of free
and fair elections, the elections could not be considered free and fair.222
Although there were widespread reports of violence and intimidation reported in the
run-up to the election, the South African government released a statement on the 2002
elections in Zimbabwe on 13 March 2002. According to the official website of the
Department of International Relations and Cooperation, the South African government
noted the outcome of the Presidential elections in Zimbabwe, and it welcomed the fact
that the actual elections and subsequent processes proceeded without any significant
220
221
222
Para 73 of the Report.
Paras 86-96 of the Report.
Para 99 of the Report.
378
conflict among the participants.223 The government also declared the Zimbabwe
elections fair and legitimate. The Khampepe-Moseneke Report was not made public for
a period of twelve years, and then only after the lengthy legal battle by the Mail &
Guardian.
5.4.7 Similar examples of strategic litigation
The application in Freedom Under Law v National Director of Public Prosecutions224 was
a matter of public interest and national importance on account of its raising significant
issues of propriety, accountability and justifiable conduct in the governance of the
Republic. The main issue was whether certain decisions made by the various
respondents to withdraw criminal and disciplinary charges against the fifth respondent,
Lieutenant-General Richard Mdluli, the Head of Crime Intelligence in the South African
Police Service, were unlawful. The Court described the approach of the respondent in
the proceedings as dilatory and obstructive, holding that it was necessary to expedite
the prosecution of Mdluli, not only in the public interest, but also in the interests of
Mdluli, who could not resume his duties while the charges were pending.
The Court held that the statement of the respondent that ―it would be presumptuous
and foolhardy‖ to prosecute was wrong in law and symptomatic of the irrationality of
his decision, evincing as it does a lack of rational connection between the purpose of his
decision, the various empowering provisions, the evidence before him and the reasons
he gave for his action. Therefore, the decision to withdraw the murder and related
charges was taken in the face of compelling evidence for no proper purpose and was
irrational and therefore reviewable on legality and rationality grounds. The Court set the
decision aside and ordered the prosecution of Mdluli. However, on appeal, the Supreme
Court of Appeal confirmed all the decisions by the High Court, except the order to
proceed with the criminal proceedings and the disciplinary proceedings without delay.225
223
224
225
Department of International Relations and Cooperation: Statement of the South African Government
on the Elections in Zimbabwe http://www.dirco.gov.za/docs/2002/zimb0313a.htm dated 13 March
2002 accessed December 2015.
[2013] 4 All SA 657 (GNP).
National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Freedom Under Law 2014 (2) SACR 107 (SCA).
379
The SCA held that this would constitute interference with the functions of the executive
and a transgression of the separation of powers.
In Trustees, Biowatch Trust v Registrar: Genetic Resources,226 the applicant instituted
action against government agencies to compel them to comply with their responsibilities
under the Genetically Modified Organisms Act.227 The Court held that the case was
about the failure of state officials to meet their constitutional obligations. The applicant
requested access to a range of documents from the respondent to allow it to do a risk
assessment on certain genetically modified organisms in South Africa. Essentially, the
information sought covered the content of permit applications submitted under the
Genetically Modified Organisms Act; the decisions on those applications; and the
processes of decision-making bodies established under the Act. After these requests
were ignored, the applicant instituted application proceedings in court for the release of
the information.
The Court held that the applicant had a clear right to most of the information sought –
eight out of the eleven categories identified in the applicant‘s requests – and that the
applicant‘s rights under section 32228 of the Constitution had been infringed by the
respondent‘s failure to grant access to the records.
In Democratic Alliance v South African Broadcasting Corporation Ltd,229 the applicant
applied for an urgent interdict directing the immediate suspension of the Chief
Operations Officer of the respondent, pending the finalisation of disciplinary
proceedings and review of decisions by the Board of the respondent and the Minister to
recommend and confirm his appointment. Orders directing the institution of such
disciplinary proceedings and the appointment of a suitable replacement were also
sought. The application was based on the findings and recommendations of remedial
action by the Public Protector following an investigation into corporate governance
failures, maladministration and undue political interference in the affairs of the
226
227
228
229
2009 (6) SA 232 (CC).
15 of 1997.
Everyone has the right of access to any information held by the state.
2015 (1) SA 551 (WCC).
380
respondent. The Court held that the disregard of the Public Protector‘s findings
constituted irreparable harm to the public interest. Therefore, the applicant made out a
proper case that SABC and the public would suffer irreparable prejudice unless the
order (to institute disciplinary action against the Chief Operations Officer of the
respondent) were put into operation.
In Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission,230 the applicant instituted
review proceedings against the respondent for an order declaring its decision to advise
the President to appoint certain candidates, and not others, unlawful and/or irrational
and therefore invalid. The Court held that, in weighing up the applicant‘s interest
against the respondent's need for confidentiality, the relief sought would not advance
the constitutional and legislative imperatives of the respondent. Therefore, the applicant
was not being deprived of the procedural and substantive safeguard, which was the
underlying rationale for the rule. The application was dismissed.
In Magidimisi v Premier of the Eastern Cape,231 the applicant sought to ensure that the
respondents, all functionaries of the provincial government, took the necessary steps to
ensure that money judgments ordered by the court against the province were paid. The
applicant‘s grounds for doing this were that the Constitution and other legislation placed
such an obligation on the respondents, but that they had failed to fulfil those
obligations. The Court held that not only private persons or entities had to comply with
court orders made against them, but also the executive and legislative arms of
government and all other organs of state. Furthermore, it was clear that the
respondents were under a misapprehension as to the nature and extent of their
constitutional duty to obey and give effect to court orders.
The Court held that full compliance with a court order was the only proper fulfilment of
the respondent‘s constitutional and legislative obligations to respect and give effect to
court orders. The Court described the response of the respondent in its affidavits as
arrogant and even callous. The Court confirmed that one of the fundamental principles
230
231
2015 (2) SA 498 (WCC).
2006 JOL 17274 (CK).
381
of the rule of law is that everybody, including the state, is subject to the law and
judgments of the courts. Each of the four respondents bore the constitutional duty to
act in accordance with the rule of law, which in the context of the application meant
that they had to ensure that court orders for payment made against the province were
paid. The Court therefore ordered that the respondents take the administrative and
other steps necessary to ensure that the Eastern Cape Government complied with any
prior orders within 14 days of the date of the order. Furthermore, the respondents had
to deliver a report in writing to the registrar of the court and to the applicant‘s
attorneys within 21 days of the date of the order, on the manner and extent of their
compliance.
In Meadow Glen Home Owners Association v City of Tshwane Metropolitan
Municipality,232 the appellants complained that the respondent made no proper attempt
to comply with the terms of orders the courts previously granted against it. The
appellants attempted to have the Director: Housing Resource Management of the
respondent committed to prison for contempt of court arising from an alleged failure by
the respondent to comply with one of those orders. The Court held that an order for
contempt of court was not appropriate in the circumstances. Instead, the Court held
that there was a real likelihood of the parties‘ finding a workable solution if there was
the will to do so. In this instance, the parties had to find innovative methods to resolve
the competing interests of the different factions of the community.
5.4.8 Conceptual analysis of the decision
Because of the many cases discussed and the consequent reversal of applicants and
respondents, in the analysis of M & G v President of the Republic of South Africa, the M
& G will be referred to as the respondent and the Presidency as the applicant.
232
2015 1 All SA 299 (SCA).
382
The process to have the report released dragged on for a period of twelve years.
Lawyers for the respondent stated before the release of the report:233
A concomitant risk is that state officials will be inclined to evade accountability simply
by refusing access to a record and then dragging the matter through the courts until
the issue becomes moot.
This certainly seemed to have been the strategy of the executive in trying to block the
release of the report.
After a glimpse into the content of the report, both the High Court and the Supreme
Court of Appeal stated that the arguments that the executive relied on were
disingenuous and untrue. The executive‘s argument that the government would be
prejudiced in its diplomatic relationship with another country was also held to be
spurious. In fact, the only reason that can be gleaned from the battle to withhold the
report is that it would have been publicly embarrassing for the executive should the
report be released into the public domain.
It is impossible to know how much money the executive spent on trying to keep the
report secret. Cost orders against the state included the cost of the two hearings in the
High Court, the cost of two hearings in the Supreme Court of Appeal and the cost of
one hearing in the Constitutional Court. All the cost orders included the cost of two or
three counsel. The amount of money spent unsuccessfully to stop the release of the
report must be exorbitant.
It is very clear that the granting of punitive cost orders against an organ of state when
litigation is misused is not an effective way of ensuring that the state comply with the
range of positive duties placed upon it by the Constitution.234
The lawyers appearing on behalf of the executive should have informed their instructing
agents that no reasonable grounds existed to prevent the release of the report. The
statement that the strategy of the executive was to prevent the release of the report by
233
234
Legalbrief Today Constitutional values threatened by Khampepe appeal – lawyer No:3626 October
2014.
As discussed in section 2.8.3 of chapter 2 and para 5.6.
383
dragging the matter through the courts until it became moot, or until the applicant ran
out of money, seems likely. It further shows the executive guilty of wasting state
resources on trying to defend the indefensible, undermining the office of the Presidency
and eroding public trust in the processes of democratic government.
Such a strategy by an organ of state does not conform to the positive duty imposed on
organs of state to place all available and relevant information before the courts. 235
Furthermore, it makes a mockery of the candour and openness constitutionally required
from organs of state when engaging in litigation.236 The state litigant did not behave as
the model litigant. It paid lip service to the constitutional obligation of honesty and
professional and ethical behaviour that is required of an organ of state when
litigating.237 The punitive cost orders granted against the executive did not in any way
ensure that it fulfilled its constitutional obligations. It shows that there is a pressing
need for rules or guidelines to ensure that the state litigant fulfils its constitutional
obligations.
In the similar examples of strategic litigation referred to above, all but one of the
applicants were successful in holding organs of state accountable.
In the Helen Suzman Foundation case, the court was loath to interfere with the issue of
the privacy of the members of the JSC. In Magidimisi, the court was unimpressed with
the conduct of the respondents. However, the court still refused to find the respondents
guilty of contempt of court. The court issued an order highlighting the constitutional
duties the respondents had to adhere to. But the Constitution is forward-looking in its
application.238 Comprehensive and enforceable guidelines to regulate the conduct of the
state litigant are needed to pre-empt the violation of constitutional obligations. In
Meadow Glenn, the court was of the opinion that the facts of the case were of a nature
that allowed the parties to reach a just conclusion by themselves. The Court therefore
235
236
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) para 107.
237
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
238
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 42.
384
ordered the parties to the litigation to come to a suitable arrangement between
themselves.
All these cases highlight the procedural hurdles that the courts experience when they
attempt to hold state legal representatives, state instructing agents and organs of state
constitutionally accountable. The legal battle for the release of the KhampepeMoseneke Report, as well as the similar examples of strategic litigation cited, effectively
illustrates that enforceable guidelines are needed to ensure that lawyers acting for an
organ of state, as well as the instructing agents of the organ of state, comply with
constitutional obligations imposed upon the state.239
5.5 Theoretical approaches to ethics in litigation
In section 2.8.3 and section 5.4 it was argued that a punitive costs orders granted
against the executive do not in any way ensure that it will fulfil its constitutional
obligations. Therefore, enforceable guidelines are needed to ensure that lawyers acting
for an organ of state and the instructing agents for the organ of state comply with
constitutional obligations. Holding legal representatives accountable to the court and
their client is an issue of legal ethics. The question is, however, whether existing ethical
legal principles can hold state legal representatives and their instructing agents to
account. Can legal ethics ensure that the state litigant acts like the model litigant?
It is trite that an attorney has a duty to obey a client‘s instructions. This duty is,
however, not absolute. It is subject to an overriding obligation to the court. This can be
described as follows: Firstly, counsel represents the client and is therefore an agent for
the client.240 Secondly, counsel is an officer of the court and is under a duty to assist the
judiciary in the administration of justice.
The expression ―duty to the court‖ means that the practitioner owes a duty to the
larger community, which has a vested public interest in the proper administration of
239
240
Such guidelines are discussed in the final chapter of this work.
Gani 2004 Advocate 41 and Cape Society v Vorster 1949 (3) SA 421 (C) para 425.
385
justice.241 The court, in enforcing this duty, is then acting as a guardian of the due
administration of justice. The implication of this ethical obligation is that the aim of legal
proceedings should not be to get the best result for a client at any cost; the aim should
be to get the best results within the legal and ethical framework imposed on the legal
practitioner as a member of an honourable profession and as an officer of court.242 The
duty owed to the court by legal practitioners can be described as follows:243
No instructions of a client, no degree of concern for the client‘s interest, can override
the duty which a practitioner owes to the court.
However, the duty owed to a client by the legal practitioner is also constrained by other
considerations. Therefore, an attorney should refuse to comply with instructions
requiring him or her to do something unlawful or unethical, or would involve a breach
of a statutory duty, a rule of professional conduct or practice, a court order, a duty to
the court or an undertaking given by the attorney.244 Courts exercise supervisory powers
over the conduct of attorneys, not only in order to discipline and punish errant
practitioners, but also, and more important, in order to protect the public.245
5.5.1 Institutions and sources that regulate the conduct of attorneys and advocates
In terms of section 7(1) of the Admission of Advocates Act,246 the Court may suspend
any person from practice, or order that the name of any person be struck off the roll, if
it is satisfied that he or she is not a fit and proper person to continue to practise as an
advocate.
In terms of section 22(1)(d) of the Attorneys Act,247 an attorney may be struck from the
roll or suspended from practice if he or she, in the discretion of the court, is not a fit
and proper person to continue to practise as an attorney.
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
Hoffmann Lewis and Kyrou‘s Handy hints 27.
Hoffmann Lewis and Kyrou‘s Handy hints 27-28.
Kyle v Legal Practitioners‘ Complaints Committee (1999) 21 WAR 56 para 58.
Hoffmann Lewis and Kyrou‘s Handy hints 23.
Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope v Budricks 2003 (2) SA 11 (SCA) 2003 (2) SA para 16(e)
74 of 1964.
53 of 1979; disciplinary proceedings against attorneys are still regulated by s 71 of the Attorneys Act
53 of 1979 at this time, pending the commencement of the Legal Practice Act 28 of 2014.
386
In Die Prokureursorde van Die Oranje-Vrystaat v Schoeman,248 Steyn J said the
following:
'n Hof sal sekerlik nie ligtelik die skrapping van 'n praktisyn se naam van die rol waarop
dit verskyn beveel nie, maar behoort nie te huiwer om dit te doen in gevalle waar die
omstandighede dit verg nie. Daar moet ongetwyfeld gekyk word na die oortreder as
persoon, en die omstandighede wat hom as individu aankleef moet sorgvuldig oorweeg
word, maar daar moet ook verder gekyk word, en breër belange – dié van die betrokke
Orde, van die gemeenskap en van die regsbedeling – moet ook in ag geneem en
oorweeg word. Daarbenewens moet die houding van 'n oortreder se beroepsgenote
wat deur middel van die Orde of beherende liggaam waarvan hy lid is aan die Hof
meegedeel word, ook in ag geneem word. En waar so 'n Orde meen dat die besondere
oortreder nie langer as lid daarvan deug nie, en verhoed moet word om die betrokke
professie verder te beoefen, moet ernstige aandag aan daardie sienswyse geskenk
word. Maar 'n Hof is nie daaraan gebonde nie en is verplig om sy eie oordeel op al die
relevante bewysmateriaal en feite te vel en daarvolgens te handel.
In Prokureursorde, Transvaal v Van der Merwe249 the Court argued that:
Deur die pleging van 'n ernstige misdaad soos onwettige diamanthandel het die
respondent karaktereienskappe tentoongestel wat nie strook met die standaard van
eerbaarheid en integriteit wat van 'n prokureur verwag word nie. Sodanige gedrag
ontneem die vertroue van die Howe, die algemene publiek en van die persone wat met
die regspleging te doen het, en bring onherroeplike skade aan die professie mee. Die
optrede van die respondent val binne die kader van oortredings of misdade wat van so
'n ernstige aard is dat so 'n oortreder nie verder as 'n prokureur behoort te praktiseer
nie aangesien hy nie meer in 'n vertrouensposisie in enige Hof kan optree nie. Die
Prokureursorde kan sulke optrede nie duld nie en moet ter beskerming van die
professie, die regspleging en die publiek streng optree om te verseker dat die
professionele kodes in die toekoms gehandhaaf sal word. Die respondent het hom
skuldig gemaak aan onprofessionele en/of oneerbare en/of onbetaamlike gedrag en sy
naam moet gevolglik van die rol van prokureurs verwyder word. Die gedrag en optrede
van die respondent soos uiteengesit in hierdie eedsverklaring en aanhangsels, kan nie
by 'n lid van dié eerbare professie waarvan hy 'n lid is geduld word nie.
In Machumela v Santam Insurance,250 the failure to comply with the requirement of the
Rules of Court was not due to any fault of the appellant himself but to a fault and the
inexperience on the part of a professional assistant in the office of his attorney of
record at the seat of the trial court.251 The Court held that as no blame attached to the
appellant himself in connection with the failure to comply with the Rules of Court, his
attorney was at fault. The Court stated that justice required that a special order as to
248
249
250
251
1977 (4) SA 588 (O) 602(h).
1985 (2) SA 208 (T) 209(i)-(j).
CO LTD 1977 (1) SA 660 (A).
663(h).
387
the costs be made. Therefore, the party and party costs of the proceedings had to be
paid to the respondent by the attorney of record for the appellant de bonis propriis.252
The appellant's attorney was also not entitled to recover any of the costs in respect of
the application from the appellant.
It is clear that the courts, as the moral authority of the legal professions, have the
power to regulate and discipline members of the professions. In the case of a legal
practitioner misleading the court or misusing the court process to gain advantage for
his client, a punitive cost order against the client or even an order de bonis propriis to
punish the errant practitioner will usually be sufficient. In cases of extreme misconduct,
the courts will also not hesitate to remove the practitioners concerned from the roll of
practising attorneys or advocates. However, as was shown in section 5.4.8 above, a
punitive cost order against the instructing agent for an organ of state and the state
legal representative is not effective. The tax paying public pay for their blunders. This is
a matter of concern. Fuller states that the lawyer's role imposes on him a ―trusteeship
for the integrity of those fundamental processes of government and self-government
upon which the successful functioning of our society depends‖.253 This is especially true
for state legal representatives and their instructing agents, who ought to act diligently
in a manner that gives effect to constitutionally imposed duties. Therefore, it is
imperative that the state lawyer‘s role, and the responsibilities of the instructing agent
for the organ of state, be identified and clearly defined. This would allow the courts to
hold the instructing agent and the state legal representative responsible for any abuse
of the legal and court process.
5.5.2 Lawyer‘s duties to court
The analysis in section 2.8 in chapter 2 above has shown that the Constitution places a
range of positive duties on organs of state. Organs of state must assist and protect the
courts to ensure the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness
252
253
6649(c).
Fuller and Winston 1978 Harvard Law Review 384.
388
of the courts.254 The duty that is imposed on organs of state in order to ensure the
effectiveness of the courts, which duty includes a positive obligation to place before the
courts relevant and material evidence.255 Furthermore, public administration must be
governed by the democratic values and principles enshrined in the Constitution,
including the principles of professional ethics, impartiality, openness, accountability and
participation.256
The courts have indicated that the commencement, defence and conduct of litigation by
the government or government departments constitutes the exercise of public power.257
As such, state litigation is subject to the same scrutiny as any other exercise of public
power. Therefore, state litigation should comply with the principle of legality and the
rule of law.
An attorney is subject to a code of ethics, has a duty to the court to conduct him- or
herself in a proper manner and has a responsibility to act honestly and openly towards
his or her colleagues.258 Both professions (advocates and attorneys) have strict ethical
rules aimed at preventing their members from becoming parties to the deception of the
court.259
In Brenner's Service Station and Garage (Pty) Ltd v Milne,260 the Court held that
attorneys should not allow themselves to descend to the level of manipulating the
court's procedures so that their true purpose is frustrated. The true function of the
courts in this regard is to try disputes between litigants who have real grievances and
so to see to it that justice is done. Attorneys who manipulate the court system in an
effort to secure the best outcomes for their clients would be guilty of malpractice.
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 3.
Magistrate Pangarker v Botha 2015 (1) SA 503 (SCA) para 38.
Kekana v Society of Advocates of South Africa 1998 (4) SA 649 (SCA) 649(f); ethical rules for
advocates are found in the Uniform Rules of Professional Conduct of the General Council of the Bar
of South Africa, available at http://www.sabar.co.za/rules-of-ethics.html accessed February 2016;
and for attorneys in the Rules for the Attorneys‘ Profession, published in Government Gazette No.
39740 of 26 February 2016, which came into operation on 1 March 2016.
1983 (4) SA 233 (W) para 240A.
389
In S v Malumo,261 the Court acknowledged that there was a duty between attorney and
client, but reminded the appearing counsel that although she had a duty to act towards
the best interest of her client, she was an officer of the court in the first place. This
meant that she had to assist the court to finalise the inordinately prolonged trial as
soon as circumstances allowed it.
In Khunou v M Fihrer & Son (Pty) Ltd,262 the Court argued that the rules of civil
procedure exist in order to enable courts to perform a duty with which the orderly
functioning of society is interwoven. The Rules of Court are designed not only to allow
litigants to come to grips, as expeditiously and as inexpensively as possible, with the
real issues between them, but also to ensure that the courts dispense justice uniformly
and fairly, and that the true issues before the court are clarified and tried in a just
manner.
The Court stated that the necessarily flexible Rules of Court leave opportunity for
unscrupulous litigants and those who would wish to delay or deny justice to manipulate
the courts' procedures so that their true purpose is frustrated.263 The Court further
pointed out that the Court's officers, including and especially its attorneys, have a
sacred duty. In terms of this duty, legal practitioners should not allow the
administration of justice to fall into disrepute. When attorneys do not measure up to
this standard, a court will mark its disapproval either by an appropriate order as to
costs against the defaulting practitioner or by referring the matter to the relevant Law
Society for disciplinary action.
In Li Kui Yu v Superintendent of Labourers,264 the Court considered it a serious offence
to interfere with the administration of justice by taking an action that is bound to
prevent a court from granting a remedy. The courts have held that a legal practitioner
who misleads the court would be guilty of unprofessional conduct and so would a legal
261
262
263
264
S v Malumo (In Re Ndala) 2014 (3) NR 690 (HC) para 11.
1982 (3) SA 353 (W) page 355(f)-(h).
Page 356(a)-(c).
1906 TS 181 page 194.
390
practitioner be who lies to another legal practitioner to frustrate the Rules of Court.265
Attorneys should therefore ensure that the Rules serve their true purpose, not only
through their own actions, but also by preventing their clients from using the Rules in a
manner which would frustrate the true purpose of the Rules.
The legal practitioner also has a duty to inform the court of any legal issues relevant to
the matter before the court. In Toto v Special Investigating Unit,266 the Court held as
follows:
It is trite that it is the duty of a litigating party's legal representative to inform the
court of any matter which is material to the issues before court and of which he is
aware. This Court should always be able to accept and act on the assurance of a legal
representative in any matter it hears and, in order to deserve this trust, legal
representatives must act with the utmost good faith towards the Court. A legal
representative who appears in court is not a mere agent for his client, but has a duty
towards the Judiciary to ensure the efficient and fair administration of justice. The
proper administration of justice could not easily survive if the professions were not
scrupulous of their dealings with the Court.
The ethical duty a practitioner has towards the court is critical to ensuring the fair and
efficient administration of justice. Therefore, the legal practitioner should act with the
utmost good faith towards the court and the courts should be able to rely on an
assurance given by a practitioner in relation to any issue.267 Furthermore, the legal
practitioner is obliged to inform the court of any matter which is material to the issues
before the court and of which he or she is aware.268
The same legal duty towards the court exists when the instructing agency is an organ
of state. In S v Shaggie,269 this was described as follows:
Then there is the question of due compliance by the state, of its obligation to comply
with the practice directives of this court. The state's written argument was, as could be
expected in the light of the appellant's non-argument, quite brief. The only references
to the record were to the judgment of the court below. In spite of this the state said
that we had to read all 4 000 pages of the record. This is unacceptable. The state has
a duty towards the court to ease its workload and not to bog it down.
265
266
267
268
269
Disciplinary Committee for Legal Practitioners v Murorua 2012 (2) NR 481 (HC) paras 33 and 34.
2001 (1) SA 673 (E) (2000 (5) BCLR 553) para 683(a)–(f).
Gani 2004 Advocate 41.
Schoeman v Thompson 1927 WLD 282 para 283.
S v Staggie 2012 (2) SACR 311 (SCA) para 23.
391
The instructing agents of state and the state legal representatives therefore also have a
legal duty towards the courts.
The state further has the duty not to frustrate the courts in their enforcement of
constitutional rights.270 In this matter, the conduct of the MEC and her department,
though falling short of contempt, had veered towards thwarting the relief sought by the
Board. The Court described the conduct of the MEC as follows:
The MEC, in her responses to the opposition by the board, appeared indignant and
played the victim. She adopted this attitude while acting in flagrant disregard of
constitutional norms. She attempted to turn turpitude into rectitude.
The Court stated that a costs order de bonis propriis was justified in such
circumstances. The Court further held that it was time for courts seriously to consider
holding officials who behave in such a high-handed manner personally liable for costs
incurred. The courts therefore recognises that when an organ of state is the instructing
agent, a cost order de bonis propriis might be an appropriate order to hold a state
official accountable to the Constitution.
In Permanent Secretary Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government v
Ngxuza,271 the Court described the legal strategy of the provincial government as
follows: ―The applicants did so by recourse to every stratagem and device and
obstruction, every legal argument and non-argument that it thought lay to hand.‖
The Court held that the strategy employed by the government spoke of contempt for
people and process that does not befit an organ of government under our constitutional
dispensation.272 The Court held that the province‘s approach to the proceedings was
contradictory, cynical, expedient and obstructionist. It conducted the case as though it
was at war with its own citizens. This was completely at odds with the duty of legal
270
271
272
Gauteng Gambling Board v MEC for Economic Development, Gauteng 2013 (5) SA 24 (SCA) paras
G(41)–(43) and (48).
2001 (4) SA 1184 SCA para 17.
Para 19.
392
practitioners, as officers of the court, where they serve the interests of justice itself by
acting as a bulwark against the admission of fabricated evidence.273
The preservation of professional ethics have been left almost entirely in the hands of
individual practitioners; absolute personal integrity and scrupulous honesty are
therefore demanded of each of them.274
The analysis in section 2.8.3 in chapter 2 has shown that organs of state and their legal
representatives frequently misuse the court process and often fail to comply with
constitutionally imposed positive duties, and that flouting of positive constitutional
duties by state litigants and their legal representatives persists, which places an undue
constitutional limitation on strategic litigation.
This strategy employed by some state officials constitutionally limits the positive
application of strategic litigation and restrains the realisation of constitutional rights.
The analysis in chapter 2 further concluded that the current practice of curing vexatious
proceedings with a punitive cost order is not effective when the state, ―clutching the
unlimited public purse‖, is the offending party.275 Adverse cost orders against the state
punish the innocent taxpayer. It is clear that the current court rules and practice
directives of the Law Societies and Council of the Bar do not allow the courts to fulfil its
role as custos morum of the profession.276
It follows that there is a need in South African law of civil procedure for a set of
guidelines or principles with which the government litigant must comply. This would
allow the courts to serve the interest of the public and the professions by holding state
legal representatives and their instructing agents accountable to constitutional
obligations.
5.6 Conclusion
273
274
275
276
Kekana v Society of Advocates of South Africa 1998 (4) SA 649 (SCA) 655(i).
Kekana 656(a).
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 789 (CC) para 87.
In General Council of the Bar v Matthys 2002 (5) SA 1 (ECD) paras 4-6, the Court described the
inherent right of the courts to control and discipline practitioners who practice within its jurisdiction
as a duty exercised in the interest of the public and the profession.
393
The case studies above show that strategic litigation is to an extent limited when the
state is a party to the proceedings. These limitations do not flow from the Constitution
or legal norms but rather from procedural and practical considerations that are in some
instances imposed by the courts.
Case studies 2 and 3 show that the constitutional limitations to strategic litigation
against the state can be clarified by subscribing to a wider approach to judicial review,
as was argued in chapter 3 of this work. Should the courts subscribe to the principle of
justification in judicial review, the values inherent in the Constitution can be realised.
The principle of acknowledgement would allow for the values of justification, openness,
equality and participation to be considered during adjudication. This calls for a rejection
of the theory of deference in adjudication, which is currently applied by the courts.
The Walker case study and the similar examples of strategic litigation referred to in that
section also show the tension between rationality and formal justice, on the one hand,
and substantive justice, on the other. However, non-compliance with the rationality
principle and formal justice can be justified by relying on the principle of reciprocity that
flows from the underlying value system in the Constitution, as was argued in chapter 4.
Should the courts recognise that the underlying value system of the Constitution and,
therefore, the principle of reciprocity are applicable to the judge as well as litigants,
substantive justice can be realised.
The case study in section 5.4 shows that punitive cost orders are not effective in forcing
an organ of state that is a party to litigation to adhere to constitutional obligations. The
state with its unlimited public purse is not prevented from misusing the litigation
process to protect individuals from political embarrassment. It is clear that existing
procedural norms and remedies of court are not effective in preventing abuse of the
legal process by organs of state.
Section 5.5 shows that current norms governing the conduct of legal representatives of
the state as a party to litigation are not effective in ensuring impeccable ethical
conduct.
Even
though
there
are
legal
obligations
imposed
on
state
legal
representatives, these are not enough to ensure that organs of state comply with
394
constitutionally imposed duties. Therefore, clearly defined and enforceable guidelines
are needed to hold legal representatives of the state as well as their instructing agents
constitutionally accountable.
395
Chapter 6: Conclusions
6.1 Introduction
Chapters 2 to 4 of this study have shown that, in practice, strategic litigation is
constitutionally limited when the state is party to the proceedings. These limitations do
not flow from the Constitution or legal norms but rather from procedural and practical
considerations that are, in some instances, imposed by the courts themselves. These
practical considerations flow from incorrect interpretation and application of the
Constitution. This often leads to a situation in which constitutional duties imposed on
organs of state when litigating are ignored or incorrectly discharged by the state
litigants.
Section 6.2 of this Chapter examines the constitutional limitations identified in the
study. The discussion shows that practical measures can remove procedural limitations
to strategic litigation. However, the failure by organs of state to fulfil their constitutional
duties requires a new approach in South African civil procedure and constitutional law.
Section 6.3 investigates the model litigant obligation as applied in Australian law and
considers whether these Australian guidelines can be successfully applied in South
African law. The possible application of the model in South Africa, including the
introduction and regulation of the guidelines, is investigated.
6.2 Constitutional limitations to strategic litigation
The analysis in chapter 2 showed that there are numerous advantages to strategic
litigation and that the judiciary has important institutional advantages in the tasks it
assumes in strategic litigation. However, the judiciary also has the duty, responsibility
and authority to hold organs of state constitutionally accountable. Primary advantages
of strategic litigation include holding organs of state accountable to the Constitution,
righting constitutional wrongs and exposing corruption. These are essential for the
protection of the individual litigating against the state, but also for the protection of the
Constitution and the South African constitutional state. Secondary advantages may
396
occur even when the litigation itself has not been successful. This includes the publicity
generated by the litigation, which in itself is a powerful motivator to hold organs of
state accountable to the Constitution. A well-organised civil society in South Africa
makes its voice heard and engages in strategic litigation with the aim of protecting the
Constitution.
The procedural rules governing strategic litigation are well-established in South Africa
with a wide range of constitutional remedies available to assist the courts in righting a
constitutional wrong. However, the analysis shows that the courts are at times unable
to hold organs of state to account when they flout constitutionally imposed positive
duties and misuse the mechanisms of the law. When organs of state ignore positively
imposed constitutional duties, it places unwarranted constitutional limitations on the
possible achievements of strategic litigation.
The analysis in chapter 3 has shown that strategic litigation can serve as an effective
check to prevent the abuse of powers in the context of the doctrine of the separation of
powers. The main objective of the doctrine of the separation of powers is to prevent
the abuse of power by any one branch of government. However, another aim of the
doctrine is to prevent the overconcentration of power in a single institution or
individual. In the South African constitutional context, the lack of effective checks and
balances between the executive and legislative branches and the resulting political
power concentration have opened the door to political activism through strategic
litigation to counterbalance the power of the executive. Although the lack of effective
checks and balances to curb the power of the executive is a cause for concern, it shows
that South Africa is still in the process of moving away from a government system
based on parliamentary supremacy into a constitutional dispensation. The courts can
assist in this transition by addressing the issue of the overconcentration of power in
public bodies, something the courts have largely neglected since the certification of the
1996 Constitution.
The courts have the right and duty to intervene to prevent the violation of the
Constitution. However, intervention by the courts in cases of constitutional violation
397
could be obstructed if the courts persist with a standard for judicial review based on
deference to other organs of state. This means that the courts defer to an organ of
state even when that organ is guilty of a constitutional violation. Such deference places
an undue constitutional limitation on strategic litigation. What is necessary is a standard
for judicial review based on a policy of non-discrimination, openness, justification,
accountability and participation, and the founding values of the Constitution. Davis
articulated a culture of justification for judicial review.1 This culture takes into account
the democratic prerogative of the elected arms of government to fashion and
implement public policy within the framework of the Constitution. It accepts that the
role of judicial review is to foster a culture of democracy, and that the judiciary‘s point
of departure should be that it operates in a governmental system based on the doctrine
of the separation of powers. The approach of a culture of justification as proposed by
Davis finds the correct balance for judicial review in both an objective interpretation of
constitutional provisions and the values inherent to the Constitution and the doctrine of
the
separation
of
powers.
Judicial
review
requiring
openness,
justification,
accountability and participation could assist the courts to hold the state litigant to a
different standard than the private litigant. The notion of equality before the law and
the right to equal benefit and protection of the law can then be realised.2 The powerful
position of the state litigant, with access to more resources, money and legal
representatives than the ordinary private litigant, can then be balanced with the right to
equal enjoyment of the law and with the right to participation that the private litigant
also should enjoy. The principle of openness can be realised by requiring that the state
litigant places all relevant information at its disposal before the court. The principles of
justification and accountability can be realised by ensuring that the state only litigates
when it is in the public interest to do so or when the litigation is needed to vindicate the
Constitution. Then, if the state litigant subscribes to these values, the state litigant
would be the model litigant.
1
2
Section 3.5.3.
Section 9 of the Constitution.
398
The analysis in chapter 4 highlights the essential role that judges play in strategic
litigation. It is of the utmost importance for judges to be independent and impartial in
litigation against organs of state. The process of appointing judges in South Africa is
well-balanced, but the composition of the JSC and the resultant overconcentration of
executive power in the JSC are a cause for concern. The appointment of judges
currently invites arbitrariness, as it allows executive interference in the judicial
appointment process. The appointment of judges oriented towards the ideology of a
certain political party creates the possibility that such judges will have an interest in the
outcome of a case in which such party is a party to the proceedings. This relates
directly to strategic litigation, in which judicial impartiality would hardly be possible
when an organ of state or a political party is a party to the litigation. Excessive
executive influence in the JSC has the potential of placing constitutional limitations on
strategic litigation when an organ of the state is a party to the litigation. An executiveminded judiciary or a judiciary that is perceived to be executive-minded may have a
―chilling effect‖ on strategic litigation against the state. The appointment of nonpartisan, non-political and appropriately qualified judges is therefore essential.
It is widely accepted that the Constitutional Court plays a prominent role in the South
African political landscape, the law and politics being inescapably linked. However,
judges must interpret the Constitution fairly and consistently and remain free from
undue political influence. This can be ensured if the courts address the issue of the
overconcentration of political power in public bodies such as the JSC.
The analysis in chapter 4 further showed that judges cannot be absolutely impartial.
Judges are human beings with their own predilections, preconceptions and personal
views. However, the often vague and undefined values ingrained in the Constitution
lend themselves, by their nature, to a degree of subjective interpretation. The
interpretation of the Constitution by the courts, including the interpretation of the
undefined rights and values, is critically important in strategic litigation.
It is critical that subjective interpretation is not based on the concealed and capricious
pre-conceived political, moral or religious notions of the judge. This is especially true in
399
what are referred to as ―hard cases‖, where an objective way of reaching a judgment
based on the accepted sources of law is problematic. Hard cases sometimes require
subjective interpretation from the judge, imposing on the judge his or her own moral,
religious or political belief. However, judges are assumed to be people of conscience
and intellectual discipline, capable of judging a particular controversy fairly based on
the details of that case only. Furthermore, legal tradition (in the form of community
expectations), the legal training of the judge and the traditions of the bench, the
advocates' bars and the different law societies condition a judge to be fair and just in
adjudication.
Nevertheless, a judge must recognise the introspective view that comes into play when
adjudicating. This requires a judge to consider his or her conscience and own moral
position, the facts and evidence of the case, the litigants and the constitutional rights
and values at stake, and then to make sure that his private and individual moral
presumptions do not cloud the judgment. This introspection acknowledges that inherent
personal views may influence the judgment of the court, which gives rise to a theory of
acknowledgement that allows judges to frame subjective predispositions into the court‘s
reasoning. Such an articulation of the influence of substantive reasoning would be more
preferable than a bland denial of subjective predispositions and an absence of
justification. The theory of acknowledgment provides legitimacy and objectivity to the
judgment by exposing the subjective interpretational element to criticism. Then political
judging is not the problem; it becomes a problem when it is not recognised and
acknowledged as such. The theory also removes the possibility that the political
leanings of the judge might constitutionally limit strategic litigation when the state is a
party to the litigation. This provides rationality and objectivity by justifying the court‘s
decision and opening the decision for public scrutiny and rational criticism.
Justice as a principle in adjudication plays a prominent part in the social ordering of a
community and consists of two aspects, namely formal and substantive justice. The
prime goal for the enlightened state must be securing and preserving optimal fairness
and justice for all. The South African state is founded upon values. These values lend
moral conviction and validity to legal norms. Therefore, the values of dignity, equality,
400
fairness and justice should be the norm in constitutional interpretation and adjudication.
There is an underlying moral value system in the Constitution that should inform all
legal norms, as well as the Constitution itself. This moral value system is based on the
principles of fairness and justice, which can be realised by subscribing to the ethical
norm of reciprocity: treating others as you want them to treat you. The concepts of
self-worth and dignity require individuals to display respect for the identities of others
that differ from their own, and this is reciprocated by the other. Reciprocity is therefore
integrated in the very core of the text of the Constitution. Reciprocity is based on
mutual respect and requires that no individual seek to impose an individual vision on
others. The principle of reciprocity facilitates the right to participation by preventing the
arbitrary imposition of the personal view of the judge. This means that where meaning
is given to undefined constitutional values the judge must acknowledge the inner self
and articulate the reasoning process that gave rise to the decision of the court for
public scrutiny. Reciprocity allows the judge to adhere to the constitutional commitment
to justice, which includes treating litigants equally, thereby bestowing dignity and selfworth on the litigant and fostering a culture of justice, openness, justification and
participation in adjudication.
The case studies in chapter 5 show that existing court remedies are not effective in
forcing organs of state to meet constitutional obligations when it is a party to litigation.
Punitive cost orders do not prevent state organs from misusing the litigation process to
protect politically connected individuals or to safeguard organs of state from political
embarrassment. It is therefore clear that existing procedural norms and remedies are
not effective in preventing abuse of the legal process by organs of state. Furthermore,
it is clear that current legal ethical norms are not enough to hold state legal
representatives, their instructing agents or organs of state accountable to the courts
and the Constitution. Organs of state are constitutionally accountable, but do not
always conform to the obligations that are imposed on them by the Constitution. This
places undue constitutional limitations on strategic litigation. After all, organs of state
holding the unlimited public purse and public resources are powerful litigants. The
situation is exacerbated when the organ of state does not discharge its positive
constitutional duties and does not abide by the rules of civil procedure.
401
Therefore, clearly defined and enforceable guidelines are needed to hold legal
representatives of the state and their instructing agents constitutionally accountable.
The need for the regulation of public sector lawyers is recognised by these lawyers
themselves, or at least by some of them. During the inaugural annual Government Law
Conference held in 2012, Advocate Wolmarans, Chief State Law Adviser in the Office of
the Premier of KwaZulu-Natal, confirmed that –3
[l]awyers working for government were not just public servants, but remained officers
of the court and should strive to maintain freedom, independence, integrity,
impartiality and non-partisanship. Public sector lawyers serving the executive and the
legislature must guard against being overly ―executive-minded‖ in their approach.
According to Wolmarans, employers of public sector lawyers must recognise that the
roles and responsibilities of public sector lawyers as lawyers supersede those as public
sector employees. He continued by stating:
As public sector lawyers, we must firstly, and always, serve and uphold the values and
principles of constitutionalism and the rule of law in providing professional and nonpartisan legal services and legal advice to government. We must ensure that we
understand and apply these principles at all times.
Also speaking at the above-mentioned conference, Advocate Dibetso-Bodibe said that
government, being the biggest litigant, wielded ―financial muscle‖ against citizens when
engaging in litigation.4 She continued by saying public sector attorneys sometimes did
not realise that they were litigating against the community that pays taxes, and that,
therefore, they should spend taxpayers‘ money wisely. Tellingly she added, ―We should
be model litigants and behave as such‖. She also stated that bad cases should not be
pursued unnecessarily. This she articulated as follows:
We should not litigate for the sake of litigating. Do not use delaying tactics when
litigating and avoid personality-driven cases. Fight fairly. Every matter does not
necessarily require a court order. If you can settle at the earliest point in time, then do
that. Do not institute and/or pursue appeals unless the state believes that there exists
a reasonable prospect for success.
3
4
The speech was published in Kriel 2013 DEREBUS 115.
The speech was published in Kriel 2013 DEREBUS 116.
402
When litigation is inevitable, said Dibetso-Bodibe, the state litigant must –5
(a)
act consistently in handling claims;
(b)
deal with claims promptly;
(c)
focus on the core issues involved;
(d)
ensure all relevant documents are presented to the courts;
(e)
keep costs to a minimum;
(f)
pay legitimate claims without litigation, including making partial settlements
or interim payments where liability has been established; and
(g)
manage litigation in a timely manner.
She concluded by stating that the public legal sector should be transformed to provide
legal services of the highest standard to protect and safeguard the interests of the state
and to promote access to justice for all. The transformation envisaged by DibetsoBodibe can be realised by subscribing to the model litigant obligation
6.3 The model litigant obligation
According to the Rule of Law Institute of Australia, the model litigant rules, or model
litigant obligations, are guidelines on how a government body ought to behave before,
during and after litigation with another government body, a private company or an
individual.6 In Australia, the Commonwealth and Australian states all have a commonlaw responsibility to act as a model litigant.7 This responsibility applies in all areas of the
law and all stages of the trial, whether the state is plaintiff or defendant. The obligation
5
6
7
Kriel 2013 DEREBUS 117.
Model Litigant Rules, Rule of Law Institute of Australia http://www.ruleoflaw.org.au/priorities/modellitigant-rules/ accessed February 2016.
Lee The State as model litigant Victorian Government Solicitor‘s Office Lunchtime Seminar Series
2006 available at Institute of Australia http://www.ruleoflaw.org.au/priorities/model-litigant-rules/
accessed February 2016.
403
is not viewed as a handicap to the state, but rather as a way in which to assess the
state‘s conduct to ensure that the highest standard of propriety and ethics are met.
6.3.1 The model litigant obligation as applied in Australia
In Australia, governments of the Commonwealth and some states and territories have
introduced policy guidelines to ensure that the state act fairly in litigation against its
citizens.8 The obligation to adhere to those standards is commonly referred to as the
obligation to act as a model litigant and emanates from the executive and the judicial
branches. Chami states that the obligation to act as a model litigant extends beyond
merely obeying the law and abiding by the ethical obligations that apply to legal
practitioners. The ethical obligations provide for minimum standards of conduct,
whereas the model litigant obligation involves striving for aspirational standards of the
highest character.9
In order to improve and maintain standards in litigation, the State of Victoria has
introduced policies in the form of guidelines to ensure that the state complies with the
obligation to act as a model litigant.10 These guidelines oblige on the State of Victoria,
its departments and agencies to behave as a model litigant in the conduct of litigation.
The obligations require that the State of Victoria, its departments and agencies –
(a)
act fairly in handling claims and litigation brought by or against the state
or an agency;
8
9
10
(b)
act consistently in the handling of claims and litigation;
(c)
deal with claims promptly and not cause unnecessary delay;
(e)
make an early assessment of –
Chami 2010 AIAL Forum 47. New South Wales, Victoria, Queensland and the Australian Capital
Territory have each introduced their own model litigant policies in the form of guidelines, which
apply to the provision of legal services in matters involving the agencies of those respective
jurisdictions.
Chami 2010 AIAL Forum 48
Guidelines on the State of Victoria‘s obligation to act as a model litigant
http://www.opp.vic.gov.au/wps/wcm/connect/18c9ac00404a14a4abfafbf5f2791d4a/15_Application_
of_model_litigant_guidelines.pdf?MOD=AJPERES accessed November 2015.
404
(i) the state‘s prospects of success in legal proceedings; and
(ii) the state‘s potential liability in claims against the state;
(f)
pay
legitimate
claims
without
litigation,
including
making partial
settlements of claims or interim payments, where it is clear that liability is
at least as much as the amount paid;
(g)
consider seeking to avoid and limit the scope of legal proceedings by
taking such steps, if any, as are reasonable having regard to the nature of
the dispute, to resolve the dispute by agreement, including participating in
appropriate
dispute
resolution
(ADR)
processes
or
settlement
negotiations;
(h)
where it is not possible to avoid litigation, keep the costs of litigation to a
minimum, including by –
(i)
not requiring the other party to prove a matter which the state or the
agency knows to be true;
(ii)
not contesting liability if the state or the agency believes that the main
dispute is about quantum;
(iii) taking such steps, if any, as are reasonable to resolve such matters as
may be resolved by agreement and to clarify and narrow the
remaining issues in dispute;
(iv) monitoring the progress of the litigation and, where appropriate,
attempting to resolve the litigation, including by settlement offers,
offers of compromise and ADR;
(i)
when participating in ADR or settlement negotiations, ensure that as far
as practicable the representatives of the state or the agency –
(i)
have authority to settle the matter to facilitate appropriate and
timely resolution; and
405
(ii)
(j)
participate fully and effectively;
do not rely on technical arguments unless the state‘s or the agency‘s
interests would be prejudiced by the failure to comply with a particular
requirement;
(k)
do not take advantage of a claimant who lacks the resources to litigate a
legitimate claim;
(l)
do not undertake and pursue appeals unless the state or the agency
believes that it has reasonable prospects for success or the appeal is
otherwise justified in the public interest; and
(m)
consider apologising where the state or the agency is aware that it or its
representatives have acted wrongfully or improperly.
The obligation applies to litigation (including before courts, tribunals and inquiries, and
in arbitration and other alternative dispute resolution processes) involving organs of
state, as well as Ministers and officers where the state provides a full indemnity in
respect of an action for damages brought against them personally. The obligation
extends beyond obeying the law and abiding by ethical obligations that apply to legal
practitioners. The model litigant obligation involves striving for aspirational standards of
the highest character.11
There are a number of cases where the model litigant obligation was considered by
Australian courts. In Morely & Ors v Australian Securities and Investments
Commission,12 the Court held that, because the Australian Securities and Investments
Commission (ASIC) effectively acted as a prosecutor in civil penalty cases, it was under
an obligation to act fairly, analogous to the duty owed by prosecutors in criminal
proceedings.13 The Court further held that the government agency has no legitimate
11
12
13
Chami AIAL Forum 48.
[2010] NSWCA 331.
Para 705.
406
private interest of the kind, which often arises in civil litigation. It acts, and acts only, in
the public interest as identified in the regulatory regime.14
In R v Martens,15 the applicant claimed that material evidence vital to his case was
withheld or not adequately investigated. After he was convicted, his wife obtained the
evidence. The Queensland Court of Appeal found that the conviction was unreasonable
and not supported by evidence and his conviction was quashed. The Court described
the conduct of the government agencies as follows:16
It is a poor reflection upon the two organisations that one should have failed to find
them, and denied their existence, and the other object to their use in the reference on
the ground that the petitioner should have obtained them earlier.
In Deputy Commissioner of Taxation v Clear Blue Developments Pty Ltd,17 the
Commissioner of Taxation sought an order for costs, which the Court refused to grant.
The Court held as follows:18
I do not propose to award professional costs to the Deputy Commissioner. Indeed, so
to do would be to reward work which is not of a standard to be expected of a person
to be a solicitor on the record for a person to whom the model litigant obligations
adhere.
Australian courts therefore recognise the model litigant obligation and uses it to great
effect when an organ of state misuse the court process or do not act in the public
interest.
According to Lee, ensuring compliance with the model litigant obligation is primarily the
responsibility of the organ of state which initiated the litigation. In addition, lawyers
engaged in such litigation will need to act in accordance with the obligation and assist
their client to do so. Lee continues that the obligation does not prevent the state and its
organs from acting firmly to protect their interests. It does not preclude all legitimate
14
15
16
17
18
Para 716.
[2009] QCA 351.
Para 170.
(No 2) [2010] FCA 1124.
Para 48.
407
steps being taken to pursue claims by the state and its organs and testing or defending
claims against them.19
The Office of Legal Services Coordination (OLSC), in the Attorney-General‘s department,
assists the Attorney-General in relation to his responsibilities regarding legal services to
the Commonwealth20 by providing guidance notes and performing educational functions.
The OLSC also investigates alleged breaches of the Directions. Breaches are brought to
the attention of the Office by way of self-reporting by government agencies, judicial
comments, media reports or complaints made directly to the OLSC. The Legal Services
Directions 2005 (LSD), in which the Commonwealth government‘s Model Litigant Rules
are set out, state that the model litigant obligation arises from the responsibility of the
Attorney-General for the maintenance of proper standards in litigation.21
The guidelines are meant to be integral to the rule of law, because of the substantial
imbalance of power in litigation with organs of state. This imbalance of power occurs
because of the access to substantial resources that organs of state enjoy. These
resources and powers include the power to investigate matters, the statutory powers to
compel people to provide information to organs of state and, in some instances, more
experience and specialist expertise in dealing with complex and contentious legal
matters.
The model litigant obligation is therefore essential for two reasons: firstly, to hold the
state litigant accountable to the public and the Constitution and ensuring that they act
in the public interest and according to the Constitution and the law; and, secondly, to
restructure the imbalance of power between the state litigant and the private citizen to
19
20
21
Lee The State as model litigant Victorian Government Solicitor‘s Office Lunchtime Seminar Series
2006 available at Institute of Australia http://www.ruleoflaw.org.au/priorities/model-litigant-rules/
accessed February 2016.
Judiciary Amendment Bill 1998, Chapter 8.
Section 4.2 of the LSD available at https://www.legislation.gov.au/Details/F2006L00320 accessed
March 2016.
408
effect to the notion of equality as expressed in section 9 of the South African
Constitution.22
6.3.2 Justifications for the obligation
6.3.2.1 Justification in Australia
In Melbourne Steamship Co Ltd v Moorehead,23 the Court had the following to say when
the state relied on a technical point of pleading:
I am sometimes inclined to think that in some parts – not all – of the Commonwealth
the old fashioned, traditional and almost instinctive, standard of fair play to be
observed by the Crown in dealing with subjects, which I learned a very long time ago
to regard as elementary, is either not known or thought out of date. I should be glad
to think that I am mistaken.
In Hughes Aircraft Systems International v Airservices Australia,24 the Court held as
follows:
There is, I consider, much to be said for the view that, having no legitimate private
interest in the performance of its functions, a public body (including a state owned
company) should be required as of course to act fairly towards those with whom it
deals, at least in so far as this is consistent with its obligation to serve the public
interest (or interests) for which it has been created.
According to Lee, the model litigant obligation is important because of the following:25
The model litigant rules are very important because they are all about fair play, about
how government should conduct its litigation, about ensuring that the public has good
reason to trust its public officials and the way its public officials and lawyers conduct
litigation affecting rights of its own citizens. The Government must not abuse its
power. It must not act arbitrarily or capriciously.
The duty of a public body to serve the public interest and to act fairly towards those it
serves is therefore recognised as a positive duty in Australia. In P & C Cantarella,26 the
22
23
24
25
26
Section 9(1) of the Constitution provides that everyone is equal before the law and has the right to
equal protection and benefit of the law.
(1912) 15 CLR 333 para 342.
(1997) 76 FCR 151 para 196.
Lee The State as model litigant Victorian Government Solicitor‘s Office Lunchtime Seminar Series
2006 available at Institute of Australia http://www.ruleoflaw.org.au/priorities/model-litigant-rules/
accessed March 2016.
[1973] 2 NSWLR 366 page 383.
409
Court held that that the model litigant obligation extends from the executive‘s
obligations to justice as part of the rule of law:
The duty of the executive branch of government is to ascertain the law and obey it. If
there is any difficulty in ascertaining what the law is, as applicable to the particular
case, it is open to the executive to approach the court, or afford the citizen the
opportunity of approaching the court, to clarify the matter. Where the matter is before
the court it is the duty of the executive to assist the court to arrive at the proper and
just result.
The duty of an organ of state to act fairly towards the public is a powerful motivator for
the model litigant obligation. However, there is also a more controversial justification in
play. Chami states that in order to do justice, the imbalance in power and resources
between government and private litigants requires that government litigants act in a
manner which is more restrained than that expected of their opponents.27
This refers to the ―standard of fair play to be observed by the Crown in dealing with
subjects‖.28 Therefore, the model litigant obligation exists to level the playing field
between the state litigant, with the powerful public resources behind it, and the private
litigant, whose resources might be constrained and nowhere near the resources of the
state.
According to Appleby, the government is a repeat player in the justice system with a
large amount of resources at its disposal, and government lawyers often have a higher
public profile. Therefore, the government is said to enjoy a number of advantages,
including greater expertise and access to specialist knowledge in relation to substantive
law and court processes.29
6.3.2.2 Justification in South Africa
The analysis in section 2.8.2 in chapter 2 showed that the Constitution imposes positive
duties on organs of state when they engage in litigation. The duty to ensure the
27
Chami 2010 AIAL Forum 49.
28
Melbourne Steamship Co Ltd v Moorehead (1912) 15 CLR 333 342.
29
Appleby 2014 UNSW Law Journal 98.
410
effectiveness of the courts puts a positive obligation on the organs of state to place
relevant and material evidence before the courts.30
In South Africa, the primary source expressing the need for the model litigant obligation
is judicial pronouncement. This was articulated in Matatiele Municipality v President of
the Republic of South Africa,31 as follows:
In this respect, the Constitution requires candour on the part of government. What is
involved is not simply a matter of showing courtesy to the public and to the courts,
desirable though that always is. It is a question of maintaining respect for the
constitutional injunction that our democratic government be accountable, responsive
and open.
The Court further held that there is a strong need for government to provide an
explanation for the introduction of legislation. The foundational values of the rule of law
and of accountable government do not exist in discreet categories; they overlap and
reinforce each other.32 Openness of government promotes both the rationality that the
rule of law requires and the accountability that multi-party democracy demands. It is
therefore clear that the decision by an organ of state to litigate needs to be rationally
justified.
Public administration should be governed by the democratic values and principles
enshrined in the Constitution, including the following principles:33
(a)
A high standard of professional ethics must be promoted and maintained.
(b)
Efficient, economic and effective use of resources must be promoted.
(c)
Public administration must be accountable.
(d)
Transparency must be fostered by providing the public with timely,
accessible and accurate information.
30
31
32
33
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill Constitutional Litigation 4.
2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) para 107.
Para 110.
Section 195(1) of the Constitution.
411
The principles contained in section 195(1) apply to the administration in every sphere of
government, organs of state and public enterprises,34 which means the principles apply
when an organ of state acts as litigant in the courts as well.
Organs of state, through legislative and other measures, must assist and protect the
courts to ensure the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness
of the courts.35 Organs of state, as part of government, therefore have an obligation to
assist the judiciary in achieving justice. Organs of state should lead by example when
engaging in litigation; they should act as the ―model litigant‖.
It is important to realise – and it is recognised by the South African public sector
lawyers quoted above – that public sector lawyers derive their authority from the
Constitution. As such, their conduct should satisfy the positive duties imposed on the
state. Furthermore, they appear on behalf of state officials who are responsible and
accountable to the public, the very people against whom they litigate. The main duty of
public officials, and in particular the public sector lawyers, should be to enhance the
South African Constitution and the law. Furthermore, organs of state have no legitimate
private or self-interest of their own separate from the public interest they are
constitutionally bound to serve.36 Therefore, an organ of state should only take a
decision to litigate when the litigation would vindicate the Constitution and serve the
public interest.
6.4 Application of the model litigant obligation in South Africa
6.4.1 To whom should the model apply?
As was shown in section 5.5 of chapter 5, the courts are more than able to fulfil their
role as custos morum of the legal professions when private legal representatives or
their clients ignore or misuse the court process. The threat of an order of cost de bonis
propriis against the errant private legal representative or a punitve cost order against a
vexatious private litigant provides sufficient protection for the court process.
34
35
36
Section 195(2) of the Constitution.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution.
Hughes Aircraft v Airservices Australia (1997) 76 FCR para 151.
412
Furthermore, court rules and legislation provide protection against the misuse of the
court process by overzealous private litigants.
The Vexatious Proceedings Act37 may be used when a person has persistently and
without legal ground instituted legal proceedings against the same or different persons.
In terms of section 2(1)(b) of the Act, the court may order that no legal proceedings be
instituted by such a person without leave of the court. The purpose of the Act is to put
a stop to the persistent and ungrounded institution of legal proceedings. The Act does
so by allowing a court to screen a person who has persistently and without any
reasonable ground instituted legal proceedings in any court. This screening mechanism
protects two important interests, namely the interests of the victims of the vexatious
litigant who have been repeatedly subjected to the costs, harassment and
embarrassment of unmeritorious litigation, and the public interest that the functioning
of the courts and the administration of justice proceed unimpeded by the clog of
groundless proceedings.38
For the Act to be applied there are a number of prerequisites. The application to have a
person declared a vexatious litigant can be instituted by the state attorney or by a
person acting under his or her authority or by a person against whom legal proceedings
have been instituted or are being contemplated.39 Furthermore, a declaration is only
competent when a person has "persistently and without reasonable ground instituted
legal proceedings" in a division of the High Court or a magistrate's court. This does not
apply to an organ of state.
As far as procedural remedies are concerned, an edict of perpetual silence is a remedy
designed to put one who threatens legal action on terms to proceed with the action or
else to be subjected to an edict of perpetual silence.40 Therefore, the edict involves the
court telling the defendant to bring his claim within a set time, or to abandon it.
37
3 of 1956.
38
Beinash v Ernst & Young 1999 (2) SA 116 (CC)
Section 2(1)(a) and (b) of the Act.
Body Corporate - Montpark Drakens v Smuts (22380/05) 2006 ZAGPHC 38.
39
40
413
There is ample protection for the court and court process when a private litigant or
legal representative abuses the process.
6.4.2 Structure of the proposed model in South Africa
The guidelines are not meant to replace or supersede the Constitution or current legal
ethical and court rules. The guidelines should be drawn up in simple and unpretentious
language to give guidance to the state legal representative, the state instructing agent
and the organ of state about the positive constitutional duties they must comply with
when engaging in litigation. The proposed structure of the model in South Africa is
based on the model that is is in the State of Victoria in Australia.
In terms of the proposed model, organs of state, their legal representatives and
instructing agents are required –
(a)
to ensure that the instructing agent of the organ of state understands the
constitutional obligations placed on the state before embarking on litigation;
(b)
to act fairly in handling claims and litigation brought by or against the organ of
state;
(c)
to act consistently in the handling of claims and litigation;
(d)
to deal with claims promptly and not cause unnecessary delay;
(e)
to make an early assessment of –
(i)
the state‘s prospects of success in legal proceedings;
(ii)
the state‘s potential liability in claims against the state; and
(iii) pay legitimate claims without litigation, including making partial settlements
of claims or interim payments, where it is clear that liability is at least as
much as the amount paid;
(f)
to consider seeking to avoid and limit the scope of legal proceedings by taking
such steps, if any, as are reasonable, having regard to the nature of the dispute,
414
to resolve the dispute by agreement, including participating in alternative dispute
resolution (ADR) processes or settlement negotiations;
(g)
when it is not possible to avoid litigation, to ensure that the agent of the organ
of state instructing the state legal representative does so in writing and clearly
identifies him- or herself in the instructions, and that such written instructions
are made available to the court if it so requests;
(h)
when it is not possible to avoid litigation, to keep the costs of litigation to a
minimum, including by –
(i) not requiring the other party to prove a matter the state or the organ of
state knows to be true;
(ii) not contesting liability if the state or the organ of state believes that the
main dispute is about quantum;
(iii) taking such steps, if any, as are reasonable to resolve such matters as may
be resolved by agreement and to clarify and narrow the remaining issues in
dispute;
(iv) monitoring the progress of the litigation and, where appropriate, attempting
to resolve the litigation, including by settlement offers, offers of compromise
and ADR;
(v) placing all relevant evidence available to the litigating official or department
before the court to allow the proceedings to come to a just conclusion; and
(vi) not relying on technical arguments unless the state‘s or the agency‘s
interests would be prejudiced by the failure to comply with a particular
requirement;
(i)
not to take advantage of a claimant who lacks the resources to litigate a
legitimate claim;
415
(j)
not to undertake and pursue appeals, unless the organ of state believes that it
has reasonable prospects of success or the appeal is otherwise justified in the
public interest; and
(k)
to consider apologising when the organ of state becomes aware that it or its
representatives have acted wrongfully or improperly.
The guidelines require nine positive and three negative forms of behaviours from the
state litigant. The positive behaviours required from the state litigant are to ensure that
constitutional obligations are fulfilled, to act fairly, to act consistently, to act promptly
and to make an early assessment of the merits of the case, and, in addition, to give
written instructions before commencing litigation, which instructions should be made
available to the court at its request, to keep costs to a minimum, to have the necessary
authority to settle the case and to place all relevant evidence available to the state
litigant before the court.
The negative requirements are not to rely on technical arguments, not to take
advantage of a claimant who lacks resources to pursue a valid claim, and not to appeal
a decision unless there is the reasonable prospect of success.
The guidelines aim to ensure that the state legal representative, the instructing agent
and the organ of state act honestly, ethically and in accordance with court rules, the
law and the Constitution. The guidelines do not preclude the organ of state from
engaging in litigation when it has to protect valid public interests, especially in relation
to sensitive information that must be protected in the interest of national security, and
neither do the guidelines preclude the organ of state from striving to win its case and
seeking and enforcing cost orders.
These guidelines can be introduced by the legislature as amendments to court rules.
The guidelines can also be introduced by the Constitutional Court in terms of section
173 of the Constitution, which provides that the Constitutional Court, the Supreme
Court of Appeal and the High Court of South Africa each has the inherent power to
protect and regulate their own process. Guidelines compelling organs of state to act
416
morally in litigation would fall within the scope of the courts‘ regulating their own
processes.
Section 165(4) of the Constitution provides that organs of state, through legislative and
other measures, must assist and protect the courts to ensure the independence,
impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts. The language implies
an enforceable standard. Ensuring compliance with the guidelines should primarily be
the responsibility of the state legal representative and the organ of state for which he
or she appears. The guidelines can also be enforced by the courts in awarding cost de
bonis propriis against an offending legal representative or instructing agent of the state.
The guidelines will ensure that the state instructing agent is readily identifiable, should
the conduct of the official warrant a punitive cost order. In the case of serious
misconduct by the state legal representative, the courts can order the Law Society of
South Africa or General Council of the Bar to investigate the conduct of the offending
legal representative. Penalties can include suspension and even removal from the roll of
practising attorneys or advocates.
The Legal Practice Council, which is envisaged in Chapter 2 of the Legal Practice Act,41
can also develop or draft the guidelines. In terms of the Act, the proposed Council will
have the powers to develop norms and standards to guide the conduct of legal
practitioners, candidate legal practitioners and the legal profession.42
It is submitted that should guidelines of this nature be adopted in South Africa, they
would significantly reduce the volume of unwarranted government litigation before the
courts. State legal representatives and their instructing agents would have clear
guidelines on when the state may litigate and what obligations the state has to meet to
act morally and legally when litigating. The model litigant obligation could also assist in
realising substantive justice as argued in section 4.5.2 in chapter 4. When the playing
field is levelled by the moral litigant obligation, the private litigant can compete with the
state litigant on an equal footing, thereby allowing for constitutional violations to be
41
42
28 of 2014.
Section 6(b)(i) of the Act.
417
rectified and substantive justice to be realised. It is proposed that the courts adopt the
model litigant obligation, as currently in operation in Australian federal and state law, as
guidelines to ensure that the state adhere to its constitutional obligations and duties.
In Chapter 1, the question was asked what the constitutional limits to strategic litigation
involving the state are. The Constitution, correctly interpreted, applied and enforced,
provides for ample protection against organs of state misusing the courts and the
litigation process. Section 165 of the Constitution provides for an independent judiciary
and states emphatically that no person or organ of state may interfere with the
functioning of the courts and that organs of state, through legislative and other
measures, must assist and protect the courts to ensure the independence, impartiality,
dignity, accessibility and effectiveness of the courts.43 Furthermore, section 9 of the
Constitution provides for equality before the law and the right to equal protection and
benefit of the law. Section 195 of the Constitution requires ethical conduct by an organ
of state when it engages in litigation. However, these limitations imposed on the state
litigant are often ignored or incorrectly applied by state legal representatives, their
instructing agents and the courts owing to the lack of effective and enforceable
guidelines setting out the constitutional duties of organs of state when litigating. The
model litigant obligation or guidelines can provide sufficient protection for the individual
or organisation litigating against an organ of state, thereby removing unconstitutional
limitations to strategic litigation.
43
Section 165(3) and (4) of the Constitution.
418
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Literature
Ackermann 2004 New Zealand LR
Ackermann LWH ―The legal nature of the South African constitutional revolution‖
2004 New Zealand LR 4 633-646
Adelman 1994 Journal of Law and Society
Adelman S ―Accountability and Administrative Law in South Africa's Transition to
Democracy‖ Journal of Law and Society Vol. 21 No. 3 1994 317-328
Akkas 2004 Bond Law Review
Akkas SA ―Appointment of Judges: A Key Issue of Judicial Independence‖ Bond
Law Review Vol 16 2 Article 8 2004 200-210
Alarie and Green 2009 Osgoode Hall Law Journal
Alarie B and Green B ―Policy preference change and appointments to the
Supreme Court of Canada‖ Osgoode Hall Law Journal 47.1 2009 1-46
Amit 2011 SAJHR
Amit R ―Winning isn‘t everything: Courts, context, and the barriers to effecting
change through public interest litigation‖ SAJHR 27 2011 8-38
Anderson 1990 Stan. L. Rev.
Anderson DL ―Note, when restraint requires activism: Partisan gerrymandering
and the status quo ante‖ Stan. L. Rev. 42 1990 1549-1559
Anderson 1993 Third World Legal Studies
Anderson MR ―Litigation and Activism: The Bhopal Case‖ Third World Legal
Studies Vol. 12 Article 11 1993 177-187
Andrews 2006 Osgoode Hall Law Journal
Andrews PE ―The South African Judicial Appointments Process‖ Osgoode Hall
Law Journal Volume 44 Number 3 2006 565-572
419
Appleby 2014 UNSW Law Journal
Appleby G ―The government as litigant‖ UNSW Law Journal Vol 37(1) 2014 94124
Barkin 1990 U. Miami L. Rev.
Barkin JM ―The Hohfeldian approach to law and semiotics‖ 44 U. Miami L. Rev.
1119 1990 1119-1142
Barry 2014 TSAR
Barry GN ―Impeachment on the Highveld: the dismissal of Chief Justice Kotzé by
President Paul Kruger on 16 February 1898‖ TSAR 4 2014
Bax and Van der Tang 1993 ―Theses on control‖
Bax C and Van der Tang G ―Theses on control in Constitutional Law‖ in Zoethout
et al Control in Constitutional Law (Kluwer Academic Publishers 1993)
Baxter 1984 Administrative Law
Baxter Administrative Law (Juta 1984)
Bilchitz and Williams 2012 SAJHR
Bilchitz D and Williams A 2012 ―Religion and the public sphere: Towards a model
that positively recognises diversity‖ 28 SAJHR 146 2012 146-175
Bishop 2008 ―Remedies‖
Bishop M ―Remedies‖ in Woolman S, Michael Bishop M, and Brickhill J (eds)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd (Juta 2008)
Blackstone 1765 Commentaries
Blackstone W Commentaries on the laws of England Book IV (Oxford Clarendon
Press 1765)
Bluntschli 2000 The Theory of the State
Bluntschli JK The Theory of the State (Batoche Books 2000)
Bork 1990 The Tempting of America
420
Bork RH The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law (New York
The Free Press 1990)
Bosman and Hosten 1979 Inleiding tot die Suid-Afrikaanse reg en regsleer
Bosman F and Hosten WJ Inleiding tot die Suid-Afrikaanse reg en regsleer
(Butterworth 1979)
Botein 1952 Trial judge
Botein B Trial judge (Simon and Schuster Inc. New York 1952)
Botha, Van der Walt and Van der Walt 2003 Rights and Democracy
Botha H, Van der Walt AJ and Van der Walt CJ Rights and Democracy in a
Transformative Constitution (African Sun Media 2003)
Boyer 1999 New Yorker
Boyer PJ ―Big Guns‖ New Yorker May 17 1999
Brownlie 2012 Basic Documents
Brownlie I Basic Documents in International Law 6th ed (Oxford University Press
2012)
Busky 2000 Democratic Socialism
Busky DF Democratic Socialism: A Global Survey (Greenwood Publishing
2000)
Cameron 1987 ―Legal Standing and the Emergency‖
Cameron C ―Legal Standing and the Emergency‖ in Haysom and Mangan (eds)
Emergency Law Johannesburg Centre for Applied Legal Studies 1987
Cappelletti 985 Catholic University Law Review
Cappelletti M ―Repudiating Montesquieu? The expansion and legitimacy of
Constitutional Justice" Catholic University Law Review Volume 35 Issue 1 1985 132
Cardozo 1946 The nature of the judicial process
421
Cardozo BN The nature of the judicial process 13th Printing (Yale University Press
1946)
Carroll 2002 Constitutional and Administrative law
Carroll A Constitutional and Administrative law (Harlew Longman 2002)
Chami 2010 AIAL Forum
Chami Z ―The obligation to act as a model litigant‖ AIAL Forum 64 2010 47-59
Chaskalson 2000 SAJHR
Chaskalson A ―The Third Bram Fischer Memorial Lecture: Human dignity as a
foundational value of our constitutional order‖ SAJHR (16) 193 2000 193-205
Chayes 1976 Harvard Law Review
Chayes A ―The role of the judge in Public Law Litigation‖ Harvard Law Review Vol
89 No 7 1976 1281-1316
Choudhry 2009 Constitutional Court Review
Choudhry S ―He had a mandate: The South African Constitutional Court and the
African National Congress in a dominant party democracy‖ Constitutional Court
Review 2 2009 1-86
Connaghan 2003 University of Miami Law Review
Connaghan J ―Schlag in Wonderland‖ University of Miami Law Review 543 2003
543-571
Cooper-Stephenson 1990 Charter Damages Claims
Cooper-Stephenson K Charter Damages Claims (Carswell Toronto 1990)
Corder 1988 Essays On Law
Corder H (ed) Essays On Law and Social Practice in South Africa (Juta 1988)
Corder 2004 Legal Studies
Corder H ―Judicial authority in a changing South Africa‖ Legal Studies Volume 24
Issue 1-2 2004 253-274
422
Corder 1992 SALJ
Corder H ―Lessons from (North) America (Beware the ‗legalization of politics‘ and
the ‗political seduction of the Law‘)‖ 109 SALJ 204 1992 204-224
Corder 1984 Judges
Corder H Judges at work (Juta 1984)
Craig 1994 Administrative Law
Craig P Administrative Law 3rd ed (London Sweet and Maxwell 1994)
Currie and De Waal 2001 The new constitutional and administrative law
Currie I and De Waal J The new constitutional and administrative law Volume 1
(Juta & Company 2001)
Currie and De Waal 2005 The Bill of Rights Handbook
Currie I and De Waal J The Bill of Rights Handbook 5th ed (Juta 2005)
Dahl 1957 J. Pub. L.
Dahl RA ―Decision-making in a democracy: The Supreme Court as a national
policy-maker‖ 6 J. Pub. L. 279 1957 279-295
Damaska 1998 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series
Damaska MR ―Truth in adjudication‖ Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series
Paper 1575 1998 289-308
Davies 2006 SAJHR
Davies DM ―Adjudicating the Socio-Economic Rights in the South African
Constitution: Towards ‗Deference Lite‘?‖ SAJHR 22 301 2006 301-327
Davis et al Fundamental Rights
Davis D et al Fundamental Rights in the Constitution 1st ed (Juta 1997)
Davis 2006 Acta Juridica
423
Davis DM ―To Defer and then When? Administrative Law and Constitutional
Democracy‖ Acta Juridica: Comparing Administrative Justice across the
Commonwealth 2006 23-41
De Beer and Vettori 2007 PELJ
De Beer RJ and Vettori S ―The enforcement of socio-economic rights‖ PELJ (10)3
2007 2-26
De Klerk 2010 PELJ
De Klerk FW ―Future perspective on constitutional stability‖ PELJ (13)2 2010 2-13
De Vos and Freedman 2014 South African Constitutional Law
De Vos P and Freedman W South African Constitutional Law in Context (Oxford
University Press 2014)
De Vries 2006 Politeia
De Vries ID ―Courts: The weakest link in the democratic system in South Africa:
A power perspective‖ Politeia Vol 25 No1 2006 41-56
Dean 1986 SAJHR
Dean WHB ―Our Administrative Law – A dismal science‖ SAJHR 2 1986 164-176
Denvir 1975 N.C. L. Rev.
Denvir J ―Towards a political theory of public interest litigation‖ N.C. L. Rev. 54
1975-1976 1133-1160
Devenish 2003 THRHR
Devenish GE ―The doctrine of separation of powers with special reference to
events in South Africa and Zimbabwe‖ THRHR 2003 84-99
Devenish 1998 A Commentary
Devenish GE A Commentary on the South African Constitution (Butterworths
Durban 1998)
Dicey 1959 Introduction to the Study of the Law
424
Dicey AV Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution 10th ed
(Macmillan Press London 1959)
Du Plessis 2005 PELJ
Du Plessis L ―Learned Staatsrecht from the heartland of the Rechtsstaat‖ PELJ
(8)1 2005 77-106
Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill 2013 Constitutional Litigation
Du Plessis M, Penfold G and Brickhill J Constitutional Litigation (Juta 2013)
Dworkin 1977 Taking Rights Seriously
Dworkin R Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press 1977)
Dworkin 2008 Is Democracy Possible Here?
Dworkin R Is Democracy Possible Here? Principles for a New Political Debate
(Princeton University Press 2008)
Dyzenhaus 1998 SAJHR
Dyzenhaus D ―Law as Justification: Etienne Mureinik‘s conception of legal
culture‖ SAJHR 14 1998 11-37
Dyzenhaus 1998 Judging the judges
Dyzenhaus D Judging the judges, judging ourselves: Truth, reconciliation and the
apartheid legal order (Oxford: Hart Publishing 1998)
Ellmann 2009 Constitutional Court Review
Ellmann S ―Making the path of the Law‖ Constitutional Court Review 2 2009 97143
Ewing The Modern Law Review
Ewing KD ―The Human Rights Act and Parliamentary democracy‖ The Modern
Law Review Vol 62 Issue 1 2003 79-99
Fallon 1984 N.Y.U. L. Rev.
425
Fallon RH ―Of justiciability, remedies, and public law litigation: notes on the
jurisprudence of Lyons‖ 59 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1 1984 1-75
Faure and Lane 1996 Designing new political institutions
Faure M and Lane J South Africa: Designing new political institutions (Sage
Publications 1996)
Fernandez-Armesro 1999 Truth: A History and a guide
Fernandez-Armesro F Truth: A History and a guide for the perplexed (St. Martin‘s
Press New York 1999)
Figgis and Laurence 1990 Lord Acton
Figgis JN and Laurence RV Lord Acton in letter to Bishop Mandell Creighton April
5 1887 published in Historical Essays and Studies (London: Macmillan 1990)
Friedman 2006 New York University Law and Economics Working Papers
Friedman B ―The Politics of Judicial Review‖ New York University Law and
Economics Working Papers Paper 45 2006 257-337
Fuller and Winston 1978 Harvard Law Review
Fuller LL and Winston KI ―The forms and limits of adjudication‖ Harvard Law
Review Vol. 92 No. 2 1978 353-409
Gani 2004 Advocate
Gani H ―Aspects of practice‖ Advocate April 2004 40-41
Gildenhuys and Knipe 2000 The Organisation of Government
Gildenhuys JSH and Knipe A The Organisation of Government (Van Schaik 2000)
Giliomee, Myburgh and Schlemmer 2001 Democratization
Giliomee H, Myburgh J & Schlemmer L ―Dominant party rule, opposition parties
and minorities in South Africa‖ Democratization 2001 161-182
Goodsell 2007 BYU J. Pub. L.
426
Goodsell T ―Constitution, custom, and creed: Balancing human rights concerns
with cultural and religious freedom in today's South Africa‖ 21 BYU J. Pub. L. 109
2007 111-154
Govindjee et al 2009 Introduction to Human Rights
Govindjee A et al Introduction to Human Rights Law (LexisNexis 2009)
Guest 1997 Ronald Dworkin
Guest S Ronald Dworkin 2nd ed (Edinburgh University Press 1997)
Guthrie 1967 The Greek Philosophers
Guthrie WKC The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle (London Methuen
1967)
Hamilton, Madison and Jay 1968 The Federalist
Hamilton A, Madison J and Jay J The Federalist Papers (Toronto Bantam Books.
1982)
Harcourt 1996 Harvard Human Rights Journal
Harcourt BE ―Mature adjudication: Interpretive choice in recent death penalty
cases‖ 9 Harvard Human Rights Journal 1996 266-268
Harms 2009 PELJ
Harms LTC ―Judging under a Bill Of Rights‖ PELJ (12)3 2009 2-20
Hart 1961 The concept of law
Hart HLA The concept of law 2nd ed (Clarendon Press 1961)
Hart 1994 The concept of law
Hart HLA The concept of law 2nd ed (Clarendon Law Series 1994)
Hertogh and Halliday 2004 Judicial review
Hertogh M and Halliday S Judicial review and bureaucratic impact in future
research (Cambridge University Press 2004)
Hiemstra 2005 Trilingual Legal Dictionary
427
Hiemstra Trilingual Legal Dictionary 6th ed (Juta 2005)
Hoexter 2000 SALJ
Hoexter C ―The future of judicial review in South African administrative law‖ SALJ
117 484 2000 484-519
Hoexter 2012 Administrative Law
Hoexter C Administrative Law in South Africa 2nd ed (Juta 2012)
Hoexter and Olivier 2014 The judiciary in South Africa
Hoexter C and Olivier M The judiciary in South Africa (Juta and Company Ltd
2014)
Hoffmann 2011 Lewis and Kyrou‘s Handy hints
Hoffmann IM Lewis and Kyrou‘s Handy hints on legal practice 3rd ed (LexisNexis
2011)
Hohfeld 1913 Yale L.J.
Hohfeld WN ―Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial
Reasoning‖ 23 Yale L.J. 16 1913 16-59
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ
Hulme D and Pete SA ―Vox populi? Vox humbug! – Rising tension between the
South African executive and judiciary considered in historical context – Part one‖
PELJ (15) 5 2012 16-43
Hulme and Pete 2012 PELJ
Hulme D and Pete SA ―Vox populi? Vox humbug! – Rising tension between the
South African executive and judiciary considered in historical context – Part two‖
PELJ (15) 5 2012 45-67
Jackson and Tushnet 2006 Comparative Constitutional Law
Jackson VC and Tushnet M Comparative Constitutional Law 2nd ed (Foundation
Press 2006)
428
Jaffe 1968 U. Pa. L. Rev.
Jaffe LJ ―The Citizen as Litigant in Public Actions: The Non-Hohfeldian or
Ideological Plaintiff‖ 116 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1968 1033-1047
Jones 2002 Regent University Law Review
Jones G ―Proper judicial activism‖ Regent University Law Review Vol 14 2002
141-179
Jowell and Oliver 2007 The Changing Constitution
Jowell J and Oliver D The Changing Constitution 6th ed (Oxford 2007)
Kalven and Rosenfield 1941 University of Chicago Law Review
Kalven H Jr and Rosenfield M ―The contemporary function of class suit‖
University of Chicago Law Review 684 1941 684-721
Kelbrick 2010 Civil Procedure
Kelbrick R Civil Procedure in South Africa (Kluwer Law International 2010)
Kende 2003 CHAP. L. REV.
Kende MS ―The South African Constitutional Court's embrace of socio-economic
rights: A comparative perspective‖ 6 CHAP. L. REV. 137 160 2003 137-160
Kennedy 1986 Journal of Legal Education
Kennedy D ―Freedom and constraint in adjudication: A critical phenomenology‖
Journal of Legal Education 1986 518-562
Klare 1998 SAJHR
Klare KE ―Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism‖ 14 SAJHR 1998
146-188
Klug 2000 Constituting democracy
Klug H Constituting democracy: Law, globalism and South Africa's political
reconstruction (Cambridge University Press 2000)
Koopmans 2003 Courts and Political Institutions
429
Koopmans T Courts and Political Institutions: A Comparative View (Cambridge
University Press 2003)
Kriel 2013 DEREBUS
Kriel K ―Public sector lawyers – lawyers first, public sector employees second‖
DEREBUS 12 2013
Labuschagne 2004 Politeia
Labuschagne P ―State instability in South Africa: a matter of an organic state
trapped within constitutional state?‖ Politeia Vol 30 No 2 2011 4-24
Labuschagne 2011 Politeia
Labuschagne P ―The doctrine of separation of powers and its application in South
Africa‖ Politeia Vol 23 No 3 2004 84-102
Labuschagne 2007 n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding
Labuschagne PAH n Funksionele en strukturele ontleding van die 1993- en 1996-
Grondwet met spesiale verwysing na die Trias Politica-Leerstuk Doctoral Thesis
UNISA (unpublished) 2007
Laing and Wilcox 2014 The natural law reader
Laing J and Wilcox R The natural law reader (Wiley Blackwell 2014)
Landman 2000 Judge‘s Forum Advocate First Term
Landman A ―Impeaching the judges: South Africa's copybook‖ Judge‘s Forum
Advocate First Term 2000 43-44
Langa 2006 Stell LR
Langa P ―Transformative constitutionalism‖ Stell LR 3 2006 351-360
Le Roux 2009 ―Six (individually-named) notes‖
Le Roux W ―Six (individually-named) notes on the counter-aesthetics of refusal‖
in Karin van Marle Refusal, transition and post-apartheid law (African Sun Media
2009)
430
Leighninger 2009 Cape
Leighninger M Democracy, Growing Up The Shifts That Reshaped Local Politics and
Foreshadowed the 2008 Presidential Election Cape 5 2009 1-16
Lenta 2004 SAJHR
Lenta P ―Democracy, Rights Disagreements and Judicial Review‖ 20 SAJHR 1/20
2004 1-31
Liebenberg and Quinot 2012 Law and poverty
Liebenberg S and Quinot G Law and poverty: Perspectives from South Africa and
beyond (Juta 2012)
Little 2001 Conn. L. Rev.
Little MA ―A Most dangerous indiscretion: The legal, economic, and political
legacy of the Governments' tobacco litigation‖ 33 Conn. L. Rev. 1143 2000-2001
1143-1205
Loubser and Midgley 2009 The Law of Delict
Loubser M and Midgley R The Law of Delict in South Africa (Cape Town Oxford
University Press 2009)
Malan 2014 PELJ
Malan K ―Reassessing judicial independence and impartiality against the
backdrop of judicial appointments in South Africa‖ PELJ (17)5 2014 1965-2040
Malherbe and Van Eck 2009 TSAR
Malherbe R and Van Eck M ―The state‘s failure to comply with its constitutional
duties and its impact on democracy‖ TSAR 2 2009 209-223
Marnewick 2007 Litigation skills
Marnewick CG Litigation skills for South African Lawyers 2 ed (LexisNexis
Butterworths 2007)
Mbazira 2009 Constitutional Court Review
431
Mbazira C ―The role of transboundary dialogue: A response to Stephen Ellmann‖
Constitutional Court Review 2 2009
Mbazira 2007 Enforcing the economic, social and cultural rights in the South African
Constitution
Mbazira C Enforcing the economic, social and cultural rights in the South African
Constitution as justiciable individual rights: the role of judicial remedies Doctoral
Thesis (unpublished) University of the Western Cape 2007
McGregor 2014 SA Merc LJ
McGregor M ‖Blowing the whistle? The future of affirmative action in South
Africa‖ (Part 1) 26 SA Merc LJ 60 2014 60-92
McLean 2009 Constitutional deference
McLean K Constitutional deference, courts and socio-economic rights in South
Africa PULP 2009
Michelman 2008 ―Constitutional supremacy‖
Michelman FI ―Constitutional supremacy and appellate jurisdiction in South
Africa‖ in Woolman S, Roux T and Bishop M Constitutional Law of South Africa
2nd ed (Juta 2008)
Michelman 2008 ―The rule of law‖
Michelman FI ―The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the Constitution‖ in
Woolman S, Roux T and Bishop M Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (Juta
2008)
Mnyongani 2012 Stellenbosch Law Review
Mnyongani FD ―Duties of a lawyer in a multicultural society: A customary law
perspective?‖ Stellenbosch Law Review 352 2012 352-369
Mojapelo 2013 The doctrine of separation of powers
Mojapelo PM The doctrine of separation of powers (a South African perspective)
Paper delivered at the Middle Temple South Africa Conference Advocate 2013
432
Molot 2003 Yale Law Journal
Molot JT ―An old judicial role for a new litigation era‖ Yale Law Journal Vol. 113
27 2003 27-118
Montesquieu 1748 The Spirit of the laws
Montesquieu The Spirit of the laws (The Federalist Papers 1748)
Motala and Ramaphosa 2002 Constitutional Law
Motala Z and Ramaphosa C Constitutional Law: Analysis and Cases (Oxford
2002)
Mureinik 1994 SAJHR
Mureinik AA ―Bridge to Where? Introducing the Interim Bill of Rights‖ SAJHR 10
31 1994 31-48
Mureinik 1986 SALJ
Mureinik E ―Administrative Law in South Africa‖ SALJ 103 615 1986 615-645
Mureinik 1988 ―Dworkin and apartheid‖
Mureinik E ―Dworkin and apartheid‖ in Corder H (ed) Essays on Law and Social
Practice (Juta 1988)
Nishihara 2001 PELJ
Nishihara H ―The significance of constitutional values‖ PELJ (4)1 2001 1-16
Nordht 2001 DJCIL
Nordht R ―Group actions in Sweden: Reflections on the purpose of civil litigation,
the need for reforms, and a forthcoming proposal‖ 11 DJCIL 381 2001 381-404
O‘Regan 2008 ―On the reach of the Constitution‖
O‘Regan K ―On the reach of the Constitution and the nature of constitutional
jurisdiction: A reply to Frank Michelman‖ in Woolman S and Bishop M (eds)
Constitutional Conversations (PULP 2008)
O‘Regan 2005 PELJ
433
O‘Regan K ―Checks and balances reflections on the development of the doctrine
of separation of powers under the South African Constitution‖ PELJ (8)1 2005
120-150
Okpaluba and Osode 2010 Government liability
Okpaluba C and Osode PC Government liability (Juta 2010)
Olmstead 1990 History of Religion
Olmstead CE History of Religion in the United States Prentice-Hall Englewood
Cliffs N.J. 1990
Oseko 2011 Judicial independence in Kenya
Oseko JO Judicial independence in Kenya: constitutional challenges and
opportunities for reform Doctoral Thesis (unpublished) University of Leicester
2011
Pennock and Smith 1964 Political science
Pennock JR and Smith DG Political science: An introduction (New York:
Macmillan 1964)
Peté et al 2011 Civil Procedure
Peté et al Civil Procedure: a Practical Guide 2nd ed (Oxford 2011)
Pieterse 2004 SAJHR
Pieterse M ―Coming to terms with the judicial enforcement of socio-economic
rights‖ SAJHR 20 3 2004 418-447
Plasket 2009 Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science
Plasket C ―South Africa (a country report entitled Representative Standing in
South African Law" Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social
Science 256 (2009)
Posner 1990 The problems of jurisprudence
Posner RA The problems of jurisprudence (Harvard University Press 1990)
434
Pretorius 2010 SAJHR
Pretorius JL ―Fairness in transformation: A critique of the Constitutional Court's
affirmative action jurisprudence‖ SAJHR 536 2010 536-570
Radbruch 2006 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
Radbruch GR ―Five minutes of legal philosophy (1945)‖ Oxford Journal of Legal
Studies Vol 26 no 1 2006 13-15
Ranchod 2007 Policy: Issues & Actors
Ranchod K ―State-civil society relations in South Africa: some lessons from
engagement‖ Policy: Issues & Actors Volume 20 no 7 2007 1-23
Rautenbach and Malherbe 1996 Constitutional Law
Rautenbach IM and Malherbe EFJ Constitutional Law 2nd ed (Butterworths 1996)
Roach 1995 Constitutional Remedies in Canada
Roach KW Constitutional Remedies in Canada (Ontario Canada Law Book Inc
1995)
Roskin 2015 e-Study Guide for: Political Science
Roskin MG e-Study Guide for: Political Science: An Introduction Chapter 3:
Political ideologies Content 13th ed (Technologies Inc Publications 2015)
Roux 2002 Forum Constitutionnel
Roux T ―Understanding Grootboom — A response to Cass R Sunstein‖ Forum
Constitutionnel 12:2 2002 41-51
Roux 2013 The politics of principle
Roux T The politics of principle (Cambridge University Press 2013)
Scheuerman 1993 Oregon Law Review
Scheuerman KE ―Rethinking judicial elections‖ Oregon Law Review 72 459 1993
459-485
Schmitt 1927 The Concept of the Political
435
Schmitt C The Concept of the Political Chapter 7 in Crisis of Parliamentary
Democracy (Rutgers University Press 1927)
Schokman, Creasey and Mohen 2012 Short guide: Strategic litigation
Schokman B, Creasey D and Mohen P Short guide: Strategic litigation and its role
in promoting and protecting human rights (Advocates for International
Development 2012)
Shapiro 1981 Courts: A comparative and political analysis
Shapiro M Courts: A comparative and political analysis (The University of Chicago
Press 1981)
Southall 2014 Africa Spectrum
Southall R "Threats to Constitutionalism by Liberation Movements in Southern
Africa" 2014 Africa Spectrum 79-99
Sunstein 2001 Constitutional Forum
Sunstein CR ―Social and economic rights? Lessons from South Africa‖
Constitutional Forum 11:4 2001 123-132
Sweet 2003 Faculty Scholarship Series
Sweet AS ―Why Europe rejected American judicial review - and why it may not
matter‖ Faculty Scholarship Series Paper 1297 2003 2744-2780
Tacitus 1894 Germania
Tacitus Germania Aberdeen Translated into English by K. B. Townshend
(University Press 1894)
Thornton 1996 Legislative Drafting
Thornton GC Legislative Drafting 4th edition (Butterworths 1996)
Tobias 2008 U. Rich. Rev
Tobias C ―Reconsidering Virginia‘s judicial selection‖ 43 U. Rich. Rev. 37 2008 3749
436
Turley HARV. J. ON LEGIS
Turley JA ―Crisis of faith: Tobacco and the Madisonian democracy‖ HARV. J. ON
LEGIS 37 2000 433-482
Unknown 2008 Mail & Guardian
Unknown ―ANC meets forum over Merafong demarcation‖ Mail & Guardian 25
Jun 2008
Van der Vyver 2000 Emory Int'l L. Rev.
Van der Vyver ―State-sponsored proselytization: A South African experience‖ 14
Emory Int'l L. Rev. 779 815 2000 797-848
Van der Westhuizen 2008 AHRLJ
Van der Westhuizen J ―A few reflections on the role of courts, government, the
legal profession, universities, the media and civil society in a constitutional
democracy‖ AHRLJ 8 2008 251-272
Van Doren 1986 SALJ
Van Doren JW ―Critical Legal Studies and South Africa‖ SALJ 106 1986 648-661
Van Heerden, Govindjee and Holness 2014 Speculum Juris
Van Heerden A, Govindjee A and Holness D ―The constitutionality of statutory
limitation to the right of access to information held by the state in South Africa‖
Speculum Juris (1) 2014 27-54
Van Marle 2010 SALJ
Van Marle K ―Jurisprudence, friendship and the university as heterogeneous
public space‖ 127 SALJ 628 2010 628-645
Van Zyl 2009 PELJ
Van Zyl D ―The judiciary as a bastion of the legal order in challenging times‖
PELJ (12)2 2009 2-13
Vanderbilt 1953 Nw. U.L. Rev.
437
Vanderbilt AT ―The essentials of a sound judicial system‖ 48 Nw. U.L. Rev. 1
1953 1-15
Venter 2007 Speculum Juris
Venter F ―Judges, politics and the separation of powers‖ Speculum Juris (1) 2007
60-74
Venter 2003 PELJ
Venter F ―Politics, socio-economic issues and culture in constitutional
adjudication‖ PELJ (6)2 2003 129-166
Venter 2012 McGill Law Journal
Venter F ―South Africa: A Diceyan Rechtsstaat?‖ McGill Law Journal / Revue de
droit de McGill Vol 57 no 4 2012 727-747
Venter 2005 ZaöRV
Venter F ―The Politics of Constitutional Adjudication‖ ZaöRV 65 2005 129-166
Venter 2001 PELJ
Venter F ―Utilizing constitutional values in constitutional comparison‖ PELJ (4)1
2001 1-22
Venter 2015 Constitutionalism and religion
Venter F Constitutionalism and religion (Edward Elgar Publishing 2015)
Vick 2002 Texas International Law Journal
Vick DW ―The Human Rights Act and the British Constitution‖ Texas International
Law Journal Volume 3 2002 329-372
Volcansek 2007 Fordham Urb. L.J.
Volcansek ML ―Appointing judges the European way‖ Fordham Urb. L.J. Vol
XXXIV 2007 363-385
Wade and Bradley 1985 Constitutional and Administrative law
438
Wade ECS and Bradley AW Constitutional and Administrative law 10th ed
(Longman 1985)
Weerda 1960 Calvin
Weerda J Calvin Evangelisches Soziallexikon 3rd ed (Stuttgart col. 210 1960)
Wesson 2004 SAJHR
Wesson M ―Grootboom and beyond: Reassessing the socioeconomic
jurisprudence of the South African Constitutional Court‖ 20 SAJHR 2004 284-308
Whitman 1980 Mich Law Review
Whitman CB ―Constitutional Torts‖ Mich Law Review 79 1980 5-71
Wolf 1946 Tradition
Wolf HJ ―The origin of judicial litigation among the Greeks‖ Tradition Vol 4 1946
31-87
Woolman 2008 ―Application‖
Woolman S ―Application‖ in Woolman S, Roux T and Bishop M (eds)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (Juta 2008)
Woolman and Bishop 2008 Constitutional Conversations
Woolman S and Bishop M (eds) Constitutional Conversations (PULP 2008)
Woolman, Roux and Bishop 2008 Constitutional Law
Woolman S, Roux T and Bishop M (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed
(Juta 2008)
Woolman 2007 SALJ
Woolman S ―The amazing, vanishing Bill of Rights‖ SALJ Vol 124 4 2007 762-794
Woolman 2007 The selfless Constitution
Woolman SC The selfless Constitution: Experimentation & flourishing as the
foundations of South Africa‘s basic law Doctoral Thesis (Unpublished) University
of Pretoria 2007
439
Case law
South Africa
Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement SA v Premier of the Province of KwaZulu-Natal 2010
(2) BCLR 99 (CC)
Abdi v Minister of Home Affairs (734/10) [2011] ZASCA 2 (2011)
Adbro Investment Company Limited v Minister of the Interior 1961 (3) 283 (T)
Administrator, Transvaal, and Others v Zenzile and Others 1991 (1) SA 21 (A)
Affordable Medicines Trust and Others v Minister of Health and Others 2006 (3) SA 247
(CC)
AS v Minister of Home Affairs (SGHC) unreported case no 101/2010 (12 January 2010)
Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation [1948] 1 KB 223
August and Another v Electoral Commission and Others 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC)
Azanian Peoples Organisation (AZAPO) and Others v President of the Republic of South
Africa and Others 1996 (4) SA 671 (CC)
Bacela v MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government 1998 1 All SA 525 (E)
Bakamundo v Minister of Home Affairs (SGHC) unreported case no 17271/2009 (12 May
2009)
Bannatyne v Bannatyne (Commission for Gender Equality, as amicus curiae) 2003 (2)
SA 363 (CC)
Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Environmental Affairs 2004 (4) SA 490 (CC)
Beinash v Ernst & Young 1999 (2) SA 116 (CC)
440
Body Corporate - Montpark Drakens v Smuts (22380/05) 2006 ZAGPHC 38
Bosman v Bredell 1932 CPD 385
Brenner's Service Station and Garage (Pty) Ltd v Milne and Another 1983 (4) SA 233
(W)
Bushula and others v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape and
Another 2000 (2) SA 849 (E)
Cape Society v Vorster 1949 (3) SA 421 (C)
Carmichele v Minster of Safety and Security and Another 2003 (2) SA 656 (CC)
Centre for Child Law and Others v Minister of Basic Education and Others 2013 (3) SA
183 (ECG)
Children's Institute v Presiding Officer, Children's Court, Krugersdorp, and Others 2013
(2) SA 620 (CC)
Children's Resource Centre Trust and Others v Pioneer Food (Pty) Ltd and Others 2013
(2) SA 213 (SCA)
Chirwa v Transnet Limited and Others (2008) 29 ILJ 73 (CC)
Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education 2000 (4) SA 757 (CC)
City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (17 February 1998)
City of Cape Town v South African National Roads Agency Ltd and Others 2015 (3) SA
386 (SCA)
City of Johannesburg v Rand Properties (Pty) Ltd 2006 6 BCLR 728 (W)
441
Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso and Others v
Commanding Officer Port Elizabeth Prison and Others 1995 (4) SA 631 (22
September 1995)
Committee for Justice and Liberty v National Energy Board (1976) 68 DLR (3d) 716
Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v
Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home
Affairs and Others 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC)
De Lange v Smuts 1998 3 SA 785 (CC)
De Vos and Another v Minister of Constitutional Development and Others; Snyders and
Another v Minister of Constitutional Development and Others Case No 4502/10;
Case No 5825/14 WC 2015
Democratic Alliance v Ethekwini Municipality 2012 (2) SA 151 (SCA)
Democratic Alliance v President of the Republic of South Africa 2010 ZAGPPHC 194
Democratic Alliance v South African Broadcasting Corporation Ltd and Others 2015 (1)
SA 551 (WCC)
Disciplinary Committee for Legal Practitioners v Murorua and Another 2012 (2) NR 481
(HC)
Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others 2006 (6)
SA 416 (CC)
DS v RM 2015 (3) SA 424 (WCC)
Du Plessis v De Klerk 1996 3 SA 850 (CC)
East London Local Transitional Council v MEC of Health, Eastern Cape 2001 3 SA 1133
(CK)
442
East Zulu Motors (Pty) v Empangeni/Ngwlezane Transitional Local Council and Others
1998 (2) SA 61 (CC)
Eveleth v Minister of Home Affairs & Another 2004 (11) BCLR 1223 (T)
Ex Parte Minister of Safety and Security and Others: In Re S v Walters and Another
2002 (4) SA 613 (CC)
Ex parte Minister of Social Development 2006 5 BCLR 604 (CC)
Ex parte Nell 1963 (1) SA 754 (A)
Executive Council, Western Cape Legislature v President of the Republic of South Africa
1995 (4) SA 877 (CC)
Executors of McCorkindale v Bok 1884 1 SAR 202
Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC)
Faircape Property Developers (Pty) Ltd v Premier, Western Cape 2002 6 SA 180 (C)
Federation of Governing Bodies of South African Schools (Gauteng) v MEC for Education
Gauteng 2002 1 SA 660 (T)
Fedsure Life Assurance & others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan
Council and Others Case 1999 (1) SA 374
Ferreira v Levin NO and Others; Vryenhoek and Others v Powell NO and Others 1996
(1) SA 984 (CC)
First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v Commissioner for the South African
Revenue Services and Another; First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v
Minister of Finance 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (16 May 2002)
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC)
443
Freedom Under Law v National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others [2013] 4 All
SA 657 (GNP)
Gaertner and Others v Minister of Finance and Others 2013 (4) SA 87 (WCC)
Gauteng Gambling Board and Another v MEC for Economic Development, Gauteng 2013
(5) SA 24 (SCA)
General Council of the Bar v Matthys 2002 (5) SA 1 (ECD)
Giant Concerts CC v Minister of Local Government, Housing and Traditional Affairs,
KwaZulu-Natal and Others 2011 (4) SA 164 (KZP)
Giant Concerts CC v Rinaldo Investments and Others 2013 (3) BCLR CC
Gory v Kolver NO and Others 2007 (4) SA 97 (CC)
Governing Body of Mikro Primary School v Western Cape Minister of Education 2005 2
All SA 37 (C)
Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others 2001
(1) SA 46 (CC)
Graaff-Reinet Municipality v Van Ryneveld‘s Pass Irrigation Board 1950 (2) SA 420 (A)
Gundwana v Steko Development CC and Others 2011 (3) SA 608 (CC)
Hailulu v Anti-Corruption Commission and Others 2011 (1) NR 363 (HC)
Harris v Minister of the Interior 1952 (4) SA 769 (A)
Head of Department of Education: Free State Province v Welkom High School 2014 (12)
SA (CC)
Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education v Hoërskool Ermelo 2010
(2) SA 415 (CC)
444
Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission 2015 (2) SA 498 (WCC)
Helen Suzman Foundation v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others;
Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others 2015 (1) BCLR 1
(CC)
Highveldridge Residents Concerned Party v Highveldridge Transitional Local Council and
Others 2002 (6) SA 66 T
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC)
Hugh Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa 2011 (3) SA 347 (CC)
In re: Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 744
CC
Independent Electoral Commission v Langeberg Municipality 2001 (3) SA 925 (CC)
Institute for Democracy in South Africa v African National Congress 2005 (5) SA 39 (CC)
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC)
Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority and Others 2002 (4) SA
294 (CC)
Jacobs en ‗n Ander v Waks en Andere 1992 (1) SA 521 (A)
Jaga v Dönges, N.O. and Another 1950 (4) SA 653 (A)
Jayiya v MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape 2004 2 SA 611 (SCA)
Johannesburg Consolidated Investment Co Ltd v Johannesburg Town Council 1903 TS
111
445
Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality v Gauteng Development Tribunal and Others
2010 (6) SA 182 (CC)
JT Publishing v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 514 CC
Judicial Service Commission and Another v Cape Bar Council and Another 2012 (11)
BCLR 1239 (SCA)
Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of the Republic of South Africa 2011 (5) SA
388 (CC)
K v Minister of Safety and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC)
Kate v MEC for Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape 2005 1 SA 141 (SE)
Kekana v Society of Advocates of South Africa 1998 (4) SA 649 (SCA)
Khosa and Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Others v
Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 6 SA 505 (CC)
Khumalo and Others v Holomisa 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC)
Khunou and Others v M Fihrerand & Son (Pty) Ltd and Others 1982 (3) SA 353 (W)
Krygkor Pensioenfonds v Smith 1993 (3) SA 459 (A)
Kyle v Legal Practitioners‘ Complaints Committee (1999) 21 WAR 56
Laerskool Middelburg v Departementshoof Mpumalanga Departement van Onderwys
2003 4 SA 160 (T)
Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope v Budricks 2003 (2) SA 11 (SCA) 2003 (2) SA
Lawyers for Human Rights v Minister of Home Affairs 2004 (4) SA 125 CC
Le Roux and Others v Dey 2011 (3) SA 274 (CC)
446
Li Kui Yu v Superintendent of Labourers 1906 TS 181
Lombard v Minister van Verdediging 2002 3 SA 242 (T)
Logbro Properties CC v Bedderson NO 2003 (2) SA 460 (SCA)
Lord v Allison (1986) 3 BCLR (2d) 300 (SC)
M & G Media Ltd v President of the Republic of South Africa 2013 (3) SA 591 (GNP)
M & G Limited and Another v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
[2010] ZAGPPHC 43 Case No 1242/09 4 June 2010 (unreported)
Machumela v Santam Insurance CO LTD 1977 (1) SA 660 (A)
Magidimisi v Premier of the Eastern Cape 2006 JOL 17274 (CK)
Magistrate Pangarker v Botha and Another 2015 (1) SA 503 (SCA)
Mahambehlala v MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape 2002 1 SA 342 (SE)
Makwickana v Ethekwini Municipality and Others 2015 (3) SA 165 (KZD) C 2015 (3) SA
Matatiele Municipality and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
2006 (5) SA 47 (CC)
Maritzburg College v CR Dlamini NO case no 2089/2004 (NPD) (not reported)
Marlboro Crisis Committee and others v City of Johannesburg 2012 ZAGPJHC 187
Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions 2007 (5) SA 30 (CC)
Mateis v Ngwathe Plaaslike Munisipaliteit 2003 4 SA 361 (SCA)
Matiso v Minister of Defence 2005 6 SA 267 (Tkh)
Mbanga v MEC for Welfare Eastern Cape 2001 8 BCLR 821 (SE)
447
Meadow Glen Home Owners Association and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan
Municipality and Another 2015 1 All SA 299 (SCA)
MEC for Education: KwaZulu Natal v Pillay 2008(1) SA 474 (CC)
MEC for the Department of Welfare v Kate 2006 (4) SA 478 (SCA)
MEC for Social Development Eastern Cape, Head of the Department of Social
Development Eastern Cape and Minister of Justice v Magidimisi case no 2180/04
(SECLD) (not reported)
Merafong Demarcation Forum v President of the Republic of South Africa 2008 (5) SA
171 (CC)
Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development v Nyathi and Others 2010 (4) BCLR
293 (CC)
Minister of Defence v Potsane and Another; Legal Soldier (Pty) Ltd and Others v
Minister of Defence and Others 2002 (1) SA 1 (CC)
Minister of Education v Harris 2001 11 BCLR 1157 (CC)
Minister of Education, Western Cape and Another v Beauvallon Secondary School and
Others 2015 (2) SA 154 (SCA)
Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism and Others v Phambili Fisheries (Pty) Ltd
and Another 2003 (6) SA 407 (SCA)
Minister of Health v Brückner 2007 5 BLLR 418 (LAC)
Minister of Health and Another v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd and Others 2006 (8)
BCLR 872 (CC)
Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 5 SA 721 (CC)
448
Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Reintegration
of Offenders (NICRO) and Others 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC)
Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Somali Association of South Africa Eastern Cape
(SASA EC) and Another (831/2013) [2015] ZASCA 35 (25 March 2015)
Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others v The Southern Africa
Litigation Centre 2016 (1) SACR 161 (GP)
Minister of Safety and Security v De Lima 2005 (5) SA 575 (SCA)
Minister of Safety and Security v Hamilton 2004 (2) SA 216 (SCA)
Minister of Safety and Security v Van Duivenboden 2002 (6) SA 431 (SCA)
Minister of the Interior and Another v Harris and Others 1952 (4) SA 769 (A)
Mistry v Interim National Medical and Dental Council of South Africa and Others 1997
(7) BCLR 933 (D)
Mistry v Interim National Medical and Dental Council of South Africa 1998 7 BCLR 880
(CC)
Mjeni v Minister of Health and Welfare, Eastern Cape 2000 4 SA 446 (TKH)
Modder East Squatters and Another v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd; President of the
Republic of South Africa and Others v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 3 All SA 169
(SCA) 2004
Mohamed and Another v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (Society
for the Abolition of the Death Penalty in South Africa and Another Intervening)
2001 (3) SA 893 (CC)
449
Moise v Greater Germiston Transitional Local Council: Minister of Justice and
Constitutional Development intervening (Women‘s Legal Centre as amicus curiae)
2001 (4) SA 491 (CC)
Molaudzi v S 2015 (2) SACR 341 (CC)
Motswagae v Rustenburg Local Municipality (1413/2009) [2011] ZANWHC 61 (15
September 2011)
Motswagae and Others v Rustenburg Local Municipality and Another 2013 (3) BCLR 271
(CC)
Mpofu v MEC for Welfare and Population Development, Gauteng case no 99/2848 (W)
(not reported)
Mukaddam v Pioneer Foods (Pty) Ltd and Others 2013 (5) SA 89 (CC)
Myburgh Park Langebaan (Pty) Ltd v Langebaan Municipality 2001 (4) SA 1144 (C)
N v Government of Republic of South Africa 2006 6 SA 575 (D)
Nabal v Bok 1883 1 SAR 60
NAPTOSA and Others v Minister of Education Western, Western Cape Government and
Others 2001 (2) SA 112 (C)
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Others v Minister of Home Affairs
and Others 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC)
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Others v Minister of Home Affairs
and Others 1999 (3) BCLR 280 (C)
National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 1 BCLR 39
(CC)
450
National Director of Public Prosecutions v Freedom Under Law 2014 (2) SACR 107
(SCA)
National Director of Public Prosecution v Zuma 2009 2 SA 277 SCA
National Education Health & Allied Workers Union (NEHAWU) v University of Cape Town
and Others 2003 (3) SA 1 (CC)
Ndevu v MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape case no 597/2002 (SECLD) (not reported)
New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd v Tshabalala-Msimang and Another NNO;
Pharmaceutical Society of South Africa and Others v Minister of Health and
Others 2005 (2) SA 530 (C)
New National Party of South Africa v Government of the Republic of South Africa and
Others 1999 (3) SA 191 (CC)
Ngxuza v Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape 2001 2 SA 609
(E)
Nyathi v MEC for Department of Health, Gauteng and Another [2008] ZACC 8
Nyathi v MEC for the Gauteng Department of Health & Another 2008 (5) SA 94 (CC)
Oostelike Gauteng Diensteraad v Transvaal Munisipale Pensioenfonds en Ander 1997
(8) BCLR 1066 T
Paulsen and Another v Slip Knot Investments 777 (Pty) Limited [2015] ZACC 5
Permanent Secretary Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government and
Another v Ngxuza and Others 2001 (4) SA 1184 (SCA)
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA and Another in Re: The Ex Parte
Application of The President of The Republic of South Africa and Others 2000 (2)
SA 674 (CC)
451
Pheko and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality 2012 (2) SA 598 (CC)
Phillips and Another v Director of Public Prosecutions, Witwatersrand Local Division and
Others 2003 (3) SA 345 (CC)
Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC)
Premier, KwaZulu-Natal, and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others 1996 (1) SA 769 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1561 (CC)
Premier of Mpumalanga v Executive Committee of State-aided Schools, Eastern
Transvaal 1999 (2) SA 91 (CC)
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v M & G Media Limited Case CCT
03/11 [2011] ZACC 32
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v M & G Media Ltd 2011 (2) SA 1
(SCA)
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v M & G Media Ltd 2012 (2) SA 50
(CC)
President of the RSA and Others v M & G Media LTD 2015 (1) SA 92 (SCA)
President of the Republic of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 1999 4
SA 147 (CC)
Prinsloo v Van der Linde and Another 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC)
Prokureursorde, Transvaal v Van der Merwe 1985 (2) SA 208 (T)
Prokureursorde van Die Oranje-Vrystaat v Schoeman 1977 (4) SA 588 (O)
Qozeleni v Minister of Law and Order 1994(1) BCLC 75 (E)
Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet Ltd t/a Metrorail 2005 (2) SA 359 (CC)
452
Rangani v Superintendent-General, Department of Health and Welfare, Northern
Province 1999 (4) SA 385 (T)
Rates Action Group v City of Cape Town 2004 12 BCLR 1328 (C)
Rinaldo Investments (Pty) Ltd v Giant Concerts CC and Others [2012] 3 All SA 57 (SCA)
Reuters Group PLC v Viljoen NO and Others 2001 (2) SACR 519 (C)
S v Acheson 1991 (2) SA 805 (Nm HC)
S v Bhulwana; S v Gwadiso 1995 (2) SACR 748 (CC)
S v Boesak 2001 (1) SA 912 (CC)
S v Makwanyane and Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC)
S v Malumo and Others (In Re Ndala) 2014 (3) NR 690 (HC)
S v Mamabolo 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC)
S v Manamela and Another (Director-General of Justice intervening) 2000 (3) SA 1 (CC)
S v Mhlungu and Others 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC)
S v Ntuli 1996 (1) BCLR 141 (CC)
S v Staggie 2012 (2) SACR 311 (SCA)
S v Van Niekerk 1972 3 SA 706 (A)
S v Zuma and Others 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC)
SA Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association v Minister of Justice and
Constitutional Development and Others, and Another Application 2015 (2) SA
430 (WCC)
453
Sanderson v Attorney-General, Eastern Cape 1998 (2) SA 38 (CC)
Schoeman v Thompson 1927 WLD 282
Schoonbee v MEC for Education, Mpumalanga 2002 4 SA 877 (T)
Shaik v The State (1) [2006] SCA 134 (RSA)
Somyani v MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape case no 1144/01 (SECLD) (not reported)
Soobramoney v Minister of Health (Kwazulu-Natal) 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC)
South African Association of Personal Injury Lawyers v Heath 2001 (1) BCLR 77 (CC)
South African Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union v Irvin and Johnson Ltd
2000 (3) SA 705 (CC)
South African Liquor Traders Association v Chairperson, Gauteng Liquor Board 2006 8
BCLR 901 (CC)
South African National Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 (3) BCLR 321 T
South African Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC)
South African Police Service v Solidarity OBO Barnard 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC)
Sparks v Sparks 1998 (4) SA 714 (W)
Steenkamp v Provincial Tender Board of the Easter Cape 2007 (3) BCLR 280 (CC)
Steyn v The State 2001 (1) SA 1146 (CC)
Speaker of the National Assembly v De Lille 1999 4 All SA 241 (A)
Suid-Afrikaanse Onderwysunie v Departementshoof, Departement van Onderwys,
Vrystaat 2001 3 SA 100 (O)
454
The Permanent Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape Provincial Government
and Others v Ngxuza and Others 2001 (4) SA 1184 (SCA)
Thebus and Another v S 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC)
Theewaterskloof Holdings (Pty) Ltd, Glaser Afdeling v Jacobsen en Andere 2002 (3) SA
401 (LCC)
Thiagraj Soobramoney v Minister of Health: Province of KwaZulu-Natal D&CLD 5846/97,
21 August 1997 (unreported)
Total Computer Services (Pty) Ltd v Municipal Mayor, Potchefstroom Local Municipality
and Others 2008 (4) SA 346 (T)
Toto v Special Investigating Unit and Others 2001 (1) SA 673 (E) (2000 (5) BCLR 553)
York Timbers Ltd v Minister of Water Affairs and Forestry and Another 2003 (4) SA 477
(T)
Transvaal Agricultural Union v Minister of Land Affairs 1997 (2) SA 621 (CC)
Transvaal Agricultural Union v The Minisiter of Land Affairs and the Commission of
Restitution of Land Rights 1996 (12) BCLR 1573 (CC)
Trustees, Biowatch Trust v Registrar: Genetic Resources, and Others 2005 (4) SA 111
(T)
Trustees in the Insolvent Estate of Theodore Doms v Bok NO 1887 2 SAR 189
United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(African Christian Democratic Party and Others intervening; Institute for
Democracy in South Africa and Another as Amici Curiae) (2) 2003 (1) SA 495
(CC)
Van Der Merwe and Another v Taylor NO and Others 2008 (1) SA 1 (CC)
455
Van Deventer v National Director of Public Prosecutions NO (64268/2013) [2015]
ZAGPPHC 550 (7 August 2015)
Van Eeden v Minister of Safety and Security 2003 1 SA 389 (SCA)
Van Niekerk v Pretoria City Council 1997 (3) SA 839 (T)
Van Rooyen v The State Case CCT 21/01 2002 (CC)
Van Straaten v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others 2009 (3) SA 457
(CC)
Veeron Rambali v Ethekwini Municipality and Others case no. 11162/09 (KZD)
(unreported)
Vulindlela Furniture Manufacturers (Pty) Ltd v MEC Department for Education and
Culture, Eastern Cape 1998 4 SA 908 (TK)
Vumazonke v MEC for Social Development, Eastern Cape 2005 6 SA 229 (SE)
Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria 1997 (4) SA 189 (T)
Whittaker v Roos and Another 1911 TS 1092 at 1102
Xiayua v Minister of Home Affairs case number 39412/06 (T) (not reported)
York Timbers Ltd v Minister of Water Affairs and Forestry 2003 4 SA 477 (T)
Zimbabwe Exiles Forum v Minister of Home Affairs [2011] ZAGPPHV 29
Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei and Others 1995 (4) SA 615 (CC)
Zondi v Member of the Executive Council for Traditional and Local Government Affairs
and Others 2004 (5) BCLR 547 (N)
456
Zondi v MEC, Traditional and Local Government Affairs and Others 2005 (4) BCLR 347
(CC)
Australia
Deputy Commissioner of Taxation v Clear Blue Developments Pty Ltd (No 2) [2010] FCA
1124
Hughes Aircraft Systems International v Airservices Australia (1997) 76 FCR 151
Melbourne Steamship Co Ltd v Moorehead (1912) 15 CLR 333
Morely & Ors v Australian Securities and Investments Commission [2010] NSWCA 331
P & C Cantarella [1973] 2 NSWLR 366
R v Martens [2009] QCA 351
Canada
Brown v British Columbia (Minister of Health) (1990) 48 CRR 137
Collin v Lussier (1983) 6 CRR 89
Manitoba Provincial Judges Assn. v Manitoba (Minister of Justice) 1997 3 SCR 3
Nelles v Ontario 60 DLR (4th) 609 1989 (SCC)
Patenaude v Roy 123 DLR (4th) 78 (1994) (Que CA)
R v S (R.D.) (1997) 118 CCC (3d) 353
R v Big M Drug Mart Ltd (1985)18 DLR (4th) 321
R v Mills (1986) 29 DLR (4th) 161
457
Reference re: Remuneration of Judges of the Provincial Court of Prince Edward Island;
Reference re: Independence and Impartiality of Judges of the Provincial Court of
Prince Edward Island; R. v. Campbell; R. v. Ekmecic; R. v. Wickman; Manitoba
Provincial Judges Assn. v. Manitoba (Minister of Justice) 1997 3 S.C.R. 3. 123
Saskatchewan Human Rights Commission v Kodellas (1989) 60 DLR (4th) 143
Schachter v Canada (1991) 93 DLR (4th) 1, [1992] 2 SCR 679
Vespoli v The Queen 12 CRR 185 1984 (Fed CA)
Vorvis v ICBC 58 DLR (4th) 193 1989 (SCC)
Namibia
Rally for Democracy and Progress and Others v Electoral Commission of Namibia and
Others 2013 (2) NR 390 (HC)
Vaatz: In re Schweiger v Gamikaub (Pty) Ltd 2006 (1) NR 161 (HC)
United Kingdom
Bremer Vulcan Schiffbau und Maschinenfabrik v South India Shipping Corp [1981] 1 All
ER 289
Kuljer v EU Council (no 2) [2002] 1 WLR 1941
Minister of Home Affairs v Fisher (1980) AC 319(PC)
R v Home Secretary, Ex Fire Brigades Union 1995 2 513
Taylor and Another v Lawrence and Another [2002] 2 All ER 353
Taylor and Another v Lawrence and Another [2002] 2 All ER 353
United States of America
458
Arizonians for Official English v Arizona 520 US 43 1997
Bivens v Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Bureau of Narcotics 403 US 388, 3901, 409 (1971)
Brown v Leyds (1897) 4 Off Rep 17
Carey v Piphus 435 US 247 (1978)
Carlson v Green 446 US 14, 28, 28 n 1 (1980)
Citizens United v Federal Election Commission 130 S. Ct. 876 (2010)
Davis v Passman 442 US 228 (1979)
Marbury v. Madison 5 U.S. 137 1803
Milliken v Bradley 433 US 267 (1977)
Monroe v Pape 365 US 167 1961
Newport v Facts Concerts Inc 453 US 247, 271 (1981)
Republican Party of Minnesota v White 536 U.S. 765 (2002)
United States v Lee 106 US 196 223 (1882)
United States v Morgan 313 U.S. 409 (1941)
Uricich v Kolesar 54 Ohio App 309 7 N.E. 2d 413
Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co v Sawyer 343 US 579 610 (1951)
Legislation
South Africa
Admission of Advocates Act 74 of 1964
459
Aliens Control Act 96 of 1991
Attorneys Act 53 of 1979
Businesses Act 71 of 1991
Constitutional Court Complementary Act 13 of 1995
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993
Constitution Twelfth Amendment Act of 2005
Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012
Cross-boundary Municipalities Laws Repeal and Related Matters Act 23 of 2005
Customs and Excise Act 91 of 1964
Defence Act 44 of 1957
Disaster Management Act 57 of 2002
Electoral Act 73 of 1998
Electoral Laws Amendment Act 34 of 2003
Genetically Modified Organisms Act 15 of 1997
Implementation of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court Act 27 of 2002
Independent Broadcasting Authority Act 153 of 1993
Informal Trading By-law (KwaZulu-Natal), 2014
Intergovernmental Relations Framework Act 13 of 2005
460
Intestate Succession Act 81 of 1987
Judicial Matters Second Amendment Act 122 of 1998
Judicial Service Commission Act 9 of 1994
Judicial Service Commission Amendment Act 20 of 2008
Labour Relations Act 66 of 1995
Legal Practice Act 28 of 2014
Local Authorities Ordinance Act 25 of 1974
Local Government Transition Act 209 of 1993
Magistrates‘ Courts Act 32 of 1944
Magistrates Act 90 of 1993
Medicines and Related Substances Act 101 of 1965
Medicines and Related Substances Control Amendment Act 90 of 1997
National Prosecuting Authority Act 32 of 1998
Pound Ordinance (Kwazulu-Natal) 32 of 1947
Promotion of Access to Information Act 2 of 2000
Promotion of Administrative Justice Act 3 of 2000
Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of 2000
Publications Act 42 of 1974
Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 32 of 1961
461
Separate Representation of Voters Act 46 of 1951
South Africa Act, 1909
South African Medicines and Medical Devices Regulatory Authority Act 132 of 1998
South African National Roads Agency Limited and National Roads Act 7 of 1998
Social Assistance Act 59 of 1992
State Liability Act 20 of 1957
Superior Courts Act 10 of 2013
Supreme Court Act 59 of 1959
Thekwini Municipality: Informal Trading By-law 2014
Vexatious Proceedings Act 3 of 1956
Austria
Republican Constitution, 1920
Australia
The Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act 1900
Canada
Constitution Act, 1867
Constitution Act, 1982
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part 1 of the Constitution Act 1982
Minnesota‘s Code of Judicial Conduct Canon 5(A)(3)(d)(i)
Quebec Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms, 1975
462
Supreme Court Act R.S.C. 1985
France
Constitution of France, 1958
India
Constitution of India, 1950
Kenya
Constitution of Kenya, 1969
Constitution of Kenya, 2010
Namibia
Constitution of Namibia, 1990
Republic of Ireland
Constitution of Ireland, 1937
Seychelles
Constitution of the Seychelles, 1983
Solomon Islands
Constitution of the Solomon Islands, 1978
Sweden
Swedish Code of Judicial Procedure, 1942 (SFS 1942:740)
United Kingdom
Constitutional Reform Act, 2005
463
Human Rights Act, 1998
United States of America
Civil Rights Act (USA) 17 Stat. 13 1871
Federal Tort Claims Act (United Stes of America) 28 U.S.C. 2680(h)
Zimbabwe
General Laws Amendment Act 2 of 2002
Zimbabwean Electoral Act, 1992
Zimbabwean Electoral Act (Modification) Notice, 2002
Zimbabwean Electoral (Amendment) Regulations, 2002
International instruments
Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct (2001) as revised at The Hague (2002)
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, Adopted by the Seventh United
Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders
held at Milan from 26 August to 6 September 1985 and endorsed by General
Assembly resolutions 40/32 of 29 November 1985 and 40/146 of 13 December
1985
European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms
November 4 1950 213 U.N.T.S 221
Government publications
Code of Judicial Conduct, adopted in terms of section 12 of the Judicial Service
Commission Act 9 of 1994, published in Government Gazette No. 35802 of 18
October 2012
464
Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act of 2012; Government Gazette No. 36128
2013
eThekwini Municipality: Informal Trading By-law 2014; Provincial Gazette for KwaZuluNatal No. 1173, Municipal Notice No. 70 of 27 June 2014
Judicial Complaints Procedure Regulations; GN R1240 in Government Gazette No.
19309 of 1 October 1998
Regulations for Judicial Officers in the Lower Courts, 1993, GN R361 in Government
Gazette No. 15524 of 11 March 1994
Regulations Regarding Grants, Social Relief of Distress and Financial Awards in Terms of
the Social Assistance Act, 1992, promulgated under Government Notice R.373 in
Government Gazette No. 17016 of 1 March 1996
Rules for the Attorneys‘ Profession , Government Gazette No. 39740 of 26 February
2016
Constitutional Court Rules; GN R1675 in Government Gazette No. 25726 of 31 October
2003
Internet sources
ABA Commission on Separation of Powers and Judicial Independence 1996
http://www.abanet.org/govaffairs/judiciary/report.html
African Human Security Review African Commitments to civil society engagement: A
review of eight Nepad countries
http://www.africanreview.org/docs/papers/civsoc.pdf
American Bar Association Judicial selection: The Process of Choosing Judges
http://www.americanbar.org/content/dam/aba/migrated/JusticeCenter/Justice/P
ublicDocuments/judicial_selection_roadmap.authcheckdam.pdf
465
American Judicature Society Judicial Selection in the States: Appellate and General
Jurisdiction Courts 2013
https://web.archive.org/web/20141208194400/http://www.judicialselection.us/u
ploads/documents/Judicial_Selection_Charts_1196376173077.pdf
American Judicature Society Merit Selection: The Best Way to Choose the Best Judges
2014
http://web.archive.org/web/20141002185322/http://www.judicialselection.com/u
ploads/documents/ms_descrip_1185462202120.pdf
Black's Law Dictionary Online Legal Dictionary http://thelawdictionary.org/reasonable/
Burgh House Principles, Study Group of the International Law Association on the
Practice and Procedure of International Courts and Tribunals, in association with
the Project on International Courts and Tribunals: Burgh House Principles
http://www.ucl.ac.uk/laws/cict/docs/burgh_final_21204.pdf
Canadian Bar Association Federal judicial appointment process 2005 Page d‘accueil:
http://cba.org/abc
Canadian Judicial Council: Commentaries on Judicial Conduct (1991)
https://www.cjcccm.gc.ca/cmslib/general/news_pub_judicialconduct_Principles_e
n.pdf
Chaskalson 2012 www.timeslive.co.za
Cheung Wai-lam The Process of Appointment of Judges in Some Foreign Countries: The
United States Research and Library Services Division Legislative Council
Secretariat www.legco.gov.hk/yr00.../erp01.pdf
Chief Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng addressing the Association of Regional Magistrates of
Southern Africa‘s Litigator: https://litigator.co.za/hands-off-judiciary-warns-chiefjustice
466
Christopher F Plymouth Colony Legal Structure Histarch.uiuc.edu.
Clark County Board of Freeholders Partisan or Nonpartisan Elections 2013-2014
http://www.clark.wa.gov/freeholders/documents/BOF_Partisan_TopicBrief.pdf
De Vos P What do we talk about when we talk about ―transformation‖? Constitutionally
Speaking (27 July 2009)
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/category/transformation/page/6/
De Vos P On the appointment of a Chief Justice Constitutionally Speaking (29 July
2011) http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/
De Vos P Justice Mogoeng: An unwise decision Constitutionally Speaking (16 August
2011) http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/
Department of International Relations and Cooperation: Statement of the South African
Government on the Elections in Zimbabwe
http://www.dirco.gov.za/docs/2002/zimb0313a.htm dated 13 March 2002
Dugard J Closing the doors of justice? The South African Constitutional Court‘s
approach to direct access Open Democracy 25 May 2015
https://www.opendemocracy.net/openglobalrights/jackie-dugard/closing-doorsof-justice-south-african-constitutional-court%E2%80%99s-approac
Gordon A and Bruce D Transformation and the independence of the judiciary in South
Africa Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation: Project on Justice and
Transition 2007 www.csvr.org.za.
Guidelines on the State of Victoria‘s obligation to act as a model litigant
http://www.opp.vic.gov.au/wps/wcm/connect/18c9ac00404a14a4abfafbf5f2791d
4a/15_Application_of_model_litigant_guidelines.pdf?MOD=AJPERES
467
Haferkamp HP Enzyklopädie zur Rechtsphilosophie IVR (Deutsche Sektion) und
Deutsche Gesellschaft für Philosophie http://www.enzyklopaedierechtsphilosophie.net/inhalts
Harlan JM Flast v Cohen: dissent http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Flast_v._Cohen
JSC Criteria for Judicial Appointment 2010 http://www.justice.gov.za/saiawj/saiawj-jsccriteria.pdf.
Legal Information Institute Legal Dictionary: The doctrine of vagueness
https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/vagueness_doctrine
MacKay R Appointments to the Supreme Court of Canada Parliament of Canada Library
of Parliament Research Publications
http://www.parl.gc.ca/Content/LOP/ResearchPublications/2011-65-e.htm
Miller Center Commission No. 7 Report of the Commission on the Selection of Federal
Judges 1996 http://www.millercenter.virginia.edu
Model Litigant Rules Rule of Law Institute of Australia
http://www.ruleoflaw.org.au/priorities/model-litigant-rules/
Olson W A de facto fourth branch of Government July 4 1999 at Olson W A de facto
fourth branch of Government July 4 1999, at July 1999 archives
www.overlawyered.com
Reinsch R The equality of self-government v egalitarianism 2013
http://www.libertylawsite.org/2013/02/19/the-equality-of-self-government-vegalitarianism/
Rickard C The South African Judicial Services Commission Paper from the Conference
on Judicial Reform: Function, Appointment and Structure Centre for Public Law
University of Cambridge 2003 University of Cambridge Error! Hyperlink
reference not valid.
468
Sachs response to interview questions at the JSC
http://www.constitutionalcourt.org.za/site/judges/transcripts/albertlouissachs.ht
ml
Savela A (ed) Quality Project of the Courts in the Jurisdiction of the Court of Appeal of
Rovaniemi, Finland Evaluation of the quality of adjudication in courts of law:
Principles and proposed Quality Benchmarks (2006)
http://www.courtexcellence.com/~/media/Microsites/Files/ICCE/QualityBenchma
rksFinlandDetailed.ashx
Segall EJ The Court: A talk with Judge Richard Posner The New York Review of Books
http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2011/sep/29/court-talk-judge-richardposner/ 2011 accessed November 2015
Seventh Miller Center Commission Report of the Commission on the Selection of Federal
Judges 1994 http://www.millercenter.virginia.edu
The Federalist Society for Law and Public Policy Studies The Case for Judicial
Appointments: Appointment (Executive or Legislative) https://www.fedsoc.org/publications/detail/the-case-for-judicial-appointments
The Local Government Handbook
http://www.localgovernment.co.za/locals/view/63/merafong-city-localmunicipality
The Millennium Development Goals of South Africa 2015
http://www.parliament.gov.za/content/MDG%20Report2011_Web.pdf
The Judicial Branch https://www.whitehouse.gov/1600/judicial-branch
Umrabulo Special Edition African National Congress NGC discussion 2015
http://www.anc.org.za/docs/umrabulo/2015/ngc_disc_docsy.pdf
469
Uniform Rules of Professional Conduct of the General Council of the Bar of South Africa
available at http://www.sabar.co.za/rules-of-ethics.html
Weinrib LE Appointing judges: Philosophy, politics and practice Ontario Law Reform
Commission http://www.lawlib.utoronto.ca/conferences/judiciary/readings/judges.pdf
470