Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk
Mads P. Sørensen
This is a post-print version of the paper. Please see the final version here: Journal of Risk Research,
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
Abstract
While risk research normally understands risk as an entity that can be calculated using statistics and
probabilities – and which therefore also can become the object of insurance technology – it is the production
of new, non-calculable risks and therefore also risks that cannot be insured against, which is at the centre of
Ulrich Beck s risk societ theor . The article e a i es Beck s co ceptualizatio of risk a d discusses how he
has clarified and further refined the concept since publishing Risk Society in 1986. The article shows, first, how
Beck understands risk as an entity that is neither danger nor risk in the traditional sense but rather something
in between, which he refers to as a - ade disasters a d ew risks . The discussio the addresses Beck s
position in relation to the ontological status of risk, which is an intermediate position between realism and
constructivism. The non-calculability and non-insurability of the new risks are also examined. The article
discusses what it means that the new risks are not visible and the significance of non-knowledge for how we
understand them. Finally, the new conditions of existence for politics, states and individuals are outlined in
the after ath of Beck s risk societ theor . The article co cludes with a discussion of the analytical potential
of the theory.
Introduction
Risk Society was not really supposed to be called risk society. The title of Ulrich Beck s famous book from
1986 (Beck, 1992) could have been very different. With isk , Be k is getti g at so ethi g other than that
which risk studies conventionally associate with the term. In an interview from 2001, he explains that it was
first after the publication of the book that he became aware of how the concept of risk in academic literature
basically means that which I specifically would not express with the word; that is, the in principle calculability
of civilization-created uncertainty. Risk means calculable uncertainty. While with risk society I was
specifically getting at non-calculable uncertainty (Sørensen, 2002: 125, own translation). In the same
interview, Beck further explains that although Risk Society therefore possibly should have been titled
differently, the concept had still managed to convey that which is most important; that is, the message that
something is incalculable (ibid.).
In that sense, it was important for Beck that the book and the concept managed to convey the feeling that
we had entered into a new type of society – and even into a second phase of modernity. Beck wrote his book
in the mid-1980s, not least in the light of Daniel Bell s book on the emergence of the post-industrial society
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
(Bell, 1973) and Jean-François Lyotard s book The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (Lyotard,
1984), a time in which there seemed to be a need for a new and more precise conceptualization or label for
Western society and the historical period (Sørensen and Christiansen, 2013: ch. 3). Be k s offering became,
as we all know, Risk Society, which he posited as a replacement for industrial society. At the same time, he
pointed out how we had moved towards a new kind of modernity, a second modernity, where modernity is
confronted with itself and forced to deal with itself. Beck therefore also referred to this second modernity as
a reflexive modernity (Beck, 1994a; Beck et al., 2003). B usi g this te
reflector tha
, he as getti g
o e at reflex or
efle tio , whereas the core in Giddens conceptualization of reflexive
ode izatio
(Giddens, 1994) is an ever increasing reflection in society over the course of modernity via the continuous
production and inclusion of new knowledge. According to Beck, modernity is now cast back towards itself,
like light that has struck a reflector is cast back towards its source. As he puts it, the reflexivity of modernity
can lead to reflection on the self-dissolution and self-endangerment of industrial society, but it need not do
so (Beck, 1994b: 177).
Beck s theory must therefore also be understood as a g a d theo
o a diag osis of the ti es , as
Outhwaite (2009) points out. This is to be understood here as neither negative nor condescending, as this
concept is otherwise sometimes used. On the contrary, i Be k s ase it is o e likel a adge of honour. Far
f o e e o e is of ou se e ited a out Be k s so iolog . Ma
iti s feel he is too shallo a d ge e alizi g
in his diagnostics.1 Nevertheless, it seems fair to say that he has managed more than most to articulate the
general sense of a shift towards a more uncertain and insecure society that would appear to be spreading in
recent years despite the fact that we are generally living longer and better than ever before.
For Beck, the symbol of this new uncertainty is the accident at the Chernobyl nuclear power plant, which
occurred at the same time he was completing Risk Society in April 1986. Before the book was published, he
managed to briefly reflect on the significance of Chernobyl in the preface to the German edition (Beck, 1986:
7–11). Here, he
ites of ho
the ook s des iptio of the i possi ilit of o se i g the da ge s, thei
dependence on knowledge, super-nationality, ecological expropriation and the transformation of normality
to the absurd seen in relation to the Chernobyl accident is really just a pale description of reality (Beck, 1986:
10–11). Nevertheless, Risk Society became an international bestseller, and even though it is possible to find
The purpose of this paper is to gi e a i t odu tio to Be k s isk o ept, to sho ho it was first defined and later
redefined several times. Elsewhere I have examined the criticism that has been raised against Beck s theo (Sørensen
and Christiansen, 2013: 123-140) and will refer the reader, who wants a more critical examination of the theory, to
these pages he e
o
iti is of Be k s theo like ise a e fou d.
1
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
traces of 1980s West Germany in the book, its timeliness and its contemporary diagnostic power would not
appear to have diminished since its initial publication. Quite to the contrary.
So it all began with an error. Or at least with something of which Beck was unaware, that being that the
concept of risk at the core of Risk Society is normally used to express the exact opposite of how he is using it.
This proved to be a rather productive mistake. For this error called for further clarification and definitions,
thereby opening up for a life-long exploration of what lay in the concept. In the following, I will attempt to
account for some of the key clarifications so as to identify and explain a deeper u de sta di g of Be k s isk
concept. Finally, I will discuss the new conditions for decision-making that we now find ourselves in politically
a d p i atel
ith the e e ge e of the e
isks a d the u e t pote tial of Be k s risk society theory.
Both hazard and risk
While Beck basically uses the o epts da ge a d isk s o
ousl i Risk Society, he draws a distinction
between the two in his next book, Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk (Beck, 1995), which was published in
German with the title Gegengifte in 1988, corresponding to that which Niklas Luhmann also uses (Luhmann,
1990). With Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk, Beck now understood risks in line with the tradition in risk
esea h, as determinable, calculable uncertainties , a d drew a distinction et ee pre-industrial hazards,
not based on technological-economic decisions, and thus externalizable (onto nature, the gods), and
industrial risks, products of social choice, which must be weighed against opportunities and acknowledged,
dealt with or simply foisted on individuals (Beck, 1995: 77).
Using this distinction, Beck is also able to distinguish between pre-industrial high cultures, which are marked
by non-man-made hazards (e.g., natural disasters, epidemics), and classical industrial society, where such
dangers are supplemented with new, self-produced risks. As opposed to the pre-industrial hazards, the new
risks have a limited range; only a limited group of people in a limited area and time period are exposed to
them (Beck, 1995: 78). This renders them calculable and makes it possible to take out insurance against them.
Beck uses unemployment, workplace accidents and traffic accidents as examples of such man-made risks.
But what about the risks that are at the centre of the risk society? How are we to understand the holes in the
ozone layer, global warming, the threat of terrorism, genetic engineering, radioactive emissions from nuclear
power plants and the global financial crisis? Are they hazards or risks? In fact, they are neither hazards nor
risks – or, using a term that Beck generally believes to characterize the new modernity (Beck and Lau, 2005:
527), it is
oth/a d ; they have both characteristics of hazards and risks. We are exposed to them in the
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
same manner as the pre-industrial hazards. Unlike the pre-industrial hazards, however, they have no external
causes. Like the risks we knew from industrial society, they are man-made or self-produced. But they are also
like the pre-industrial hazards in that they are something to which we are exposed and cannot avoid or insure
ourselves against. In this book, Beck therefore calls them
alls the
e
a - ade disaste s (Beck, 1995: 78), while he
isks i a othe te t (Beck, 1991b).
Between realism and constructivism
The question then becomes how we are to better understand these man- ade disaste s or e risks ? Are
they real? Or is there rather talk of constructions of the fears of our time (cf. Douglas and Wildavsky, 1982)?
Once again, Beck would answer both-and. To begin with, he understands the new risks to be side effects of
our industrial way of life (Beck, 2009: 212–234; Beck et al., 2001). For Beck, it is precisely the success of
industrial modernity in the fight against poverty and material misery that has led us to the risk society. Here,
we are confronted with the side effects of the first modernity. Using global warming as an example, one of
the side effects of the burning of fossil fuels is increased C02 emissions, which in turn is the primary cause of
global warming. The risk society is therefore not to be understood as a ultu e of fea
Fu edi,
, where
hysteria and irrational fear becomes widespread. According to Beck, the new risks have a real core, to which
Nassehi also refers when writing that Beck assumes that the isks ha e a o je ti e ealit (Nassehi, 2000:
255, own translation).
Nevertheless, the epistemological and o tologi al status of the e
the e eptio of Be k s theo
isks has ee a o te tious poi t i
(Rasborg, 2001: 28).2 It is also possible to find traces of both realistic and
constructivist understandings of risk i Be k s autho ship. In Risk Society, Beck writes that [i]t is not clear
whether it is the risks that have intensified, or our view of them. Both sides converge, condition each other,
strengthen each other (Beck, 1992: 55). For Beck, risks are always risks within a knowledge relation. It is
therefore not possible to separate the risk itself and public perception of it from one another.
In World at Risk, Beck (with reference to Strydom, 2002) describes his own position as weak constructivism
or o st u ti ist ealis
(Beck, 2009: 88). Here, he writes the following:
The point is no longer merely how realities are created in world risk society (for example, through
corresponding reports concerning threats in the mass media); there is also the question of how reality
“ee M the
, h. ;
a d “ø e se a d Ch istia se
society theory and not least his concept of risk.
2
: h.
fo a e ie of the iti is
of Be k s isk
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
i itself is
e p odu ed th ough dis ou se politi s a d oalitio s
ithi i stitutio al o te ts of
decision, action and work. (Beck, 2009: 89–90)
Despite the objective core in the new risks, they first become risks in our societal perception of them. But
that s ot all. Our understanding of risks also rubs off on reality – in other words, our understanding of reality
plays a role in reproducing or changing it. For example, our understanding of the holes in the ozone layer as
man-made – that they are a side effect of the use of CFC gases since the 1930s – has helped to re-close them,
as this understanding led to a comprehensive phasing out of CFCs, which would now appear to have had a
significant impact (Solomon et al., 2016).
Beck is thus attempting to balance between constructivism and realism. He points out how the new risks in
the global risk society will always be found between social staging and eal physical th eats Be k,
:
ch. 2). He therefore also objects to a stronger constructivism as found in, for example, Douglas and Wildavsky
(1982). Beck (again with reference to “t do ,
o st u ti is
, a d he
efe s to thei
o st u ti is
as st o g o
aï e
ites that the ha e o e looked the fa t that people in the Stone Age did not have
the capacity for nuclear and ecological self-destruction and that the threats posed by lurking demons did not
exhibit the same political dynamic as the man-made risks of climate change (Beck, 2009: 84).
Beyond insurance: the challenge of non-calculable threats
Subsequent to the publication of Risk Society i
, Be k s further work exploring and defining the new
risks leans up against French social scientist François Ewald, a student of Foucault. Ewald understands the
modern state as a provident state in which the insurance principle plays a main role (Ewald, 1991, 1993).
According to Ewald, the modern society is alone in using the insurance principle as the basis for society. He
says that society enters into modernity, as soon as insurance becomes a matter of society, as soon as the
social contract comes to resemble an insurance contract. Insurance is at the core of modern society (Ewald,
1991: 288, own translation).
Beck uses the insurance principle to clarify that which distinguishes the new risks from the old ones. In
Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk, Beck thus reflects on his own theory in light of Ewald s work (Beck, 1995:
106–110). Among other things, he writes of how risk calculations and private and state insurance policies
become the manner by which industrial modernity deals with its self-produced risks but that insurance
arrangements prove themselves to be inadequate when confronted by nuclear, ecological, genetic and
chemical man- ade disaste s (Beck, 1995: 107). The new risks break with the old ones in at least three
ways, which renders them far more difficult for insurance technology to handle: firstly, they involve global,
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
f e ue tl i epa a le da age ; secondly, it is not possible to predict them or calculate their consequences;
and thirdly, it is often impossible to delimit them in terms of time and space. These new risks therefore
break with the insurance principle, which is specifically based on transparency and calculability (Bonß,
1995). When it is no longer possible to accurately identify risk groups or on the background of collected data
from past accidents and incidents to calculate the probability that an event will occur – and be unable to
say anything about the extent of the damage should it occur – then it is also impossible to take out insurance
against such man-made disasters.
The inability to insure oneself against the new risks becomes crucial for how Beck understands them. In an
essay published together with the German translation of Ewald s major work, Der Vorsorgestaat [L état
providence – The Welfare State] (Ewald, 1993), Beck explicitly writes that we are moving from the industrial
society and into the risk society when private insurance arrangements are no longer adequate; when we
encounter difficulty taking out insurance in relation to industrial technical-scientific projects (Beck, 1993:
541).3 Beck repeats this point in World at Risk: The entry into risk society occurs at the moment at which
the a ufa tu ed isks u de
i eo a
ul the p o ide t state s p e aili g isk al ulatio s. Those ho ask
for an operational criterion for this transition find their answer here: the absence of private insurance
protection (Beck, 2009: 110).
Insurance arrangements – private and state arrangements alike – have a dual function, according to Beck:
they are supposed to neutralize damage, thereby also neutralizing fear. And when they are no longer able
to do so, the
[f]ree-floating fears are being set free (Beck, 2009: 139). In the following, we will return to
what this means for the political and private decision-making processes. Before doing so, we will examine a
couple of additional aspects characterizing the new risks that distinguish them from the old risks.
Second-hand non-experience
Another important aspect that Beck has already pointed out in Risk Society is that the new risks are only
visible to us through scientific theories, experiments and instruments (e.g., Beck, 1992: 27). Whereas we
immediately sense the danger and risks of riding a bike through London or using a drilling machine at work,
holes in the ozone layer, global warming and other new risks are only visible to us as mediated by science. It
is impossible for us directly via our senses to determine whether or not global warming is in fact taking place
Beck s i te p etatio of the e i su a e te s has ee
iti ized, ot least
Ca p ell a d Cu ie
, ho
argue, among other things, that Beck has misunderstood the use of probabilities in risk analysis. Ericson and Doyle
(2004) have also criticized Be k s u de sta di g of the i su a e s ste . Beck used this criticism to specify his
understanding of the insurability/non-insurability of risk (cf. Sørensen and Christiansen, 2013: 135–137).
3
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
and is something to be feared. Only through the senses of science (i.e., theories, experiments, instruments)
are we able to see these dangers. Beck the efo e efe s to ou e pe ie e of the e
isks as second-hand
non-experience (Beck, 1992: 71–72).
The potential in this observation becomes apparent in the study of how people in areas where radioactive
leaks have taken place understand the dangers surrounding them. Kuchinskaya (2011) has carried out an
interesting study of how lay people understand the risks of radiation in the contaminated areas in Belarus
after the Chernobyl disaster. In this sense, radiation offers a good example of how our senses are put out of
play by the new risks. We cannot see, smell or feel radiation. We can only see (and hear!) it using scientific
tools such as Geiger counters. Ho e e , the people i Ku hi ska a s stud did ot p i a il see the risk of
radiation through science. Science was often translated into administrative practices of economic
compensation for those living in the affected areas. To lay people, economic compensation therefore became
a sign of radiation. As one of her interviewees said when asked about radiation in the area where he lived:
What radiation? We are not paid for radiation anymore (Kuchinskaya, 2011: 415).
Kuchinskaya s study also revealed how important our senses are to us in order to understand risks. In order
to deal with the radiation hazard and to be able to talk about it, it was constantly translated into sensory
phenomena such as wild mushrooms and berries (that you are not supposed to eat) together with the money
you get from the state for living in a contaminated area. The thyroid gland also became a tangible issue, the
basis for conversations about radiation, as most of the illnesses that affect radiation victims affect the
thyroid.
As I shall etu
to i the dis ussio
elo , Be k s o se atio of ho ou se ses ha e e o e useless and
without function in relation to the new risks (Beck, 1991a: 68) might shed some light on why it is so difficult
to get people to act on threats such as global warming. For while we now depend on science more than at
any time in the past in relation to being able to tell where danger lurks, Beck claims that we are also becoming
more sceptical and critical of science. We no longer accept scientific findings or what we are told by
authorities as authoritative knowledge in the same manner as did past generations. As Lyotard already
observed in his studies of the state of science in the highly developed societies, contemporary science has
lost its monopoly on the truth (Lyotard, 1984). This is partly the result of how institutionalized, scientific
doubt and scepticism are leaked directly to the public via the media to a greater extent today than was earlier
the case. In the aforementioned interview, Beck comments on this situation that
science – precisely because of its differentiation, its reflectiveness and its institutionalized doubt and
questioning of itself – contributes to the uncertainty not being reduced but actually increasing. One
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
might argue that this seemingly minimal difference between a situation in which scientific expertise
reduces uncertainty and a situation in which scientific expertises – in plural – so to speak pour gasoline
on the bonfire of political controversies might be the crucial difference between a world that believes
in progress and the one to which I refer to as a risk society. (Sørensen, 2002: 125, own translation)
Non-knowledge and unknown unknowns
Before examining the consequences of this more closely, it is important to include one final aspect of the
new risks, that being how non-knowledge is an important feature of these risks. Gross has gone so far as to
suggest that Beck should have named the risk society the non-knowledge society (Gross, 2016). Doing so
might possibly over-e phasized o e aspe t of Be k s o ept of isk, ut the e is o dou t that this aspe t
has become a core element in Be k s understanding of the new risks.
Beck has for example written about non-knowledge in World at Risk (Beck, 2009: 115-128) and in The Politics
of non-k o i g Be k a d Wehling, 2012). Beck also touches upon non-knowledge in the aforementioned
interview from 2001. He e, he e plai s ho
e must understand risks on the border between knowledge
and non-knowledge (Sørensen, 2002: 125, own translation). He also emphasizes that in relation to the new
risks we are often groping in the dark in our attempts at understanding them. He therefore calls for a
sociology of non-knowledge, partly because we are increasi gl deali g ith manufactured non-knowledge .
Beck is thus of the opinion that non-knowledge is becoming something with which we must learn to live; that
it is becoming one of the fundamental conditions of life in the risk society.4 In the World at Risk, he writes:
Living in the world risk society means living with ineradicable non-knowing [Nichtwissen] or, to be more
precise, with the simultaneity of threats and non-knowing and the resulting political, social and moral
paradoxes and dilemmas. Because of the global character of the threat, the need and burden of having
to make life-and-death decisions increase with non-knowing. (Beck, 2009: 115)
According to Beck, we must therefore learn to accept that regardless of how much research we carry out, we
will never be able to produce certain knowledge about the new risks. With every new scientific breakthrough
also comes the production of new non-knowledge.
4
Beck is far from alone with his interest in the significance of non-knowledge in contemporary society. Smithson
(1989), Kerwin (1993) and more recently Gross (2010) have made some of the most important contributions to this
discussion.
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
First modernity was marked by an almost unlimited faith in science – that, over time, science will be able to
get into all of the nooks and crannies of a given issue or problem. This is replaced by a more nuanced
perspective on science in the risk society, where on the one hand there is recognition of the need for science
to tell us more than ever before about where the dangers are lurking, but on the other hand also an
understanding that we will not always be able to produce certain knowledge about the new risks. Beck says
that [n]on-knowledge rules in the world risk society Be k,
:
, meaning that we now find ourselves
in the difficult and paradoxical situation that we must find solutions to problems that we are often unable to
articulate.
One of the examples Beck uses repeatedly (e.g., Beck, 2009: 47, 117–118) to illustrate the difficulty of making
the right decisions in the world risk society is the history of CFC gases. From the 1930s onwards, CFCs replaced
liquid ammonia as a coolant in refrigerators. They were also used as propellants in spray bottles and as a
cleaning agent. In the course of the 1970s, awareness increased of how CFCs were damaging the ea th s
ozone layer. And in the course of the 1980s, scientists were able to show how our use of CFCs had resulted
in a dramatic thinning of the ozone layer over the Antarctic – that holes had actually developed in the ozone
layer, resulting in fa less p ote tio f o
the su s ha
ful UV a s tha p e iousl .
For Beck, the history of CFC gases demonstrates how dangerous the new risks are; or rather, how dangerous
a situation we have brought ourselves into as a result of the production of these new risks. Here, the problem
is not least non-knowledge; our insufficient knowledge of the risks. As mentioned above, it was first in the
course of the 1970s that the negative side effects of CFCs were genuinely recognized. In other words, more
than 40 years passed from their introduction as coolants in refrigerators and a propellant in spray bottles
before scientific knowledge was produced about how these gases were actually harming the ozone layer. For
more than 40 years, it was therefore not possible to restrain this new, self-produced risk – for the simple
reason that nobody had any idea that it existed.
According to Beck, examples like this cast light on how the boundary between knowledge and nonknowledge has become blurred and how at any given time at which we have to make decisions on the
application of a new technology, there will be knowledge of which we are unaware – and might not ever
become aware. Beck and Wehling (2012) see indication of this recognition spreading. They distinguish
between a classic, modern understanding of non-knowledge as not-yet-knowing – like a territory that has
yet to be explored and mapped (Bauman) – and a new, more complex understanding of non-knowledge
that is able to encompass both not-yet-knowing (i.e., the knowledge that we are aware we lack) and the so-
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
called u k ow u k ow s (the knowledge we do t know that we lack) (Beck and Wehling 2012).5 Thus,
unknown u k o
s were in play when we began using CFCs in the 1930s. But the importance of these
unknown u k o
s first became apparent 40 years later, when the link between CFCs and the holes in
the ozone layer was discovered. According to Daase and Kessler (2007: 414), it is typical that unknown
unknowns first become visible in connection with disasters – and it is therefore often first too late in relation
to being able to do something about them. In the case of the CFC gases, we discovered the problems in time
to be able to do something about them. But these kinds of stories contribute to a sense of insecurity – for
what else have we possibly overlooked?
New living conditions in the risk society
Thus far, I have outlined the main features of Beck s concept of risk, as the term has been defined and
redefined since the publication of Risk Society in 1986. An extra detail that Beck points out in relation to
risks – and which is relevant in relation to the above discussion of unknown unknowns – is the difference
between catastrophes and risks: Risk does not mean catastrophe. Risk means the anticipation of
catastrophe (Beck, 2006: 332). At the moment a terror attack takes place, it goes from being a risk to being
a catastrophe. The risk society is therefore not primarily about dealing with catastrophes – but rather with
the anticipation of catastrophes. In the risk society we are therefore dealing with something that has not
yet become real – and which we want to prevent from becoming real (Beck, 2006: 332). This might be a new
terror attack, a new global financial crisis, a radioactive leak from a nuclear power plant, (even greater)
global warming, the uncontrollable spread of GMOs or other possible catastrophes.
With the risk society theory, Beck shows how the anticipation of such catastrophes now plays a vital role in
society and he manages to use his risk concept to cast light on the difficult decision-making situation
characterizing both politics and our everyday lives with respect to the production of new risks. Like few
others, Beck is thus sensitive to the uncertain ground upon which we are often standing when we find
ourselves having to make both political and private decisions that involve the new risks. These kinds of
decisions have obviously always involved non-knowledge, but the uncertainty has increased, as the new
risks are more unpredictable than traditional risks and they transcend spatial and temporal boundaries. This
means that it becomes increasingly difficult to deal with them. As the new risks are also potentially more
dangerous than the traditional risks and given how we are unable to immediately perceive them and directly
have opportunity to control whether or not they actually exist but are instead forced to turn to a science
U k o u k o s a e also efe ed to i the lite atu e as u e og ized ig o a e Me to ,
ig o a e “ ithso ,
o es ie e G oss,
: .
5
,
eta-
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
community that disagrees with itself, then we are left standing with a new, massive challenge for the
political decision-making process that also has consequences for the private sphere. For how can we decide
on something about which we have no knowledge? Or about which science produces very different
answers? How are we supposed to deal with the risks that possibly run across national, cultural and social
boundaries and along the length of time over numerous generations? And what do we do when faced with
the dilemma that the new risks, due to their potentially extremely destructive consequences, require that
we become involved and address them while at the same time there will probably always be relevant
aspects of these risks about which we lack knowledge when we have to make decisions about them?
These are merely a few of the difficult questions that have swirled up in the wake of Beck s risk society theory
and which require that citizens, experts, authorities and the media think in new ways; not least in relation to
how to deal with non-knowledge (Nielsen and Sørensen, 2015). One of the strengths of Beck s theory is that
it manages to cast light on the difficulties and opportunities that are part of this new decision-making
situation on a general, overall le el a d do so i
elatio to the i di idual pe so s everyday life. In numerous
books, Beck has thus analysed the new conditions facing politics and contemporary states and which force
them to re-think themselves in order to be able to deal with the global risks and succeed in the new, global
meta-power game resulting from the transition to the risk society (cf. e.g., Beck 2005; 2006a). He has also
warned the social sciences against believing that the world can be divided in more or less isolated, nationstate containers that can be studied in isolation from one another (e.g., Beck and Grande 2010; Beck and
Sznaider 2006). To the contrary, partly because of the emergence of the new risks, we are living in an
increasingly interconnected world, which must also be the basis for the social sciences – anything else would
be a futile s ie e of u ealit
or zo
ie s ie e (Beck 2006a: 21), as that would mean that the social
sciences would be based on something that no longer exists: separate nation-state societies.6
The fa t that Be k s isk so iet theory has had the clout it has is, however, not least related to the
understanding of the actual conditions of existence of humankind that have always been a central element
in his theory. Beck s concept of risk is not merely of interest for actuarial science or risk studies – or a concept
that can say something about the challenges facing politics, the states and social sciences. It is also a concept
that manages to shed light on many of the everyday problems and dilemmas that ordinary people are
experiencing today. On a daily basis, we are all facing questions that are related to the new risks and which
a
6
e u de stood usi g Be k s isk so iet theo . These include question such as whether or not to allow
See Sørensen and Schneider (2017) for an example of how difficult it is to separate developments in single nationstates. This article also shows how Ulrich Beck s so iolog a e used as a f uitful sta ti g poi t fo detailed e pi i al
analyses.
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
your children to be vaccinated; whether or not to boycott genetically modified food; or whether or not you
should take a genetic test that can tell you for which diseases you are genetically disposed. Questions about
your family finances (e.g., if interest rates will remain stable so that you are able to remain in the home you
have bought) o the fa il s e t a atio – whether, in light of the terrorist attacks in recent years, you dare
take your family on vacation to France or Turkey or whether it would be safer to choose Spain – can be related
to the risk society and the new risks. Beck s theory is thus able to conceptualize the new uncertainty that
ordinary people experience in their everyday lives.
Conclusion
Even though Ulrich Beck according to himself
istake l e titled his ook a d theo
Risk Society in 1986
due to his lack of knowledge of the risk research tradition – and spend the rest of his life explaining, clarifying
and exploring what the risk concept stands for – now, more than 30 years after it was first introduced, risk
society theory still stands strong as a diagnosis of the times and a productive perspective for analysis. Two
examples can be used to illustrate this. First, risk society theory can be used to shed light on the complicated
game taking place when international agreements on global economic, security policy and environmental
problems have to be negotiated. Taking the example of global warming, Beck s theory can explain why we
can be expected to find a solution to this problem despite national, social and geographical differences, but
also why it is so difficult to reach agreement on concrete action. Usi g Be k s theo , it is possi le to e plai
both the failure at the United Nations Climate Change Conference, COP15, in Copenhagen in 2009 and the
success in Paris 6 years later at COP 21. In Risk Society, Beck thus emphasizes the positive opportunities
opened up by the new risks. The new risks cut across traditional boundaries. They abolish the distinction
between rich and poor, black and white, Muslim and Christian. In other words, the new risks provide us with
opportunities to create new risk communities. This can help explain the agreement from Paris, where despite
all of the differences between countries rich and poor, big and small – for not to mention less affected and
more affected – it was actually possible to reach a global agreement that acknowledges that climate change
is a common concern of humankind and the need for an effective and progressive response to the urgent
th eat of li ate ha ge (Paris Agreement, 2015: 1).
But what about the failure in Copenhagen, then? Why was an agreement not reached then inasmuch as we
live in a global risk community in relation to global warming? Even though Beck kept repeating that the new
risks would not automatically lead to the establishment of new political communities and the reaching of
transnational agreements – but that on the contrary they could also result in, for example, a reinforced
nationalism – he nevertheless emphasizes the levelling properties of the new risks in relation to the class
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
differences at the individual level and wealth, geography and power relations at the global level. This is a
major theme in Risk Society, where Beck formulated it in the following: poverty is hierarchic, smog is
democratic (Beck, 1992: 36). Beck has in this relation been criticized for not taking the effects of existing
social imbalances seriously enough (e.g. Bovenkerk, 2003 and Mythen, 2005). Class distinctions still matters.
We are not affected in the same way by the new risks.
Beck seems to have admitted to this in his later works (e.g. Beck, 2007; 2009; 2010). Besides the incentives
that are built into the new risks with respect to the promotion of the construction of new political risk
communities, he thus also develops a deeper understanding of how social, national and other differences
continue to play a main role when the rules of the game in such risk communities are negotiated. For
example, in World at Risk (Beck, 2009: 140–143) Beck emphasizes how there are often differences between
those who are making decisions about a given risk and those who are exposed to it; those who must live with
the unexpected side effects of such decisions. Here, he also points out how there is an ominous link between
poverty, social vulnerability, corruption and the accumulation of risks; and that the poorest people in the
world often live in the blind spots, and hence the most precarious lethal zones, of the world risk society
(Beck, 2009: 142). In relation to the climate negotiations, these kinds of disparities between the polluters
and those who now must pay for their pollution also play in. There are also relevant differences in power
politics and geography (e.g., between low-lying and high-lying areas), that provide different incentives to do
something about the problem. The problems we have described above in relation to the invisibility of the
risks and their considerable content of non-knowledge – which has also created problems in the climate area
and opened up for scepticism, which in itself has delayed and at times partially short-circuited the attempts
at curbing global warming in earnest – have further complicated the game that has been about reaching a
climate deal. P eside t T u p s de isio i the sp i g of
to pull out of the Pa is ag ee e t also sho s
how fragile these new, transnational communities build around new risks are. National interests will always
play a key role in decisions to join or leave such communities.
Beck s risk society theory thus appears to present a useful, but also very broad framework for understanding
the game that led to the failure in Copenhagen but also the more successful result in Paris. Another area with
potential for risk society theory that will be briefly mentioned here is the analytical potential of the theory in
relation to the conflicts that emerge between laypeople, scientific experts and authorities in relation to
health programmes, new infrastructure projects, new technologies and so forth. When parents refuse to let
thei
hild e
e a i ated, he
itize s g oups p otest agai st the o st u tio of a e
u lea po e
plant, or when consumers express their scepticism in relation to genetically modified food products, this kind
of opposition will often be seen as irrational from the perspective of the authorities and science. But that
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
hi h appea s athe i atio al f o
o e pe spe ti e a , usi g Be k s theo , e understood as perfectly
rational action from the lay perspective. Risk society theory thus demonstrates how the new risks reinforce
the general individualization process characterizing modernity and force individuals to find their own
strategies with which to deal with them.7 The new risks therefore look very different from the lay perspective
as opposed to the perspective of the authorities and science. Beck already drew attention to this in Risk
Society, where he wrote, among other things, that: What scientists call late t side effe ts and u p o e
o
e tio s are for them [the parents]
oughi g hild e
who turn blue in foggy weather and gasp for air,
with a rattle in their throat (Beck, 1992: 61). The individualization process means that citizens (as parents,
neighbours, consumers etc.) ultimately have to find ways whereby they are able to deal with the
unpredictability of the new risks, their considerable content of non-knowledge and their potentially very
destructive character. Therefore, if we wish to transition from being offended in relation to the apparent
irrationality of citizens and gain a deeper understanding of the array of conflicts between authorities,
s ie tifi e pe ts a d o di a
itize s, Be k s isk so iet theo
ight
ell offer a constructive place to
begin.
References
Beck, U. 1986. Risikogesellschaft. Auf dem Weg in eine andere Moderne. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Beck, U. 1988. Gegengifte. Die organisierte Unverantwortlichkeit. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Beck, U. 1991a. De a th opologis he “ ho k – Tschernobyl und die konturen der Risikogesellschaft. In
Politik in der Risikogesellschaft. Essays und Analysen, edited by U. Beck, 67–81. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Beck, U. 1991b. Ü e le e sf age, “ozialst uktu u d ökologische Aufklärung. In Politik in der
Risikogesellschaft, edited by U. Beck, 117–139. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Beck, U. 1992. Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: SAGE.
Beck, U. 1993. ‘isikogesells haft u d Vo so gestaat – Zwischenbilanz einer Diskussion. In Der
Vorsorgestaat, edited by F. Ewald, 535–558. Frankfurt aM: Suhrkamp.
This a ti le has ot affo ded oo to del e deepe i to Be k s thought o e i g i di idualizatio , hi h has ee
a key phenomenon in his risk society theory from the very beginning. The entire second part of Risk Society (Beck,
1992) thus addresses individualization, while Beck has also later written extensively about the new radicalized
individualization process that is in play in second modernity, including works he has co-authored together with his
wife, Elisabeth Beck-Gernsheim (see e.g., Beck and Beck-Ge shei
. Fo a o p ehe si e i t odu tio to Be k s
thoughts on individualization, see Sørensen and Christiansen (2013: ch. 4).
7
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
Beck, U. 1994a. The Reinvention of Politics: Towards a Theory of Reflexive Modernization. In Reflexive
Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order, edited by U. Beck, A. Giddens,
and S. Lash, 1–56. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. 1994b. Self-Dissolution and Self-Endangerment of Industrial Society: What Does This Mea ? In
Reflexive Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order, edited by U. Beck, A.
Giddens, and S. Lash, 174–183. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. 1995. Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. 2005. Power in the Global Age. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Be k, U.
. Li i g i the World Risk Society. Economy and Society 35 (3): 329–345.
Be k, U.
. Be o d lass a d atio : ef a i g so ial i e ualities i a glo alizi g Wo ld , British Journal
of Sociology, 58(4): 679-705.Beck, U. 2006a. The Cosmopolitan Vision. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. 2009. World at Risk. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. 2010. ‘e appi g so ial i e ualities i a age of li ate ha ge: fo a os opolitan renewal of
so iolog , Global Networks 10(2): 165-181.
Beck, U., and E. Beck-Gernsheim. 2002a. Individualization: Institutionalized Individualism and Its Social and
Political Consequences. London: SAGE.
Beck, U., and E. Grande. 2010. Varieties of Second Modernity: The Cosmopolitan Turn in Social and
Political Theory and ‘esea h. British Journal of Sociology 61 (3): 409–443.
Beck, U., W. Bonß, and C. Lau. 2003. The Theory of Reflexive Modernization: Problematic, Hypotheses and
Research Programme. Theory, Culture & Society 20 (2): 1–33.
Beck, U., B. Holzer, and A. Kieserling. 2001. Nebenfolgen als Problem soziologischer Theoriebildung. In
Die Modernisierung der Moderne, edited by U. Beck and W. Bonß, 63–82. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Beck, U., and N. Sznaider. 2006. Unpacking Cosmopolitanism for the Social Sciences: A ‘esea h Age da.
British Journal of Sociology 57 (1): 1–23.
Beck, U., and P. Wehling. 2012. The Politics of Non-Knowing: An Emerging Area of Social and Political
Conflict in Reflexive Modernity. In The Politics of Knowing, edited by F. D. Rubio and P. Baert, 33–57.
London: Routledge.
Bell, D. 1973. The Coming of Post-Industrial Society. New York: Basic Books.
Bonß, W. 1995. Vom Risiko. Unsicherheit und Ungewißheit in der Moderne. Hamburg: Hamburger Edition.
Bovenkerk, B.
. Is “ og De o ati ? E i o
Politics, 29: 24–38.
e tal Justi e i the ‘isk “o iet . Melbourne Journal of
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
Campbell, S., and G. Currie. 2006. Agai st Be k: In Defence of Risk Analysis. Philosophy of the Social
Sciences 36 (2): 149–172.
Daase, C., and O. Kessler. 2007. Knowns and Unknowns i the Wa o Te o : Uncertainty and the
Political Construction of Danger. Security Dialogue 38 (4): 411–434. doi: 10.1177/0967010607084994
Douglas, M., and A. Wildavsky. 1982. Risk and Culture: An Essay on the Selection of Technological and
Environmental Dangers. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Ericson, R. V., and A. Doyle. 2004. Catastrophe Risk, Insurance and Terrorism. Economy and Society 33 (2):
135–173.
Ewald, F. [1989] 1991. Die Ve si he u gs-Gesellschaft. In Politik in der Risikogesellschaft, edited by U.
Beck, 288–301. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Ewald, F. 1993. Der Vorsorgestaat. Frankfurt aM: Suhrkamp.
Furedi, F. 2002. Culture of Fear: Risk Taking and the Morality of Low Expectation. 2nd edn. London:
Continuum.
Giddens, A. 1994. Living in a Post-Traditional Society. In Reflexive Modernization: Politics, Tradition and
Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order, edited by U. Beck, A. Giddens and S. Lash, 56–109. London: Polity
Press.
Gross, M. 2010. Ignorance and Surprise: Science, Society, and Ecological Design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gross, M. 2016. ‘isk as Zombie Category: Ul i h Be k s Unfinished Project of the Non-k o ledge
Society. Security Dialogue 47 (5): 386–402.
Kerwin, A. 1993. None Too Solid: Medical Ignorance. Science Communication 15 (2): 166–185.
Kuchinskaya, O. 2011. A ti ulati g the Signs of Danger: Lay Experiences of Post-Chernobyl Radiation Risks
and Effects. Public Understanding of Science 20 (3): 405–421.
Luhmann, N. 1990. Risiko Und Gefahr. Soziologische Aufklärung 5: 137–169.
Lyotard, F. [1979] 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Merton, R. K. 1987. Three Fragments from a Sociologist's Notebooks: Establishing the Phenomenon,
Specified Ignorance, and Strategic Research Materials. Annual Review of Sociology 13: 1–28.
Mythen, G. 2004. Ulrich Beck. A Critical Introduction to the Risk Society. London: Pluto Press.
Mythen, G.
Online 10 (3).
. Fo
Goods to Bads ? ‘e isiti g the Politi al E o o
of ‘isk. Sociological Research
Mythen, G. 2007. ‘eapp aisi g the ‘isk “o iet Thesis: Teles opi Sight or Myopic Vision? Current
Sociology 55 (6): 793–813.
Post-print version of Mads P. Sørensen Ulrich Beck: exploring and contesting risk , Journal of Risk Research, 2017.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2017.1359204
Nassehi, A.
. ‘isikogesells haft. In Kneer, G.; Nassehi, A. and Schroer, M. (eds.) Soziologische
Gesellschaftsbegriffe. 2. Edition. Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag. 252–279.
Nielsen, K. H., and M. P. Sørensen. 2015. Ho to Take Non-knowledge Seriously, o the Unexpected Virtue
of Ig o a e . Public Understanding of Science, 1–8. DOI: 10.1177/0963662515600967
Outhwaite, W. 2009. Canon Formation in Late 20th-Century British Sociology. Sociology 3: 1029–1045.
Paris Agreement (2015):
http://unfccc.int/files/meetings/paris_nov_2015/application/pdf/paris_agreement_english_.pdf
Rasborg, K. 2001. From Industrial Modernity to Risk Modernity? A Critical Discussion of the Theory of the
‘isk “o iet . In The Transformation of Modernity: Aspects of the Past, Present and Future of an Era,
edited by M. Carleheden and M. Jacobsen, 19–39. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Smithson, M. 1989. Ignorance and Uncertainty: Emerging Paradigms. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Solomon, S., D. J. Ivy, D. Kinnison, M. J. Mills, R. R. Neely III, and A. Schmidt. 2016. E e ge e of Healing in
the Antarctic Ozone Layer. Science 353 (6296): 269–274. DOI: 10.1126/science.aae0061.
Strydom, P. 2002. Risk, Environment and Modernity. Open University Press: Buckingham.
Sørensen, M. P. 2002. Interview med Ulrich Beck. Slagmark. 34: 125–144.
Sørensen, M. P., and A. Christiansen. 2013. Ulrich Beck: An Introduction to the Theory of Second Modernity
and the Risk Society. Abindon: Routledge.
“ø e se , M. P., a d J. W. “ h eide .
ethodologi al atio alis a d zo
. “tudies of atio al esea h pe fo a e: A ase of
ie s ie e ?. Science and Public Policy. 44 (1): 132-145.