CRITICAL POLITICAL THEORY AND
RADICAL PRACTICE
Mainstream political theory has been experiencing an identity crisis for as long as I can
remember. From even a cursory glance at the major journals, it still seems preoccupied either
with textual exegesis of a conservatively construed canon, fashionable postmodern forms of
deconstruction, or the reduction of ideas to the context in which they were formulated and the
prejudices of the author. Usually written in esoteric style and intended only for disciplinary
experts, political theory has lost both its critical character and its concern for political practice. Behaviorist and positivist political “scientists” tend to view it as a branch of philosophical
metaphysics or as akin to literary criticism. They are not completely wrong. There is currently
no venue that highlights the practical implications of theory or its connections with the larger
world. I was subsequently delighted when Palgrave Macmillan offered me the opportunity of
editing Critical Political Theory and Radical Practice.
When I was a graduate student at the University of California: Berkeley during the 1970s,
critical theory was virtually unknown in the United States. The academic mainstream was
late in catching up and, when it finally did during the late 1980s, it predictably embraced the
more metaphysical and subjectivist trends of critical theory. Traditionalists had little use for
an approach in which critique of a position or analysis of an event was predicated on positive
ideals and practical political aims. In this vein, like liberalism, socialism was a dirty word and
knowledge of its various tendencies and traditions was virtually nonexistent. Today, however,
the situation is somewhat different. Strident right-wing politicians have openly condemned
“critical thinking,” particularly as it pertains to cultural pluralism and American history. Such
parochial validations of tradition have implications for practical politics. And, if only for this
reason, it is necessary to confront them. A new generation of academics is becoming engaged
with immanent critique, interdisciplinary work, actual political problems, and, more broadly,
the link between theory and practice. Critical Political Theory and Radical Practice offers
them a new home for their intellectual labors.
The series introduces new authors, unorthodox themes, and critical interpretations of the
classics and salient works by older and more established thinkers. Each after his or her fashion
will explore the ways in which political theory can enrich our understanding of the arts and
social sciences. Criminal justice, psychology, sociology, theater and a host of other disciplines
comes into play for a critical political theory. The series also opens new avenues by engaging
alternative traditions, animal rights, Islamic politics, mass movements, sovereignty, and the
institutional problems of power. Critical Political Theory and Radical Practice thus fills an
important niche. Innovatively blending tradition and experimentation, this intellectual enterprise with a political intent will, I hope, help reinvigorate what is fast becoming a petrified
field of study and perhaps provide a bit of inspiration for future scholars and activists.
Stephen Eric Bronner
Published by Palgrave Macmillan:
Subterranean Politics and Freud’s Legacy: Critical Theory and Society
by Amy Buzby
Politics and Theatre in Twentieth-Century Europe: Imagination and Resistance
by Margot Morgan
Rosa Luxemburg: Her Life and Legacy
edited by Jason Schulman
This page intentionally left blank
Rosa Luxemburg
Her Life and Legacy
Edited by
Jason Schulman
ROSA LUXEMBURG
Copyright © Jason Schulman, 2013.
Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2013 978-1-137-34981-1
All rights reserved.
Chapters 1–8 originally appeared in New Politics and are reprinted here
courtesy of Marvin and Betty Mandel, co-editors.
First published in 2013 by
PALGRAVE MACMILLAN®
in the United States— a division of St. Martin’s Press LLC,
175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010.
Where this book is distributed in the UK, Europe and the rest of the world,
this is by Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited,
registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills,
Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS.
Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies
and has companies and representatives throughout the world.
Palgrave® and Macmillan® are registered trademarks in the United States,
the United Kingdom, Europe and other countries.
ISBN 978-1-349-46810-2
ISBN 978-1-137-34332-1 (eBook)
DOI 10.1057/9781137343321
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Schulman, Jason, 1973–
Rosa Luxemburg : her life and legacy / edited by Jason Schulman.
pages cm.—(Critical political theory and radical practice)
Includes index.
1. Luxemburg, Rosa, 1871–1919. 2. Women socialists—Germany—
Biography. 3. Women communists—Germany—Biography. 4. Women
revolutionaries—Germany—Biography. 5. Socialism—Germany—
History. I. Title.
HX274.7.L89S38 20103
335.4092—dc23
[B]
2013026016
A catalogue record of the book is available from the British Library.
Design by Newgen Knowledge Works (P) Ltd., Chennai, India.
First edition: December 2013
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Contents
Introduction
Reintroducing Red Rosa
Jason Schulman
Chapter 1 Red Dreams and the New Millennium:
Notes on the Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg
Stephen Eric Bronner
1
11
Chapter 2 A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
Alan Johnson
21
Chapter 3 A Second Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
David Camfield
39
Chapter 4
Rosa Redux: A Reply to David Camfield and
Alan Johnson
Stephen Eric Bronner
49
Chapter 5 Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg
Thought?
Paul Le Blanc
73
Chapter 6
85
Socialist Metaphysics and Luxemburg’s Legacy
Michael J. Thompson
Chapter 7 Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
Barry Finger
Chapter 8 Moving On: New Replies to New Critics
Stephen Eric Bronner
99
119
vi
●
Contents
Chapter 9
Between Gospel and Church: Resisting the
Canonization of Rosa Luxemburg
Amber Frost
141
Chapter 10 Where Do We Go from Here? Rosa Luxemburg
and the Crisis of Democratic Capitalism
Chris Maisano
151
Chapter 11 Contra Bronner on Luxemburg and
Working-Class Revolution
Michael Hirsch
167
Appendix Reflections on Red Rosa: An Interview with
Stephen Eric Bronner
Conducted by Jason Schulman
185
Notes on Contributors
197
Index
201
INTRODUCTION
Reintroducing Red Rosa
Jason Schulman
F
or those with a socialist politics that is uncompromising in
both its commitment to democracy and its opposition to capitalism, it is common to raise the name of Rosa Luxemburg. A
Polish German secular Jew, a Marxist political economist and political theorist, she was the most prominent leader of the left wing of the
German Social Democratic Party (SPD) and a founder of the Social
Democracy of the Kingdom of Poland and Lithuania (SDKPiL)
and, later, the Spartacus League and the German Communist Party
(KPD). Repeatedly jailed for her political activities in both Poland
and Germany, she was ultimately murdered with her comrade Karl
Liebknecht by the right-wing SPD leadership’s militarist Freikorps
(Volunteer Corps) allies in the aftermath of the failed Spartacus
Revolt in Berlin in 1919. Luxemburg thus became both a heroine and
a martyr of the socialist workers’ movement. Though the Communist
International of Josef Stalin, in the 1930s, denounced her as a “counterrevolutionary Menshevik” and sought to eradicate her influence,
anti-Stalinist Marxists of various stripes came to her defense, however critically, and would continue to do so in subsequent decades.1
And even today, more than 94 years after her death, Rosa Luxemburg
refuses to finally die.
2
●
Jason Schulman
The current wide interest in Luxemburg’s life and work is illustrated
by Verso’s ongoing publication of her complete works in English—a
great undertaking—and the flurry of reviews and discussion that
immediately followed the release of the first volume, The Letters of
Rosa Luxemburg.
g 2 This Luxemburg revival has in fact been building up for some time, presaged by the republication of her economic
magnum opus, The Accumulation of Capitall, by Routledge in 2003;
the publication also in 2003 of David Harvey’s The New Imperialism
(Oxford University Press), which draws from Luxemburg’s work for
its theory of “accumulation by dispossession”; the appearance in 2004
of The Rosa Luxemburg Readerr (Monthly Review Press), the first onevolume collection of her economic and political writings in English; a
conference on The Accumulation of Capitall held in 2004 in Bergamo,
Italy; and an international conference on her ideas as a whole that
was also held in 2004 at the South China Agricultural University
in Guangzhou.3 Also, as Estrella Trincado notes, Luxemburg has
become increasingly popular with critics of capitalist globalization,
particularly in Latin America.4
This is not the first time that Luxemburg has been rediscovered.
Parts of the New Left of the 1960s, particularly in Europe, found
in her writings a revolutionary-democratic alternative to both official Social Democracy and official Communism.5 Reading her 1904
article “The Organizational Questions of Russian Social Democracy”
as well as her 1918 essay “The Russian Revolution,” one could find
something akin to a “premature critique” of Stalinism; in Reform or
Revolution (1900) and The Mass Strike, the Party, and the Trade Unions
(1906), Luxemburg provides, respectively, a dissection of the ideological foundations of class-collaborationist Social Democratic “revisionism” and an attempt to make the practice of the SPD live up to
the revolutionary content of its official theory (Marxism) via lessons
learned from the Russian Revolution of 1905. Her strident opposition
to the First World War—and to the support of that war by most of
the leadership of international Social Democracy, particularly that of
the SPD—also made her an emblem for many New Left–era radicals
fighting to end the Vietnam War, and again today for radicals opposing the United States’ occupation of both Afghanistan and Iraq.
The return of Rosa Luxemburg coincides with the latest rekindling
of interest in her primary intellectual and political influence, Karl
Introduction
●
3
Marx. There is, after all, nothing like a global crisis of capitalism
to bring forth Marx from the grave once again. Whisked off to the
dustbin of history after the fall of Stalinist Communism, today even
mainstream commentators are looking to Marx for explanations
l
of the failures of global neoliberal capitalism and copies of Capital,
Vol. 1 are flying off of bookstore shelves in Marx’s native Germany.
The critique of political economy has made a comeback, and those
who practice it have gained notice even in the publications of the
high priests of capitalism; witness the praise—however tempered—
for David Harvey’s The Enigma of Capital and the Crises of Capitalism
in the Financial Timess and Robert Brenner’s The Economics of Global
Turbulencee in the Wall Street Journall. As noted earlier, Luxemburg’s
The Accumulation of Capitall is also being rediscovered, with some
arguing that “her discussions of capital’s ‘Struggle against the Peasant
Economy,’ the role of ‘International Loans,’ and ‘Militarism as a
Province of Accumulation’ . . . read as if she [were] writing about
present-day multinationals, international financial institutions and
military-industrial complexes.”6 Notably, relatively neglected economic works by Luxemburg, such as her Introduction to Political
Economyy and lectures at the SPD’s school in Berlin (1907–14), are
now appearing complete in English for the first time.7
But even if interest in Marx and Luxemburg has returned,
Marxism—that is, a mass movement informed by the work and political perspective of Marx—has not. This is perhaps surprising, given
that socialism has proven that it will not simply go away, particularly
as an epithet used by the American Right. But what are the politics
of socialism? Here—despite his well-documented radical-democratic
standpoint—it is impossible to solely invoke Marx; given the multiple
authoritarian states that once ruled in his name, it becomes necessary
to also invoke specific subsequent Marxists in order to construct a useable and desirable Marxist political tradition as an alternative to what
became codified as “Marxist-Leninist” orthodoxy. In this regard, few
figures stand out as prominently as Rosa Luxemburg.
One of the most prominent scholars of Luxemburg’s thought
is Stephen Eric Bronner, professor of Political Science at Rutgers
University. The author of Rosa Luxemburg: A Revolutionary for Our
Timess (Penn State University Press, 2004), he has defended Luxemburg
as the “most important representative of a libertarian socialist tradition
4
●
Jason Schulman
inspired by internationalism, economic justice, and a radical belief in
democracy.”8 He explains her contemporary relevance:
Luxemburg was a Marxist of the old school. There was nothing
special about her commitment to republicanism and social equality. What made her unique was the special emphasis she placed
upon the role of democratic consciousness, and what I would call a
cosmopolitan pedagogy, whereby one exploited community learns
from another in an ongoing revolutionary process. Democratic
consciousness and cosmopolitan pedagogy have both played a crucial role in the rebellions that are cascading from one nation to
another in the Middle East.
Moreover, Bronner writes,
Luxemburg never equated democracy with the will of the majority
or even social justice; she knew that perhaps, above all, democracy
rested on the protection of the minority. Her famous line from
The Russian Revolution (1918) still rings true: “Freedom is only and
exclusively freedom for the one who thinks differently.”9
But Bronner shows no interest in constructing a new “MarxistLuxemburgist” orthodoxy. In an earlier piece from the democratic
socialist journal New Politicss, he claims that it is now necessary to free
Luxemburg’s thought “from an outmoded teleology and [to draw] the
right political consequences.”10 Such consequences include an understanding that it no longer makes sense to present socialism “as the
otherr, the emancipated society,” particularly as revolution “is no longer
the issue in the western democracies.” It follows that “socialism” must
“initially be understood as a practice intent upon mitigating the whip
of the market throughh the state and abolishing the exercise of arbitrary
power byy the state.”11 Put another way, socialism is best conceived of
today as “the ongoing creation of economic and political conditions in
which working people can expand the range of their knowledge, their
experiences, and their private as well as their public pursuits.”12
This redefinition of socialism and particular reading of Luxemburg’s
legacy engendered much debate within the pages of New Politicss. Many
participants believed that Bronner’s argument conceded too much,
Introduction
●
5
that it “foreclose[d] the historical possibility of human emancipation”
and underestimated the extent to which existing, capitalist states “are
barriers to addressing exploitation, oppression, alienation and ecological destruction.”13 They feared that such a position would lapse
into the old “revisionist” stance of Luxemburg’s opponent in the SPD,
Eduard Bernstein, who believed that the ultimate goal of an emancipated society “is nothing” while “the movement is everything.” Some
argued that Bronner was too forgiving of the flaws of actually existing
liberal democracy and too dismissive of the democratic possibilities of
a polity based on workers’ councils (soviets). Some also claimed that
Bronner set up too much of a distinction between Luxemburg and her
sometime-ally/sometime-rival, the Russian revolutionary V. I. Lenin,
to Lenin’s detriment, that he was too quick to believe in the possibility of furthering internationalism through institutions such as the
United Nations, and too sympathetic to one aspect of Luxemburg’s
thought rarely embraced by socialists: her opposition to national liberation movements.
And yet, all the debaters agreed with Paul Le Blanc’s comment
that “the Marxist analysis of capitalism remains powerful, while
the perspective of revolutionary working-class struggle for socialism
is in a shambles.”14 So—as Lenin once asked—what is to be done?
Furthermore, how can the legacy of Rosa Luxemburg help us to do
it? That, ultimately, is the pivot in the debate, a discussion that highlights why Luxemburg remains important—and that sheds new light
on the political meaning of socialism.
*
*
*
This collection reprints, for the first time, the debate from New Politicss,
a journal that has always been “Luxemburgist” in spirit. An institution of the American Left since its founding in 1961, it is perhaps
best known for having published the seminal article by Hal Draper,
“The Two Souls of Socialism,” in 1966. It was also the first Englishlanguage publication to publish articles by the dissident Polish socialists
Jacek Kuroń and Karol Modzelewski. Like Luxemburg herself, NP
P has
long insisted on the inseparability of democracy and socialism, and
the publication of Rosa Luxemburg: Her Life and Legacyy is consistent
with NP ’s mission of offering—as it says in the journal’s “Why We
6
●
Jason Schulman
Publish” section—“bold and imaginative radicalism.”15 Also included
in this volume are three new pieces that reflect upon the debate—now
over a decade old—and add new insights, as well as a new interview
with Bronner that revisits some of the issues from the initial dispute
and posits new questions.
A wide range of themes appears throughout the original debate.
One pertains to the present status of Marxism. Is the economic and
political enterprise of socialism now, as Bronner states, predicated on
little more than an ethical commitment? Are the teleological aspects
of traditional Marxism obsolete, its “scientific” pretensions now
anachronistic? Can we speak of an “authentic” Marxism today? Can
it again be a theory and practice of human liberation? In regards to
Luxemburg’s Marxism, specifically, if it is true (as Norman Geras once
wrote) that she unified theories of the bourgeois state, the character of
proletarian democracy, and a viable socialist strategy, does that unity
still hold—or is an immanent critique of her perspective now necessary in order to develop one more appropriate to the present?
In relation to the issue of contemporary socialist political strategy,
other questions arise. Are existing liberal republican states simply not
reliable vehicles for efforts to limit the rule of the market, or do they
make it possible to address grievances and mitigate certain injustices
perpetuated by capitalist elites? Can internationalist aims be furthered through institutions that are decidedly non-working-class in
origin? Is the current marginality of socialism in political thought
and public and social affairs due mainly to the embrace by too many
socialists of antiquated political ideas (specifically, workers’ councils)
as well as an unrealistic dependence upon outmoded political strategies and “solutions” to the problems of capitalism? Again, in relation to Luxemburg’s thought, was she correct in claiming that the
fate of humanity is tied up with the choice between “socialism or
barbarism”—or has history shown that there are other alternatives
between “socialism” and “barbarism” in any given moment of crisis?
Can revolution still be the ultimate goal of the labor movement, as
Luxemburg insisted it must be?
The new essays both bring up new issues and interrogate the
original ones. Amber Frost maintains that as the Left insists on the
relevance of the architects of its theories, it often draws incongruous connections between recent and current events (the 1999 Seattle
Introduction
●
7
uprising, Occupy Wall Street) and historical schools of thought, as
well as narrowly focuses on myopic areas of work. Only with more
comradely discursive exchange and a stronger connection to the
Left’s own activist history, she says, is it possible to effectively glean
insight from Rosa Luxemburg’s work. A stronger engagement by
socialists with socialist-feminist thought and radical queer theory is
also necessary.
Chris Maisano also connects the Luxemburg debate to the current moment. In Europe and North America, capitalist elites have
taken advantage of the economic crisis to attack both the welfare state
and the labor movement. While opposition to austerity is widespread,
citizens have not been able to adequately express their opposition
through electoral politics and public policy. This crisis of representation has compelled emergent movements like Occupy Wall Street
to completely reject parties, representation, and the state in favor of
“horizontalism” and prefigurative politics. Thus far, however, these
efforts have not been successful in translating popular discontent into
a sustainable political challenge to the rule of capital. Maisano argues
that as Occupy’s fortunes ebb, leftists should turn to the legacy of
Rosa Luxemburg to help them integrate direct action and representation, spontaneity and organization, participation and leadership.
The final new piece, by Michael Hirsch, returns to the German
Revolution of 1918–23, a “turning point of history where history failed
to turn” (as C. L. R. James once said of the Bolshevik Revolution).
It does so in order to combat the implication that the right-wing
SPD leadership was “constrained” in supporting the First World
War and in acting as an agent for big capital and the military, when
in fact Luxemburg and her comrades showed that German workers
had other options. Arguing that Luxemburg was nott a teleological
thinker, Hirsch claims that she merely (and rightly) viewed capitalism
as inherently unstable, that socialism was no natural successor; barbarism was equally likely, with the choice in the working class’s hands.
This is why she counterpoised reform to revolution as ends, blaming
the SPD’s abandonment of revolutionary goals on its party and trade
union apparatuses morphing into cooperators with capital. Contra
Luxemburg, says Hirsch, Bronner overestimates capital’s capacity to
mollify discontent and restrain workers from solidifying sociologically and politically. Luxemburg is pertinent today for those fighting
8
●
Jason Schulman
austerity measures and those who know that electoral victories are
possible but state power through the ballot box is not.
* *
*
Despite the global discrediting of neoliberalism, the Left remains in
disarray and at a strategic impasse. The social democratic Left, to
the extent that it has not simply collapsed into the neoliberal Right,
dreams of reviving the social-welfare regimes of the “Golden Age of
Capitalism”—despite the impossibility of returning to the old days
of the “Keynesian consensus.” The “Marxist-Leninist” and Trotskyist
parties remain small and stagnant, splintered into tiny factions incapable of significant growth, nearly all of them governed by “democratic centralist” regimes that are long on centralism and short on
democracy. New forms of anarchism and its cousin, autonomism,
have played major roles in worldwide radicalism since the birth of the
alter-globalization movement, paralleled by the rise of the Zapatistas
in Mexico and the piqueteross in Argentina, reemerging again in the
Occupy phenomenon after a near-decade of relative dormancy and
theorized as a way to “change the world without taking power.”16 But
there is no reason to believe that it is possible to change the world
without taking power; as Leo Panitch notes, what is required is that
“the balance of social forces that are in conflict in any society find
expression in the transformation—in terms of organisation as well as
policies—of the states in those societies.”17 Otherwise, all that is left
is “resistance,” which all too often fails to lead to significant material
change, typified by “the paramilitary nihilism of the [black-masked,
property-destroying] black bloc, fetishizing physical confrontation
with the police, preferring personal acts of rebellion in the here and
now over the unglamorous job of organizing a conscious class movement. ‘Educate, Agitate, Organize’ has faded into ‘Agitate, Agitate,
Agitate!’”18
The current near-universal impotence of the Left is reason enough
to take another look at the thought of Rosa Luxemburg, who never
failed to emphasize each part of the “educate, agitate, organize” slogan.
We must again read Luxemburg not because she provides a readymade model of revolutionary strategy to be emulated, not because
she has all the answers to the Left’s current dilemma, but because
Introduction
●
9
her democratic, internationalist, antimilitarist, antiopportunist, and
emancipatory socialist principles were the right principles. We need
her sense of “democratic consciousness” and “cosmopolitan pedagogy.” We can no more treat her writings as holy writ than she did
those of Marx and Engels, but we also cannot do without her. The
main questions one will find in the debate within these pages are
how best to apply her legacy today, how to discern what remains relevant, and what must be left behind. That is enough to demonstrate
its pertinence for those trying not only to understand the world, but
to change it.
Notes
1. See Leon Trotsky, “Hands Off Rosa Luxemburg!” (1932), http://www
.marxists.org/-archive/trotsky/1932/06/luxemberg.htm; Max Shachtman,
“Lenin and Rosa Luxemburg” (1938), http://www.marxists.org/archive
/shachtma/1938/05/len-lux.htm; Paul Mattick, “Luxemburg versus Lenin”
(1935), http://www.marxists.org/archive/mattick-paul/1935/luxemburg
-lenin.htm (all accessed May 24, 2013), as well as Paul Frölich, Rosa
Luxemburg: Her Life and Work,
k Edward Fitzgerald, trans. (London: Victor
Gollancz, 1940). For later critical defenses see Tony Cliff, Rosa Luxemburg
(London: International Socialism, 1959); Lelio Basso, Rosa Luxemburg: A
Reappraisall, Douglas Parmée, trans. (London: Deutsch, 1975); Norman
Geras, The Legacy of Rosa Luxemburgg (London: Verso, 1983); and Raya
Dunayevskaya, Rosa Luxemburg, Women’s Liberation, and Marx’s Philosophy
of Revolution (Champaign-Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991).
2. Georg Adler, Peter Hudis, and Annelies Laschitza, eds.; George Shriver,
trans. The Letters of Rosa Luxemburgg (London: Verso, 2011).
3. The Guangzhou conference “included eighty participants from China,
Japan, India, Russia, Germany, Austria, Switzerland, France, Norway and
the US. While this was not the first time that a conference on Luxemburg
had been held in China, it represented the most far-ranging and comprehensive discussion of her work in the history of the country.” Peter
Hudis, “Rosa Luxemburg in China: A Report on the ‘Rosa Luxemburg’
Conference 21–22 November 2004—South China Agricultural University,
Guangzhou, China,” Historical Materialism Vol. 13 No. 3 (2005), p. 318.
4. Estrella Trincado, “The Current Relevance of Rosa Luxemburg’s Thought,”
Socialist Studies / É
Études socialistess Vol. 6 No. 2 (Fall 2010), p. 142.
5. Dick Howard: “With the growth of a New Left during the past decade,
a practicall reflection on the bases of socialism has again begun after years
of Stalinism and silence. More recently, attempts to theorizee the new
10
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
●
Jason Schulman
practice have been undertaken . . . In the renewed debate, the name of Rosa
Luxemburg is more and more frequently mentioned.” “Introduction,” Dick
Howard, ed. Selected Political Writings of Rosa Luxemburgg (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 1971), p. 9.
Ingo Schmidt, “Capital Ideas,” Red Pepperr (May 2011), http://www.red
pepper.org.uk/capital-ideas/ (accessed May 24, 2013). See also Riccardo
Bellofiore, ed., Rosa Luxemburg and the Critique of Political Economyy (New
York: Routledge, 2009).
See Peter Hudis, ed., The Complete Works of Rosa Luxemburg, Volume 1:
Economic Writings I (London: Verso, 2013).
Stephen Eric Bronner, “Red Dreams and the New Millennium: Notes on
the Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg,” New Politicss Vol. 8 No. 3 (Summer 2001),
p. 162.
Stephen Eric Bronner, “Rosa in Cairo,” Reader Supported Newss (February 8,
2011), http://readersupportednews.org/opinion2/289–134/4890-rosa
(accessed May 24, 2013).
Bronner, “Red Dreams and the New Millennium,” p. 163.
Ibid, pp. 165–66.
Stephen Eric Bronner, “Rosa Redux: A Reply to David Camfield and Alan
Johnson,” New Politicss Vol. 8 No. 4 (Winter 2002), p. 160.
David Camfield, “A Second Reply to Bronner,” New Politicss Vol. 8 No. 4
(Winter 2002), p. 141.
Paul Le Blanc, “Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?,”
New Politicss Vol. 9 No. 1 (Summer 2002), p. 204.
See “About New Politicss,” http://newpol.org/about (accessed May 24, 2013).
John Holloway, Change The World without Taking Powerr (London: Pluto
Press, 2002); John Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London: Pluto Press, 2010).
Leo Panitch, “Global Capitalism and the Left,” New Left Project (December
20, 2012), http://www.newleftproject.org/index.php/site/article_comments
/global_capitalism_and_the_left (accessed June 2, 2013).
Bhaskar Sunkara, “Why We Loved the Zapatistas,” Jacobin No. 1 (Winter
2011), http://jacobinmag.com/2011/01/why-we-loved-the-zapatistas/
(accessed June 2, 2013).
CHAPTER 1
Red Dreams and the New Millennium:
Notes on the Legacy of
Rosa Luxemburg*
Stephen Eric Bronner
R
osa Luxemburg always seemed larger than life. An intellectual and a social activist, possessed of enormous charisma,
she exacted tremendous loyalty from her friends and often
a grudging admiration from her enemies. She struggled both as a
woman and a Jew in the socialist labor movement and died a martyr’s
death at the hands of the Freikorpss during the Spartacus Revolt of
1919. Her letters published following these events, and the castigation
of her legacy during the “bolshevization” of the German Communist
Party during the 1920s, provide abundant evidence of her courage,
her sensitivity, and her humanism. None of this, however, gives her
any particular salience for the present. Luxemburg disliked turning
personal issues into political ones. She would probably have noted
that there were many less heralded men and women—just as sensitive
and just as brave—who died just as tragically. Luxemburg would have
said: “Look to my work.”
Especially in our neoliberal culture, however, her form of political commitment is as unfashionable as the values she held dear.
Luxemburg was consistent in criticizing a strategy based purely on
the quest for economic reform and unwavering in her contempt for
12
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
authoritarianism. She was a Marxist with a romantic vision of revolution and an economistic belief in the ultimate “breakdown” of capitalism. She remains the most important representative of a libertarian
socialist tradition inspired by internationalism, economic justice, and
a radical belief in democracy.
Appropriating her legacy, however, involves more than regurgitating
the old slogans or finding the appropriate citations from her pamphlets
and speeches. Luxemburg knew things had changed from the time of
Marx, and she worried publicly over the “stagnation of Marxism”: the
outmoded claims about political events inherited by the party regulars,
including the independence of Poland, no less than the unresolved
questions about the workings of capitalism. Since her death, even more
profound changes have taken place. And what is good for the goose is
good for the gander. The same critical method Luxemburg employed
against Marx must now be turned against what appears inadequate
about her own views. It is indeed a matter of freeing her thinking
from an outmoded teleology and drawing the political consequences.
Perhaps the following will offer some steps in the right direction.
* *
*
Luxemburg was no slave of Marx. But she too believed that capitalism
would create its own gravediggers. And if she liked to quote the famous
line from Engels that the future hinged on the choice between “socialism or barbarism,” no less than most of her contemporaries, she felt
confident about which would ultimately prove victorious. Everything
about her politics derived from her dialectical understanding of capitalism and the revolutionary mission of the proletariat. Indeed, from
the very beginning, she intuited that the political power of capital
rested on the degree of organizational and ideological disunity among
workers.
Luxemburg’s concern with internationalism followed from this
insight and her dissertation written at the University of Zurich, The
Industrial Development of Polandd (1898), already provided the outline for her distinctive critique of “national self-determination.” Polish
independence had been a demand of the Left for generations. In this
work, however, Luxemburg argued that Polish independence would
only slow the progress of capitalist development and thus the growth
Red Dreams and the New Millennium
●
13
of the proletariat within the (Russian) empire as a whole. Unqualified
support for Polish nationalism would privilege symbolism over the
need for a constitutional republic to replace the imperial regime. The
arguments of Marx and his followers, she maintained, were actually
anti-Marxist and self-defeating.
Luxemburg saw any endorsement of nationalism as a breach of
proletarian principle. Her work highlighted the way this ideology
strengthens capitalism by dividing workers, justifies the wars in
which they will fight, and inhibits their ability to deal with what she
correctly considered an international economic system. She would
develop these themes further in her major economic work: The
Accumulation of Capitall (1913). It, too, would prove critical of views
taken for granted in the labor movement. Marx had claimed that
capitalism is based on investment and without it the system will collapse. Given his insistence that production always outstrips demand,
however, no logical reason exists why capitalists should continue to
invest and reinvest. Something within the very structure of capitalism
must, Luxemburg reasoned, allow for the consumption of its surplus
and thereby offer an incentive for ongoing investment. Imperialism
was her answer.
New markets and cheap resources, the prospect of modernizing precapitalist territories both within the nation-state and abroad, seemed to
provide the safety valve for capitalism. She indeed viewed the existence
of such territories as the condition for the survival of capitalism. Should
they ever become capitalist in their own right, which the dynamics of
economic production guaranteed, then the international system would
suffer an immediate “breakdown.” But that remained for the future.
In the meantime, spurred by their own self-interest, capitalist states
would have no other choice than to compete with one another frantically for a steadily diminishing set of colonies. Militarism and nationalism subsequently become intrinsic elements of imperialist strategies
generated by capitalism: war is built into the system and incapable of
reform. Thus, Luxemburg called for revolution.
*
*
*
No less than most Social Democrats of her generation, Luxemburg
longed for a republic. Such was, in fact, the way in which the
14
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
“dictatorship of the proletariat” was generally understood in the
decades between the fall of the Paris Commune in 1871 and the triumph of the Bolsheviks in 1917. The European labor movement prior
to the First World War functioned on a continent still dominated by
monarchies and the commitment to a republic was the political dividing line between Right and Left. Conservative programs everywhere
called for authoritarian institutions and restraints on “the masses.”
Social Democracy alone provided the alternative vision. Insisting that
the working class would expand with the expansion of capitalism,
assuming that its parties embodied the proletarian class interest, it
only made sense to call for the creation of political institutions in
which the labor movement could organize freely and ultimately rule
as the majority. Therein lies the connection between Marxism and
republicanism.
Luxemburg was a romantic, but never fully a utopian: the new
socialist society was always identified with a certain institutional
arrangement for the practice of politics. Her critique of “revisionism”
in Reform or Revolution (1900), which made her famous throughout
the labor movement, was far less based upon contempt for reform
tout courtt than on her contention that an unqualified “economism”
undermined the revolutionary commitment necessary for instituting a republic. Luxemburg herself supported “revisionists” in various
electoral campaigns and fought for numerous reforms including the
40-hour week. She did not reject reform out of hand, but only insisted
that it should be employed to whet the appetite of the masses for
more radical political demands. Luxemburg was no different than
Kautsky or Lenin or most other members of the socialist Left regarding the connection between reform and revolution. She was unique
only in her understanding of what was necessary to bring the revolution about and the radical democratic purpose it should serve. This
was what she sought to articulate in The Mass Strike, the Party, and
the Trade Unionss (1906).
The Russian Revolution of 1905, what Trotsky called the “dress
rehearsal” for 1917, was the pamphlet’s inspiration. A series of spontaneous strikes beginning in Baku in 1902 gradually engulfed the
Russian Empire. These seemingly spontaneous actions were, of
course, indirectly influenced by years of underground party activity. Luxemburg extrapolated from these events in order to develop
Red Dreams and the New Millennium
●
15
her general political theory. She believed that the party should now
preoccupy itself less with immediate organizational interests than
with forming the perquisite consciousness required for the political
struggle. Thus, committed radicals should foster a certain “creative
tension” between party and base in order to mitigate the bureaucratic tendencies of the former and the adventurist experiments of
the latter.
This tension was exemplified, according to Luxemburg, in the
mass strike. Here is the core of her notion regarding the “self-administration” of the working class. Deriving from a tradition reaching back
over the Paris Commune to Rousseau, she understood democracy not
merely in terms of securing civil liberties, but also inherently demanding its practical exercise. Socialism must therefore logically involve
the extension of democracy rather than its constriction. The purpose
of the labor movement was not merely the introduction of reformist
legislation, but the creation of an institutional arrangement wherein
workers might administer their own affairs without alienation or the
impediments of bureaucracy. Her beautiful letters, written amid the
factory takeovers in Warsaw during 1905, evidence her enthusiasm
for the burgeoning “soviet” or “council” movement and the introduction of democracy into everyday life.
But this new enthusiasm never fully supplanted her original goal.
Luxemburg intuited that only a republic could guarantee the maintenance of civil liberties. Genuine democracy is not simply equivalent
with the will of the majority, she realized, but also with the ability to
protect the minority. Her famous line from “The Russian Revolution”
r u. There is a sense in which her entire
(1918) was not (merely) an aperç
political project rested on the belief that “freedom is only and exclusively freedom for the one who thinks differently.” Luxemburg foresaw how the Communist suppression of bourgeois democracy in 1917
would unleash a dynamic of terror ultimately paralyzing the soviets
and undermining public life in the nation as a whole. Even in 1919,
while the Spartacus Revolt was brewing in Germany, Luxemburg
vacillated between her traditional commitment to a republic and the
new popularity of workers’ councils. Only when she was outvoted
would she completely identify with the “soviet republic” (Raterepublik)
and the policy of her less sober followers’ intent on emulating the
events in Russia.
16
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
The Russian Revolution indeed inspired revolutions all over Europe
and the formation of Communist parties around the world. Luxemburg
was skeptical about the plans for a Communist International. She was
fearful about its domination by the fledgling Soviet Union and the
identification of socialism with its national interests. Neither authoritarianism nor nationalism was understood by her as some historical “deviation” demanded by the present, which the dialectic would
set right in the future. She instead considered both as infringements
upon that future. In the same vein, neither the party nor the revolution should serve as an end unto itself. It was the freedom of working
people with which Rosa Luxemburg was concerned. This ultimately
made her a rebel in both major camps of the labor movement. It is also
what makes her salient for the present.
* *
*
Rosa Luxemburg lived during what has appropriately been called
the “golden age of Marxism.” The years between 1889 and 1914
witnessed a growing labor movement with a thriving public sphere
whose political parties were everywhere making ever-greater claims to
power. It was a time when each could see the socialist future appearing as present. That time is over. Marxism can no longer be construed
as a “science”; the industrial proletariat is on the wane; and the labor
movement is obviously no longer what it once was.
“Actually existing socialism” had its chance and little from history
suggests that workers’ councils can either deal with a complex economy or guarantee civil liberties. New utopian speculations, moreover,
cannot compensate for the lack of any serious alternative to the liberal republican state. The institutional goal of the revolution initially
sought by Luxemburg has, in short, been realized. Presenting socialism as the otherr, the emancipated society, no longer makes sense. It is
necessary to approach the matter in a different way.
Modern capitalism is no longer the system described by Charles
Dickens. Its liberal state has been used to improve the economic lives
of workers, foster participation, and provide the realisticc hope for a
redress of basic grievances. Luxemburg was wrong: the choice is not
between socialism and barbarism. Not only has history shown that the
Red Dreams and the New Millennium
●
17
two are not mutually exclusive, it has also shown there is much room
in between. The issue is no longer “capitalism” in the abstract, or the
future erection of “socialism,” but the pressing need for a response to
neoliberal elites intent upon rolling back the gains made by the labor
movement in the name of market imperatives.
Or putting it another way: the contemporary problem is not the
prevalent commitment to reform, which concerned Rosa Luxemburg,
but the lack of such a commitment. Revolution is no longer the issue
in the Western democracies and, in turn, this has general implications
for the meaning of socialism under modern conditions: whatever else
the term might imply, it must initially be understood as a practice
intent upon mitigating the whip of the market throughh the state and
abolishing the exercise of arbitrary power byy the state.
Such an economic and political enterprise is now, furthermore,
predicated on little more than an ethical commitment. Teleology,
if not ideology, has lost its allure. Capitalism can survive and, more
importantly, most people believe it will. But, ironically, there is a sense
in which the very success of neoliberalism may attest to the validity
of Luxemburg’s claim that the fight for economic reform is a “labor
of Sisyphus.” Without an articulated alternative and a meaningful
form of revolutionary agency, it is still necessary to roll the rock of
reform back up the hill. This cannot be left in the hands of Social
Democratic, or ex-Communist parties, intoxicated by neoliberalism
and the unprincipled compromises associated with the “third way” or
what is now being called “progressive governance.” Indeed, without
forgetting the institutional arrangements in which real politics takes
place, those with a more radical commitment to social justice must
now increasingly seek new forms of alliance between workers and
members of the new social movements.
Justice is a river with many tributaries. Most women and gays,
minorities and environmentalists, have a stake in protecting the gains
made by labor in the past as surely as labor has a stake in furthering
many of their concerns in the future. The mass demonstrations contesting the inequalities and devastation generated by global capitalism,
which began in 1999 in Seattle and triggered other mass demonstrations elsewhere, provide a case in point: they not only exerted real
pressure on the Democratic Party, and momentarily united competing
18
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
groups in a spirit of internationalism, but also raised precisely those
calls for international labor standards and environmental protection
repressed in the mainstream discourse.
The genuinely progressive response to globalization still requires
formulation. But nothing so demeans the internationalist spirit cherished by Rosa Luxemburg like the current insistence of some leftists
upon the primacy of ethnic aspirations or national sovereignty over the
international obligations of states to the planetary community. The
proletarian internationals of the past have collapsed. The only institutions capable of furthering internationalism are now intertwined
with capitalist interests and they tend to privilege strong states over
their weaker brethren. But I think Luxemburg would have realized
that the choice between furthering relatively progressive ends through
imperfect institutions and simply opposing their empowerment is no
choice at all. She was never fooled into believing that insistence upon
national sovereignty would align her with the masses of the formerly
colonized world rather than the corrupt elites who still rule them in
the most brutal fashion.
Luxemburg may not have anticipated the rise of national liberation movements. She was surely mistaken in believing that the
First World War had put an end to purely national conflicts and she
ignored questions concerning the right to resist invasion. But there
was a way in which she understood nationalism far better than her
opponents. Luxemburg realized that nationalism, like authoritarianism, has its own dynamic and that it cannot simply be manipulated
for socialist purposes or for the prospect of economic gain. Instead
of relying upon historical “laws,” or dialectical sophistry, Luxemburg
always correctly insisted on establishing a plausible relation between
means and ends.
Diseases like cholera, dysentery, and AIDS are ravaging continents.
Entire species are disappearing, global warming is taking place, pollution is intensifying, garbage is littering the planet. All this while
a global society is taking shape in which wealth and resources are
evermore inequitably distributed, political power is evermore surely
devolving into the hands of transnational corporations, and petty
ideologues are evermore confidently whipping up atavistic passions
with the most barbaric consequences. The nation-state is incapable of
dealing with most of these developments, and the usual invocations
Red Dreams and the New Millennium
●
19
of national sovereignty, or the disclaimer on any form of international
intervention under any circumstances, are simply an abdication of
responsibility.
No less than Machiavelli and Kant, in this vein, Luxemburg would
have agreed with the dictum: “He who wills the end also wills the
means thereto.” Either planetary issues of this sort will have the possibilityy of being dealt with in the international arena through existing
international institutions with the powers of sanctioning transgressors or they will assuredlyy not be dealt with at all. Human rights and
new forms of transnational welfare policy constitute the only concrete
prospects for a livable planet. The slogan of “the worse the better” has
always been a losing proposition: the belief that intensified repression or exploitation will somehow automatically produce a progressive
response is an illusion. The question facing the Left is whether to
embrace outmoded forms of thinking or provide new meaning for an
old vision. Make no mistake: its internationalist, socialist, and democratic values are in danger of petrifying. They must be adapted to
meet new historical conditions without surrendering their bite. This
is no easy undertaking and the possibilities for opportunism are enormous. But, then, Rosa Luxemburg never walked away from a challenge: I don’t think she would walk away from this one either.
Note
* The following is the text of a lecture given at the Rosa Luxemburg Foundation
in Berlin on June 19, 2000; it was translated and published in the German journal in Utopie-Kreativv No. 123 (January, 2001), pp. 9–16.
CHAPTER 2
A Critical Reply to Stephen
Eric Bronner
Alan Johnson
W
hat is the “salience for the present” of Rosa Luxemburg’s
thought? That was the timely question posed by Steve
Bronner’s article. Steve has done much to preserve
Luxemburg’s legacy in his 1979 edited collection, The Letters of Rosa
Luxemburg, and his 1981 book, A Revolutionary for Our Times: Rosa
Luxemburg. Twenty years ago Steve wrote, “Luxemburg understood
that it was Marx’s method, not anyone of his particular judgments,
that provided the key to emancipation.”1 Now Steve thinks the condition for an appropriation of Luxemburg’s thought is a rejection of the
dogmatic and teleological Marxist framework within which it was
developed. I do not find this reversal persuasive. In Part 1 I suggest
there are some general problems with this “post-Marxist” method of
appropriating the legacy of Marxism. In Part 2 I challenge some of the
new political conclusions Steve has drawn from his new Luxemburg.
Part 1: Ransacking the Legacy
Context is everything. I agree with Steve that simply regurgitating the
old slogans of long-dead Marxists is worse than inadequate. And yes,
we need the labors of critical re-appropriation, not idolatry. However,
22
●
Alan Johnson
these are banalities and it has been under the cover of such banalities
that a wholesale caricature of the entire Marxist tradition, so-called
post-Marxism, has established itself as the new common sense. The
y by Ernesto Laclau and
1987 work, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy,
Chantal Mouffe, is the most important work of the new caricaturists.
The central claim of that book—which Steve seems to have accepted
wholesale—is that the entire Marxist tradition is at its core a dogmatism, a crude determinism, an “economic neccesitarianism” unable to
cope with the complexity of the world. The new caricaturists tell us
that the thought of Marxism’s best practitioners, such as Luxemburg
or Gramsci, can be of some limited use for socialists today only on
condition that the useful bits (this insight, that concept, etc.) is extricated from the “teleological” and “deterministic” Marxist matrix in
which it was deformed. The result has resembled nothing so much
as the sack of Rome. When the Goths smashed up Roman buildings
and dragged away bits of stone they created two things: rubble and
fetishes. The post-Marxist Goths do something similar. They ransack Marxism for the concept of hegemony, which they hold aloft as
the foundation for a new politics of “radical democracy.” However,
they detach the concept from both the material structures and determinants that condition the battle and from the social agencies with
the interest and capacity to enter the fight. This is rejected as so
much “teleological” rubble, from the theory of historical materialism
(“monist”/“necessitarian”) and the theory of capitalist exploitation
and the capitalist state (“essentialist”/“economist”), to the theory of
the revolutionary potential of the working class (“Jacobin”/“religious”/
“classist”/“eschatalogical”).
Laclau and Mouffe’s impoverished and impoverishing reconstruction of Marxism, really a parody, has eaten through the United States
and European far left like a cancer. The precondition of progress is to
contest and refute it through our own scrupulous scholarly interrogation and creative development of the Marxist revolutionary project.
The English Marxist Raymond Williams argued that Marxism
must balance two kinds of theoretical work. First, “legitimating theory”: in other words we have to keep asking, “what was the legitimate
inheritance of an authentic Marxism—including the identification of
an authentic Marxist Marx—and thus, hopefully, an authentic revolutionary tradition.” Second, “operative theory”: in other words we
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
23
have to produce “theoretical analysis of late capitalist society; theoretical analysis of the specificities of [particular national] societies; theoretical analysis of the consequent situations and agencies of socialist
practice.” Either kind of theoretical work practiced in isolation from
the other is impoverished. A purely legitimating form of theory will
be unable to reconnect to the “confused and frustrating politics of
our own time and place.” A purely operative theory is likely to be
eclectic, to mistake short-term problems for long-term crises, and to
simply relinquish, rather than creatively develop, hard-won theoretical advances.
Marxism, warned Williams, can never reach a “finished” state. It
must be re/made “in many of its elements [in] essentially unfamiliar
ways” as it faces, square-on, “the altered social relations” of late capitalism. Williams’s own explorations of, for instance, the nature of a
contemporary materialism, of the environmental impact of capitalist
social relations, and of the new social movements, and their transformation of the prospects and forms of socialist transition, were efforts
at creative renewal. He sought to bring the Marxist tradition—to
which he came late—into a creative confrontation with the present,
to refine and renew Marxism.
Legitimating theory is often sneered at as “idolatry” or “sectarian.”
This is a mistake. We democratic revolutionary socialists, miniscule
in number and beleaguered, have to fight tooth and nail in this field.2
Doing decent operative Marxist theory today probably depends upon
doing “sectarian” legitimating Marxist theory. Marxism certainly has
to be retrieved from layers of Stalinist filth. However, it also has to be
defended against the post-Marxist reduction of the entire tradition to
an “economic necessitarianism.”3
I think the effort to liberate Luxemburg’s thought from a “teleological” Marxist cast results in something less than the full measure
being taken of its contemporary relevance. There are three points in
Steve’s article where this is so.
First, Steve claims Luxemburg had a “romantic vision of revolution.” This is a view common to bourgeois, “Leninist,” and, now,
post-Marxist commentators. However, the “romantic” label misses
much in her thought. One of the merits of Norman Geras’s book,
also titled The Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg, was to challenge this legend
and, with great exegetical care, draw out the “hard-headed strategic
24
●
Alan Johnson
realism” involved in Luxemburg’s “theorisation of . . . revolutionary
realities.” Luxemburg unified, as components of a distinctively democratic Marxist political matrix, theories of the nature of the bourgeois
state, the character of proletarian democracy, and the outline of a
viable socialist strategy. Steve seemed to me to spend much of his
article wrenching these apart again. Geras summarized Luxemburg’s
insight in these terms:
Method of motion and phenomenal form of the proletariat’s revolutionary struggle, the mass strike was in her eyes a way of breaking through the barriers erected by the bourgeois state against any
direct expression of the will of the masses. It was a way of releasing
and galvanising their energies, of overcoming the divisions and the
weakness, created by bourgeois ideology and partly by the proletarian condition itself, in order thereby both to concentrate their
strength and to impart to them a sense of it. . . . Socialism requiring by its very nature the control of the working masses over the
entirety of the social process, it was not possible to envisage that the
road to socialism might bypass the direct intervention and active
participation of these masses in movements of unprecedented scope
and vigour . . . The proletarian revolution had its own specific forms
proper to its unique objectives . . . Luxemburg was the very first to
draw the lesson of 1905 for the advanced capitalist countries and
to begin to pose the question of power there in a serious, and no
longer purely propagandistic way . . . Luxemburg’s lifelong emphasis on the importance of proletarian, socialist democracy was not
just a matter of some praiseworthy moral commitment on her part.
It was that, but not just that. For it was also a matter of the most
hard-headed strategic realism.4
Second, Steve alleges that Luxemburg held “an economistic belief
in the ultimate ‘breakdown’ of capitalism.” This is indisputable. She
thought that once capitalism was dominant throughout the world,
“Accumulation must come to a stop. The realization and capitalization of surplus value become impossible to accomplish . . . the collapse
of capitalism follows inevitably as an objective historical necessity.”
Now this may be wrong but it is not, as Steve says, a “teleology.” For
it to be that, it would have to include not only the idea of inevitable
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
25
capitalist breakdown but also an inevitable socialist triumph lodged
immanently within the structure of capitalism. However, no such
view can be found in Luxemburg. She wrote, “Bernstein doesn’t
understand in relation to capitalism as a whole, that society’s objective development merely gives us the preconditions of a higher level
of development, but . . . without our conscious interference, without
the political struggle of the working class for a socialist transformation or for a militia, neither the one nor the other will ever come
about.” For Luxemburg the collapse of capitalism is guaranteed, the
victory of socialism is not. As Geras pointed out, there is a “resolute refusal, embodied in her political activity and theory, to countenance any form of economism or to wait for that economic process
to work itself out.”5 In fact, Luxemburg’s view is very similar to Max
Shachtman’s that if socialism does not replace capitalism then forms
of barbarism will.
Third, Steve argues that Luxemburg “foresaw how the Communist
suppression of bourgeois democracy in 1917 would unleash a dynamic
of terror.” This suggests a simple continuity between Lenin and
Stalin, and between the revolution and the counterrevolution. It risks
throwing away the theoretical conquests the anti-Stalinist tradition
made—at what expense!—over three-quarters of a century, not just
those attempts at a materialist analysis of the degeneration of the revolution but more recent reconstructions of the political and ideological mistakes of the Bolsheviks from within the revolutionary socialist
tradition such as Samuel Farber’s book Before Stalinism: The Rise and
Fall of Soviet Democracyy (Verso, 1990).
Having said that, there is a common misunderstanding of
Luxemburg’s critique of the Bolsheviks, which Steve does help us avoid.
It is often thought that Luxemburg opposed the closing down of the
Constituent Assembly, then changed her mind and supported it. In
fact neither claim is true. She was prepared to support the Assembly’s
closure on the grounds advanced by the Bolsheviks, that it was, by
the time it met, politically unrepresentative of the country. Her criticism, surely right, was that Lenin and Trotsky “failed to arrive at the
conclusion which follows immediately” from their own argument,
namely, “without delay, new elections to a new Constituent Assembly
should have been arranged.” Worse, “Trotsky draws a general conclusion concerning the inadequacy of any popular representation
26
●
Alan Johnson
whatsoever” and begins talking dismissively of “‘the cumbersome
mechanism of democratic institutions.’” Luxemburg points out that
“the remedy which Trotsky and Lenin have found, the elimination of
democracy as such, is worse than the disease it is supposed to cure;
for it stops up the very living source from which alone can come the
correction of all the innate shortcomings of social institutions. That
source is the active, untrammeled, energetic political life of the broadest masses of the people.”6
Part 2: Marxism Today
I have suggested some contextual and exegetical problems with Steve’s
new appropriation of Luxemburg’s thought. I now contest a number
of claims Steve makes based on this appropriation.
Claims about Marxism and Science
Steve claims that Marxism could be thought of as a science in the
“golden age” of 1889–1914. As “that time is over,” Marxism “can no
longer be construed as a science.” Of course it all depends on what you
mean by science. What most Marxists meant by it in the period Steve
selects, 1889–1914 (after Marx but before the First World War and
Russian Revolution, the time of the Second International), was positivistic, crudely assimilating Marxism to the paradigm of the natural
sciences and doing Marxism great damage in the process. However,
why take that moment in Marxism’s history as some mark of Cain?
Why view the collapse of those misplaced scientistic hopes as a collapse of Marxism per se? Why conclude that all socialists have left is
“an ethical commitment?” The positivistic Marxism of the Second
International had both particular economic and political conditions
of possibility and many Marxist opponents. A very different Marxism
emerged during and after the First World War and the Russian
Revolution, the activist Marxism of Lenin, Luxemburg, Lukács, and
Korsch. In the United States, Sidney Hook wrote an excellent book
Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx: A Revolutionary Interpretation.
Published in 1933, Hook pointed out the “disastrous consequences”
of trying to make Marxism an objective science “both in logic and
historic fact.” Steve erases this bright shining moment in Marxism’s
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
27
history (quickly shut down by Stalinism) when a very different relation was established, in theory and practice, between Marxism and
the human making of History. Hook argued that to reject the passive
mechanical scientism of the Second International was to reclaim not
reject the Marxism of Marx:
Lenin and Luxemburg appealed [to] scientific knowledge. But scientific knowledge was not merely a disinterested report of objective
tendencies in the economic world but a critical appreciation of the
possibilities of political action liberated by such knowledge. The
spontaneity which the syndicalists exalted at the cost of reflection
was not enough. Unless a militant ideology or theory directed that
spontaneous will, its energies would run out in sporadic and futile
strike tactics . . . economic development [can] only produce by its
own immanent movement the presuppositions of socialism. Power
is bestowed neither by God nor the economic process. It must be
taken. When Marx spoke of communism as being the result of a
“social necessity” he was referring to the resultant of a whole social
process, one of whose components was the development of objective economic conditions, the other the assertion of a revolutionary class will. . . . Economic forces and revolutionary organisation,
Lenin insisted, are not related to each other as mechanical cause
and effect but are independent components of a dialectical whole.
Marxism does not have to be an outmoded teleology or an economic
necessitarianism. It has been before, and can be again, a theory and
practice of human liberation.
Claims about the Working Class
Steve claims that “the industrial proletariat is on the wane” and “the
labor movement is obviously no longer what it once was.” However,
we are living through the conjunctural political collapse of the two
dominant forms of working-class politics: Communism and Social
Democracy. We are not living through some postmodern “farewell
to the working class.” This is hardly comforting. However, it does
tell us what the basic job is: the political reconstitution of a (globally
gargantuan) working class as an independent political force. Hard
28
●
Alan Johnson
task it may be. Utopian, because of some systemic “waning” of the
proletariat, it is not. There are dozens of countries in which the industrial working class is growing explosively—Turkey, Argentina, Brazil,
China, India, South Africa, Thailand, Malaysia, and South Korea.
Globally, there are more industrial workers in 2001 than at any previous time in human history. In addition, it is much more productive
not just bigger.7 When Karl Marx published Capitall in 1867 there
were barely 250,000 trade unionists in Britain and very few anywhere
else. Today there are 165 million trade unionists worldwide. The
problem, I repeat, is a conjunctural one of political collapse, not a
“waning” of the structural capacities of the working class.
Claims about Workers’ Councils
Steve writes, “‘actually existing socialism’ had its chance and little from
history suggests that workers councils can either deal with a complex
economy or guarantee civil liberties.” Steve also argues that the “liberal republican state” is the realization of “the institutional goal of the
revolution initially sought by Luxemburg.”
Steve’s linking of the impossibility of workers’ councils to the failure of Stalinism in this way is unfortunate. It blurs the difference
between Stalinism, an exploitative social system, which crushed all
democracy, parliamentary or council, representative or direct, and
the revolutionary Marxist tradition, which embraced workers’ councils in theory and practice. Also troubling is Steve’s comment that
Stalinism and socialism “are not mutually exclusive.” I wonder if this
risks undermining the struggle, practical and theoretical, of an entire
historical tradition to preserve something more than radical liberalism from the wreck of Stalinism.
I am tempted to respond to Steve’s dismissal of workers’ councils
with the question “how do you know?” for when were workers’ councils seriously tried only to fail due to some genetic weakness rather than
counterrevolutionary violence? Blurring the lines between Stalinism
and socialism tends to bracket this question out.
It is also misleading to say that the “liberal republican state” is
the realization of Luxemburg’s political vision. Quotes do not resolve
if she was right or adequate for today but they do establish what
she thought. In What Does the Spartakusbund Want?? we find, “The
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
29
essence of the socialist society is that the great working mass ceases
to be a ruled mass and instead lives and controls its own political and
economic life in conscious and free self-determination. Thus from
the highest offices of the state down to the smallest municipality, the
proletarian mass must replace the outdated organs of bourgeois class
rule—the federal councils, parliaments, municipal councils—with
their own class organs; the workers’ and soldiers’ councils.”8
Luxemburg, like Marx and Engels, stood for the democratic republic. More than anyone, Luxemburg understood that only the democratic republic could give shape to the idea of “dictatorship of the
proletariat” in a form compatible with self-emancipation. But she
reminded Bernstein that “the poultry yard of bourgeois parliamentarism” could not be the means to achieve “the most formidable transformation of history, the passage from capitalist society to socialism.”
Appropriating the legacy of Luxemburg’s thought would show how
she struggled, and failed, to integrate both these insights amid the
turmoil of war and revolution. For Rosa Luxemburg had the advantage over Marx of being alive to assimilate the fundamental lesson of
the revolutions of the period 1917–23. Everywhere, the popular revolt
reached a certain scale and intensity, councils or soviets or committees grew up alongside older representative democratic institutions.
Hannah Arendt pointed out that the reason the history of these democratic forms has been ignored is that “wherever they appeared, they
were met with utmost hostility from the party bureaucracies and their
leaders from right to left, and with the unanimous neglect of political theorists and political scientists.” She added, “Workers’ councils,
such as those in Russia in 1917, have for more than one hundred years
now emerged whenever the people have been permitted for a few days
or a few weeks or months, to follow their own political devices without a government (or a party program) imposed from above.”9 The
relationship of councils to parliaments became the subject of intense
debate within the Marxist movement. These debates are often little
known, let alone discussed. They offer no easy answers. However,
based as they are upon the most advanced practical expressions of
self-emancipation in human history, our task is to take the utmost
care in their reclamation for the present. I doubt that casting the “liberal republican state” as the “realization” of Luxemburg’s vision is adequate to this task. For the “liberal republican state” exists nowhere.
30
●
Alan Johnson
Whatever of its forms are preserved/transformed, the brute fact is that
the “only” thing that lies between the actually existing liberal republican state (the one which serves the corporations and steals elections)
and the democratic republic (the institutional form of popular sovereignty) is a revolution.
However, the institutional shape of the socialist polity is a radically underdeveloped area of Marxist political theory. To take just
one example to illustrate the wider point, it is often thought axiomatic
that Marxists support the ending of the separation of powers between
legislature and executive. Actually, this was not accepted throughout
the Marxist movement. Karl Kautsky’s writings in the years immediately following the Russian Revolution, for example, are a sophisticated Marxist argument for the indispensability of separation. And
on the question of the administration of a socialist society, Kautsky’s
thoughts might be useful additions to Lenin’s remark that “every cook
can rule.”10 Revolutionary socialists should have the confidence to
return to these debates, and to the ideas of the Left Mensheviks, ending all the intellectual bans and prohibitions we have inherited.
It is not for wanting to open up these debates that Steve should
be criticized but for the opposite: closing the debate down by a rash
dismissal of the potential of direct democratic forms to play a central
role in both the transition and in the institutional shape of a socialist
polity.
Claims about Capitalism and Socialism
Back in 1981 Steve usefully reminded socialists that “the liquidation
of socialism as an alternativee to capitalism through the emphasis upon
particular reforms per see has resulted in an identity crisis for social
democracy.”11 Today, Steve claims that presenting socialism as a wholly
alternative social system, as the other, is wrong (the italics, on both
occasions are his). Again, Steve seems to be surrendering valuable theoretical positions for little return. The world is globalizing before our
eyes but under the direction of multinational capitalist corporations
and unaccountable institutions of global economic and political governance. It can seem guided by nothing more than moneymaking and
ethnic violence. There is a global crisis of reformism. Socialism has
never seemed more like the other to me.
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
31
Steve motivates this particular reversal by some sentences about
“modern capitalism” and “the liberal state”:
Modern capitalism is no longer the system described by Charles
Dickens. Its liberal state has been used to improve the economic
lives of workers, foster participation, and provide the realistic hope
for a redress of grievances. Luxemburg was wrong: the choice is not
between socialism and barbarism.
Capitalist governments can ward off disaster by subsidizing industries,
manipulating fiscal policies, and introducing welfare legislation.
Steve sounds curiously like Luxemburg’s old opponent Eduard
Bernstein. Or the British Labor Party theoretician Tony Crosland in
his book The Future of Socialism, written in 1956. But after Bernstein
came capitalism’s own Thirty Years War. And after Crosland we had
the end of the Long Boom to which he had pinned his socialist hopes,
world economic crisis, a triumphant neoliberal campaign to drive
down workers’ living standards, the steady erosion of the social wage,
the desocial democratization of the world, and the squeeze on popular participation in decision making. In the United States, in 1997,
35.6 million people, close to one in seven Americans, lived below the
official poverty line. Globally, obscene levels of inequality, murderous
ethnic violence, war, and continued environmental catastrophe vie for
the status of the social problem most likely to finish us off. According
to the United Nations Human Development Report for 1999, income
per person in half the countries of the world was lower at the end of
the 1990s than at the beginning. Among those who live in developing countries (three out of four human beings) over half lack access
to safe sewers, one in three lack clean water, one in four lack adequate
housing, and one in five have no health services. In the face of all that
Steve’s remarks about “modern capitalism” can sound rather like the
Dickens character Mr. Podsnap, who, when asked about the good
fortune of being an Englishman, replied:
“‘It was bestowed Upon Us By Providence. No Other Country is so
Favoured as This Country . . .”
“And other countries,” said the foreign gentleman. “They do
how?”
32
●
Alan Johnson
“They do, Sir,” returned Mr. Podsnap, gravely shaking his head,
“they do—I am sorry to be obliged to say it—as they do.”
Against Steve’s intent I am sure, his new understanding of “modern
capitalism” and “the liberal republican state” has a bit of Podsnappery
about it:
“And Capitalism,” said the teleological Marxist, remorsefully, “It
does how?”
“It does,” returned Mr. Bronner severely: “It does—I am sorry
to be obliged to say it—in Every Respect Better. Its Liberal State
is Literally Unsurpassable. Its Rate of Political Participation is
Unmatched. The Integrative Power of its Welfare Services and
the Adaptive Power of its Fiscal Policies renders it Hegemonic and
Crisis-Free.”12
Elsewhere in his article, Steve himself indicts the barbarism of the
world. The point is, for this reader at least, that this indictment sits at
odds with the Podsnappish remarks about “modern capitalism” and
the new theory of “the liberal republican state.” There are, I think,
two incompatible positions, jostling.
Claims about Internationalism
Fourth, Steve recommends Luxemburg’s opposition to the call for
national self-determination as a nationalistic demand that divides
the working class. For all Steve’s concern for the dangers of a dogmatic Marxism unable to engage in the complex task of constructing contingent political majorities, he has embraced the most crude,
dogmatic, indeed politically useless aspect of Luxemburg’s thought.
Ironically, it is an aspect of her thought derived from precisely those
elements within Marxism of teleology and determinism (“Luxemburg
argued that Polish independence would only slow the progress of
capitalist development, and thus the growth of the proletariat,” says
Steve). What of the rich legacy of debates among, for instance, the
early Bolsheviks concerning national oppression, national minorities, the right to self-determination, the question of federal political
structures, and the relation of socialism to all of the above? These
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
33
discussions remain unsurpassed, by Marxists at least, to this day.
Actually it’s much worse than that. We are living through a kind of
Grand Regression in which the sophisticated calibration of class and
nation attempted by the Bolsheviks has given way to a Manichean
view of the world in which the Great Satan in Washington clashes
with various “objective anti-imperialists” from the strutting generals
to the acid-throwers.
Steve is not a subscriber to that particular Grand Regression.
However, he does risk a regression of his own with the claim that
to favor national self-determination is to “endorse nationalism” and
to “insist on the primacy of ethnic aspirations.” But Lenin was not
insisting on the “primacy of ethnic aspirations” when he argued that
“when national oppression makes joint life absolutely intolerable then
the interests of the class struggle will be best served by secession.”
Steve confuses the Zinovievist efforts to manipulate nationalism for
socialist ends, especially in Asia, with Lenin’s policy of “clearing the
decks” for the class struggle by fighting for “consistent democracy.”
That policy—though we have to think for ourselves about how to
apply it—is relevant today. There is no way past, through, or around
nationalism other than consistent democracy married to socialist
organization and politics.
Steve also claimed that “the only institutions capable of furthering
internationalism are now intertwined with capitalist interests and they
tend to privilege strong states over their weaker brethren.” However,
in the spirit of Luxemburg’s internationalism, we should support the
interventions of these “imperfect institutions” to prevent slaughter.
I assume Steve means the UN and NATO.
The left does face excruciating dilemmas today, situations in which
we lack forces on the ground and where the only realistic obstacle to
slaughter is the intervention of the UN or NATO, or the armed forces
of some bourgeois state or alliance of states. Take Rwanda. I might
have tried to formulate the sentences opposing any intervention as
“imperialist” but they would not take shape in my mouth. At least not
without a feeling of shame. And yet, I also know that intervention can
itself lead to a far worse slaughter than anything which prompted the
intervention, as it has in Iraq. I also know that it will be other, progressive forces that will face “interventions” in the future, and that my
support of any intervention will have extended legitimacy to the Big
34
●
Alan Johnson
Powers. The historic defeat of socialism may be the root cause of the
dilemma, but what is there to do but wrestle with it? In the Falklands
War, the Gulf War, and the Kosovan conflict. I thought socialists
should be against both reactionary contenders. Rwanda seems to me
to be a different case, and socialists should not have opposed all forms
of intervention on principle. However, Steve, if I am reading him correctly, is not really wrestling with a dilemma. He is arguing there is no
dilemma because the UN and NATO are “furthering internationalism” albeit “imperfectly.” However, it is one thing to say the saving
of 1 million lives in Rwanda outweighs the need to deny any support
to bourgeois state forces. It is another to issue a blanket statement
that the UN and NATO are “furthering internationalism.” This is
to turn Marxism upside down. It is certainly to forget some advice
Luxemburg gave her comrades concerning the First World War: “Our
party should have been prepared to recognise the real aims of this
war, to meet it without surprise, to judge it by its deeper relationship
according to their wider political experience.”13
Claims about Socialist Strategy
I agree entirely with Steve that the fight to protect threatened welfare
benefits and democratic rights from rollback, and then to use that
resistance as a springboard to fight for further reforms, is a key to
socialist advance. I agree “revolution is no longer the issue in the western democracies.” That is just, for now, a fact. I also agree we must
“seek new forms of alliances between workers and members of the
new social movements.” Talk of “independent working class politics,”
which defines itself by hostility to such social movements, is useless,
not least because it misses the precondition of ‘‘independent working
class politics”: the political constitution of the multiethnic and gendered working class as a unity-in-difference.
However, Steve seems to argue that these fights will take place
“through the state” and through the “existing international institutions” or they will not take place at all. Again, despite his critique
of Marxism as dogmatic I find this . . . dogmatic. Why not some
combination of popular struggles outside coordinated with interventions inside existing democratic institutions? Isn’t that the most likely
strategic line of march for any popular movement? In addition, as
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
35
representative institutions are dominated—utterly, absolutely—by
corporate money power and the executive/permanent secret state, isn’t
it obvious that only a popular organized power outside Parliament
could win reforms inside Parliament? And this is only to talk of
reforms. When we talk of socialism as a new principle of social organization and a new society, and act on that talk, then the Marxist
theory of the state, which the post-Marxists are not interested in, will
become (to paraphrase Trotsky on war) very interested in them. As
William Morris put it, at that point, “rather than lose anything which
it considers of importance, it will pull the roof of the world down
upon its head.” The conjunctural weakness of our side, and the fact
that revolution, because of that weakness, is not on the agenda, is no
reason to forget basic truths gained at tremendous cost. In this case it
is the knowledge that there is a structural unity to the capitalist order
such that no sequence of reforms can peacefully change capitalism
into socialism. The young Sidney Hook put it well:
The attempt made by “liberal” Marxists . . . to separate the existing
economic order from the existing state, as well as their belief that
the existing state can be used as an instrument by which the economic system can be “gradually revolutionised” into state capitalism or state socialism must be regarded as a fundamental distortion
of Marxism. . . . For Marx every social revolution must be a political
revolution, and every political revolution must be directed against
the state.14
This need not mean an ultra-left rejection of reforms that would only
isolate the Left. Indeed, we could do a lot worse than think about
how to develop afresh for our own times the kind of transitional
political strategy Ernest Mandel mapped in the 1960s, the strategy of
structural reforms. This strategy was based upon the notion of coordinating a massive popular power, a network or coalition of forces,
permanently organized to press its demands with a supportive block
of popular elected representatives, ultimately a workers’ government.
Mandel aimed to update Marx’s notion, developed in his own time
by Trotsky, of a transitional political method in order to “effect an
integration between the immediate aims of the masses and the objectives of the struggle which objectively challenge the very existence of
36
●
Alan Johnson
the capitalist system itself.”15 Today, a transitional political strategy
would have to be based upon all popular struggles, and not only those
of the labor movement, it would be led by a multiplex political coalition and not “the” revolutionary party, and it would, of course, be
coordinated internationally. Perhaps something like this strategy has
the potential to be the contemporary version of the mass strike; what
Luxemburg called the “method of motion” or “phenomenal form” of
socialist advance. Perhaps.
But what is sure is that in the ranks of post-Marxism we will only
travel backwards, to the very beginning of the twentieth century when
Luxemburg complained that Bernstein “transforms socialism into a
variety of liberalism” and so “deprives the socialist movement . . . of its
class character.”
Steve’s thoughts on Luxemburg strike me as hovering somewhere
between these alternatives.
Notes
1. Stephen Eric Bronner, A Revolutionary for Our Times: Rosa Luxemburg
(London: Pluto, 1981), p. 107.
2. For an example of the most thoughtful and rigorous legitimating theory,
see the work of Norman Geras: Literature of Revolution: Essays on Marxism
(London: Verso, 1986) and Discourses of Extremity. Radical Ethics and PostMarxist Extravagancess (London: Verso, 1990).
3. Steve also indulges in some caricatured presentations of “the Left” against
which his implicit alternative is able to avoid scrutiny. For instance he insists
we have to stop using the slogan “the worse the better” and we have to stop
thinking that “intensified repression or exploitation will somehow automatically produce a progressive response.” It might be because I came into
politics with Thatcher and Reagan but in over 20 years of activity in student
unions, trade unions, the Labor Party, and more than one Marxist organization, I have not heard one person say anything like that. Ever. However,
the idea that hordes of dogmatic Marxists are out there saying things like
this all the time is central to the post-Marxist imaginary/mythology. The
post-Marxist alternative thatis hiding in the corner, hoping to avoid proper
scrutiny, is the idealist idea that there is just no connection at all between
capitalist crisis and the possibility of socialism.
4. Norman Geras, The Legacy of Rosa Luxemburgg (London; Verso, 1976),
pp. 122–24.
5. Ibid., p. 23.
A Critical Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
37
6. Rosa Luxemburg, The Russian Revolution (New York: Workers Age
Publishers, 1940), pp. 35, 38.
7. Paul Kellogg, “Goodbye to the Working Class?” International Socialism
Vol. 2 No. 36 (Autumn 1987), pp. 105–11.
8. Rosa Luxemburg, “What Does the Spartacus League Want?,” Dick Howard,
ed. Selected Political Writings of Rosa Luxemburgg (New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1971), p. 368.
9. Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Schocken
Books, 1951), p. 159. Thanks to Marvin and Betty Mandell for this point.
10. See Massimo Salvadori, Karl Kautsky and the Socialist Revolution, 1880 –1938
(London: Verso, 1979).
11. Bronner, A Revolutionaryy, p. 111.
12. Apologies to the memory of E. P. Thompson from whose essay “The
Peculiarities of the English” in The Poverty of Theoryy (New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1978, pp. 36–37) this little jest is adapted.
13. Rosa Luxemburg, “The Junius Pamphlet: The Crisis in the German SocialDemocracy,” in Mary-Alice Waters, ed., Rosa Luxemburg Speakss (New York:
Pathfinder, 1970). p. 279.
14. Sidney Hook, Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx: A Revolutionary
Interpretation (New York: The John Day Company, 1933), p. 271.
15. Ernest Mandel, A Socialist Strategy for Western Europee (Nottingham: Institute
for Workers’ Control, December 1968).
CHAPTER 3
A Second Reply to Stephen
Eric Bronner
David Camfield
I
n his “Notes on the Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg,” Stephen Eric
Bronner reflects on the question of the contemporary significance
of the ideas of the thinker and fighter he calls “the most important representative of a libertarian socialist tradition inspired by internationalism, economic justice, and a radical belief in democracy.” At
a time when the global justice movement is leading more people to
question neoliberal—and, for some, capitalist—certainties and to
search for alternatives, Bronner’s question is timely. His rejection of
dogmatically “regurgitating the old slogans or finding the appropriate
citations from her pamphlets and speeches” and his suggestion that
the inadequacies of Luxemburg’s thought deserve to be treated much
as Luxemburg critically appraised Marx’s work are praiseworthy.
However, Bronner’s argument—essentially, that it “no longer
makes sense” to conceive of socialism “as the otherr, the emancipated
society”—and therefore Luxemburg’s legacy for radical politics is a
determined struggle for reforms—concedes too much. Certainly, a
dogmatic reassertion of classical Marxism—even in its most intelligent variants—with a few minor innovations tacked on represents an
inadequate response to the challenges facing radical political thought
in the twenty-first century. But perspectives that underestimate the
40
●
David Camfield
extent to which liberal-democratic states are barriers to addressing
exploitation, oppression, alienation, and ecological destruction, and
which foreclose the historical possibility of human emancipation, are
at least as wanting. I also believe that Bronner’s article is inaccurate
with respect to Luxemburg’s ideas on two significant issues. I will
begin with this last point, since it seems related to Bronner’s view of
Luxemburg’s legacy, and then explain what I believe is the critical
weakness in what Bronner proposes as a strategic direction for the
Left. Finally, I will offer a different interpretation of Luxemburg’s
political legacy, which, I hope, does not shy away from confronting
the major challenges facing those for whom Luxemburg’s socialism
continues to be a source of inspiration (as well as other radicals).
Luxemburg, Reforms, and Bourgeois Democracy
Luxemburg’s role as a leading figure in the debate over “revisionism”
in the Second International is well known. Bronner writes that her
critique of Bernstein’s theoretical expression of revisionism in Reform
or Revolution “was based far less upon contempt for reform tout court
than on her contention that an unqualified ‘economism’ undermined
the revolutionary commitment necessary for instituting a republic.” True, Luxemburg’s position was (like Marx) one of fighting for
reforms within capitalist society in ways that changed the participants
and prepared for social revolution.1 She did not contemptuously reject
the struggles for tangible changes in which working-class people
inevitably engage as a result of their conditions of life. Her withering
intellectual dissection of Bernstein’s work was not, though, primarily
motivated by a concern that economism (restricting socialist politics
to struggles for higher wages, better conditions of work, lower rents,
etc.) was an obstacle to replacing the German imperial state with a
republic. Rather, it was animated by her fear that those for whom the
movement was everything and the final end nothing were abandoning the aim of replacing capitalism:
people who pronounce themselves in favour of the method of legislative reform in place of and in contradistinction to the conquest of
political power and social revolution, do not really choose a more
tranquil, calmer and slower road to the samee goal, but a different
A Second Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
41
goal. Instead of taking a stand for the establishment of a new society
they take a stand for surface modification of the old society . . . not
the realisation of socialism, but the reform of capitalism: not the
suppression of the system of wage labour, but the diminution of
exploitation, that is, the suppression of the abuses of capitalism
instead of the suppression of capitalism itself.2
Considering the actions of the Social Democratic Party and the “revisionist” current in Germany between 1914 and 1933, this was a prescient assessment.
Bronner notes that Luxemburg insisted that democracy had to
be a “practical exercise” and that the socialist objective was institutions through which the working class could run society “without
alienation or the impediments of bureaucracy,” such as the workers’
councils (soviets) first created in the Russian Revolution of 1905. He
goes on to write that “Luxemburg foresaw how the communist suppression of bourgeois democracy in 1917 would unleash a dynamic
of terror ultimately paralyzing the soviets and undermining public life.” Here Bronner conflates Luxemburg’s perceptive critique of
early antidemocratic actions of the Bolsheviks in power, which she
saw as hurting a revolution she whole-heartedly supported, with the
stance of Karl Kautsky and other political opponents of the Russian
Revolution. It was not the “suppression of bourgeois democracy in
1917” she criticized. She rightly did not see the unelected Provisional
Government overthrown in October 1917 as a democratic regime of
any kind. For Luxemburg, bourgeois democracy, where it existed, had
to be replaced because it was insufficiently democratic. As Norman
Geras has written, “she insisted that, in order to build socialism, the
masses would have first to explode through that very framework of
bourgeois-democratic
s
institutions which both Bernstein and Kautsky
wanted to preserve intact.”3 The goal was, in Luxemburg’s words, was
“to create a socialist democracy to replace bourgeois democracy.” This
had to begin
simultaneously with the beginnings of the destruction of class
rule and of the construction of socialism . . . at the very moment
of the seizure of power by the socialist party. It is the same thing
as the dictatorship of the proletariat. Yes, dictatorship! But this
42
●
David Camfield
y not in its
dictatorship consists in the manner of applying democracy,
elimination, in energetic, resolute attacks upon the well-entrenched
rights and economic relationships of bourgeois society . . . this dictatorship must be the work of the classs and not of a little leading
minority in the name of the class.4
Bronner’s claim about the “suppression of bourgeois democracy” is
probably referring to Luxemburg’s criticism of the Bolsheviks in her
pamphlet “The Russian Revolution” for abolishing the Constituent
Assembly. This, she wrote, “was decisive for their further position.”5
Yet, here she did not criticize the Bolsheviks in the manner implied
by Bronner. She was clearly an outspoken advocate of a thoroughgoing replacement of bourgeois democracy, which she saw as a form of
capitalist rule. Her criticism in this case referred solely to the closing
down of a democratic institution in a society in which she believed
the dictatorship of the proletariat had been established, and the consequences of this action for the Russian Revolution. She believed it was,
in Geras’s words, “one manifestation of a certain carelessness towards
democratic rights in general on the part of the Bolsheviks under pressure.”6 In criticizing the Bolsheviks, never did she defend “bourgeois
democracy.” It is also important to note that after her release from
prison, where she had drafted her pamphlet on the basis of the limited information available to her at the time, she concluded that her
judgment about the closing of the Constituent Assembly had been
mistaken.7
A Strategic Direction for the Left?
Bronner’s article is not merely “Luxemburgology.” It is to his credit
that he accepts the challenge of critically assessing what the Left
should take from Luxemburg’s writings more than eight decades after
her murder. It is his conclusion that is most debatable, rather than his
decision not to simply assert the continued relevance of Luxemburg’s
work. For Bronner claims that because our times are so different
from what he calls “the golden age of Marxism” between 1889 and
1914 (a remarkably one-sided way to view the heyday of the Second
International, considering that its role in what transpired between
1914 and 1945 was prepared in the earlier period) that Luxemburg’s
A Second Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
43
politics of revolutionary-democratic struggle for the self-emancipation
of the working class are today nonsensical. He writes that “the industrial proletariat is on the wane; and the labor movement is obviously
no longer what it once was.” Socialism as an alternative mode of social
organization in place of capitalism is not relevant or even desirable,
since workers’ councils could probably not run a “complex economy”
or ensure democratic rights. There is no “serious alternative to the liberal republican state.” Socialism today is about “mitigating the whip
of the market throughh the state and abolishing the exercise of arbitrary
power byy the state.” A reformist struggle against neoliberalism involving alliances between organized labor and other social movements
and a fight to free international institutions from capitalist influence
is what the Left should be engaging in.
What is most startling about this is that, in effect, Bronner concludes that the legacy of Luxemburg is in fact a principled updated
version of the politics of Bernstein and the “revisionist” wing of the
Second International before the First World War. Irony may be a
hallmark of contemporary Western intellectual culture, but this is a
remarkable convergence a century after Luxemburg penned Reform
or Revolution.
There are a number of good reasons to question this conclusion.
Above all, the liberal state upon which Bronner’s perspective ultimately depends is not a reliable vehicle for efforts to limit the power
of the market. Mass struggles—such as those in France—have slowed
neoliberalism’s dismantling of the social programs provided by the
state. But it is increasingly evident that state power is an integral
and active dimension of global capital’s offensive. Recent displays of
undisguised violence against global justice demonstrators in several
countries are merely an obvious example. More routinely, state power
is used to force the unwaged to work in order to qualify for meager
welfare benefits, to prevent migrants from crossing borders, and in a
host of ways to monitor, fine, deport, evict, harass, imprison, injure,
and kill people. In capitalist democracies, most of this coercion is
legal and sanctioned by elected authorities, of whatever party; where
it is not, unelected top officials are often able to do much as they
please. This is so precisely because existing state power is capitalist
state power. Its institutions have developed to politically administer
societies in which class and other social struggles may be suppressed
44
●
David Camfield
or dormant but continue to reemerge (and sometimes win reforms)
because people’s needs are frustrated by capital, male supremacy, racial
oppression, heterosexism, and other relations of domination exercised
through “liberal republican” states as well as in other ways. As such,
any limits to the market or the repressive exercise of state power are
fragile, ultimately dependent on the mobilizing power of social movements in maintaining them.
While Luxemburg’s view that “the present state . . . is a class state.
Therefore its reform measures are not . . . the control of society working
freely in its own labour process” is accurate, it is not an original contribution to state theory. But her revolutionary-democratic insistence
on the failings and class character of capitalist democracy ought to
inform the more sophisticated understanding of state power we need
to formulate political strategy today.8 Of course, capitalist democracy
undoubtedly remains preferable to more authoritarian forms of state
power, and needs to be defended. Anything that limits the ability
of the governments of the United States and other Western states to
use international institutions such as the UN in their own interests
ought to be welcomed, without suggesting that such institutions can
free themselves of the state relations in which they are implicated.
Building movements that put demands for reforms on liberal states in
a capitalist world is vital. However, to my mind, this does not constitute an adequate strategy.
Luxemburg’s Legacy: Another Interpretation
The weakness of working-class politics in the early twenty-first century is undeniable. As Bronner notes, Social Democracy and Stalinism
have largely adopted neoliberalism. Yet, on a global scale, the working
class is larger than ever. Those employed in manufacturing in the
advanced capitalist states have been pummelled by capitalist restructuring, but the ability and propensity to struggle against capital was
never the exclusive property of this one layer. In many countries, as
writers like Kim Moody and Gerard Greenfield have shown, there
are unions and community-based workers’ organizations (including
those of women and other oppressed people) that have made progress
with the difficult task of discovering (sometimes rediscovering) methods of struggle that enable people to not just protest against capital’s
A Second Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
45
agenda but to effectively combat it. Some organizations of peasants,
indigenous people, students, and others have done the same. It is to
these pioneering movements and struggles that we ought to direct our
attention.9
Of course, few of these movements claim to present an alternative to capitalism or a strategy for realizing it, although—despite
the political crisis on the international Left that reached new depths
after the collapse of the Stalinist societies, which too few understood
were not only nonsocialist but antisocialist—there are activists within
them who are consciously anticapitalist. Although the weakness of
independent working-class organization creates distinct problems, the
growth and radicalization of the global justice movement presents an
important opportunity to renew anticapitalist politics internationally.
It is for this reason that it is especially worth debating Luxemburg’s
legacy today.
In my view, Luxemburg’s legacy today is a socialist political strategy that takes as its starting point struggles, however small, in which
working class and oppressed people assert their needs against employers, governments, and other establishments of domination. Building
such struggles in ways that foster democratic self-organization, solidarity, and militancy makes for movements that are more effective at
achieving tangible gains in the face of neoliberalism. Such movements
are also more likely to be transformative for their participants, allowing them to develop and enhance their abilities to understand and
change society. Such collective action can be conceptualized as conducive to building working-class capacities to act and think against
and beyond capitalism.10 This is the indispensable basis for politics
that are counterhegemonic, rather than just attacking the status quo,
however spectacularly. Such an approach is also necessary because of
the extent to which since the mid-1970s the working class in many
countries has been decomposed. While they have not ceased to exist,
many radical and militant working-class traditions have been seriously eroded, and workers’ mass organizations weakened (this has
included the strengthening of bureaucracy within them).
It is impossible to predict the future of the struggles and selforganization of the world’s workers (urban and rural), peasants,
and oppressed groups. Without doubt, we should not expect a cataclysmic “breakdown” of capitalism, as forecast in Luxemburg’s The
46
●
David Camfield
Accumulation of Capital,
l and we should not hope for one. Economic
crises are assured. However, this ought not to be seen as providing a
sure ground for radical politics, since economic crises guarantee only
intensified exploitation and suffering, not working-class advance and
a crisis of class rule. In the early twenty-first century, teleological predictions that capitalism will inevitably or even probably be surpassed
are intellectually unfounded and almost as unhelpful for a renewal
of emancipatory politics as the fatalistic certainty that has become
so widely accepted (whether with contentment or resignation) that
capitalism is the unsurpassable horizon of humanity. For this reason,
it seems to me that in the “post-Seattle” moment, we should fashion from the legacy of Luxemburg (and other liberatory thinkers and
activists) a renewed politics of socialism from below, which starts
from today’s struggles, refusing sectarianism and opportunism and
spurning both certainty and despair in order to make more likely the
future possibility of socialist democracy and the transcendence of the
alienated social forms of market and state power.
Notes
1. This Marxist approach is concisely and eloquently restated in Michael A.
Lebowitz, “Reclaiming a Socialist Vision,” Monthly Review
w (June 2001),
pp. 41–47.
2. Rosa Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution (London: Bookmarks, 1989), p. 75.
3. Norman Geras, The Legacy of Rosa Luxemburgg (London: Verso, 1983), p. 160.
4. Rosa Luxemburg, “The Russian Revolution,” in Mary-Alice Waters, ed.,
Rosa Luxemburg Speakss (New York: Pathfinder, 1970), pp. 393–94.
5. Ibid., p. 384. Whether this assessment was accurate is debatable.
6. Geras, Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg, p. 186. In my opinion, Geras’s analysis
that Luxemburg’s prison pamphlet missed the point that the closing of the
Constituent Assembly was “the liquidation of a bourgeois-democratic institution by and for a democracy of the masses” and that she in practice repudiated her earlier position by advocating in Germany a multiparty republic
of democratic workers’ councils to replace parliamentary institutions is
convincing.
7. “Rosa was never quick to change her mind. She was obstinate and had
considerable confidence in her own powers of analysis . . . Possibly the only
factual error to which she ever admitted was her support for a Constituent
Assembly in Russia at the beginning of 1918” (J. P. Nettl, Rosa Luxemburg
Vol. 2 [London: Oxford University Press, 1966], p. 718). According to Paul
A Second Reply to Stephen Eric Bronner
●
47
Frölich, “During the German Revolution Rosa Luxemburg completely
corrected her views on this point and rejected the slogan upheld by the
Independents [the Independent Social Democratic Party, commonly known
by its German initials, USPD—DC]: Workers’ Councils andd a Parliament”
(Paul Frölich, Rosa Luxemburg: Her Life and Workk [New York and London:
Monthly Review, 1972], pp. 246–47).
8. Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution, p. 41. Three notable relevant works on
the state are Mark Neocleous, Administering Civil Society: Towards a Theory
of State Powerr (London and New York: Macmillan and St. Martin’s, 1996);
Philip Corrigan and Derek Sayer, The Great Arch: English State Formation
as Cultural Revolution (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985); Werner Bonefeld
and John Holloway, eds., Global Capital, National State and the Politics of
Moneyy (New York: St. Martin’s, 1995). James C. Scott’s Seeing Like a State:
How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failedd (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998) contains much interesting material, although its theoretical framework is, in my view, weaker than that of
the above-mentioned books.
9. See the examples discussed in various articles in Socialist Register 2001:
Working Classes, Global Realitiess (London, Halifax, and New York: Merlin,
Fernwood and Monthly Review, 2000).
10. See Sam Gindin, “Socialism with Sober Senses: Developing Workers’
Capacities,” Socialist Register 1998
8 (Rendlesham, New York and Halifax:
Merlin, Monthly Review and Fernwood, 1997), pp. 75–101, although I
differ with Gindin’s specific suggestions for capacity building. Two recent
attempts to develop strategy informed by this kind of analysis are Kim
Moody, “The Rank and File Strategy: Building a Socialist Movement in
the U.S.” at www.solidarity-us.org and “Working-Class Politics in the
Canadian State 2000” at www.newsocialist.org/group.
CHAPTER 4
Rosa Redux: A Reply to David
Camfield and Alan Johnson
Stephen Eric Bronner
A
mong the assorted pleasures of writing for New Politicss is the
knowledge that so much of its audience actually reads the
articles and intellectually engages them. But I found it particularly flattering when I received two responses to “Red Dreams
and the New Millennium: Notes on the Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg,”
originally delivered as a speech to the Rosa Luxemburg Foundation in
Berlin, which appeared in the last issue. Admittedly, I was somewhat
startled that the first response by David Camfield was roughly the
same length as my short article while the second, by Alan Johnson,
was even longer. Both are clearly serious in their intentions, however,
and I would like to address their arguments in a sequential fashion.
They overlap at given points, which may make for a bit of redundancy
on my part, but proceeding in this way will allow me to deal better
with the points they make and the logic they employ. Noteworthy
about these replies is their political character, their lack of invective,
and the conviction with which they argue their theoretical perspectives. It’s safe to say that we all stand on the left side of the barricades.
But there are also some real disagreements along with some mistaken
interpretations of both my work and, in my opinion, issues pertaining
50
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
to the socialist tradition. This makes a somewhat lengthy political
response necessary. I hope the reader will bear with me.
*
*
*
Let me start with David Camfield. He begins by criticizing my claim
that socialism should no longer be conceived as a utopian “other”
to the status quo. In my view, however, such an assertion ultimately
leaves the Left with nothing more than an indeterminate critique
of the whole, which lacks both analytic power and popular appeal,
unless an agent for realizing this “other” can be determined from
within capitalism itself. This point of theory was shared by Marx and
Luxemburg. It enabled them to link reform and revolution, socialism
and democracy, and the growth of capitalism with the growth of its
“gravediggers.” The question is whether the same assumption holds
under contemporary capitalism and, if it doesn’t, what this implies for
contemporary politics.
David, if you will permit me to use your first name, you completely
ignore the type of ideological assumptions generated by the context
in which Luxemburg was writing. It only made sense for her to think
that the conquest of political power by the proletariat—or what
Lukács would term the “objective potential” for that conquest—was
inscribed within the workings of capitalism. Her belief was justified
not simply by the remarkable growth in the numbers of the industrial
proletariat,1 but by the even more remarkable growth of its socialist
parties—all ideologically subscribing to Marxism—virtually everywhere in Europe: German Social Democracy, for example, “polled
10.1% of the votes in the Reichstag elections (in 1887); in 1890,
19.7%; in 1893, 23.3%; in 1898, 27.2%; and in 1903, 31.7%.”2 This
continuing growth, in her mind, ultimatelyy guaranteed the democratic
character of the coming revolution. But things didn’t work out as
Luxemburg had planned. Somehow, David, I don’t think you would
any longer be willing to say with Wilhelm Liebknecht that “we can
see the (socialist) future appearing as present.”
Just this certitude, which was understood in scientificc terms, placed
Luxemburg on the side of Liebknecht, Karl Kautsky, and Georgi
Plekhanov in their attack upon revisionism. Without such certitude,
which her contemporary defenders like to deny, socialism becomes
Rosa Redux
●
51
nothing more than a contingent enterprise and, therefore, necessarily
based on ethical assumptions: this was precisely the position of Eduard
Bernstein. I fully admit that the socialist “other” can usefully serve as
a regulative ideall informing practical activity, but understanding the
“other” in this way involves the realization that it can never be fully
actualized. Simply hopingg or believingg in the eventual appearance of
the socialist “other” without “objective” justifications is another matter entirely. That has less to do with Marxism and Luxemburg than
with the construction of a religion and the prophecies of its priests.
The leading force within the Frankfurt School, Max Horkheimer,
was on the mark when he located the “longing for the totally other”
within the religious realm.
Rosa Luxemburg was, by contrast, a materialist. Her critique of
revisionism was indeed motivated by the fear that “economism” would
result in abandoning the “final goal” of abolishing capitalism. But,
first, she believed that realizing this aim was a reall possibility—not
simply an arbitrarily introduced utopia—and, second, that the abolition of capitalism would require a political revolution. We blithely
throw terms like revolution around all the time. But Luxemburg knew
what she wanted. And what she wanted was the same that everyone
else on the Left wanted, including Lenin and Trotsky, in 1898. The
“revisionism debate” in practical termss centered on whether to emphasize the establishment of a liberal bourgeoiss republic, which would
enable the working class to secure its aims, become the majority, and
act as a socialistt majority.
To misunderstand this is to misunderstand both the character of
the socialist movement and why it was able to rally all democratic
forces on the continent during what Leszek Kolakowski termed its
“golden age” from 1889 to 1914. The characterization is completely
appropriate: there was not another period like it. During this time,
under the banner of Marxism, the first democratic mass parties grew
into a genuine political force. These socialistt parties introduced a public sphere that we, today, can only envy. They raised the dignity of
working people, they provided the vision of the modern welfare state,
and they turned class consciousness into an international phenomenon. Never before or after would such a flurry of intelligent socialist literature appear on so many subjects with such tremendous mass
appeal. The “great betrayal” of 1914, when socialist parties supported
52
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
their respective governments in the First World War, presupposed
that there was something to betray.3
Perhaps I can use this occasion to challenge some cardinal points
of orthodoxy concerning 1917 and its aftermath. The great moment
was less the Bolshevik Revolution, which had already become an
intractable and bloody party dictatorship even before the suppression
of the Kronstadt Rebellion in 1921, than the establishment of republics with socialist majorities in so many nations of Europe where none
had existed before. It was with them that a useful political legacy was
created. It was with these republics that the process of democratic
education took its first faltering steps. And the Weimar Republic was
the most radical of them.4 Its base was a Social Democratic party
that, like its sister parties elsewhere in Europe, was the onlyy force on
the continent that retained an ongoing commitment to both political
liberty and economic justice in the interwar years. There is no straight
line that leads from 1914 to 1933 or 1945.5 Indeed, while it’s easy to
criticize the German Social Democratic Party (SPD) for its commitment to a “republic without republicans,” suggesting a viable alternative is somewhat more difficult.
With which movement or party in Germany would you, David,
have worked during the 1920s and early 1930s? Liberalism was disintegrating and Communism was becoming increasingly authoritarian
following the expulsion of Paul Levi in 1921. With the suppression of
the Spartacus Revolt, and the reactionary radicalization of the middle
strata and the peasantry, there was also not the least practicall glimmer of hope for introducing councils. Whatever its vacillations, and
timidity, Social Democracy was not the principal “cause” for the victory of fascism.6 It steadfastly resisted the totalitarianism of both Left
and Right in the name of republican democracy and it produced the
most radical welfare state of the time.7
By contrast, even today, what does the ultra-left have to offer? You
would probably answer, while making a perfunctory nod to the preferability of the liberal capitalist state over more authoritarian forms of
government,8 “socialist democracy.” But, David, just what is that? The
Paris Commune had already become anachronistic in the Western
nations when Lenin and Luxemburg began to take councils seriously
after the Revolution of 1905 in Russia. As for the revolts of 1919, they
were less about the creation of a “dictatorship of the proletariat” or
Rosa Redux
●
53
even purely decentralized councils (Raete),
) 9 than about a “republic of
councils” or a “socialist republic.”10 The dividing line between these
two ideas was fuzzy. But either of them would have differed from a
“bourgeois” republic only insofar as its partisans would have hazarded
the possibilities of civil war and/or invasion by the allies in the name
of purging the old judiciary and civil service, splitting up the Junker
estates in the North, and nationalizing some basic industries.11 These
were laudable goals at the time, and I like to think that I would have
supported them. But they do not exclude commitment to a republic
predicated on liberal principles and norms. Quite the contrary. The
“socialist republic” (republique democratique et social ) was understood
from the first, that is to say from the July Revolution of 1848,12 as an
extension rather than as an abolition of the principles underpinning
e introduced in February
the liberal republic (republique democratique)
of that same year. The historical experience of this failed revolution
ironically, or “dialectically,” led to the quite correct belief of the future
that democracy in the form of a liberal republic must serve as the precondition for socialism, and not the other way around.
Speaking frankly, David, I think your critique of liberal democracy
is deeply flawed. Not the institutional structures of liberal-democratic
states, but rather the elites within those states, erect barriers to addressing exploitation, oppression, and ecological destruction. The abuses
you mention testify to the existence of antiliberal elements within the
liberal state, but they do not impeach its principles or even the way in
which it should act. Liberal states allow for the expression of diverse
interests. Reactionary elites can win out and, for any number of structural reasons, they often do. But this says nothing more, again, than
that the achievement of socialist goals has no teleological or scientific
assurances. There is, of course, an alternative approach in dealing with
diverse interests. Squash them so that only the interests of “workers”
can be articulated. In turn, however, this will require an authoritarian
or totalitarian party standing above the rule of law. There is no reason
to believe that the workers’ council provides a different solution to this
problem or that it can dispense with the need for an independent judiciary or other bureaucratic institutions to safeguard the civil liberties
of conservative critics and opponents.
Rosa Luxemburg found herself torn between republics and councils
at the end of her life: she supported calling for a National Assembly in
54
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
Germany and yet, when her own motion insisting that the Spartacists
should participate in it was defeated, she chose to stand with the
masses when they rose in 1919. I have said on any number of occasions that the only justification for the Bolshevik liquidation of the
Constituent Assembly was the belief that more radical institutions,
namely soviets, would be instituted.13 That Luxemburg withdrew
her original criticism of the Bolsheviks for abolishing the Provisional
Assembly in Russia should, again, be seen in context. She was soon
to become president of the fledgling German Communist Party, she
wished to rally Western support for the Soviet Union, and she still
(mistakenly) believed that the soviets or councils had a role to play in
the homeland of the revolution. But you mention none of this. Thus,
you confuse her tactical response to a single historical event with a
point of principle that relates to her political theory.
What makes the political theory of Luxemburg salient for the presentt is not her retraction on the matter of the Constituent Assembly,
which is why I didn’t go into it in “Red Dreams,” but her insight that
terror always produces a dynamic that, once turned on, can’t be shut
off like a water faucet. Not in the section concerning the Constituent
Assembly of her pamphlet “The Russian Revolution,” but in the section titled “The Problem of Dictatorship,” would she write: “But with
the repression of political life in the land as a whole, life in the soviets
must also become more and more crippled. Without general elections,
the free struggle of opinion, life dies out in every public institution,
becomes a mere semblance of life in which only the bureaucracy
remains as the active element.”14
Doesn’t this highlight the dynamic of repression? General elections
and the free struggle of opinion, which naturally involves freedom of
speech and assembly, are furthermore liberal “bourgeois” values. And,
if that is not enough, her notion that “freedom is only and exclusively
freedom for the one who thinks differently,” crystallizes the equally
“bourgeois” idea—underpinning the liberal rule of law—that the
freedom of the individual cannot be arbitrarily subordinated to the
whims of the state or the exigencies of any institution. In this regard,
from its inception, the European labor movement chose to shoulder
what I have called a dual burden:15 the commitment to liberal republican principles, which apply universally to all, and the particular class
commitment to economic justice. Given the political weakness of the
Rosa Redux
●
55
bourgeoisie, in Germany and in most nations on the continent, it
had little choice. Most socialist parties were initially forced to operate
under monarchical regimes and it is no accident that revolutionary
radicalism was always weakest where “bourgeois” democratic institutions and norms were strongest.
You say, David, that you are concerned with addressing “exploitation, oppression, alienation and ecological destruction.” You mention
community-based workers’ organizations and speak about anticapitalist politics. But you don’t seem to draw any implications from your
own admission that they have not articulated an alternative either
in terms of the economy or more importantly, for our purposes, the
liberal state. You say that you wish to limit the power of the market.
But how do you intend to do this without legislation? I completely
agree with you that mass mobilization from below, arguably even
against the organizational interests of reformist parties, serves as
a precondition for the introduction of radical reforms. And I also
agree that your community-based organizations may be particularly
transformative for their participants. Neither in their demands nor
in their style, however, have these “mass struggles” or communitybased worker organizations rendered the pursuit of legislative redress
irrelevant or evidenced anything “other” than an ethicall and reformist
commitment to change. None of them to my knowledge either connects revolutionaryy theory with revolutionaryy practice or deals with
existing problems in terms that make “bourgeois” democracy seem
anachronistic. Your “other” hovers in the air without a foot in reality. It exists outside the famous “unity between theory and practice”
that Marxism promised to provide. If you are content with that, well,
fine. But I am not.
*
*
*
With this last point in mind, perhaps I can now turn to the criticisms
of my friend Alan Johnson. I have always admired him as a writer, as a
colleague on the editorial board of New Politicss, and as an editor of the
journal Historical Materialism. Alan’s reply to my article raises some
important questions. It is also informed by passion and a profound
political commitment. But that very passion and political commitment have, I think, led to some very strange conclusions about my
56
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
method and some fundamentally mistaken assumptions about my
politics and values.
“Ransacking the legacy?” Alan, please! I didn’t arbitrarily chastise
Luxemburg for this or that fault, and I didn’t treat her legacy as a
smorgasbord. I tried to do to her precisely what Marx did to Hegel:
that is to say provide an immanent critique of her understanding of
economic development, political democracy, and internationalism.
I engaged these core conceptss of her work in order to develop a perspective more appropriate to the present. You may think, of course,
that the commitment to immanent critique is a “banality.” But, if
this is really what you believe, then how would you philosophically
prevent any self-styled historical method from petrifying into a frozen transhistorical system? From your piece, in fact, I still don’t even
know whether you wish to retain the teleological moment of Marx
or not. It doesn’t help to speak vaguely about the need for a “creative
confrontation with the present” unless you suggest how it should be
methodologically undertaken.
Raymond Williams was a fine literary critic, in my opinion, but
a very weak philosopher. And that is especially the case given the
way you use him to justify the search for an “authentic Marxism”
or, even more abstractly, “an authentic Marxist Marx.” I will come
back to this. But I can tell you now that, from my perspective, thinking of this sort creates a barrier to progress. Fleetingly you praise
Korsch and Lukács, which is fine, but somewhat odd, since the roots
of my general approach derive from them, along with various classical socialist thinkers including Luxemburg,16 and certain members of
the Frankfurt School. What inspires me about Lukács and Korsch,
however, is precisely their ruthless application of the critical method,
or what is usually termed immanent critique, and their unrelenting
emphasis upon historical context.17 There is no fixed goal, there is
no institutional form, there is no particular claim, there is nothing
that escapes criticism. Thus, Lukács threw down the gauntlet in the
famous opening passage to History and Class Consciousness:
Let us assume for the sake of argument that recent research had disproved once and for all every one of Marx’s individual theses. Even
if this were to be proved, every serious orthodox Marxist would
still be able to accept all such modern findings without reservation
Rosa Redux
●
57
and hence dismiss all of Marx’s theses in toto —without having to
renounce his orthodoxy for a single moment. Orthodox Marxism,
therefore, does not imply the uncritical acceptance of the results
of Marx’s investigations. It is not the “belief” in this or that thesis,
nor the exegesis of a “sacred” book. On the contrary, orthodoxy
refers exclusively to methodd.18
Passages such as this help explain why the “revisionism” of Lukács
and Korsch should have been condemned at the Fifth Congress of the
Comintern in 1924. Identifying orthodoxy with the critical method,
of course, winds up ultimately destroying any form of orthodoxy.
There is no place in Lukács and Korsch in particular, or critical theory in general, for “legitimating theory” let alone—given their assault
on reification and instrumental rationality—attempts to “balance” it
with “operative” theory. The method of Lukács and Korsch inherently
opposes the invocation of terms like “authentic” Marxism let alone an
“authentic Marxist Marx.” No less than with Luxemburg, I applied
the same form of immanent criticism to them, and my other favorite
thinkers, that they applied to the icons of the past and the contemporaries of their time.19 This indeed is in the spirit of their enterprise.
Lukács, Korsch, and the partisans of critical theory recognized
that innovation is impossible when anyy calculation is undertaken with
regard to how different interpretations of the tradition in different historical situations correspond to some abstract notion of “authentic”—
a term that, by the way, has religious origins and was made famous by
Kierkegaard and later the existentialists20 —or “pure” Marxism. It is
not simply that Marxism has “to be retrieved from layers of Stalinist
filth”—who speaks this way any longer?—but, more importantly, of
confronting the fundamental miscalculations and mistakes of Marx
and other classical authors. Unless, of course, theyy are considered sacrosanct. But I have never had much use for holy scripture. Korsch
knew what he was talking about in his classic work of 1923, Marxism
and Philosophy, when he called for the rigorous “application of the
materialist conception of history to the materialist conception of history itself.”21
But, Alan, there is more: How you get from your defense of an
authentic Marxism to the heresy of Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe
baffles me. To suggest that my approach has anything to do with theirs,
58
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
moreover, is really quite bizarre. I haven’t written anything about their
Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. Any of my graduate students will tell
you,22 however, that I am sharply critical of their naive valorization of
social movements, their antiorganizational stance, their communitarian impulse, and their postmodern interpretation of Gramsci—whose
ideas, including that of hegemony, also never had any significant impact
on my thinking. As for “radical democracy,” Alan, you should know
that I am one of the very few leftists who has offered an explicit critique
of “democratic theory.”23
A particular problem with “radical democracy” lies in its romantic roots: its earliest modern exponent was Rousseau. But there is
also a romantic streak running through Marxism, which concerns
me as much as any “economic necessitarianism.” I use it as a point
of departure in dealing with Luxemburg. Alan seems to believe that
his quotation from Norman Geras undermines my claims concerning her “revolutionary romanticism.” I believe it justifies my contention. The quote gives no hint about the importance of identifying
the structural constraints in which revolutionary action takes place.
There is no trace of organizational analysis in any meaningful sense
of the term. Nothing is said about what institutional arrangements
should be implemented when “the masses” become exhausted and
leave the battlefield. Potential conflicts of interest between those
classes comprising “the masses” are ignored. Then, too, there is no
sense of what proved to be the disastrous costs of introducing the
mass strike into the very different context of Germany or, putting it
w one should “pose the question of power there
another way, just how
in a serious way.”
Luxemburg got clobbered on the question of the mass strike and,
in her stubborn insistence upon turning it into an “offensive” weapon,
she helped split the German Left, diminish her own influence within
the party, and pave the way not for Eduard Bernstein, but for the
triumph of those genuinely right-wing nationalist, imperialist, careerist bureaucrats like Friedrich Ebert, who would lead the SPD into its
“great betrayal.” The quotation from Geras provides nothing more
than a defense of revolutionary will and voluntarism. It is as pure an
example of political romanticism as one might find. If Luxemburg
unified a theory of the bourgeois state, the character of proletarian
democracy, and a viable socialist strategy—which I doubt she ever
Rosa Redux
●
59
did successfully—historical reality sundered the connection between
them long before I picked up a pen.
As for the discussion about teleology, well, perhaps we disagree
about the meaning of the word. It need not imply the victory of socialism, although I believe it did for Luxemburg, but any resultt inscribed
within a developmental process. The ultimate breakdown of capitalism
is a case in point. Now, with regard to that breakdown, let’s cut to the
chase: Does the development of capitalism generate its “gravediggers”
or not? If not then socialism becomes a contingent enterprise or, putting it in the terms of the time, a purely “ethical” demand or project.
Putting forward the abstract choice between socialism and barbarism,
Alan, does not clinch your case. Quite the opposite. Every Marxist of
the time knew socialism would ultimatelyy prove victorious,24 which
enabled the choicee to fit neatly into the teleological framework.
Luxemburg was not alone in pointing to the alternative between
socialism or barbarism. It was raised every time a major crisis occurred
and essentially ignored with respect to the final outcome of history.
None of these crises presaged the end of capitalism. By viewing the
choice in this way, however, orthodox Marxists could demand vigilance and commitment and yet retain the certainties of teleology.
But there is a larger question. Is framing the choice in this way relevant any longer? History has shown that there are other alternatives
between “socialism” and “barbarism” in any given moment of crisis.
If “the collapse of capitalism is guaranteed, the victory of socialism is
not,” moreover, the struggle for socialism again becomes contingent
in character and “ethical” in form since its future success lacks any
objective foundation. I don’t think Luxemburg would have liked your
interpretation.
Also moving from the claim, which Luxemburg indisputably made,
that state terror retains its own dynamic to the claim that—therefore—
I believe in the existence of a “simple continuity between Lenin and
Stalin and between the revolution and the counter-revolution” not only
evinces false causality, but attributes to me a position that I don’t hold.
There was no reason for me to develop an argument on Communism
in my talk, since it was about Luxemburg, but the fact is that I wrote a
very long chapter dealing with the connection between Lenin and his
successors that completely contradicts Alan’s assertion. Check it out.25
I have always been anti-Leninist in orientation but, in good dialectical
60
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
fashion, I have also always maintained that the connections between
Lenin and Stalin are marked by continuity and discontinuity on a
number of issues. While all Leninist states have been authoritarian
and repressive, I argue, Leninism does not inevitablyy lead to totalitarianism. But your cheerleading is woefully out of place. Leninism is
as dead as a doornail everywhere other than among the sects that are
reminiscent of antagonistic amoeba fighting each other to death in a
drop of water. The “theoretical conquests” of the anti-Leninist and
anti-Stalinist tradition were made less by ultra-left Bolsheviks than by
the partisans of Social Democracy and critical theory.
With respect to nationalism, again, your critique is misdirected.
I wrote in Socialism Unboundd that Lenin was never a simple nationalist or a proponent of ethnic identity, and that his idea of national selfdetermination was tied to an internationalist vision. But, whatever
one may think of it, his theory assumedd the existence of a Communist
party and an international organization that would serve as a corrective, or a break, on nationalist enthusiasms and channel them into
socialist internationalism. To believe that nationalism will somehow
turn into internationalism withoutt such an organization is a perfect
example of the pseudo-dialectical two-step.
Ideology, Max Weber noted in “Politics as a Vocation,” is not like
a taxi-ride that can be halted at any corner. Uncritically supporting
national self-determination without insisting upon liberal republican
commitments has only resulted in more extreme expressions of both
nationalism and authoritarianism. That is why I think that, while
Luxemburg was perhaps politically less acute on the subject in her
own time, she was ultimately much more prophetic than Lenin on the
subject of nationalism. She understood that nationalism had its integrity, a logic and a dynamic of its own, and that it could not simply be
manipulated by organizational whims. You want me to take Lenin at
his word on the revolution. Why should I? Whenever a Communist
party has identified socialism with industrialization, which is all that
it can do when the revolution takes place in an economically underdeveloped nation, the result in practice, if not in theory, has been either
authoritarianism like in Cuba or totalitarianism like in China. Should
I have faithh that it can be otherwise? You certainly don’t justify your
belief by providing much history beyond 1917–23. And that’s a long
time ago.
Rosa Redux
●
61
Don’t take this the wrong way: I appreciate your kind words about
Luxemburg and the Constituent Assembly. They serve as a useful
corrective to David’s view of my position. But I’m afraid that you
don’t draw the appropriate conclusions. Criticisms of Communist
“mistakes” undertaken in the name of soviets, which never ruled the
Soviet Union in the first place or had a realistic possibility of doing
so, may produce interesting information, but in theoretical terms it
is yet another indulgence in revolutionary romanticism. How about
instead looking at the institutions introduced by Lenin, the mechanistic transformation of his theory of revolution into a theory of rule,
his inability to imagine the constraints imposed by economic underdevelopment, his substitution of not simply the party for the class,
but his identification of the party with the state, and his willingness
to unleash a dynamic of terror that began with other parties, extended
to other institutions like trade unions, impacted upon anarchists and
socialists of good will, and ultimately wound up destroying every
critical “faction” within the party itself?
You write that the “institutional shape of the socialist polity is a
radically underdeveloped area of Marxist theory.” No kidding! But
then why not start dealing seriously with the problem by looking back
to the vagaries of Marx and the sophistries of Lenin? The separation of powers endorsed by Kautsky, whose commitment to republican principles was unflinching,26 by the way, is not exactly what you
might call an intellectual breakthrough. It was already a mainstay of
liberal republicanism and there is nothing in Kautsky to suggest that
councils, which seek to overcome alienation by unifying the disparate
functions of competing bureaucratic institutions, can better institutionally serve either the cause of economic justice or the defense of
civil liberties than a republic.
You ask how I can dismiss the soviets when soviet rule has nowhere
been tried. My answer is simple: because that’s exactly what the
Christians still say about Christianity. Its best and most radical offshoots, now lost in the mists of history, actually had more staying
power than the councils. I have already suggested, incidentally, not
that the liberal republic is the realization of Luxemburg’s vision, but
that at the end of her life she was torn between the republic and the
councils. You don’t mention any new ideas for resolving the tensions
between them? I think I know why. Hardly a single serious theoretical
62
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
development regarding the council has occurred since the 1920s.
Indeed, with this in mind, the belief that I am closing down the
debate over republics and councils is ludicrous.
My work endorses experiments with “secondary” or “associative”
organizations that might provide a more direct form of democracy,
and I have even suggested that the council can be integrated into
the liberal republican state.27 But this is different from maintaining
that the council can supplant the modern republican state. Embracing
such a stance requires turning your back on political reality. That
soviets have appeared for a few days or months whenever the masses
have been in a revolutionary mood, does not exactly inspire me with
confidence. It’s also time to squelch that myth propagated by Hannah
Arendt about soviets arising in everyy revolution—unless you identify
revolution only with those you like. There were no soviets in India,
or in Algeria, or in Cuba, or in the majority of other revolutions that
shook the non-Western world.
Without even a thought for any of this, however, you claim that the
“liberal republican state exists nowhere.” But, if I recall correctly, the
last great revolutions—of 1989—were undertaken not in the name
of some fuzzy notion of democracy. They were instead undertaken
in the name of liberal constitutional rule. I could, of course, be mistaken. In any event, let me ask you: Is there anywheree any mass-based
political organization that is seriously talking about a revolution or the
move from a liberal republic to a “democratic” republic? Where on the
planet, right now, is the question of councils or socialistt revolution on
the agenda? Tell me, as someone who believes in a Marxist “science,”
why I should trust your speculations on the subject without looking at
reality? Should I—yet again—have faithh that it can be otherwise?
Alan, from what I can see, your entire argument relies on faith —in
councils, in revolution, in national self-determination, in socialism—
that you dress up as “science.” In doing so, however, you misconstrue
the purpose behind establishing Marxism as a science in the first place.
Of course, it was “positivistic”! The idea was to provide the claims and
predictions of Marx with an objectivity akin to the “natural sciences,”
which are always to some degree “positivistic,” and thereby differentiate his new materialism from all forms of metaphysics. Sidney
Hook—who attended Korsch’s lectures and used them for Towards
the Understanding of Karl Marx 28 —employs a rearguard action in his
Rosa Redux
●
63
use of “science.” He understands Marxian science in Hegelian terms:
as a “science of consciousness.”29
But such a stance undermines the very attack on metaphysics that
“science” was supposed to provide since the times of Bacon and Kant.
Unless a distinction is drawn between social theory and the natural
sciences, which was the intent of Western Marxism and critical theory
from the beginning, the door opens for some new version of the “dialectics of wheat.” Once the basic questions of methodology involving
evidence and falsifiability arise, moreover, partisans of the “new science” usually have little to say. This is not the place for yet another
discussion of how the attempt to create a “new science” degenerates
into cosmology.30 There is perhaps a way in which the Hegelian
understanding of science might influence a “theory of liberation.”
Nevertheless, this is not as easy as you make it sound.
If the use of “liberation” is not to result in yet another “banality,”
then it must be infused with a bit more imagination than is exhibited
here. A “theory of liberation” requires more than the incorporation
of “economic necessity” with “revolutionary will.” Leaving aside the
dualism, which incidentally can only be overcome if you privilege
one or the other,31 such a theory must insist upon transforming each
objective moment of the “totality” and the subjective experiencee of
that totality as well. This will necessarily involve introducing psychology to analyze the dynamics of the family, theories of symbolic
interaction to understand everyday life, existentialism to provide
categories for explaining the experience of reality, and an articulated
utopia—that goes far beyond platitudes about “participation” and the
vision of an endless political meeting—in order to inform the project.
But that is only the beginning. What will happen to your “authentic”
Marxism—and your “authentic Marxist Marx”—when your theory
finds itself being forced to integrate insights from Freud, Husserl,
Heidegger, and a host of thinkers with very non-Marxist methodologies, but who have actually dealt with problems that can, at best, only
be teased from the work of the master?
I believe we must become a bit more modest with regard to both
Marxism and socialism. My critique of the old theory is really quite
simple: I believe that the political moment must take priority over
the economic moment of analysis, that the contingency of outcomes
must be emphasized over any kind of “scientific” assurances, that
64
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
the ethical commitment to socialism must supplant any teleological understanding of its development. This philosophical position
is, I think, warranted by historical reality. How it stands in accordance with orthodoxy, or whatever Alan understands by “authentic”
Marxism, is irrelevant to me. By the same token: remembering the
reall achievements of the labor movement, the fight for time, and for
the dignity of working people, gives socialistt theory a hook in reality.
It places modern socialists in an antitotalitarian tradition of radical
reformism. It forces young people both to recognize structural constraints and the kind of struggle that was required to introduce what
is so often derided as mere “legislation.” It creates the possibility for
reconnecting theory with practice. And—most important—it raises a
meaningful hope for socialist politics.
“Socialism has never seemed more like the otherr to me” sounds,
by contrast, like a ringing endorsement of resignation and bitterness
inspired by the failure of history and the labor movement to fulfill an
inherently unrealizable desire. It seems, Alan, that the world has not
measured up to your expectations. I understand your despair. Franz
Biberkopf felt the same way in the great novel Berlin Alexanderplatz,
by Alfred Doblin. This character found himself condemned to hell
and, upon finally meeting the Devil, he asked why he was there. The
Devil had a great answer: “Because you believed that reality was created for you.”
* *
*
Much in this debate has taken us far afield from the basic points
of what was originally a short speech with modest intentions. My
concern was with suggesting that the institutional analysis associated
with Marxism is woefully inadequate and that it is now less a question
of whether to privilege reform or revolution than whether to privilege
the commitment to social democratic reform or the neoliberal retreat
from it. I sought to reinvigorate internationalism, rather than consider
it as some sort of vague slogan or abstraction, by making reference to
the only real international organizations that exist. In the same vein,
I wished to provide a practical referent for socialism rather than leave
it hanging as an “other” without concrete articulation or an agent to
realize it. This does not mean that I have abandoned socialism, only
Rosa Redux
●
65
that I understand it in different terms. I don’t identify socialism with
any particular institutional form, including councils, and I view its
purpose today less as the pursuit of some utopian “other” than as
the ongoing creation of economic and political conditions in which
working people can expand the range of their knowledge, their experiences, and their private as well as their public pursuits. My position
is in accord with the intention of “The Right to Be Lazy” by Marx’s
son-in-law, Paul Lafargue, and the suggestion by my former teacher
Henry Pachter,32 who was himself a student of Korsch, that socialism should be understood as “the highest stage of individualism—its
realization for all.”
There is no “final goal,” in my opinion, only the asymptotic attempt
to further freedom. And socialism has a role in that. But this requires
a concretee understanding of its contribution. Over the last 20 years I
learned we need a notion of socialism that is associated with what has
been concretelyy achieved in the fight against capitalism and that retains
a concretee sense of its original democratic impulse. This concretee sense,
I believe, comes from identifying socialism with mitigating the whip
of the market, embracing those movements and programs that helped
foster that goal, and furthering democracy according to the most radical tenets of liberal republicanism. There is nothing in my thinking
to suggest that unqualified support should be given to the United
Nations or any other institution, only that the new transnational
organizations will provide the arenas in which future struggles will be
fought. That tensions—even unresolvable tensions—exist between
the liberal republican state and the imperatives of global capitalism
does not constitute a serious criticism. Tensions will always arise
between global and domestic imperatives regarding both economics
and politics. There is no reason to believe that the introduction of
workers’ councils will resolve them. Isn’t it time to stop looking at the
future through a cracked lens inherited from the past?
Alan and David both labor under the same misapprehension. My
point was not to interpret Luxemburg, as David put it trenchantly, by
transforming her legacy into the thought of Eduard Bernstein. I hate
to break it to you both, but my philosophical stance is not his.33 Just
as there is more than one theory of revolution, there is more than one
theory of reform. My view highlights the class ideall as a basic organizing tool of socialistt politics: classical revisionism seeks the liquidation
66
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
of class identity in the name of a national party (Volkspartei) and
trumpets the need for a “partnership” with other classes. My view
underscores internationalism in theory and practice: classical revisionism basically presupposes a national form of political action. My
view privileges the primacy of the political in fostering economic
change: classical revisionism suggests that only with a “small minority” is it possible to consider noneconomic demands. My view calls
for intensifying a “creative friction” between the organization and its
clientele; classical revisionism is technocratic in its orientation. My
view accepts the need for revolution, though as a tactic rather than
the strategic goal, when working people are incapable of having their
most basic grievances addressed or their democratic rights recognized:
classical revisionism does not. My view emphasizes the dangers of an
“ideology of compromise”: classical revisionism generates a position
in which compromise is an end unto itself. My view worries over the
degeneration of the reformist impulse: classical revisionism retained
an unwavering belief in “evolutionary socialism.” In all these ways,
I consider myself informed less by the spirit of Eduard Bernstein than
by the spirit of Rosa Luxemburg.
The lesson of historical materialism is that it must be used in a historical way with respect to both means and ends: it must deal with the
situation as it exists. I never said that the working class was shrinking
worldwide or that poverty was being eradicated in global terms; I have
even said it’s quite possible that many of Marx’s economic predictions may turn out to be true. But I maintain that there is no longer
any necessary translation of this economic development into political
powerr and that, in turn, the power of capital still rests on the degree
of organizationall and ideologicall disunity among workers. If the two of
you think that defrosting an institutional vision from the last century
is the way to build this organizational and ideological unity, or that
we can begin with the old assumption that “workers have nothing to
lose but their chains” . . . well . . . good luck.
Keep defining “socialism” as you want without reference to the
broader history of the labor movement. Keep maintaining that there
is no connection between Leninism and Stalinism. Keep your anachronistic notions of national self-determination and workers’ councils.
Keep your irrelevant view of “science.” Keep your insular beliefs. But
then, when you glance at the world, perhaps you will consider: Is
Rosa Redux
●
67
everything simply “false consciousness?” Was everyone an idiot except
your “tiny minority,” who still knows everything better, but to whom
no one ever listens? Perhaps you will begin to think about why?
A great work of literature could provide a clue. I enjoyed how Alan
used Charles Dickens to satirize me and now, in closing, perhaps I
can be permitted to offer something equally satirical of you both from
A Tale of Two Cities. I trust each of you knows the passage and I also
trust that each of you will get the point:
The leprosy of unreality disfigured every human creature in attendance upon Monseigneur. In the outermost room were half a
dozen exceptional people who had had, for a few years, some vague
misgiving in them that things in general were going rather wrong.
As a promising way of setting them right, half of the half-dozen
had become members of a fantastic sect of Convulsionists, and
were even then considering within themselves whether they should
foam, rage, roar, and turn cataleptic on the spot—thereby setting
up a highly intelligible finger-post to the Future, for Monseigneur’s
guidance. Besides these Dervishes, were other three who had rushed
into another sect, which mended matters with a jargon about “the
Centre of Truth”: holding that Man had got out of the Centre of
Truth—which did not need much demonstration—but had not
got out of the Circumference and that he was to be kept from flying out of the Circumference, and was even to be shoved back into
the Centre, by fasting and seeing of spirits. Among these, accordingly, much discoursing with spirits went on—and it did a world
of good which never became manifest.34
Notes
1. Marx fused three different moments in his conception of class: the empirical (which meant the industrial proletariat), the structural (those who sell
their labor power), and the normative or political (class consciousness).
I believe these three moments have fallen asunder, and that it is the normative, or ethical element, that needs to be pushed into the foreground. For a
more encompassing analysis, see Stephen Eric Bronner, Socialism Unboundd,
2nd Edition (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2001), 11ff.
2. Carl E. Schorske, German Social Democracy, 1905–19177 (New York:
Harper & Row, 1955), p. 7.
68
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
3. The decision of Social Democracy to support the war must be understood,
not excused, but understood in terms of what are today a set of forgotten constraints. Note the chapter titled, “In the Cradle of Modernity:
The Labor Movement and the First World War” in Stephen Eric Bronner,
Moments of Decision: Political History and the Crises of Radicalism (New
York: Routledge, 1992), p. 13ff.
4. “The legend of Weimar’s intelligentsia has grown like ivy over the fallen
pillars of the Weimar state. But that state—which today is still the object
of historiographical opprobrium—may one day share the fate of its worldrenowned citizens; posterity may revise the judgment of those contemporaries who attribute all the glory of Weimar to its adversaries and all the
infamy to the Republic.” Henry Pachter, “The Intellectuals and the State of
Weimar” in Weimar Etudess ( New York: Columbia University Press, 1982),
p. 109.
5. The old stalwarts of German Social Democracy were not in control of the
party when its members chose to support their nation in the First World
War, and they were not even in the party when Friedrich Ebert and Gustav
Noske (also known as the bloodhound) conspired with reactionary forces in
the suppression of the Spartacus Revolt. Bernstein, Eisner, Haase, Kautsky,
and most of their comrades had broken off in 1917 to form the Independent
Social Democratic Party of Germany (USPD) over opposition to the war
and the role of councils. The SPD and the USPD only reunited in 1922
when the councilist movement had clearly been defeated. See the classic
study by David W. Morgan, The Socialist Left and the German Revolution:
A History of the Independent Social Democratic Party, 1917–222 (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1975).
6. See the chapter, “Working Class Politics and the Nazi Triumph” in Bronner,
Moments of Decision, p. 33ff.
7. Note the illuminating studies by Gerd-Rainer Horn, European Socialists
Respond to Fascism: Ideology, Activism and Contingency in the 1930ss (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1996), and William David Jones, The Lost Debate:
German Socialist Intellectuals and Totalitarianism (Urbana: University of
Illinois Press, 1999).
8. It was precisely this kind of resigned and cynical lack of conviction in the
value of republican institutions so prominent among the “liberal” intelligentsia of Weimar Germany, popularly known as Vernunftrepublikaner,
r which
reinforced the “unpolitical” values of the German bourgeoisie and simultaneously helped undermine loyalty to the regime and its republican principles. On the background, see Fritz Stern, “The Political Consequences of
the Unpolitical German” in The Failure of Illiberalism: Essays on the Political
Culture of Modern Germanyy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971),
pp. 3–25.
Rosa Redux
●
69
9. Ironically, with reference to the claims of David Camfield, the principal supporter of the council movement was the USPD, whose members
included the original mainstays of the social democratic movement. See the
excellent analysis of the council movement by Henry Pachter, “Was Weimar
Necessary? The Raetee Movement, 1918–21, and the Theory of Revolution”
in Weimar Etudess, p. 285ff.
10. Sebastian Haffner, Failure of a Revolution: Germany 1918–1919,
9 trans.
George Rapp (Chicago: Banner Press, 1986), pp. 51ff and 106ff.
11. Arthur Rosenberg, Geschichte der Weimarer Republikk (Frankfurt: Europaiesche
Verlagsanstalt, 1961), p. 5ff.
12. Karl Marx, “The Class Struggles in France, 1848–1850,” in Karl Marx and
Frederick Engels, Selected Workss 3 vols. (Moscow: International Publishers,
1969), 1:186ff.
13. Bronner, Socialism Unbound, p. 139ff.
14. Rosa Luxemburg, “The Russian Revolution,” in Mary-Alice Waters, ed.
Rosa Luxemburg Speakss (Pathfinder: New York, 1970), p. 391.
15. Bronner, Socialism Unboundd, p. 2ff.
16. Forgotten is my original claim, to which I still subscribe, that Luxemburg
provided the basic impulse for the Western Marxism wherefrom critical theory emerged. See the first printing of Stephen Eric Bronner, Rosa
Luxemburg: A Revolutionary for Our Timess (London: Pluto Press, 1981),
p. 96ff.
17. With respect to the revisionism debate, for example, they were clear about
the ways in which the defenders of orthodoxy—including Luxemburg—
missed what was really at stake. Thus, Korsch could write: “Rosa
Luxemburg did not direct her critical counterattack against the Social
Democratic practice, but against Bernstein’s theory, which was nothing
more than a truthful expression of the actual character of that practice.”
Douglas Kellner was completely accurate in claiming Korsch understood
this misdirected approach as contributing to the “crisis of Marxism.” See
Karl Korsch, Revolutionary Theoryy, ed. Douglas Kellner (Austin: University
of Texas Press, 1977), pp. 179–80 passim; in a similar vein, see, Georg
Luk ács, “Bernstein’s Triumph: Notes on the Essays Written in Honour
of Karl Kautsky’s Seventieth Birthday” in Political Writings, 1919–29,
9 ed.
Rodney Livingstone and trans. Michael McColgan (London: New Left
Books, 1972), p. 127ff.
18. Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics,
s
trans. Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1972), p. 1.
19. Stephen Eric Bronner, Of Critical Theory and Its Theoristss (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1994), pp. 12–62 passim.
20. The concern with authenticity is implicitly developed by St. Augustine
while the term itself derives from Angelus Silesius, who wished to know
70
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
whether any given “revelation” from God could be trusted. Sound familiar?
I happen to know this piece of trivia because my dissertation dealt with
precisely this concept. Stephen Eric Bronner, Authenticity and Potentiality:
A Marxian Inquiry into the Role of the Subjectt (PhD Dissertation, Berkeley:
University of California, 1975).
Karl Korsch, Marxism and Philosophyy, trans. Fred Halliday (London: New
Left Books, 1970), p. 92.
My emphasis upon a class ideal, which is articulated in most of my books,
can be seen as a response to Laclau and Mouffe. The concept clearly influenced the fine work by my former doctoral student Christine A. Kelly,
Tangled Up in Red, White and Blue: New Social Movements in America
(Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001).
See the chapter entitled “The Dilemmas of Democratic Theory” in Stephen
Eric Bronner, Ideas in Action: Political Tradition in the Twentieth Century
(Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999), pp. 17–25 passim.
The classic work on this question has, unfortunately, still not been translated into English. See Max Adler, Kausalitaet und Teleologie im Streit um
die Wissenschaftt in Marx-Studien vol. 1 (Vienna, 1904).
Note the chapter “Leninism and Beyond” in Bronner, Socialism Unboundd,
pp. 77–121.
See the chapter “Karl Kautsky: The Rise and Fall of Orthodox Marxism” in
ibid., pp. 33–53.
Note the section “The Battle for Democracy” in Bronner, Ideas in Action,
p. 306ff.
Sidney Hook “did not know enough German to understand everything. He sat next to me in a private course which Korsch gave in 1930.
I believe on his return to the United States, Hook published a reasonable
account of Korsch’s views on Marxism.” The book in question is Towards
the Understanding of Karl Marx. See the chapter titled “Autobiographical
Fragments” in Pachter, Weimar Etudes, p. 39.
The inspiration derived from Lukács and Korsch who directly criticized the
attempt to extend the dialectical method to nature. The former approvingly
noted the comment of Vico that the difference between history and nature
results from the fact that human beings have made the one, but not the other.
Luk ács, History and Class Consciousness,
s pp. 112 and 24; also see the pamphlet by Karl Korsch, Kernpunkte der materialischen Geschichtsauffassung:
Eine quellenmaessige Darstellungg (Hamburg, 1973 ed.).
Note my debate with Loren Goldner, “The Enlightenment: An Exchange,”
New Politicss Vol. 6 No. 1 (Summer 1996), p. 137ff.
Luk ács attempted to deal with the problem when, in the chapter titled “The
Changing Function of Historical Materialism,” he wrote: “For the proletariat fought capitalism by forcing bourgeois society into a self-knowledge
which would inevitably make that society appear problematic to itself.
Rosa Redux
●
71
Parallel with the economic struggle is a battle fought for the consciousness of
society. Now, to become conscious is synonymous with the possibility of taking over the leadership of society.” Luk ács, History and Class Consciousness,
s
p. 228.
32. See the wonderful essay “The Right to Be Lazy” in Socialism in History:
Political Essays of Henry Pachter,
r ed. Stephen Eric Bronner (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1984), p. 3ff.
33. Note the chapter “Eduard Bernstein and the Logic of Revisionism” in
Bronner, Socialism Unboundd, p. 55ff.
34. Charles Dickens, A Tale of Two Citiess (Grosset & Dunlap: New York, 1948),
p. 133.
CHAPTER 5
Why Should We Care What Rosa
Luxemburg Thought?
Paul Le Blanc
R
osa Luxemburg—passionate tribune of socialism, penetrating
Marxist theorist, and educator whose luminous prose has
inspired millions, revolutionary activist martyr. What are we
to make of her now?
In The Marxistss, C. Wright Mills wrote that Luxemburg “occupied a peculiar, and powerless, position between the Second and the
Third Internationals.” Because she was “passionately for democracy
and for freedom in all of the decisive meanings of those terms,” Mills
explains, and because this was fused “in her belief in the revolutionary spontaneity of the proletarian masses,” she should be seen as
having one foot in the Socialist International, the other foot in the
Communist International, “and her head, I am afraid, in the cloudier,
more utopian reaches of classic Marxism.” If someone was so disconnected from the hard realities of her own time, why should one care
what she might have thought about the complexities of ours?
Hannah Arendt’s marvelous essay on Rosa tells us that Luxemburg
has been so important to so many because she after her death she
became “a symbol of nostalgia for the good old times of the movement, when hopes were green, the revolution around the corner,
and, most important, the faith in the capacities of the masses and
74
●
Paul Le Blanc
in the moral integrity of the Socialist or Communist leadership was
still intact.” Arendt adds that “it speaks not only for the person of
Rosa Luxemburg, but also for the qualities of the older generation of
the left, that the legend—vague, confused, inaccurate in nearly all
details—could spread throughout the world and come to life whenever a ‘New Left’ sprang into being.” But she concludes by insisting on
the continuing relevance of Luxemburg’s actual ideas, expressing the
hope “that she will finally find her place in the education of political
scientists in the countries of the West” (and presumably the East, the
North, the South), since—according to Luxemburg’s biographer J. P.
Nettl, whom she quoted—“her ideas belong wherever the history of
political ideas is seriously taught.”
Stephen Eric Bronner, it seems clear, inclines very much toward
this view. And he seems admirably determined not to allow what is
valid in Luxemburg’s thought and life to be lost in the clouds of utopianism or the fog of nostalgia.
I have not read enough of Bronner’s writings. His small book on
Rosa Luxemburg is not bad, though I differ with some of the interpretation. (But for me, no one has matched Rosa’s comrade Paul Frölich’s
classic biography of her.) I have read Bronner’s edition of Rosa
Luxemburg’s letters, which is incredibly fine, and while Luxemburg
may deserve most of the credit for that, I feel genuine gratitude for
Bronner’s valuable selections, editing, notes, and introductory essay.
And I have read his warm and illuminating essay on his teacher
Henry Pachter, a very thoughtful one-time follower of Luxemburg,
who passed through Communism to the Social Democracy of Irving
Howe’s Dissentt.
But after reading his self-defense in response to the criticisms of
Alan Johnson and David Camfield, I will certainly want to look at the
other works Bronner mentions throughout his footnotes—Socialism
Unbound,
d Moments of Decision, Ideas in Action, etc. First of all, because
here is an intelligence that is wonderfully steeped in the Marxist tradition and the history of the socialist movement. But it is also an intelligence so obviously humane, alert, critical, that one is compelled (if
the reader is to do justice to himself or herself) to open one’s mind in
a manner that undermines dogmatic interpretations of valued beliefs.
This is so even if one differs with the author’s conclusions.
Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?
●
75
This is why I liked his essay “Red Dreams and the New Millennium:
Notes on the Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg.” It constituted a genuine
challenge for us to consider the contemporary relevance of Luxemburg,
and it truly helped to bring her alive. I think she herself would not have
accepted important aspects and assumptions of the argument.
t But I liked
it. Because what is more important than what Rosa Luxemburg would
have thought of Bronner’s essay is the extent to which it identifies real
issues and real problems facing us. She lived and wrote and acted in a
context in which mass working-class movements throughout Europe
were animated by socialist ideas and history crackled with revolutionary possibilities. It is silly to allow ourselves the daydream—when
we read her words or think about her life—that this defines our own
reality. So what iss Rosa’s legacy for us? Good question!
The Debate . . . and the Stakes
And then in the next issue of New Politicss, thanks to Johnson and
Camfield, there were not one but two critiques—twenty pages
of critique to the original six pages of Bronner’s talk—defending
Luxemburg’s revolutionary Marxism against the revisionist offender.
The critiques were comradely in tone, as Bronner acknowledged in
his seventeen-page rejoinder that—in a comradely tone—lambasted
his critics.
Why on earth would I be wandering into this debate on Rosa
Luxemburg?
In part, the answer is that I want to help these people stop fighting.
It seems to me the comrades are—to a certain extent—arguing past
each other: too much learning, too much knowledge, too many fineturned phrases getting in the way of identifying what’s really what
in the world and how they see the world. It isn’t clear to me to what
extent—in life, in practical politics—they actually disagree.
In part, the answer is that they are differing over more than the
legacy of Rosa Luxemburg. A little bit in his first contribution but
somewhat more in his second, Bronner seems to raise issues having
to do with the continuing relevance of Marxism and the possibility
of socialism. Since so much of my own life has been animated by a
belief in such relevance and such a possibility, I find myself drawn to
76
●
Paul Le Blanc
the debate like a moth to a nighttime porch light. Especially since a
majority of those who used to think the way I did now seem not to.
This is hardly the first time.
Once upon a time, I belonged to a relatively small would-be revolutionary party that was in trouble. It was larger than any would-be
revolutionary group existing in the United States today, and the trouble it was in was that—despite some very good work it had done (in
part, becausee of some very good work it had done), it was sinking under
the weight of its own unrealistic expectations. There was full freedom
of discussion in the organization and the right to dissent from the
party leadership, but—especially under the circumstances—anyone
who seriously made use those rights risked, at the very least, undermining his or her position as a respected comrade. What’s worse, at a
certain point the party leadership decided (in a manner neither open
nor honest) to replace one set of party dogmas with another set of
party dogmas. There were many contradictions, many confusions,
many foolish and wrong things being said and done. I would sit in
meetings, wanting to continue making my own modest contributions
to the revolutionary party and remain everyone’s friend, gritting my
teeth, saying to myself: “Don’t be a fool, don’t say anything, don’t go
looking for trouble, don’t say anything, let it go, don’t say anything.”
And then like a fool I would open my mouth and disagree with the
majority position.
Nor is my problem simply still agreeing with Luxemburg. The
majority dogma among radicals today, for example, is certainly what
Bronner writes: “Leninism is as dead as a doornail everywhere other
than among the sects that are reminiscent of antagonistic amoeba
fighting each other to the death in a drop of water.” Good heavens!
And here I am, still considering myself a Leninist. What an embarrassment. But this may be as good a place as any to explain myself.
I still consider myself a Leninist because, in large measure, I consider authentic Leninism to include a commitment to the following
propositions:
●
capitalism is inherently a vicious, exploitative, oppressive, dehumanizing system which should be replaced with socialism—rule
by the people over the economy, the free development of each
being the condition for the free development of all;
Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?
●
●
●
●
●
●
●
77
in modern capitalist society it is the working class (not simply
“factory workers,” but all those individuals and their families
dependent on the sale of one’s ability to work for a paycheck) that
is in the process of becoming a majority class and potentially has
the power to bring great changes;
socialism and the working class must be merged if the possibility of the one and the potential of the other, and the triumph of
both, are to be realized;
mass struggles for reforms that advance economic justice and
democratic rights are necessary in and of themselves but are also
important as the basis for the serious struggle for socialism—
both because this is a training ground for working-class activists capable of making socialism a reality, and because capitalism
ultimately is incapable of providing actual economic justice and
genuine democracy;
under modern-day capitalism, the state—even in the form of
the more or less democratic republic—necessarily reflects, and
is necessarily structured to reflect, the power and the needs of
the capitalist economy and of the most powerful sectors of the
capitalist class; while partial gains for the workers and oppressed
must be fought for and can sometimes be secured within that
context, a genuinely democratic republic that truly reflects the
needs and power of the working-class majority will require a
fundamental restructuring—a radical democratization—of the
structure of the state;
from the very beginning, capitalism was expansive and global—
seeking markets, raw materials, and investment opportunities
regardless of national and other boundaries—and this aggressive expansionism is intertwined with the policies and structures
of the modern-day state, constituting the imperialism of our
time: often peaceful when possible, but murderous when necessary, often expressed with the rhetoric and gestures of profound
humanitarianism, but always shaped to harmonize with the ability of capitalist power elites to overcome all impediments to the
maximization of their profits;
just as capitalism is a global system, so is the exploitation of
those who labor throughout the world an international reality, which means that the workers of all countries and regions,
78
●
●
●
Paul Le Blanc
instead of competing against each other, need to work together;
such working-class internationalism will mean the mutual
strengthening—through shared experiences and insights—of
working-class liberation forces in each country, and victories in
one sector of the world will, quite substantially and materially,
make possible victories in other parts of the world for workers
and oppressed people;
the layers of politically advanced, activist layers of the working
class (the vanguard), must organize themselves into a coherent
socialist organization, a party that is not only democratic but also
disciplined, that—with its leaflets, newspapers, and other literature, its study circles and mass meetings, its demonstrations and
trade union efforts, its reform struggles and election campaigns,
and ultimately its mass mobilizations and confrontations with
the powers-that-be—will be capable of accumulating and sharing
with more and more workers a blend of practical political experience and the knowledge and analyses associated with Marxism,
ultimately helping the working class to take political power;
socialism will, finally, not be brought about simply through the
slow and steady gathering together of an electoral and parliamentary majority—in fact a powerful majority capable of establishing working-class political power and the socialist reconstruction
of society can only be forged through militant, dynamic, revolutionary struggles that will confront and overcome capitalist
power structures in the workplaces, the communities, and the
political arena.
There are a couple of points to be made here. One is that this is not
just Leninism. There is ample material to demonstrate (including my
own books, From Marx to Gramscii and Lenin and the Revolutionary
Partyy and Rosa Luxemburg: Reflections and Writings)
s that the perspectives outlined here are hardly the exclusive property of Lenin. They
were broadly accepted—more or less—by all in the revolutionary
Marxist tradition, starting with Marx and Engels themselves, also
embracing Trotsky and Gramsci, and certainly including Luxemburg.
One could add that Luxemburg’s thought also contains vitally important criticisms of Lenin’s practice—criticisms that are essential for
any revolutionary socialism, including Leninism, which seeks to learn
Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?
●
79
from the mistakes of revolutionary socialists. But Luxemburg and
Lenin saw themselves, and they remain, partisans of the same set of
commitments.
Yet simply because all the holy names in the revolutionary Marxist
pantheon said something is true, does that make it true? Maybe it was
true once long ago when these people were still alive. Does that make
it true now? This is precisely Bronner’s challenge to us.
Capitalism, the State, and Imperialism
Which brings me to my second point. We should care what Rosa
Luxemburg thought because so much of her thought continues to be
relevant to the capitalist realities in which we find ourselves enmeshed.
Setting aside this rhetorical flourish and that overly optimistic or pessimistic error, the basic critique of capitalism—economically, socially,
politically—still holds up all too well.
That is why I have a problem with some of the key assertions in
Bronner’s challenge. In his second article he tells us that “a liberal
republic” structured along the lines of the United States “must serve
as the precondition for socialism.” He asserts that “not the institutional structures of liberal-democratic states, but rather the elites
within those states, erect barriers to addressing exploitation, oppression, and ecological destruction.” I am not in favor of our simply
turning our backs on the “bourgeois-democratic” state. To the extent
that it is democratic, that is a precious acquisition for all of us, and
especially for the working class, and we should struggle for reforms
within that context. But we should not blind ourselves to the fact that
“the Founding Fathers” (and all of the politically powerful “fathers”
who have come since) really did—quite consciously—structure the
American Republic in order to protect and advance the interests of the
market economy and of those who possess great wealth and property.
It is wrong for Bronner, in the name of going beyond Marxist dogma,
to pretend that this isn’t so.
Worse, in his first article he says this: “The only institutions capable of furthering internationalism are now intertwined with capitalist
interests and they tend to privilege strong states over their weaker
brethren. But I think Luxemburg would have realized that the choice
between furthering relatively progressive ends through imperfect
80
●
Paul Le Blanc
institutions and not intervening in order to forestall genocide in
Rwanda or Sierra Leone is self-evident.”
It is important to look at the actual history of the world over the
past hundred years to avoid making naïve mistakes. There have been
many imperialist military interventions which principled socialists
have actively opposed—from the Spanish American War and the
invasion of the Philippines, to the First World War, to US intervention in Vietnam, to the various interventions in Central America and
the Caribbean, to the bombing of innocents in Afghanistan. On the
other hand, it can be argued that there are other military interventions against which it would have been wrong to mobilize. A classic case was the US war effort against Nazi Germany in the Second
World War. One could, perhaps, identify other possible examples in
recent times.
But there is a difference between not organizing an antiwar movement and actually mobilizing for war. Should one give political support to interventions by (or advocate interventions to be carried out
by) what is essentially an imperialist war machine? Such historians
as William Appleman Williams, Gabriel Kolko, Lloyd Gardner,
and Walter LaFeber have demonstrated that US foreign policy in
1941–45 was inseparable from the imperial commitment to “the
Open Door Policy” and to establishing “the American Century” at
the expense of the world’s peoples. It should be clear that imperialist
“humanitarianism” will certainly be a pretext for the primary goal:
maintaining an imperialist world order in which, for example, the
richest 20 percent of the world’s population receives 82.7 percent of
the total world income, the world’s 225 richest people have a combined income which is equal to the combined annual income of the
world’s 2.5 billion poorest people, and 40,000 of the world’s children
die of malnutrition each day.
Bronner is wrong to speculate that the Rosa Luxemburg we know
would have agreed with his support of certain imperialist interventions. It was alien to all that she said, all that she did, all that she
was. That hardly settles the matter. It is not important that Rosa
Luxemburg would disagreed with Stephen Eric Bronner if all that
shows us is her inability to transcend her revolutionary socialist “dogmatism.” (Of course, I think she would have been not dogmatic but,
simply, right.)
Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?
●
81
What is most surprising and disheartening about Bronner’s response
to his critics is the way that the final paragraphs of his rejoinder
seem to rise in a crescendo of far-reaching innuendo, which seems to
question not only revolutionary socialism but perhaps socialism as
such—and he consigns Johnson and Camfield (representing “a tiny
minority . . . to whom no one ever listens”) to the junk heap of history.
That’s not very helpful, and it undercuts the genuine contribution
that he has to offer.
The Working Class and Socialism . . . and Our Own
Struggles for a Better World
In approaching Bronner’s genuine contribution, it may be useful to
remind ourselves of the two points made earlier about our beloved
Rosa: (1) there is a broadly defined revolutionary socialist tradition
with Luxemburg gloriously and luminously in the thick of it, and
(2) essential aspects of the analysis associated with that revolutionary
socialist tradition continue to make sense for our own time. But there
is a third point that must be made. And it brings us to what strikes me
as the most valid and important aspect of Bronner’s challenge.
If we still lived in the golden age of classical Marxism or the heroic
years of revolutionary Communism, with massive workers’ movements characterized by significant levels of class-consciousness, there
would be an obvious ways to make the revolutionary Marxist orientation relevant to the political struggles of our time. But those are not
our realities, as Bronner brutally insists over and over. “The industrial
working class is on the wane, and the labor movement is no longer
what it once was. . . . The proletarian internationals of the past have collapsed.” Yes, absolutely true. “The question facing the Left is whether
to embrace outmoded forms of thinking or provide new meaning for
an old vision.” Yes, absolutely true. “Internationalist, socialist, and
democratic principles must be adapted to meet new historical conditions without surrendering their bite.” Yes, absolutely true. One might
say (Bronner might not, but I would) that the Marxist analysis of
capitalism remains powerful, while the perspective of revolutionary
working-class struggle for socialism is in a shambles. As Bronner puts
it: “The power of capital still rests on the degree of organizationall and
ideologicall disunity among workers.”
82
●
Paul Le Blanc
So what iss to be done?
Despite a tone of self-assurance that Bronner sometimes employs
(a tone that so many of us tend toward, even—or especially—when
we are unsure), his suggested paths “forward” seem to go in different
and contradictory directions. Some of them seem to demand a relentless honesty and critical-mindedness (in regard to Marxist verities),
others seem to suspend critical thinking and indulge in self-deception
(in regard to the nature of the state and imperialism). We have seen
that some of his thoughts seem to throw into question the revolutionary socialist goal as such. Others take us in the direction of continuing the struggle in the spirit of Rosa Luxemburg. In what follows,
I want to trace precisely those elements, which one can find in the
articles both of Bronner and of his two critics.
“A more radical commitment to social justice must now increasingly seek new forms of alliance between workers and members of
the new social movements,” according to Bronner, and Alan Johnson
fully agrees, adding that the precondition of independent workingclass politics involves “the political constitution of the multi-ethnic
and gendered working class as a unity-in-difference.”
In the words of David Camfield, we need “a socialist political strategy which takes as its start-point struggles, however small, in which
working-class and oppressed people assert their needs against employers, governments and other instances of domination,” emphasizing
the need for “unions and community-based workers organizations
(including those of women and other oppressed people),” as well as
“organizations of peasants, indigenous people, students, and others,”
adding up to an inclusiveness that also characterizes the vision of
Bronner and Johnson.
“Justice is a river with many tributaries,” Bronner tells us. “Most
women and gays, minorities and environmentalists, have a stake in
protecting the gains made by labor in the past as surely as labor had
a stake in furthering many of their concerns in the future.” Johnson
tells us of the need—also explicitly embraced by the others—to “fight
to protect threatened welfare benefits and democratic rights from rollback, and then to use that resistance as a springboard to fight for
further reforms is a key to socialist advance.” All of them identify with
movement for global justice associated with massive international protests in Seattle, Prague, Washington, D.C., Genoa, and elsewhere.
Why Should We Care What Rosa Luxemburg Thought?
●
83
These are the kinds of things that we should all work on—in as
serious and as organized a manner as possible, with the relatively small
socialist groups finding ways to work in alliance rather than sectarian
competition. In fact most of the people in the diverse, fragmented,
incohesive working-class majority don’t identify with any of the existing groups, and it is most important to reach out to these brothers and
sisters who will be new to the struggle and are not about to enlist in
one or another ideological group. We cannot afford to pretend that
we are living in the glory days of either the Second International or
Third International—in many ways our organizational and ideological realities are closer to those preceding the First International. And
of course in some ways they are very different from anything that has
come before.
It seems to me that the basic elements of the revolutionary socialist tradition still make sense, but there are ways to apply them that
would make very little sense. Times are different. Just as aspects of the
Communist Manifesto made more sense in 1890 and 1930 than they
did in 1848, so will aspects of the revolutionary socialist perspective
have greater relevance later than they do now (especially if we do the
right kinds of things between now and then). We should have respect
for our history, but not at the expense of respecting, understanding,
and being able to truly affect the present-day realities of which we are
part. We need tools, not totems or artifacts.
With modesty and patience, as we help advance the struggles for
a better world and learn from the experiences associated with these
struggles, we may be able to sort more adequately through the divergent
notions of Bronner and his critics. And then what Rosa Luxemburg
and her comrades thought may take on a greater meaning than we are
able to find at this particular moment in history.
CHAPTER 6
Socialist Metaphysics and
Luxemburg’s Legacy
Michael J. Thompson
T
heodor Adorno once wrote that tradition is “unconscious
remembrance.”1 Adorno’s claim—wrought in superb dialectical fashion—was intended as a critique of the rigid structures
of meaning and thought that were inherited passively from the past.
Liberation from such thinking was possible only through a consistently critical stance toward accepted thought, even when the nature
of this thought was ostensibly “radical.” We all too often associate this
problem of tradition and its constraining character with conservatism.
But the debate that has arisen over Stephen Bronner’s article “Red
Dreams” in a previous issue of New Politicss has shown that the Left is
all too prone to this same tendency. The debate currently underway
has gone, in my view, far beyond debating the scholastic issues of Rosa
Luxemburg’s thought and penetrated into the very heart of contemporary socialist thought itself.
I should say from the inception that I am not in opposition to
Stephen’s argument as outlined in both his first article as well as in his
response to David Camfield and Alan Johnson, even though I do have
some criticisms of his argument, which I will express here. Stephen is
an advisory editor of the journal Logoss, of which I am an editor, and
was my teacher in graduate school as well. But this does not mean that
86
●
Michael J. Thompson
my contribution to this debate should be construed as anything other
than a defense of the feasibility of socialism and its ideals. I believe
that the current irrelevance of socialism and the Left, more broadly
in political thought and public and social affairs, is due largely to the
self-peripheralization of contemporary socialist thought through an
association with anachronistic political ideas as well as an unrealistic
dependence upon outmoded political strategies and “solutions” to the
problems of capitalism. This debate must therefore be seen as a debate
over the modern meaning of socialism since the criticisms of Stephen’s
views have, in my view, serious implications for socialist thought in
the early twenty-first century.
But my entry into the present debate has been prompted not simply by the line of argument on one issue over another but on what
I see as the expression of what I will call here a socialist metaphysics:
the notion held by thinkers aligned with socialist politics that certain
political ideas and forms of social organization will guarantee a liberatory course of history and that these ideas and forms of social and
political organization that have been held close to the political tradition of socialism throughout the twentieth century are ahistorical,
and uncritically embraced. They therefore operate metaphysically,
as ideas detached from reality and the empirical truths of contemporary society in all its complexities. More importantly, I see this as
the one component that has held socialist ideas back and prevented
them from properly engaging the problems of modern capitalism and
modern liberalism. The reactions to Stephen’s argument by Johnson
and Camfield seem, in my view, to be prime examples of socialist
metaphysics and it is that which I wish to address first before engaging in some remarks on Stephen’s argument.
Socialism, Democracy, and the State
I will start by addressing the problem of the relationship between
democracy and socialism. The idea of democracy has been one area
where socialist metaphysics plays itself out most strongly in this
debate. This is most evident in the discussion of workers’ councils
as a form of democratic self-organization. Alan Johnson’s discussion
of workers’ councils in his response to Stephen harks back to the
most historically situated forms of democratic participation that the
Socialist Metaphysics
●
87
socialist tradition articulated. It was not at all surprising to me to read
a critical account of Stephen’s position, but it was shocking indeed to
see the idea of workers’ councils being advocated as late as the early
twenty-first century.
The idea for the workers’ councils has its roots in the Paris
Commune and those romantic associations still persist. But any
casual acquaintance with the literature on workers’ councils paints a
picture of them being a road to democratic participation only where
parliamentary forms were not historically present. In Russia, after the
first soviet formed in 1905 in St. Petersburg, Trotsky wrote that the
workers’ councils “organized the working masses, directed the political strikes and demonstrations, armed the workers, and protected the
population against pogroms.”2 They served a purpose that unions and
the workers’ movement would in nations that already had republican
governments. They were the fighting organizations of workers and of
peasants in Russia and were progressive with respect to Russian political history and to the Tsarist state, but there was, in general, a refusal
to grant the councils that same status in western European nations.
Karl Kautsky, in The Dictatorship of the Proletariat, admitted that
workers’ councils were an impressive phenomenon, but was opposed
to them as a replacement of a fully democratic state since the exclusion
of the bourgeoisie—at least in Western nations—would exclude and
thereby disenfranchise a large portion of the public. I see little difference in modern America or Europe in this regard. Karl Renner’s argument against the councils is perhaps most relevant here. For Renner,
both workers’ councils (Arbeiterriite) and the less ambitious “factory
councils” (Betriebsriite) or “works councils” were insufficient to produce a fully realized political democracy since they were composed of
only one strata of society—the proletariat—and would be able to represent and handle only limited sectional interests.3 Since workers were
not a universal class in all political affairs, workers’ councils were considered undemocratic from a broader political perspective once they
were scrutinized more closely from the standpoint of more advanced
political formations, such as the liberal republican state in western
Europe.4
But even more, the idea of workers’ councils should be seen as
sociologically out of touch with all present political and economic
realities once we consider the problem that the “working class” has
88
●
Michael J. Thompson
itself grown increasingly heterogeneous with respect to its interests as
well as its relation to capital. Simply saying that the working class—
especially in advanced capitalist economies—is defined by its relation to capital as wage/income earners simplifies the true problem
that socialist ideas and institutions face. Furthermore, it is no longer
the case that workers’ councils would be able to provide a more progressive form of democracy than the expansion of liberal institutions
that presently exist. Democracy and socialism, it seems to me, require
the expansion of democracy into the economic sphere. Although this
is not something Johnson would deny, he is mistaken in seeing the
council system as a remedy to this problem.
At a deeper, more theoretical level, why ought we to assume that
workers’ councils are a more profound realization of democracy
than the potentialities of the liberal republican state? The expansion of liberal institutions of accountability seem more “democratic”
than a vague conception of workers’ councils, which are (1) theoretically fuzzy with little historical precedent and have absolutely
no appeall for modern workers of any kind; and (2) simply impede
the development of socialist political ideas from truly articulating
institutional alternatives to the present. I would add to Stephen’s
question presented in his reply to show any political force or party
that has workers’ councils on its agenda: “What segment of society
has even the slightest desire for such organizations?” In place of a
democracy defined in terms of Russian soviets, it may be more fruitful and much more appealing to those who are not socialists, to
work toward pushing the liberal republican state to further levels of
democratic development.
The decentralized nature of direct democratic forms are tendencies
in socialist and radical thought that hold socialist politics back from
evolving democratic institutions more suited for modern problems.
The bickering over councils seems more to me to be over an archaic,
vestigial piece of history than over a truly realistic and even desirable
social alternative to what could be achieved through the expansion of
democratic institutions linked to a state bent toward the realization of
full political democracy.
This brings me to David Camfield. The problem of the state and
democracy in socialist thought is complex, but statements such as the
following deserve some discussion:
Socialist Metaphysics
●
89
The liberal state upon which Bronner’s perspective ultimately
depends is not a reliable vehicle for efforts to limit the power of the
market. Mass struggles—such as those in France—have slowed
neoliberalism’s dismantling of the social programs provided by the
state. But it is increasingly evident that state power is an integral
and active dimension of global capitalism’s offensive.
The retreat from, and the cynicism toward, the state as well as the
move toward direct democratic forms of organization is at the same
time a retreat from the notions of universalism and accountability that
socialism and democracy have always privileged. It is a retreat because
these are not institutional forms that can necessarily deal with the
other problems of governance beyond that of the workplace. There is
no guarantee that the individuals that make up any workers’ council
will, for instance, be inclined to allow homosexuals to marry. What,
in other words, makes such nonstate, even antistate, formations more
receptive to democratic ideas? Why should they be taken seriously as
alternatives to the liberal state? There is no answer, let alone justification given in either Camfield’s or Johnson’s replies. Socialist ideas
such as these are inadequate because they end up reducing all political
phenomena to the category of capital itself. To advocate workers’ councils and to see the state as nothing more than a tool of the interests
of capital is to simultaneously emasculate the very power socialism
would have at its disposal to work against the effects and tendencies
of capital. It is only through the powerful institutions of the state—
those that are democratically accountable—that the force of capital
can be countered.
We should recall here Marx’s critique of Hegel’s theory of the state.
For Marx, the state was not inherently antidemocratic nor was it the
creation and sole vehicle of capital and the bourgeoisie, but its claim to
being the representative of the general interest was merely a pretension.
Economic interests do define much of what the capitalist state does
and how it acts, but this does not in any way mean that the state per se
is the problem and that it should be replaced by romantic social forms
promising direct democracy. If anything, it implies the requirement to
further privilege the politicall over the economic, as Stephen points out,
since it is only through this that the state can be moved toward the
promotion of the general interest at the expense of particular interest.
90
●
Michael J. Thompson
Indeed, Marx did see the Paris Commune as a significant movement
toward a higher form of democracy, one that was superior to that of
the bourgeois republican state. But it is essential to point out that
this was not Marx’s only position since he did admit that universal
suffrage granted by the liberal state could become a potent vehicle
for working-class interests and working-class power.5 Similarly, Marx
also saw that the existence of democratic institutions within the liberal state could provide a substitute for violent revolution.6
In addition, I am not sure that there have been “mass struggles”
in France for the fight against the rolling back of welfare benefits,
although I would acknowledge that mass movements have been able
to show the state that they are accountable to a large number of people
and that their policies ought to reflect this fact. The state should be
seen as more than simply the evil twin of capital; it also possesses the
power to transform social relations and expand the political protection of the weak and disenfranchised. Yes, the state works by means
of coercion at times, but who would deny that the type of repression
practiced by the state in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
in Western democracies is a reality of the past and not a definitive
aspect of the modern liberal state?
By defining itself outside of the institutions of the modern state,
socialist goals cannot be realized without an anachronistic claim to
revolution and a theoretically weak and historically bankrupt reliance
on workers’ councils as some path toward socialist democracy. Only
once socialist ideas come to grips with the political and economic
realities of the present will socialism be able to take its place as a viable
alternative to contemporary social and political life. Only once we see
that the outmoded claims to workers’ councils and the abolition of
the state are practical impossibilities and theoretical cul-de-sacs will
we see that socialism has yet to come into its own in the twenty-first
century. Illusions as to the strategies of socialist democracy should
be dispensed with and a more pragmatic politics needs to be put in
its place. Socialism may in fact require the political vision of utopia,
but it must prevent utopianism from infecting socialist institutional
proposals and tactical politics.
What seems to be missed by both Johnson and Camfield is that—
as Marx’s critique of Hegel’s theory of the state expressed it—socialism
was to emerge as the result not of the abolition of the bourgeois state,
Socialist Metaphysics
●
91
but as a result of the Aufhebung des Staats, not Engels’s “withering
away” of the state (der Staat stirb ab). Aufhebungg meaning transcendence through preservation and destruction, there seems even less
theoretical ground to continue to make such naive arguments about
the state and socialist strategy. The liberal republican state needs to be
seen in this context, and the development and enhancement of social
freedoms from civil rights to workers’ rights in the twentieth century
are testament to this.
Radical Liberalism or Socialism?
This leads me to Stephen’s claim of the primacy of politics over economics. Indeed, there is little question that the scientific Marxism
of the Second International is completely irrelevant both social
scientifically and politically. To accept a teleological argument for
political change based upon economic calculation and the collapse
of capitalism under its own weight is similarly absurd. But this does
not mean a wholesale privileging of politics over economics. Political
judgments alone, even buttressed by the best ethical argumentation,
cannot overcome the material problems of scarcity and distribution.
Economics is more than a merely descriptive enterprise, as Marx
knew full well; it is also a creative problem solver in its own right and
it requires a place besidee politics as a means of overcoming the problems of capitalism and the construction of some satisfactory form of
social democracy.
Stephen leads us to believe that politics is now the one domain in
which socialist goals can be achieved. Politics is seen as the one area
where social critique emanates from and where the radical reformation of society begins and ends. What happens, for instance, once
our political convictions lead us to the conclusion that the production process of capitalism is inherently “unethical” according to some
socialist moral stance? What happens when we want to actually move
ahead with ideas of “economic justice,” a fairly vague term today once
we consider that there is really no interest to push for even a 35-hour
work week, unions are looked at askance, and the problems of the
environment are too big and too abstract to mobilize everyday people
to actually push for even political attention to such issues? I am not
sure that the peripheral existence of social movements privileging a
92
●
Michael J. Thompson
class ideal will get us anywhere in this regard. Even if we were to push
for full employment and for a more egalitarian distribution of incomes
and raise the quality of life for the poor, this could conceivably still
be achieved within the boundaries of political liberalism. Socialism
would mean a more profound transformation of economy and society.
The problem seems to me to be in the divergence between the “clean
hands” of political ideas and ideals and the prescriptions they provide,
and the “dirty” ones of social science, economics, and actual policy
construction, something the socialist tradition has always shied away
from due to its exclusion from mainstream politics and to its own
detriment.
This has a deeper philosophical valence. Marx, like Hegel before
him, saw freedom not as the removal of barriers to one’s self-development; surely there are aspects of freedom that encompass that. More
than this, they saw that freedom was the insight into necessity; that
the overcoming of the material problems that confront humanity
requires the scientific analysis of those problems. It is, in this sense,
a partner to labor since it serves to enhance that capacity of humans
to transform their environment. Economics is, in this sense, a science
of distribution, efficiency, and production; it is not simply the vulgar economics of the Second International and the gross positivism
of Marxism’s “golden age.” We must remember that these material
problems are often either detached from political ideas (as in the case
of Soviet economic planning) or attached to simplified, ahistorical
social, psychological, and political categories (such as libertarianism or economic liberalism). This means that a new, critical political
economyy is needed just as much as there is a need to reevaluate socialist political ideals, as Stephen has taken pains to point out—a critical political economy that can address the concerns of political and
economic democratic values and also find the correct institutional
referents for the realization of such ideas. Without these institutions,
political ideas can remain only as abstractions. Regulative ideals are
important, and a useful Kantian tool for getting out of the Marxian
problem of teleology. But there is a limit to political ideas alone,
and a real need to overcome the problem of economic constraints.
Socialism has this as its primary concern over liberalism, which, by
and large, has no problem with capitalism as a system, only its inegalitarian effects.
Socialist Metaphysics
●
93
Kant and liberalism both see an opposition between the realm of
freedom and the realm of necessity. Practical reason and politics are
distinct from the material world and need not consider it in its rationale and operation. Hegel and Marx are radical precisely because
this metaphysics is defused. Now, I should point out that I see that
Stephen’s position is not wholly identical to that of Kant and of modern liberalism—at least up to a point. His broader point about the
importance of political ideas is well taken as we see from his recent
response:
Remembering the real achievements of the labor movement, the
fight for time, and for the dignity of working people, gives socialist theory a hook in reality. It places modem socialists in an antitotalitarian tradition of radicall reformism. It forces young people
both to recognize structural constraints and the kind of struggle
that was required to introduce what was so often derided as mere
“legislation.” It creates the possibility of reconnecting theory with
practice. And—most important—it raises a meaningful hope for
socialist politics.
These are important moments in the legacy of the Left and its political
push toward enhanced freedoms and new political possibilities. But it
is not necessarily socialistt in nature. To be sure, it can be argued quite
persuasively that the labor movement and its gains as well as the civil
rights movement were moments of the historical expansion and evolution of liberalism. The 40-hour work week or the rights of blacks to
vote and sit on a bus like any other white citizen are important gains,
but are they inherently socialist?? I am not sure that the issues Stephen
points to are particularly socialist even as they do point to important moments of the struggle for freedom, recognition, and human
dignity. If they are not, then there is nothing in the mere idealism of
political notions such as freedom from constraint, oppression, exploitation, etc., that cannot be dealt with—at the popular level—by the
institutions and ideology of modern liberalism.
It is also important to note that these were political ideas that
were, in a sense, permitted by the capitalist economy. Capital certainly fought the existence of organized labor, and it was only through
the struggles of the labor movement—both in the courts and on the
94
●
Michael J. Thompson
streets themselves—that modern liberalism was able to take root.7
Similarly, the Civil Rights Movement restated the core principles that
were inherent in the American Constitution from its inception. What
was needed at the time was to fight against preliberal institutions and
attitudes that still plagued America and prevented a deeper sense of
democracy from being realized.
But again, the problem of socialism is not to merely draw a line
from these struggles to more grandiose political ideals. It is also to see
that radical political ideas can become concrete only insofar as the liberal capitalist state can accommodate them. The words are important
here: insofar as the liberal capitalist state can accommodate them, not
is willingg to accommodate them. This is a crucial concern; if socialism
has at its base the core principles of human freedom, the expansion
of human and civil rights, the elimination of an arbitrary exercise
of power, and the accountability of economic institutions as well as
all political and social ones, then we are faced with the dilemma of
how far radical reformism can proceed before we run into the boundary conditions of modern capitalism and the economic constraints it
presents us with, a boundary condition that will not be able to inspire
revolution, but one that will more likely—due to the impact of reification and the evaporation of class consciousness—lead to a more
servile acceptance of the status quo.
We need not accept the vulgar Marxist thesis about “base and
superstructure.” I agree with Stephen that socialist theory requires an
emphasis on the relative autonomy of political ideas, but the primacy
of the political over the scientific aspects of social science does not
take us very far. Indeed, I would argue that the more we detach a
socialist politics from a critical political economy, the more we lapse
into a “radical liberalism,” not a viable socialism. It may be that books
on political theory can continue to debate the abstract notions of freedom and the logical implications of such and such a thesis on various
political possibilities. But this does not necessarily link theory and
practice. It may be that the most realistic relation between theory and
practice can manifest itself in the sphere of political-economic policies
that can transform social relations as well as those with the natural
environment. I would agree that this is largely driven and inspired by
political ideas, but this does not get us past the insuperable boundary
of the economics of capitalism. When Rosa Luxemburg argued, and
Socialist Metaphysics
●
95
Stephen references this, that the power of capital is a positive function
of the organizational and ideological disunity of workers, this was not
merely a political statement. Luxemburg also argued that the gains
achieved by unionized workers could always be rolled back during a
period of economic recession. It is the existence of capital and the way
it organizes society around its own logic that needs to be dealt with in
the end. In this sense, political ideas and political movements are key;
but there is also the essential need to continue to open up capitalism’s
“black box,” as Marx did in Capital, and not rely on the sphere of
politics for all emancipatory solutions.
This is not pessimism but an honest and intense realism. I am
not calling into question Stephen’s understanding of socialism, which
I agree with in principle and very much in substance as well. I am
merely arguing that the problem with privileging political ideas over
economic science leaves us at the mercy of capitalism in the end, not
in a critical position with respect to it, and also that the essence of
socialist transformation consists in changes in both political as well
as economic spheres, something Rudolf Hilferding knew all too well.
What I mean by this is that political ideals need to be linked up
to ways of managing concrete economic problems. Thinkers from
Aristotle to Smith, Lavoisier, John Stuart Mill, and Marx himself
have seen this to be the case. Economic justice is, to a certain extent,
an issue of politics: redistribution according to more “just” standards
and more participation in the workplace for laborers, for example.
But this brings us back to a crucial concern: with the expansion of
liberalism, there is no longer a desire on the part of laborers or on the
part of young people to take up these concerns. The struggles against
the World Trade Organization may show some that radical ideas still
have an ability to move younger people, but it has also betrayed an
ignorance of globalization itself as well as a naiveté with respect to
larger political institutions and has reached back to a certain anarchism without purpose.
The separation of economics from politics is an aspect of neoclassical social scientific thinking. In this sense, I wholly agree with Abba
Lerner’s insight that economics “has gained the title of the queen of the
social sciences by choosing solvedd political problems as its domain.”8
This applies mainly to the methods of neoclassical thinking. A critical political economy will be required to solve the problems that
96
●
Michael J. Thompson
capitalism creates and to pose the institutional and policy alternatives
that socialist political ideals—such as those that Stephen speaks of—
will require for progressive social and political change. Social critique
with socialist goals cannot take on the attributes that accompany the
bourgeois division of the social sciences. What we must see is that
economics, sociology, political science, and the speculative moments
of ethics, political theory, and social philosophy all play a crucial role
in the course of social transformation and always have. The highlighting of one of these with respect to any other results in one-sided
analyses and an insufficient critique: rigidified technical analysis in
the case of economics, and political and social idealism in the case of
theory and philosophy.
I do not mean to confine socialist ideas to the sphere of policy construction. I do believe that a crucial dialectic exists between abstract
political ideas and their actual translation into practice. This can be
done though policy, if such power were to be at hand, but it must
also be “on the table” when it comes to social movements as well. The
larger institutional context—economic as well as political—needs to
be configured into any progressive social movement and not left to
theory alone. Indeed, Stephen’s point about linking social movements
around the notion of class is a step toward unifying what is today a
disparate, fragmented, and sectarian Left. Economics cannot be the
answer to political problems, but we must also realize that dealing
with capitalism and a deeply ingrained liberalism requires deeper critiques and more realizable institutional alternatives.
Notes
1. Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialecticss (New York: Continuum Press,
1973), p. 54.
2. Leon Trotsky, Our Political Taskss (London: New Park, 1979).
3. “Democracy and the Council System,” in Tom Bottomore and Patrick
Goode, eds., Austro-Marxism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978 [1921]).
4. Factory councils are perhaps a more promising avenue to reform workshop
relations and expand democracy on the shop floor, but this is quite a different thing from them being able to step up to the task of promoting political
democracy more broadly.
5. Marx’s exact words are: “The carrying out of Universal Suffrage in England
would, therefore, be a far more socialistic measure than anything which has
Socialist Metaphysics
●
97
been honored with that name on the Continent. Its inevitable result, here,
is the political supremacy of the working class.” From “The Chartists” in
the New York Daily Tribune, August 25, 1852.
6. “We do not deny that there are countries like England and America, and
if I am familiar with your institutions, Holland, where labor may attain its
goal by peaceful means.” The First International: Minutes of Hague Congress
of 1872,
2 Hans Gerth, ed. (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1958),
p. 236.
7. The argument here is that labor served as a means of pushing liberalism into
workplace relations that were previously dominated by preliberal notions
of work and ownership. See the interesting work of Karen Orren, Belated
Feudalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
8. Abba Lerner, “The Economics and Politics of Consumer Sovereignty,”
American Economic Review
w (May 1972), p. 259 (emphasis in the original).
CHAPTER 7
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
Barry Finger
Keep your anachronistic notions of national self-determination
and workers’ councils. Keep your irrelevant view of “science.”
Keep your insular beliefs. But then when you glance at the
world, perhaps you will consider everything as simply “false
consciousness?” Was everyone an idiot except your “tiny minority,” who still knows everything better, but to whom no one
ever listens?
—Stephen E. Bronner, 2002
From the traditional perspective these unactualized possibilities and unrealized potentialities for liberation come to be
seen as “irrational.” Consequently, they can be dismissed—
but always in the name of the present that has become manifest. In the name of the status quo, the relative validity of
unactualized needs and demands that were expressed both in
theory and praxis are brushed aside, and termed “impossible
to achieve.”
—Stephen E. Bronner, 1987
For, just as materialism itself originally grew out of the critique of religion, so too must the mystification of capitalist ideology and production relations—the most progressive
aspects of which cannot be actualized within capitalist society
100
●
Barry Finger
and the most reactionary of which simply serve to veil the
functioning of the given order—be criticized in a concrete
manner and in terms of the concrete alternative of workers’
control that is, after all, the basis of emancipatory socialism.
—Stephen E. Bronner, 1977–78
S
omewhere in the past 25 years, Rosa Luxemburg, once a “revolutionary for our times,” became a liberal. The precise date of that
transmogrification is unknown, but its discovery was announced
with little advance fanfare, but with much subsequent consternation
in the Summer 2001 and Winter 2001–2002 issues of New Politicss.
In making his case, Stephen brought to bear, with the typical erudition, clarity of presentation and impish wit that makes his fortunate
students the envy of his political audience, the full weight of critical
Marxism, the Marxism of Georg Lukács and of Karl Korsch. All of
which is even more dazzling, given that the latter are, at least to this
untutored mind, more often associated with ultra-leftism than with
Social Democracy. So, in effect, Stephen performed the audacious
tandem mental trapeze act of having inverted Left and Right not only
in the person of Rosa Luxemburg, but of the entire socialist analytical
continuum as well.
Stephen insists, and not without considerable persuasive force, that
his viewpoint cannot be meaningfully merged with that of classical
socialist revisionism. To do so would be to repudiate the key insights
of critical materialism that rescued Marxism equally from the sterility of “orthodox doctrinalism” as well as from all belief in the genetic
inevitability of evolutionary socialism and its corollary, “ideology
of compromise,” through which the future socialist commonwealth
might be eased. But that does not absolve Stephen from the whiff
of suspicion in having dissolved socialism in an equally corrosive, if
altogether different and novel, solution.
In Stephen’s words: “I don’t identify socialism with any particular
institutional form, including councils, and I view its purposes today less
as the pursuit of the utopian ‘other’ than as the ongoing creation of economic and political conditions in which working people can expand the
range of their knowledge, their experiences and their private as well as
their public pursuit.” [my emphasis, BF] This formulation, of course,
bears a notable resemblance in tone to Bernstein’s famous assertion
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
101
that “the movement is everything, the goal is nothing.” Stephen,
moreover, explicitly confirms that his approach leaves no room for a
“final goal.” Nevertheless, too much should not be made of this similarity despite their mutual agreement that socialism is to be equated
with the reforms attained under capitalism, with the significant
caveat that Stephen—unlike the classical school of revisionism—is
alarmed at the vulnerability of working-class conquests, previously
seen as irrevocable, by the resurgent forces of neoliberalism. For this
and for other reasons that will be examined, Stephen is not burdened
with an unwavering faith in the transformation of capitalism into
socialism, and the purposes of reform as he sees it, or at least as I
understand him to see it, are not merely to attenuate the rough edges
of capitalism but to raise the ethical necessity of “mitigating the whip
of the market through the statee and abolishing the exercise of arbitrary power byy the state” as the manifold conditions for furthering
democracy.
But what is so striking about this formulation is that, with the
exception of the modifier “working,” such aims as Stephen identifies
with socialism could be endorsed by the entire spectrum of democratic
thought from the libertarian Right to the green Left. His means—of
supplanting, where necessary, the market by the state coupled with
the struggle to limit the free scope of bureaucratic power—further
differentiates him along the democratic spectrum and places him
squarely in line with a long host of social reformers on the Left. Yet,
Stephen’s party of reform is curiously distinguished exclusively by its
social composition and not by any specific attention to workers’ problems and/or class concerns. For that reason, his selection of the working class as the principal agency of this program does not strike me as
a necessaryy political or logical deduction from his analysis. There are
innumerable abuses of the market and business malpractice from pollution, to price gouging, to concentrations of oligopolic and monopoly
power and influence peddling, to the maldistribution of wealth, to
urban renewal and educational reform, which have been the traditional domain of middle-class reformers and which fully conform to
Stephen’s concerns as articulated. What this program retains in common moreover with the traditional parties of middle-class reform is its
dogged insistence on leaving intact and undisturbed a social horizon
and future aims defined solely by the limits of capitalism. Insofar as
102
●
Barry Finger
he offers any justification for “privileging” the working class, to use
an infelicitous phrase he seems so fond of, it finds scarce rationalization beyond the “hook in reality” Stephen believes might be gained
by appealing to the “real achievements of the labor movement,” the
most successful and, in its European Marxist form, most ambitious
reform movement in history. A success, it might be added, that bears
necessary connection to the very revolutionary aspirationss for a nonexploitative classless society Stephen appears to cynically dismiss as
the baggage of the “utopian other.”
However, the old revolutionary labor movement, as Stephen is at
pains to remind us, simply no longer exists. Who then would he be
casting his hook to? A labor movement whose militancy and idealism seem so diminished that the very notion of working-class power
adheres little more than as a distant memory, still less a “regulative
ideal”? He surely cannot have “faith” that such a combative labor
movement, marred by ideological and organizational disunity, can be
reconstituted along socialist lines. For that would seemingly return
us to the very teleological metaphysics that Stephen is quite certain
critical materialism so neatly disposed of. If capitalism does not create
its own “grave-diggers” and if “socialism becomes a contingent enterprise, or putting it in the terms of the time, a purely ‘ethical’ demand
or project,” what necessary connection mustt it have with the existing
working class?
* *
*
Let us leave this question in abeyance for the moment and consider
the problem from a different angle and ask: What necessary connection does this “ethical demand or project” have with socialism, as
Marx or Luxemburg understood it? When it comes down to it, all
that is being invoked—stripped of its philosophical finery—is the
call for an invigorated mixed economy against the roll back of the
welfare state. Indeed, it is a program that, in spirit, Marx might have
celebrated for expanding the scope of the “political economy of the
working class.” But such victories as accrue the “political economy
of the working class,” and fulfill the “aims” of socialism as Stephen
outlines them, are self-limiting in character precisely because they
leave undisturbed the overall accumulation structure of capitalism.
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
103
The abolition of child labor, the eight-hour day, health and safety
regulations, social security and old age pensions, trade union rights,
unemployment compensation, minimum wage laws, antidiscrimination laws, etc., all restrict the arbitrary tyranny of the individual
capitalist entity and may reduce the totality of one’s life sacrificed in
directt servitude to the capitalist class. They may even whet the appetite for social justice on a larger scale. If so, all the better. But a more
equitable distribution of the working day or of the social product still
leaves a working class forced to accept exploitation as the inescapable
condition for securing its livelihood. Whether that disturbs Stephen
or not, whether Stephen cares for ultimate aims or not, whether such
reforms adapted, intensified, polished, and brought up to date are the
indisputable embodiment of the socialist spirit, there is no sensible
standard by which such proposals—radical as that may be in today’s
climate—can ever be called a socialist program.
It is equally delusional, and the demands of accuracy outweigh
civility at having to resort to such terminology, to believe that such
reforms, for all their laudable benefits, fortify and broaden the existing
democracy. Whatever the claims of capitalism to democratic forms
of representation—to a liberal republic, whatever invaluable civil
liberties and political freedoms have been attained and maintained
through incessant struggle—the fact remains that the existence of
class divisions in society makes a genuine democracy impossible.
Conversely, it is generally preferable from a ruling-class perspective
to rule, if feasible, with the consent of the governed than to support the vastly increased cost of suppression needed to rule against
their will. But equally under the liberal republic, as under other—
authoritarian—state forms, control over the means of production,
distribution, and communication arms the economically dominant
class with power that extends over every aspect of social life. That
power may not be absolute, it may be blunted and circumscribed—
but within its arc, power is not and cannot be shared. Genuine
democracy is unattainable under a bourgeois state, because the formality of equal rights is neutralized and subverted by the socioeconomic inequality preserved by the state between ruler and ruled. Yet,
without the democratic direction and control of social policy from
below, humanity, even when it is for the moment well-fed and relatively secure, cannot be genuinely free.
104
●
Barry Finger
What then of Stephen’s estimation of the ‘‘liberal republic”?
I am unclear from the context what Stephen means by “initially ” in
his assertion that “the institutional goal of the revolution initially
sought by Luxemburg has, in short, been realized.” It may very well
mean only that she in common with her entire generation of socialist revolutionaries aspired as their immediate aim to eliminate the
systems of monarchies that dominated the continent and to replace
them with liberal republics. If so, who could take exception? Indeed,
Luxemburg considered as did Marx and Engels the liberal republic
to be “the most powerful and indispensable means for carrying on
the class strugglee.” But to suggest that the “liberal republic” was coterminous with the “general understanding of a ‘dictatorship of the
proletariat’ in the decades between the fall of the Paris Commune
in 1871 and the triumph of the Bolsheviks in 1917” is a genuine
flight of fantasy. The liberal republic was considered the most favorable arrangement for the oppressedd working class, that is the working
class still subject to the domination of capital, to gain through mass
struggle an awareness of its distinct class interests and for socialists to
educate and organize on the basis of that awareness.
No revolutionary socialist of the era believed that the bourgeoisdemocratic state—the liberal republic, if you will—could ever outgrow or outlive its purpose as an effective bureaucratic instrumentality
through which the ruling class might maintain its social legitimacy.
Form follows function not only in architecture but in the apparatus of class rule as well. What, after all, is the actual design of this
democracy? The mass is allowed to vote at set intervals and to petition for redress at all times. It remains a bystander to the passage of
legislation, a wallflower to the adoption of laws and their enforcement. The parliament proposes and the executive bureaucracy disposes in its own fashion even if that requires—especially in times of
crises—redefining the very meaning of legality, without any superintendence and guidance from below. The capitalist class exercises
its social rule not directly, but through its immediate control of the
means of shaping public opinion, its financial control of the political
parties, by its direct occupation of the legislatures, and by the leverage
over independent government officials and the deliberative machinery that its wealth accords. Stephen, in his defense of liberal democracy, affects an entirely arbitrary separation of the liberal republic
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
105
from the antidemocratic barriers implanted in its institutions by the
elites as a necessary aspect of an indivisiblee process of social domination under capitalism. The liberal republic solicits the consentt of the
governed for alternative ruling-class agendas so that the willl of the
governed might remain unknown, undeveloped, or thwarted and its
needss either unmet or met in a brokered and fractured fashion. If, on
the other hand, the people—the working class and its supporters and
allies—are to be, in any real sense, the authors of their own fate, they
would face the daunting task of fundamentally reworking the most
democratic of liberal republics they might inherit and of pioneering a
democracy with a breadth and sweep of active participation unimaginable within the confines of capitalist society and antithetical indeed
to capitalism’s very survival.
I do not wish to be misunderstood on this matter as being dismissive, sectarian, or flippant about bourgeois democracy. The tangible democratic rights that do exist under a liberal democracy, for
all their limitations, are cherished and invaluable achievements. They
were also great victories extracted or thrust upon the ruling classes in
prolonged and bloody battle by the masses from below. In the broad
sweep of capitalism it would not be erroneous to maintain that significant reforms were acceded to by the ruling classes to short circuit the demand for even greater concessions to revolutionary forces.
This is true of the eight-hour day as it is of the right to vote for the
propertyless and for women, the dismantling of American apartheid,
and the whole host of other concessions that allow the majority a
semicivilized existence. As such they remain treasured legacies of the
nineteenth- and twentieth century-revolutionary movements, that
socialists and consistent democrats are duty bound to vigilantly protect. For these rights remain ever fragile, threatened in the first place
by the oh-so democratic ruling classes themselves. There is after all a
straight bloodline connecting the Alien and Sedition Acts, the Palmer
raids, the Dies Committee, HUAC, McCarthyism, Cointelpro, and
the USA Patriot Act of today.
So, when Stephen advises that his “work endorses experiments with
‘secondary’ or ‘associative’ organizations that might provide a more
direct form of democracy and . . . [has] even suggested that the council can be integrated into the liberal republican state”—as if socialism
merely requires a democratic tweak here and there to spruce up the
106
●
Barry Finger
existing liberal republic, he betrays the political gulf that has opened
not only between himself and Luxemburg, but between himself and
the whole revolutionary socialist tradition. Stephen presents a woefully distortedd neo-Luxemburgian formulation in his assertion that
“the future of democracy in the form of a liberal republic must serve
as the precondition for socialism, and not the other way around.”
For it was Luxemburg who emphasized to the contrary that “we
have always distinguished the social kernel from the political form
of bourgeoiss democracy; we have always exposed the bitter kernel of
social inequality and lack of freedom under the sweet shell of formal
equality and freedom—not in order to reject the latter, but to spur
the working class not to be satisfied with the shell, but rather to conquer political power and to fill it with a new social content.” That is
why Luxemburg, in common with every other revolutionary socialist, but with an uncommon eloquence, could assert that the “fate of
democracy was bound up with the socialist movement.” For socialism aims to translate the democratic formalities of the liberal republic into its fullest realization precisely by providing the masses access
and control over the very material bases previously monopolized by
the capitalist class. It aims, in other words, to translate the paper
privileges of the worker-citizen into a fully functioning democracy
that invests in society’s rank and file for the first time the power to
regulate social conditions in accordance with the values of freedom
and solidarity, rather than the needs of property and profit, a context
where a free and equal citizenry can harmonize its interests by means
of rational compromise, rather than on the basis of power relations.
It therefore holds in its offing the wholesale introduction of civilized
values to the common patrimony of humanity and fashions a social
environment distinguished by the unique scope for the nourishment
of the free and creative aspect of the individual personality that those
values make possible.
* *
*
Two rejoinders are offered. Both flow from the internal logic of
Stephen’s understanding of socialism not as an historical alternative,
but as the result of radical modifications to the existing order. One
involves the question of immediacy, the other of democratic principle.
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
107
“Where on the planet, right now” he asks, “is the question of councils or socialistt revolution on the agenda?” But, even if these demands
had living resonance, he also insists that they would nevertheless be
devoid of merit. For the sole alternative to the liberal-democratic state
is an “authoritarian or totalitarian partyy standing above the rule of
law. [my emphasis, BF] There is no reason to believe that the workers’ council provides a different solution to this problem or that it can
dispense with the need for an independent judiciary or other bureaucratic institutions to safeguard the civil liberties of conservative critics
and opponents.”
And by extension, revolutionary activity is only justifiable if it
returns society threatened by the authoritarian Right to the status
quo ante.
e In Stephen’s words, “My view accepts the need for revolution, though as a tactic rather than a strategic goall , when working
people are incapable of having their most basic grievances addressed
and their democratic rights recognized.” That is, it would be indefensible, and Stephen insists, for him, unsupportable, were revolutionary
socialists to exhort workers and their allies to carry the battle beyond
the defense of an imperiled bourgeois republic to a higher form of
democracy, a workers’ democracy, the latter presumably being, in
any case, a snare. Indeed, even Stephen’s very devotion to revolutionary tactics—more accurately, insurrectionaryy tactics—divorced from
revolutionary goals rings hollow. For how would workers defend an
embattled liberal democracy except by creating new, substitute, vehicles of struggle—councils, workplace committees, militias—which,
themselves, are embryonic forms of a new revolutionary democracy?
Should revolutionary socialists be urged—or even be compelled,
perhaps by other workers—to abandon these institutions once the
immediate threat is dissolved? I wonder how Stephen might retroactively apply these principles say to the Spanish Civil War or to
Germany at the end of the First World War? How does one avoid
the conclusion that Stephen has become a liberal captive of his own
antirevolutionary dogma?
This is not an issue of councils as opposed to parliaments posed
solely in abstract hypotheticals. What can be said on this subject from
the Paris Commune on is that historical experience shows that all
revolutions erect organs of popular resistance that are at the same
time organs of popular rule, and that these organs, usually councils,
108
●
Barry Finger
tend to become the institutions of the new state power. Moreover
in all socialist revolutions witnessed in the past, there have resulted
civil wars in which upholding the parliament becomes the rallying
cry for the forces of reaction. And this is what should be expected. As
revolutionary passions push the center of the democratic consensus to
the far left, capitalist and reactionary elements can only appeal to the
masses by championing lesser democratic forms that retain historical
resonance but quickly lose their allure to the fuller more extensive
democratic order arising in its midst.
Let us look more closely at Stephen’s other objection. By raising the issue of immediacy, Stephen insists that his understanding
of socialism bears with it an attachment to realism lacking in the
wooly and idle speculations of those who seek socialism in a higher,
more complete, and extensive form of democracy. Historical materialism, he admonishes, “must deal with the situation as it exists.”
That situation is one in which the working class is kept in ignorance
and confusion of its own social position and innocent of its latent
social power to reconstruct society on a socialist footing. Immediacy
lacks, in other words, a socialist consciousness, the introduction of
which is the specific role of the socialist movement and, where that
is absent, of independent socialist intellectuals and activists. Socialist
activity means—or has meant—imbuing the exploited and oppressed
with an awareness of the fundamental reasons for their subjugation
under capitalism, of their class strength, and of their need for selfreliance and class independence. It means urging them to organize
and assemble in revolutionary parties to free themselves of all class
rule by setting up a democratic working-class government and to use
that government as a scaffolding for socialism. It demands awakening
those suffering under the yoke of oppression, exploitation, and deprivation to the understanding that the material and intellectual means
for constructing a truly free society exists and can be liberated by
their own activity. And it insists on measuring the particular actions,
tactics, and gains of the real movement not by the “‘gospel’ of practical politics”—as Luxemburg said—but by the real advances made to
class organization, militancy, and self-confidence.
The realism celebrated as an alternative by Stephen fixes the given
reality, delinks socialist activity from the complexity of the historical
process, and treats that reality as the immutable framework of political
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
109
activity. “Either planetary issues . . . will have the possibilityy of being
dealt with in the international arena through existing international
institutions with the powers of sanctioning transgressors or they will
assuredly not be dealt with at all.” Exactly in which existing international institutions does Stephen want us to place our confidence?
The UN? NATO? The WTO? The IMF? The World Bank? How
are these institutions able to counterbalance a world taking “shape
in which wealth and resources are ever more inequitably distributed,
political power is ever more surely devolving into the hands of transnational corporations, and petty ideologues are ever more confidently
whipping up atavistic passions with the most barbaric consequences”?
Stephen recognizes that these institutions that he deems “capable of
furthering internationalism are now intertwined with capitalist interests and tend to privilege strong states over their weaker brethren.” It
seems, however, to have escaped his notice that these arrangements
float on a sea of international agreements such as GATT and NAFTA
that fortify and reassert market forces. These international bureaucratic entities not only aggravate the very ills he wishes to rectify, but
do so by expandingg and deepeningg the power of the executive branch
over the legislature. The net effect is the further atrophying of the liberal state as a meaningful focal point for delivering concessions to the
oppressed, which is precisely the active democraticc function Stephen
most ardently prizes. Support for these institutions in effect nullifies his earlier stated purpose of “mitigating the whip of the market
through the state and abolishing the exercise of arbitrary power by
the state.”
*
*
*
Stephen’s other objection to socialism as an historical alternative is
rooted in the tragedy of actual working-class experience, or at least
in an implied interpretation of that experience. The question is raised
about the lessons of the Russian Revolution, a revolution whose libertarian aims were clearly to establish a society free from class domination
and state authority, but which drifted into repression, authoritarianism, and, ultimately—though clearly not seamlessly—plunged into
totalitarianism. Curiously, Stephen thinks this question a persistent
irritant, but of minor intrinsic importance, since ‘‘Leninism is as dead
110
●
Barry Finger
as doornail everywhere other than among the sects that are reminiscent of antagonistic amoeba fighting each other to death in a drop
of water.” Stephen similarly gives no quarter to the “theoretical conquests” of Third Camp socialists (“ultra-left Bolsheviks”) concerning
the Stalinist overthrow of the Russian Revolution, extolling instead
the “partisans of Social Democracy and critical theory.” Thus neither
in opposition, nor in power or defeat, neither in practice nor in theory,
is there anything truly redeemable for Stephen in the Leninist tradition of revolutionary socialism.
This is a harsh judgment. Yet one cannot help speculating as to
where these great theoretical conquests of Social Democracy are
documented. Karl Kautsky, long the leading authority of “orthodox”
Social Democracy, characterized the Soviet Union as one of stateslavery, and as of Asiatic Despotism, as Bonapartist, and as fascist,
and finally as a new form of state despotism, without providing any
new insights into the character, historical role, or significance of the
Stalinistt bureaucracy. The famous exponent of Austro-Marxism,
Otto Bauer, for all his misgivings about the Bolshevik Revolution,
was Stalinism’s lawyer foreseeing the revival of democracy arising
from the five-year plans. Theodore Dan, prominent Left Menshevik,
looked forward to the postwar unification of Social Democracy with
Stalinism. Rudolf Hilferding’s dissection of the “totalitarian state
economy,” while a trenchant and withering critique of state capitalism,
seems a tad deficient in explicitly denying an independentt class role to
the Stalinist bureaucracy. As to Dan’s comrade Rafael Abramovich’s
postwar characterization of Stalinist society as . . . well, “totalitarian,”
one would think this hardly worthy of classification as a “theoretical
conquest.” Prior to the Second World War, he and Friedrich Adler,
in contrast to Kautsky, asserted the potentially socialist nature of
the socioeconomic base of Stalinist Russia insisting that it contained
the positive germs of socialism. The only Social Democratic exception to this dismal display is the little known work of Lucien Laurat,
whose Marxism and Democracyy touched in introductory but innovative fashion on the confluent themes of bureaucratic collectivism.
As for critical Marxism, one might search in vain for Lukács’s
unlikely breakthroughs given his contention that one could not criticize Stalin without aiding Hitler. Korsch’s equation of Hitlerism with
Stalinism as twin forms of state capitalism more or less summarizes
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
111
the sum total of his vast historical departures. Of his subsequent flirtation with Maoism, the less said the better. Perhaps their intellectual
heirs added to our understanding of Stalinism and did so without
political compromise with the two camps of class rule and imperialist expansion. If so, it is curious that their contributions have yet to
register on any intellectual radar scan.
*
*
*
Stephen is being a bit facile, to say the least, in his comprehensive
dismissal of Leninist relevancy. The Russian Revolution and its fateful course dominated the twentieth century and alternative historical
interpretations of that experience conceal nothing so much as divergent political programs. The program that Stephen identifies with
and defends is Social Democracy. Referring to the interwar period,
Stephen admonishes:
Liberalism was disintegrating and Communism was becoming
increasingly authoritarian. . . . With the suppression of the Spartacus
Revolt, and the reactionary radicalization of the middle strata and
the peasantry, there was not the least practicall glimmer of hope for
introducing councils. Whatever its vacillations and timidity, Social
Democracy was not the principal “cause” for the victory of fascism.
It steadfastly resisted the totalitarianism of both Left and Right in
the name of republican democracy.
Stephen understands Social Democracy as being ultimately doomed
to a hopeless rearguard action against overpowering odds, but refuses
to accept, much less assess its own culpability for the ignominious
downfall that awaited it. But the German and the Russian Revolutions
were the two great contrasting tests of political power, of state and
revolution, two historical laboratories whereby the perspective and
momentous implications of the divergent political programs of socialism were empirically played out. The Social Democrats of Germany,
and not just Germany, but Austria and Italy—the future locus of fascism, far from directing the working classes to grasp the power that
was falling into its hands, instead crushed in servile collaboration with
their respective bourgeoisies, socialist revolution in its shell. They did
112
●
Barry Finger
so as the great defenders of liberal democracy, a liberal democracy
that, in the case of Germany, was to include, with the consent of the
reformist Social Democrats, a constitution so flawed that it could be
set aside by means of its own provisions.
Stephen invokes Luxemburg to indict Lenin, insisting that what
is “salient for the presentt is . . . her insight that terror always produces a
dynamic that, once turned on, can’t be shut off like a water faucet.”
I’m not sure where—in the present, that is—socialists face the choice
of wielding terror either in defense of a liberal republic (or one in the
making) againstt the working class, or in defense of its own revolutionary social order. But by raising the issue of “terror” in so one-sided
a fashion, with blinders for Social Democratic terrorism, Stephen is
clearly ducking the question of power and class rule, the question
of for whom and against whom; the question of fighting for socialism when the opportunity presents itself, or fighting a hopeless rearguard action after having insured that the moment had passed. What
is significant and what is just as significantly overlooked is that for
Luxemburg as much ass for Lenin, revolution is the price exacted from
humanity to avoid the even more frightful prospects of stagnation
and decay that otherwise seizes and convulses society with alarming
and foreseeable regularity. I see little in the dismal history of the past
century that refutes that proposition. The question of terror, like the
question of war, and the resort to violence in general, is a horrific and
dreadful political tactic—an option that only socialism can seriously
aim to put an end to. But our attitude as socialists to terror as to any
given war is conditioned in the first instance by our evaluation of the
politics from which the application of violence is an extension. It is
always a question of historical relativism, never of moral indifference.
This does not mean that as a socialist I feel duty bound to defend
terror, or any other specific policy of the Bolshevik Revolution, only
that my primary criterion of support is determined by their political
program.
It may be argued, and Stephen does in effect argue, that Germany
and Russia could not be evaluated as the test of two divergent social
propositions since the Bolshevik Revolution was not and could never
have been about socialism. “Whenever a Communist party has identified socialism with industrialization, which is all that it can do when
the revolution takes place in an economically underdeveloped nation, the
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
113
result (in practice if not in theory) has been either authoritarianism like
in Cuba or totalitarianism like in China.” This marvelously teleological formulation, which seemingly connects Stalinism with Leninism
as its progeny rather than as its undertaker, fails as a generalization for
two reasons. First, because the Bolsheviks, unlike the Castroites and
Maoists, were a genuinely democratic—yes, democratic—revolutionary
workers’’ party, which bore nothing in common with the class composition, political aims, internal life, or historical forces that shaped
Stalinism and the worldwide movement whose allegiance Stalinism
attracted. And second, because the Bolshevik Revolution unfolded as
a specific, functional component within a broader European political
and historical context. It cannot be evaluated as a free-floating historical archetype algebraically reduced to and equated with disparate
national upheavals existing in diametrically opposed contexts, simply
by arbitrarily singling out the alleged commonality, overstated in any
case, of relative levels of economic development.
My point is simply this. The Bolshevik Party, being of sound mind
and stern kidney and having more than a fleeting familiarity with the
basic tenets of Marxism, harbored no delusion that socialism could
be built in isolation from the shambles of Czarist Russia. But they
did come to see, as Rosa had so presciently predicted after the 1905
revolution, that there was a special link between Germany and Russia.
“The most backward country, just because it has been so unpardonably late in producing its bourgeois revolution, can show the proletariat ways and means for further class struggle both in Germany
and the most advanced capitalist countries.” Even Kautsky as far back
as 1902 had stated as much. “The epicenter of revolution,” he proclaimed, “has been moving from the West to the East. In the first
half of the nineteenth century it was situated in France, at times in
England. In 1848 Germany entered the ranks of the revolutionary
nations. . . . Now the Slavs . . . join their ranks, and the center of gravity
of revolutionary thought and action is shifting . . . to Russia.” “Russia,
having taken over so much revolutionary initiative from the West,
may now in turn become a source of revolutionary energy for the
West.” This was the common currency of the European Marxist Left.
In 1909 Kautsky could confidently intone that the working-class
movement of the West need no longer fear “prematuree revolution.”
For in the event that “war should break out, the proletariat is, at the
114
●
Barry Finger
present time, the class that can look forward to its outcome with the
greatest confidence.” Against this intellectual and political backdrop,
Lenin and his comrades had every right to insist that the revolutionary extraction of Russia from war opened the prospect of revolution
in Germany. “They were the onlyy internationalist tactics, because they
were based, not on the cowardly fear of world revolution . . . but on a
correct (and before the war, a universally accepted) estimation of the
revolutionary situation in Europe. These tactics were the only internationalist tactics, because they did the utmost in one country forr the
development, support and awakening of the revolution in all countriess.” Bolshevik tactics were rationalized on this basis alone and not
on the impossible nationalist perspective of socialism in one country,
which was a later Stalinist perversion that Stephen has all too hastily
mis-associated with Leninism. Socialist revolution, consistent revolutionaries maintained, might be initiated by Russia, but it could only
be sustained and brought to fruition in the West.
To the list of achievements of Western socialism, esteemed by
Stephen for having established “republics with socialist majorities in
so many nations where none had existed before,” might be appended
one ignominious detail. They left the Bolshevik Revolution in the
lurch, to rot in isolation. Perhaps, too, “It was with these republics that the process of democratic education took its first faltering steps.” But if this meant, as it apparently did in the interwar
years, inculcating the belief that the liberal republic could solve their
basic problems, the education of the working class was, shall we
say, incompetently handled on every level. The connection between
Social Democracy’s abandonment of the early Soviet Republic and
its fealty to bourgeois democracy at the expense of revolution, two
sides of the same proposition—this “parliamentary cretinism,” which
Luxemburg condemned for being “yesterday a weakness . . . today an
equivocation . . . tomorrow a betrayal of socialism”—contributed as
enormously as all the mistakes of the Bolsheviks combined for the
rise of totalitarianism.
* *
*
Stephen proposes to reduce events played out on a world stage instead
to the one-sided deficiencies of Leninist doctrine:
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
115
How about instead looking at the institutions introduced by Lenin,
the mechanistic transformation of his theory of rule, his inability
to imagine [!] the constraints imposed by economic underdevelopment, his substitution of not simply the party for the class, but his
identification of the party with the state, and his willingness to
unleash a dynamic of terror that began with other parties, extended
to other institutions like trade unions, impacted upon anarchists
and socialists of good will, and ultimately would end up destroying
every critical “faction” within the party itself.
Stephen is motivated by the completely laudable commitment, and
one which every socialist should reaffirm, to a socialism where “the
freedom of the individual cannot be arbitrarily subordinated to the
whims of the state or the exigencies of any institution.” Lenin, too, in
his State and Revolution conceived of socialism without any oppressive government machinery, without a privileged bureaucracy standing “separated from the people (and) elevated above it.” He drew up a
vision of the “proletarian dictatorship” as a semistate, a state without
a standing army and police; a state without a bureaucracy; a state
constituted by a “people in arms” progressively dissolving into society
and determined to realize its own extinction. Yet the regime that the
Bolsheviks gave birth to would rapidly devolve into a sick, bureaucratized state—as Lenin and Trotsky themselves often affirmed. It was
not the fulfillment of their conception of what socialism should be or
could be.
The Bolshevik regime was ruling by the seat of its pants. Stephen
leaves the reader with the inference that Bolshevism had a fundamental commitment to one-party rule, that its political appetites were at
bottom fundamentally authoritarian and that these unsavory predilections blossomed in the context of economic backwardness. But the
prerevolutionary history of the Party bears scant evidence for that
thesis, nor is such a principle to be found in the Soviet constitution.
Prerevolutionary Bolshevism was hardly monolithic, often riven with
internal dissent, rival tendencies, and unruly factions. Even during
the Civil War, Bukharin’s Left Communists operated as if they were
a separate political party. The Lenin who issued the famous April
Thesess stood virtually as a minority of one within the organization.
Unfortunately, the history of controversies that swirled and enveloped
116
●
Barry Finger
internal Bolshevik life, routinely settled—and by democratic deliberation not by frame-ups and political murders—would be too cumbersome to detail. Suffice it to say that the question of the seizure of
power, of Brest-Litovsk, of the Polish campaign, of the introduction
of the New Economic Policy, and the trade union controversy were all
decided by party congresses with all conflicting standpoints aired and
represented. On the eve of the revolution and soon after it had taken
place, the Bolsheviks attempted in vain to enlist the support of the
Social-Revolutionaries and the Mensheviks. There was no evidence
that they wished to or intrigued to govern alone. But the S-Rs and
the Mensheviks disqualified themselves by the simple and unambiguous expedient of turning their guns against the revolution. Even the
disenfranchisement of the bourgeoisie, which had never been recommended in advance by the Bolsheviks and played no part in their
prerevolutionary programs, arose as well, as Lenin maintained, “spontaneously in the course of the fight.”
In November of 1917, the Central Committee of the Party declared
that it is “excluding nobody from the Second All-Russian Soviet
Congress and is entirely ready, also now, to admit those who departed
and to recognize a coalition withh them inside the Soviets, that, consequently, the assertions that the Bolsheviks do not want to share the
power with anybody are absolutely false.” It followed that decree several days later with the proclamation that “in Russia the Soviet power
has been conquered and the transfer of the government from the hands
of one Soviet party into the hands of another Soviet party is possible
without any revolution, by means of a simple decision of the Soviets,
by means of simple reelection of the Soviets.” As far along as 1921,
the regime tolerated the semilegal existence of those Left Mensheviks,
anarchists, and Social-Revolutionaries who confined their expression of
opposition to nonmilitary means. Several soviets were led by these parties and soviet elections were carried out with multiparty slates. But by
this time, the ranks of the revolutionary proletariat had been thinned
by years of war and the collapse of the economy and demoralized by
the social disintegration, chaos, and ruin that had set in. Revolutionary
relief from abroad was not forthcoming, and the regime, which never
saw itself as much more than a revolutionary citadel, found itself ever
less capable of regeneration from below.
Rosa Redux Ad Absurdum
●
117
It was this isolation that led to the introduction of the New
Economic Policy. But the introduction of state-capitalism, capitalism under the guidance of a workers’ state—a retreat and concession to other social forces made necessary by the abandonment of the
revolution on the part of the Western working classes—raised the
prospect that the Nepman (incipient capitalists) and the peasantry
would avail themselves of existing parties, and if that were precluded,
of organized factions within the ruling party to overthrow the new
social order. At this point, the Bolsheviks attempted to square the
circle: to outlaw, as a temporary expedient, parties and factions, while
insisting that an active interchange between the masses and state
institutions, trade unions and cooperatives, was still possible. They
reassured themselves that in this possibilityy lay the ultimate guarantor of the social dominance of the working class. They were buying
time. But more disastrously, they were creating a political and social
vacuum. For the only counterweight to the burgeoning influence of
the party’s administrative apparatus was precisely the organizedd power
of the masses that had, of necessity, found expression primarily in the
very party factions but also in the semilegalized parties now outlawed.
By shattering and atomizing this power, by insuring that whatever
pressure could be brought to bear against bureaucratic autonomy was
diluted and ineffective, the party enfeebled its internal democratic
life, disarming both itself and the working class. The road was paved
for its subsequent overthrow by the bureaucracy wresting itself free of
control from below, firmly embedded in collectivized property and
increasingly structured as a class under the leadership of Stalin. But it
was not the mistakes of the Bolsheviks alone that caused the downfall
of working-class Russia. The revolutionary regime failed to hold on to
power in Russia primarily because the working classes failed to take
power in the West.
Stephen concludes with a sweeping dismissal of the Bolshevik
experience. But it was this experience alonee that proved, and for all
time, that the working class could conquer political power. It proved
as well and with horrific consequences that there is no way other than
through the consistent application and deepening of democracy that
such power, once attained, can be defended. And it is in this context
that Luxemburg, the implacable champion of democratic rights and
118
●
Barry Finger
freedoms andd of revolutionary politics, remains in concertt with the
Russian Revolution a beacon of socialist enlightenment.
* *
*
The world, until recently, was constituted by a tripartite class struggle
in which the conflict between capitalism and Stalinism overshadowed
and eclipsed that of independent working-class politics. Labor loyalties were largely split between the two major camps of class rule,
though predominantly in favor of capitalism. The welfare state, which
came to dominate the scene, was a result of a particular intersection
of events: the prolonged postwar boom predicated on the destruction
of capital values in the depression and war combined with forced savings extracted from the purchasing power of the working classes. This
allowed accumulation to proceed with sufficient fat to make possible a
series of concessions needed to retain the loyalty of the Western working masses. As the Communist empire was imploding, the falling
rate of profit already in evidence by the late 1960s was intensifying,
crushed by unmanageable welfare and military overhead costs. This
culminated in the exhaustion of the Western economies. The emerging, yet fragile, economic recovery of the past decade, based on the
globalized squeeze of working-class living standards needed to ratchet
up the rate of exploitation, does not hearken well for the preservation,
much less the expansion of the welfare state. Stephen worries about
the degeneration of the reformist impulse and warns against “defrosting an institutional vision from the last century.” Yet his vision of
the particular liberal republic shaped and conditioned by the unique
experiences of the postwar world may prove to be nonreproducible.
Perhaps it might do well to heed the traditional Russian saying and
not spit into the well from which you may again have to drink.
CHAPTER 8
Moving On: New Replies to
New Critics
Stephen Eric Bronner
I
am, of course, delighted that my little article on Rosa Luxemburg
titled “Red Dreams” should have generated such controversy concerning the status and meaning of socialism. My previous encounter with David Camfield and Alan Johnson has now inspired a debate
with Paul Le Blanc and Barry Finger—important representatives of
what might be termed “councilist Leninism” and valuable contributors to New Politics— as well as Michael Thompson, who, having published an impressive list of scholarly articles before he began Logos, is
among the best minds of a younger generation concerned with appropriating the socialist legacy. Again, though there might prove to be a
bit of redundancy, I would like to deal with each of them separately: it
is, I think, the best way to do justice to their arguments and, through
an immanent critique, better develop my own.
I would like to begin with Michael Thompson, not merely because
we are basically in political agreement, but because some philosophical disagreements may actually be more semantic than substantive
in nature, and derive from a lack of clarity on my part. Before going
into what might be seen as a philosophical excursus, however, let me
endorse the criticisms introduced by Michael concerning the salience
120
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
of workers’ councils as an alternative institutional form for the modern era. He is right: councils have traditionally been understood as
representative only of workers; limited sectional interests from other
strata have rarely been taken into account by theorists of the councils;
and even a cursory reading of the historical record does indeed make
clear that councils have only emerged under circumstances in which
liberal republics were absent. Michael is also correct, in my opinion,
when he suggests that the obsession with councils inhibits the development of socialist ideas and that they lack any appeal for modern
workers. Michael himself, however, should probably have been more
specific concerning the alternative institutions he supports for extending democracy into the economic sphere.
But let me turn to something else: it seems that there is a misunderstanding of what I meant by my call to privilege the “political” over the “economic.” That claim only makes sense in tandem
with my insistence upon privileging the contingent over the scientific and the ethical over the teleological in what was intended
as an immanent critique of Marxism. The purpose was to explode
the “teleological suspension of the ethical,” employing the phrase
Kierkegaard used against Hegel, and transform the philosophical
priorities. There was never any question of dismissing economics
or social scientific findings from the analysis. To the contrary: my
particular brand of socialist theory was, from the first, intended to
link principles with interests. Thus, I don’t quite understand why
Michael should think that I want to divorce political ideals from
policy construction.
My notion of the class ideal, which seeks to unify the interests of
working people in existing social movements and progressive organizations without privileging any in particular, can only be effective
when translated into policy proposals. Insofar as my general theory
privileges contingency over the certainties associated with the “science”
of Marxism, moreover, I harbor no illusions about the translation of
theory into practice. There is indeed no reason to believe that radical reforms will be realized by politics though there is also no reason
to believe that they can be realized by economics: there is no substitute for a movement. The question is the terms in which radical
activists will understand the need to confront existing constraints
Moving On
●
121
and the “objective” and “scientific” assumptions of classical political
economy. Economics can surely provide insights into the constraints
of the moment or the structure in which politics must operate. If
critical economics provides the diagnosis and policy prescriptions,
however, politics remains the surgeon who introduces them into the
body politic.
But, still, I applaud Michael’s emphasis upon the need for a critical political economyy and I accept the suggestion that the extent to
which we detach critical political economy from socialist politics is
the extent to which the radicalism of the latter is undermined. What
differentiates critical from classical political economy, however, is
the willingness of the former to illuminate the values hidden within
the cost-benefit thinking of the latter. Normative assumptions are
implicit within any form of economics. Critical political economy,
however, should make them explicit: its undertaking is indeed predicated on a set of humanistic norms that were probably elaborated with
more force by Kant than by Marx. I don’t think that Michael would
disagree with this. It might even be the case that we are saying the
same thing in different ways. I don’t wish to deny that freedom is the
insight into necessity, which incidentally for Hegel meant precisely
the primacy of the political in transforming reality, or that overcoming existing problems requires their scientific analysis. My point was
only, in keeping with Hegel and Marx, that politics is the vehicle for
translating the innovations of critical economics into forms of social
intervention.
What are the parameters for such intervention? The question
whether calls for the 40-hour week or enfranchisement of blacks
are “socialist in nature” is a red herring: workers during the Russian
Revolution of 1905 certainly considered the former to be the case
and formal equality among workers is obviously the precondition for
any serious notion of class solidarity. The “boundary conditions” of
modern capitalism and what reforms the liberal state can or is willingg to accommodate, by the same token, will vary with historical circumstances. Given the collapse of teleology, again, no social theory
can simply assume it will “grip the masses.” This indeed is why the
defense of reform and liberal democracy must take center stage and
why the best slogan for any modern understanding of socialism is not
122
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
“there is an alternative,” let alone “all power to the soviets,” but la lutta
continua.
* *
*
As far as actual life is concerned, thee political state especially contains
in all itss modern forms the demands of reason, even where the political
state is not yet conscious of socialistic demands.
Karl Marx
I appreciate very much the intelligent comments and generous words
of Paul Le Blanc. I also understand his preference for the Luxemburg
biography of Paul Frölich. The first biography of a major figure,
especially when the biographer knew the person, is often the most
engaging: I’ll confess my favorite biography of Karl Marx, for which
Luxemburg wrote the chapters dealing with economics, is still the
study by Franz Mehring. More salient to our debate, however, is that
Paul recognizes the original intention of my short speech on Rosa
Luxemburg. It was not to turn her into Eduard Bernstein or simply invalidate her ideas in the historical context of her time, but to
separate what remains salient in her thought from what is tainted by
the anachronistic assumptions of an anachronistic method. To this
end, in dialectical fashion, I attempted to employ the same form of
immanent criticism she employed against Marx, and that he employed
against figures ranging from Hegel to Proudhon, against her. I completely agree that she herself would probably not have accepted most
of the positions that emerged. But that is not the point. Paul is correct
when he writes:
[Rosa Luxemburg] lived and wrote and acted in a context in which
mass working-class movements throughout Europe were animated
by socialist ideas and history crackled with revolutionary possibilities. It is silly to allow ourselves the day-dream—when we read her
words or think about her life—that this defines our own reality.
If this is really the case, however, then the implications must be drawn
in theory and practice. And here, perhaps in the name of comradely
unity, Paul is too quick in dismissing what differentiates my position
Moving On
●
123
from that of my critics. The roots of the problem, I think, lie in the
justifications he provides for his own “authentic Leninism.” I already
discussed the philosophical dangers of employing an ahistorical
notion of “authenticity” for dealing with Marx in “Rosa Redux.” The
same argument becomes even more pertinent with respect to Lenin:
perhaps his thinking need not prove totalitarian, but it has surely been
authoritarian in every version in which it has been tried.
What authenticity boils down to under these circumstances is that
the “authentic” Lenin, or Marx, becomes the one that the contemporary interpreter likes: the others, even if they have received much
more forceful historical expression, are “inauthentic” because he or
she doesn’t like them. But I sense that Paul is himself uncomfortable
with this kind of sophistry and, thus, he can note that his justifications for Leninism are “hardly the exclusive property of Lenin.” But
if that is so, and words have any meaning, what makes this particular
form of Leninism “authentic”?
To discuss Leninism without making reference to the vanguard
party and the party-state, his understanding of national self-determination and his particular theory of imperialism, his idea of ethics and
revolution, is tantamount to not discussing Leninism at all. That
is probably why I mostly agree with the sentiments expressed by
Paul: they are justified neither by the theory of Marx or Lenin nor
by any reference to history. This becomes evident in his views on
the creation of a “socialist” society by a “militant” and “dynamic”
working-class majority unconcerned with electoral politics. Given
his obvious erudition, in this regard, it bothers me that he does not
say a word about what social forces are powering the creation of
this “militant” and “dynamic” majority; what kind of organization
should coordinate its diverse constituents; or what institutions will
protect the minority in the new socialist society and make it more
free than the old parliamentary republic. In the same vein: while
noting that decisions on foreign affairs should be made on a case
by case basis, and fully admitting how humanitarian slogans can
be employed for exploitative ends, I did say that the only available
institutions capable of furthering internationalism are intertwined
with capitalist interests. Paul Le Blanc seems to disagree with my
emphasis upon working through them and other existing organizations. But, whatever Luxemburg might have thought, he doesn’t
124
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
indicate any alternative options. Without confronting issues of this
sort unfortunately, we are once again left with a romantic “faith”
that leaves the discussion over socialist strategy precisely where it
was before this debate began.
There should be no misunderstanding: I agree that the liberal
capitalist state, whether of the American or European variety, privileges capital. I don’t “pretend” it isn’t so. Quite the contrary: I have
given my views on capitalist democracy and stated, quite frankly,
that the satisfaction of capitalist economic interests in this system is
the precondition for the satisfaction of all other interests.1 I am also
aware that the pursuit of economic reforms is becoming evermore
difficult in the era of globalization. But the implications generated
by the real history of revolutions are unavoidable: I am not willing
to countenance the exchange of liberty for what have always been
the tawdriest forms of equality. I also have the right to fear such an
exchange if my critics refuse to provide any institutional guarantees that such an exchange won’t take place whatever the purity of
their intentions in striving for workers’ councils and an “authentic”
socialism.
Saving socialism from the junk heap of history requires the articulation of historical and political reasons for preserving it. It may have
been tactless to suggest that my critics represent a tiny minority of a
small minority and that no one ever listens to them. But the question
is whether what I said is true—and, in my opinion, why it is true.
Paul is surely correct when he notes that “the Marxist analysis of
capitalism remains powerful, while the perspective of revolutionary
working-class struggles is in a shambles.” But, if that is indeed the
case, then it is necessary to draw the politicall consequences. There
is much in the economic theory of Marx—especially the theory of
the omnivorous commodity form and its fetishism outlined in Das
Kapital—that
l
retains its salience. With the failure of the old teleology, however, I believe that the idea of “revolution” has been robbed
of the strategicc privilege it was always given against what were understood as the tacticss of “reform” by Luxemburg, Lenin, and the rest of
the Left.
Revolution can no longer be considered the ultimate goal, of what
Lukács called the “categorical imperative,”2 of the labor movement.
The breakdown of teleology has instead reduced it to just another
Moving On
●
125
tactic. With one difference: revolution has never been acceptable to
the majority of the working class in nations with a liberal democracy.
Could someone pleasee finally tell me why not? Are workers too stupid
to know that their interests are subordinate to those of big business?
Does the system simply repress their truee desires? Or is it instead that
the system meets some of their needs and not all—thereby creating
a situation in which workers have more to lose than their chains—
while the ultra-left ignores the new developments, locks its political
imagination into an anachronistic notion of workers’ councils, and
underestimates the value of both reform and the freedom offered by
liberal democracy?
All of my critics have expressed their willingness to support reform
and even liberal democracy even though they wish to go beyondd such
politics. But how? For my part, I simply don’t see the democratic
moment in Lenin: he never thought about placing constraints on the
power of the party; he never valued civil liberties or an independent
judiciary; and he never treated any actor outside the party other than
in terms of pure expediency. His vanguard organization was, from
the first, hierarchical and militaristic and his notion of “democratic
centralism” always lacked any notion of institutional accountability
to those whom the party was to represent. Rosa Luxemburg already
underscored all of this in “The Organizational Questions of Russian
Social Democracy” (1904).
Under any circumstances, however, none of my “Leninist” critics have recognized the crucial insight of Lenin that was also made
by Roberto Michels and others: the same organization dedicated
to reform will not be able to make a revolution. The bureaucratic
and ideological requirements for one are not the same as the other.
Under authoritarian or fascist rule, where there is no possibility for a
redress of grievances and civil liberties are disregarded, the need for
revolution remains. But that is not the situation that pertains in the
Western states, and the last reall revolutions we have witnessed, those
in Eastern Europe, were undertaken from the first with an eye on a
liberal republic. If the decision is to be made to work for reforms in
practice then the revolutionary theory with its pathetic slogans must
be abandoned; on the other hand, if the revolutionary ideal is to be
maintained, then the revolution must be promoted within existing
organizations through a cadre or vanguard group. My critics can’t
126
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
have it both ways: the world, as I put it earlier, was not constructed to
meet the demands of your politics.
* *
*
He wants all or nothing. Often I think, when faced with this choice,
the world happily answers: nothing.
g
Bertolt Brecht
Turning to Barry Finger, whose piece exhibits both passion and sincerity, there is much with which I disagree and perhaps even more
that I don’t understand. My purpose was never to turn Luxemburg
into a liberal. It is here a matter of method, and the issue is not
whether she would have approved with the positions I developed
from my immanent critique. My connection with her thinking is
in line with the issues she highlighted—internationalism, political
liberty, economic equality, and the tension between organization and
base—rather than the specific interpretations of these concerns that
she advocated in the context of her time. One more time: just as
Luxemburg employed the method of Marx against various positions
taken by him, I used the critical method against her. With regard to
the question of whether I am a “Luxemburgist,” which Barry apparently considers important, let me ask: Was Marx a “Hegelian”?
Barry seems to assume that the critical method always moves “left”
as if the question concerning human freedom had been answered before
any institutional or political questions were ever raised.3 History can
often change what was once “left” into what is now “right” and vice
versa. Let me give a concrete example: the demand for a 40-hour week
and 2-week vacations were already considered part of the reformist
agenda by the time Hitler took power. But these reforms instituted by
the Popular Front served as the basis for the charge of treason, insofar
as they supposedly economically weakened France, against Leon Blum
when he was put on trial by the Vichy Government. These tame little
reforms suddenly assumed a new symbolic value. Then, too, Margaret
Thatcher turned the poll tax into a modern issue. And in the present
neoliberal context, the reforms about which Barry is so cavalier—
despite the obligatory statement about their “importance”—can be
considered in the same way.
Moving On
●
127
Barry, indeed, approaches the matter differently: forget any connection with material reality, it is enough to find the appropriate
quotation—from Luxemburg, or Lenin, or myself—and get ready to
rumble. This becomes evident in the three quotations that, in keeping with the old model of the Third and Fourth Internationals, were
taken from my writings without sense of the context in which they
were written or—far more important—any concern with which better applies to the contemporary context. The specter of heresy looms
over his entire essay: Barry notes that there is, for example, the “whiff
of suspicion” regarding my revisionism. Mea culpa!! I believe Marx
and Luxemburg—and Bernstein—need revision: any other position
leads to dogmatism. I have no problem with saying that I learned a
great deal from Eduard Bernstein,4 who incidentally can legitimately
be interpreted as employing the historical method of Marx against
the conclusions reached by the master, or admitting to overlaps in
our views beyond what I hope, by now, can be recognized as sharp
differences.
It is also perhaps time to say something about the famous line by
Eduard Bernstein that “the movement is everything, the goal is nothing.” I have never quite understood the horror with which modern
materialists greet this obviously anti-metaphysical statement. If you
believed in the Marxian science and its teleology of history more than
a century ago then, admittedly, the abhorrence for such revisionism is
clear-cut: such are the terms in which Luxemburg engaged her adversary and confronted the challenge he raised. But if you are a modern
materialist and you don’t believe in the old scientific teleology—a
point about which my critics seem to waffle with incredible nonchalance—then the revolutionary “goal” of socialism can obviously
retain nothing more than a contingent status and it must be subjected to historical criticism. Without teleological backing, the goal
of socialism becomes anchored in nothing more than ethical commitment, or faith, a development that Luxemburg devoutly feared, but to
which Barry seems to subscribe, since he offers no evidence relevant to
modern conditions for his belief in workers’ councils, the revolution,
or Marxism.
Indeed, when Barry calls me “cynical,” he gives away the game.
Even his wonderful last sentence referring to the resurrection of “genuine” or—dare I say it— “authentic” Leninism is peppered with words
128
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
like “perhaps,” “might,” and “may.” The sacred “goal” of “revolution,”
of “socialism,” thereby becomes little more than an ethical claim. It
becomes evident then that “perhaps” the longed for resurrection of
Leninism “might” not take place and we “may” have to deal with my
liberal republic. It can go one way and another, too. But this only begs
the question: Which is the better bett ? Especially if you are pushing
revolution, calling upon workers surely to sacrifice economically and
“perhaps” politically in a dramatic way, don’t you think answering
that question directly might not be a bad idea? Under circumstances
in which the “goal” retains nothing more than a purely ethical status, becomes the object of what can only be considered metaphysical
speculation, should materialists not privilege the actual concerns of
the labor movement?
Barry is correct and clever in suggesting that reformist choices
made by the old labor movement were once inspired by revolutionary
aspirations. But that was because its representatives could show that
Social Democracy was gaining force with each passing day: revolution became tied with reform; socialism with democracy; national
parties with international ideals.5 This linkage, however, no longer
exists. If I must choose between the wish for a revolutionary otherr and
the possibility of reform within a capitalist democracy then, for me,
the choice is obvious. And let’s not hear the old saw about “socialism
or barbarism.” Other choices exist in between. History now forces
us to choose between support for reform and rejection of it as well as
the defense of liberal democracy against a rising tide of neofascism.
I know already that for the ultra-left, making such choices involve difficult “decisions” that—even though reforms and liberal democracy
are considered “valuable”—must be pondered deeply. Our materialists (sic!),
c I realize, have their principles! What does it matter that they
remain unconnected with any real and pressing interests of working
people? After all, for these very important political actors, it is not as
if such “decisions” were really between being ever so slightly useful
and evermore surely reactionary. Sometimes I really do feel that Max
Horkheimer was right when he wrote: les extremes se touchent.
Enough of that: there is still the matter of the movement. Barry
is right: it is impossible to put humpty-dumpty back together again
and create a socialist movement along anyy of the old lines. But I never
advocated that. I argued instead that socialists will have to work
Moving On
●
129
within existing reformist organizations and new social movements:
what will identify them is less an outmoded rhetoric than their ability
to articulate programs and proposals capable of unifying the workingclass elements in each of these organizations and movements without
privileging any. Such is the class ideal: it can, I think, prove useful
as a political corrective under contemporary circumstances when the
whole of the Left is less than the sum of its parts and socialism still
offers, if not a new set of institutions, a project concerned with constraining the arbitrary power of capital no less than the authoritarian
tendencies within anyy state. No more. Whether any of this fits into
some prefabricated definition of socialism or some completely abstract
conception of “revolution” is, frankly, completely irrelevant to me.
Now: here we go again. You state that “without the democratic
direction and control of social policy from below, humanity, even
when it is for the moment well-fed and relatively secure, cannot be
genuinely free.” Ignoring for the moment the phrase “well-fed and relatively secure,” which is a startling admission, can I ask whether this
makes any sense? What choice is Barry actually asking us to make? Is
it all or nothing? Good luck! Then, too, what precisely is the meaning
of “democratic direction and control of social policy from below”? Or
even better there is your call for “the wholesale introduction of civilized values to the common patrimony of humanity and [. . . . ] a social
environment distinguished by the unique scope for the nourishment
of the free and creative aspect of the individual personality that those
values make possible.”
Barry, what are you talking about? Can’t you see that these phrases
are just vagaries unless put in institutional terms. Or does such a suggestion rock your faith. In my former response I spoke about the difficulties faced by decentralized institutional arrangements of protecting
civil liberties, sustaining production over time, assuring accountability, and ignoring checks and balances. You address none of this: it’s
as if by offering some incantations, and waving the magic wand of
revolutionary democracy. You say that I—not history but I—set up
the choice between liberal democracy and authoritarianism: What is
the material justification for your third alternative? Or is it that I must
believee that there is one.
As a Leninist, should you not be willing to deal with what is obviously the greatest weakness of your own tradition? Not to acknowledge
130
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
it is to perpetuate it. In the same vein, without making any positive
proposals of your own, you are quick to condemn the only international organizations that exist for dealing with transnational issues.
You also buy into the silliness about these organizations expanding
and deepening the power of the executive over the legislature, which,
given the overriding commitment to the principle of “subsidiarity,” is
certainly not true in the European Union and ludicrous with respect
to the power exercised by powerful nation-states over the United
Nations. I, too, oppose international organizations like the IMF,
which strengthen markets, and I never viewed any international institutions as sacrosanct or in need of drastic reform.
Even the best international agencies didn’t do “enough,” of course,
and the international revolutionary proletariat would undoubtedly
have done a much better job. But things are as they are and, as things
are, I am unwilling simply to dismiss the work of organizations like
UNESCO or the United Nations Relief and Works Agency that has
been virtually alone in providing support for the Palestinian refugees
since 1948. Instead of lumping everything together under the rubric of
“bourgeois,” indeed, it might be better to consider the words of Pierre
Bourdieu: “One can be against a Europe which . . . would serve as a
relay for financial markets, while being for a Europe which, through a
concerted policy, blocks the way of the uncontrolled violence of those
markets . . . Only a European social state would be capable of countering the disintegratory effects of monetary economics.”6
You say that you don’t want to be seen as “dismissive, sectarian, or
flippant about bourgeois democracy.” But, Barry, words are cheap.
That is exactly what you are in this piece. You can’t have it both ways:
express an abstract admiration for what are concrete achievements and
then call for its substitution by institutions that you won’t define. By
the same token, you misconstrue my position: I have never arbitrarily
attempted to separate the liberal state from its capitalist foundations:
I understand the constraints. It is merely that the liberal state makes
it possible to address the grievances and mitigate, if not eliminate,
certain injustices perpetuated by capitalist elites. What is the problem with invigorating the mixed economy and fighting against the
roll back of the welfare state, which you say yourself “in spirit, Marx
might have celebrated,” if revolution lacks any materialist foundation
and your democracy any serious institutional definition?
Moving On
●
131
Of course, if you set up a utopian standard of democracy, all existing forms will prove wanting. But there is nothing particularly radical
in that: Hannah Arendt set up a notion of politics derived from an
ideal interpretation of the Greek polis, and Sheldon Wolin then went
on to suggest that neither liberalism, nor fascism, nor Marxism, is
“really” political. Fine if you want to argue that way: but don’t confuse this mode of thinking with Marxism or let it infect your reading of history. Under circumstances in which the labor movement
languished under autocratic regimes, there was no practical interest
whatsoeverr in bringing about a revolution beyond the revolution concerned with instituting a liberal republic. That was—for better or
worse—what bothered Marx in “The Gotha Program,” what irritated
Luxemburg once she had discovered the mass strike, and what ultimately justified Lenin in calling his people “communists.” The fact is
that even the demand for a liberal republic, from fear of the authorities, was not explicitly mentioned in the early “programs” of German
and Austrian Social Democracy. The problem with Bernstein, in this
regard, was not his support for a bourgeois republic but his belief that
socialism could evolve without any political transformation whatsoever. No problem: I am willing to recognize the gulf between my
position and the “whole revolutionary socialist tradition.” It doesn’t
really matter when “socialist revolution” and “councils” have become
nothing more than mantras chanted by a few sectarians that actually
help the existing order invalidate any serious commitment to socialist
reform among the majority of working people.
You can, undoubtedly, find a few appropriate citations or exhortations for your position. But there was no one with real power in
the movement—August Bebel, Wilhelm Liebknecht, Viktor Adler,
Camille Huysmans, Georgi Plekhanov, or Jean Jaurès—seriously
concerned with instituting something beyond the liberal-democratic
state. I discussed the concretee differences between what was understood as the “socialist” as against the “liberal” republic when the issue
became real following the First World War. Again, however, you don’t
confront the implicit and explicit criticisms of your position: you only
consider the problems with my own. I find no need to go through
this same business again. But if I had to choose between accepting
the present form of a liberal republic and calling upon workers to
risk their livelihoods and their lives for a romantic vision of workers’
132
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
councils, which is unwilling to address any of the institutional problems I have raised, I would insist upon supporting the liberal republic
in the blink of an eye. People should not be made to suffer for fantasies.
With no disrespect meant, it might be appropriate for you to consider
the remark of a young Nazi that Ernst Bloch often liked to recount:
“One does not die for a program that one understands, one dies for a
program that one loves.”7
Regarding how my position might have applied to Germany in
1919, I answered the question in the previous discussion. So, let me
turn it around: If the majority of the working class opposed the call
for soviets,8 which it did, would you—Barry—then be willing to
impose it upon them by force? After all, you consider the working
class “kept in ignorance.” Perhaps, once presented with the “truth”
about workers’ councils by you and your merry little band, the majority would come around: but you obviously consider any real evidence
for such an assumption unnecessary. I plead guilty to your contention
that I have become a liberal captive of my antirevolutionary dogma.
But then, “perhaps,” your argument unwittingly turns you into the
authoritarian captive of your own antiauthoritarian dogma? My argument is consistent; it does not turn ends against means. But yours?
Well . . .
Here, I think, it is necessary to say a word about those socialist thinkers whom Barry castigates. Before criticizing the inability to envision the Stalinist bureaucracy by Kautsky, who was
absolutely correct in his basic characterization of the Communist
future, you might want to consider that he wrote his Dictatorship of
the Proletariatt in 1919; you also might want to consider that Leon
Blum could already speak about a “moral incompatibility” between
Social Democrats and Communists in 1920. As you know, of course,
Lukács—a genuine old Bolshevik who (inexplicably!) turned into a
Stalinist—made his peace with the regime in 1924 and many of the
later political analyses of Korsch, who became mired in sectarian
preoccupations with workers’ councils and direct action from below
after having been tossed out of the German Communist Party, were
thin. Sure Otto Bauer was mistaken in his views though you neglect
to mention that they reflected those of only a tiny minority within the
movement. Most Social Democratic critics of the Russian Revolution
pointed to the dearth of bourgeois democratic traditions, the paucity
Moving On
●
133
of economic development, and the lack of Communist commitment
to liberal values and institutions. They offered Marxist analyses of
the ways in which Marxism was being put to use: that is historical materialism. As for the “independent class role of the Stalinist
bureaucracy,”9 or “bureaucratic collectivism,” who other than a few
Trotskyists ever considered them to be the defining characteristics of
totalitarianism?
Had you even browsed the work of Max Weber, who understood
bureaucracy as the rationalization of clearly delineated tasks among
clearly delineated offices in order to foster administrative efficiency in
terms of producing maximum output from minimum input, it would
immediately have been obvious to you that neither the Stalinist nor
the Nazi states were “bureaucratic” in any meaningful sense of the
term. Quite the contrary: the totalitarian state is a bureaucratic mess
in which, for precisely this reason, the secret police is able to undermine the independence of all intermediate associations in civil society
that might deflect the exercise of coercive and ideological power by
the fuehrer- state against individual citizens. Montesquieu understood
the need for intermediate associations as well as checks and balances
against the sovereign claiming to incarnate the will of the nation;
Hegel described when what we like to call the “cult of the personality”
becomes coupled with a “democracy,” undefined by institutions capable of protecting the minority, for what he somewhat naively termed
the “absolute terror” of the French Revolution.10 But wait! Barry may
be right! What do Montesquieu and Hegel reallyy have to offer? They
have not a word to say about Stalinism. The situation is no different
for Kautsky and his friends as well as modern theorists of totalitarianism like Hannah Arendt or Franz Borkenau or Richard Lowenthal or
Herbert Marcuse or Franz Neumann or Erich Fromm or Friedrich
Pollock or Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer.11 These are all
clearly intellectual lightweights compared to . . . Well, it doesn’t matter
anyway. These great thinkers would obviously have been better served
had they written theirr books with you in mind.
Now let’s talk about history. Regarding the revolutionary possibilities for Austria or Hungary in 1919, forget it. I agree that the revolution had a chance—if only a slim chance—in the Germany of 1919
and perhaps also in Italy during the early 1920s. But there is not a
serious historian I know who suggests that power was “falling into
134
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
the hands” of the workers in the Germany of 1933,12 let alone in the
Austria of 1938 whose working class was still languishing from its
unsuccessful militancy of 1934. An argument could be made that
the SPD and KPD should have been more militant in defense of the
republic,
c which I made myself,13 but there is—again—no serious historian I know who argues that the erection of councils was a possibility after 1923 at the very latest. According to Barry, I assume, this
means we should end history there.
But isn’t it time to get beyond 1923, or is it 1921, or is it 1918?
I also have written about the historical conditions and constraints
faced by Lenin. It was understandable for Luxemburg—desperate
and broken14 —to understand the beginnings of Lenin’s terror in
terms of the lack of support extended by European Social Democracy
to the Russian Revolution. But, the twentieth century has now come
to an end. It might be time to consider whether this completely partisan standpoint shifts the blame from those who did nothing to mitigate the disaster to those who actually instigated the disaster. There is
also the question, rarely asked, why the Social Democrats (Kautsky,
Bernstein, et al.), all of whom had been mercilessly and indiscriminately attacked by the Communists, should have extended support
to a dictatorship whose degeneration they prophesized and whose
methods they ethically opposed. Isn’t that asking a bit much? Would
Lenin have sent help to the Social Democrats if the situation were
reversed? Which also begs the question: What kind of help could
Social Democracy actually have offered? Europe had been destroyed
by the First World War, the inflation in Germany would quickly prove
legendary in its impact, the victorious allies would undoubtedly have
interfered with any socialist intervention in the revolution, and—
again—there is the minor problem that the majorityy of the European
working class opposed the Communist dictatorship.
This latter issue is not exactly what I would call an “ignominious
detail.” There are many points on which Barry and I disagree as comrades and friends, and some on which we even agree. But, frankly,
I find his discussion of terror appalling. His relativistic argument justifying terror, sanctioned by nothing more than the belief of the true
believer that his party is doing what its leaders sayy that it is doing, is
a carbon copy of the murderous and delusional “ethics” offered by
any number of old Bolsheviks. All of them were contemptuous of
Moving On
●
135
liberal democratic values while they were in power and then invoked
them when they were on the dock. But that doesn’t seem to bother
Barry. His arguments go far toward explaining why the majority of
the European working class should have been skeptical about the
Communist experiment. I was genuinely shocked by the combination of sheer arrogance and teleological rationalization implicit in the
belief that “revolution is the price exacted from humanity to avoid the
even more frightful prospects of stagnation and decay.” This kind of
talk alwayss made my skin crawl.
It is absurd to suggest that Leninism must be deemed democratic
because prior to the revolution, and during the civil war, the party was
disorganized and somewhat contentious. This was a matter of historical intention rather than design. The question anyway is how the
party treated its enemies, whether its theorists were ever concerned
with its institutional accountability to the base, the rule of law, checks
and balances, or the civil liberties of its opponents. Justifying such
willful blindness in the name of the “revolution,” especially when only
one party is allowed to interpret its fate, results in nothing more than
dogmatism. Indeed, regarding the matter of coalitions with other parties, I strongly suggest that Barry consider the recollections of Isaac
Steinberg who led the only party, the “Left” Social Revolutionaries,
with whom Lenin was briefly in alliance.
Barry is concerned that I leave the reader with the “inference” that
Leninism seeks one-party rule. Inference? Yeah, right! I’m sure it’s
purely by accident that Leninism hass produced onlyy authoritarianism
like in Cuba or totalitarianism like in China. Barry doesn’t agree,
which is his right, but isn’t it incumbent upon him to provide a single
counterfactual examplee in response to my position? His arguments
about class composition also simply miss the point: there is such a
thing as the internal dynamics of an institution beyond the external
impact of the circumstances in which the given institution develops:
Hegel, again, spoke about this explicitly, Weber built on his insights,
and exponents of the “new institutionalism” highlight the notion of
“path dependency.” But dealing with non-Marxist theories is apparently irrelevant for the ultra-left: it seems enough to trot out the same
old excuses and—in the wonderful phrase of Gunther Grass from his
novel The Flounder —“talk about what would have been the case had
the opposite happened.”
136
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
More is required than faithh that things can be different. The historical record is unambiguous: whatever the usefulness of Lenin’s theory
of the party with respect to fostering revolution, it stinks as a theory of
rule. Every concrete experience of movements committed to Leninism
has produced a one-party state with a varying, if generally horrible, set
of authoritarian consequences. Every one!! And it really is insufficient
to claim that these reall experiences of Leninism are irrelevant because
the “authentic” Leninist party, which invented the party-state in the
first place and introduced terror as a legitimate political tactic, had
different intentions. Please!! Isn’t it time to move on? But wait! I almost
forgot. We can’t. Why not? Because “ for all time”—
— no reification
or idolatry taints this argument!—wee must continue to bow down
before the Russian Revolution: this event apparently provedd that the
working class could conquer power even though the real conquerors
were Communist authoritarians that exercised power undemocratically in its name. No reactionary could have offered a better set of
prescriptions for paralyzing the radical spirit. Needless to say, in closing, let me extend my thanks for what has been a terrific lesson in the
critical use of historical materialism.
* *
*
One cannot have socialism. One is a socialist.
Henry Pachter
History has withdrawn the identification of revolution with liberation and exploded the idea that socialism can serve as the absolute
otherr to capitalism. Invoking the image of a workers’ council that no
one wants makes as little sense as insisting upon the need for a revolution that has everywhere turned into a nightmare. The debate is
no longer between revolution and reform, as I suggested previously,
but between those who support the reforms traditionally associated
with social democracy and those who do not. The best of the socialist tradition was committed to constraining the arbitrary exercise of
institutional power. This indeed is what links the liberal rule of law,
with its universal implications for members of all classes and critics
of any regime, to the particular demands of workers concerning the
accountability of capital.
Moving On
●
137
Where do liberal reforms stop and socialism begin? This is a question with which all the commentators seem concerned. But it can
only be answered in the abstract. Sure: it’s possible to say that the
reforms achieved in the past have left the accumulation process intact,
the dependence of workers on capital in place, that they have been
“integrated” into the “system,” and that the ruling class permits this
because it is less costly than outright repression. But this kind of talk
is a perfect example of “reification”: it goes nowhere unless the critic
can sketch a feasible alternative form of accumulation, maintain that
the dependency of workers on capital is the same as it was in the time
of Dickens, refuse to consider that perhaps it is not simply the reforms
that have been integrated but the system itself that has been changed,
and seriously believe that the actual historical struggles undertaken
by capital against those reforms was merely for show. Indeed, if you
can’t recognize that the combination of all the reforms mentioned in
all these essays has qualitativelyy changed the conditions under which
working people live, if you consider it “delusional” to believe that the
civil rights and social legislation of the 1960s tended to “fortify and
broaden the existing democracy,” then you are living in what Hegel
termed “the night in which all cats are gray”: such a stance is not “dialectical,” or even radical, merely dogmatic.
The “limits of capitalism” have been shown to be extremely flexible
and the old talk about the choice between “socialism” and “barbarism” ignores the various alternatives in between. Those in between
are those among which, if we consider ourselves responsible political
people, we mustt choose. All the reforms mentioned by Barry in his
lengthy response were sponsored at one time or another by the labor
movement. He and Paul and Michael are surely correct to note that
some were also sponsored by middle-class reformist organizations. But
so what? Time to deal with substance rather than slogans: the value of
a reform does not lie with who proposes it, but whom it benefits.
Innovative proposals appropriate to diverse historical conditions or
what André Gorz once termed “non-reformist reforms,” no less than
the energy with which they are promulgated, can alone differentiate libertarian socialists from the mainstream. They let radicals put
something on the table, and enough evidence from the past suggests
that they can have a practicall influence. This is not the same as asking
for workers’ councils or, in what was a remarkable comment directed
138
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
against me by a member of the audience for one of my panels at the last
Socialist Scholars Conference, a condition in which “each is responsible for everything.” What a delightful world of meetings that would
be! It’s time to understand the difference between demanding utopia
and reinventing an idea of what is feasible, but ignored, under existing
circumstances. Identifying this difference, linking the feasible with
the ignored, and illuminating the implications of the compromises
undertaken by official social democratic parties committed to the
“new middle” or the “third way,” are fundamental themes of my book
Imagining the Possible: Radical Politics for Conservative Times.
s
The pursuit of reforms capable of constraining the arbitrary exercise of economic and political power by the state, and through the
state, is—and perhaps always was—the primary purpose of socialism. Does this mean that the idea will essentially become identified
with mitigating the whip of the market and expanding the realm of
individual choice? I believe so. And so do most people. The idea of
transforming the totality was an illusion from the beginning: workers
were empowered and enfranchised less by the fantasy of the soviet
than the reality of reforms associated with shortening the work week,
introducing the right to collective bargaining, and participating in
the liberal state. This does not suggest that socialism must somehow
“evolve.” The twentieth century has taught us that the welfare state
can be rolled back, that liberal democracy is fragile. With the collapse
of teleology, moreover, no form of theory can any longer guarantee
the translation of its injunctions into practice. Does this mean that
the future is bleak and socialists will find themselves on the defensive? Undoubtedly—but that is the real situation in which we find
ourselves and which we ignore at our peril.
Notes
1. Note my essay, “Transforming the State: Reflections on the Structure
of Capitalist Democracy” in Imagining the Possible: Radical Politics for
Conservative Timess (New York: Routledge, 2002), p. 145ff.
2. Georg Lukács, “Tactics and Ethics,” in Rodney Livingstone ed., and
Michael McColgan trans., Political Writings 1919–1929
9 (London: New
Left Books, 1972), p. 3ff.
3. Dialectics is not simply meant to confirm the position dear to its interpreter, but seeks instead “by means of an immanent critique to develop
Moving On
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
●
139
philosophical standpoints beyond themselves and beyond the despotism
of a thinking based on [fixed] standpoints.” Theodor W. Adorno, Critical
Models: Interventions and Catchwordss, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1998), p. 12.
This point evident in the classic biography that is far superior to what came
before, I am proud to say, has been written by another of my former students. Note the study by Manfred B. Steger, The Quest for Evolutionary
Socialism: Eduard Bernstein and Social Democracyy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997), p. 75ff and passim.
Note the discussion in “Karl Kautsky: The Rise and Fall of Orthodox
Marxism” in Stephen Eric Bronner, Socialism Unboundd, 2nd Edition
(Boulder: Westview, 2001), p. 33ff.
Pierre Bourdieu, Acts of Resistance: Against the Tyranny of the Markett, trans.
Richard Nice (New York: The New Press, 1998), p. 62.
Ernst Bloch, Erbschaft dieser Zeitt (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1973),
p. 65.
The majority “above all wanted peace and stability. I saw Social Democratic
demonstrators carrying large signs inscribed: ‘Ebert, Get Tough!’ When the
Communists—at the time called Spartacists—seized the building of the
Social Democratic daily Vorwartss in Berlin, we were all for law and order,
along with Ebert and his mercenaries who quelled the uprising. The idea of
occupying newspaper buildings was crazy and had no strategic value whatsoever. Paul Fröhlich, the biographer of Rosa Luxemburg and at the time a
leading member of the Communist Party’s leading cadre, told me later that
no one had given the order: he was convinced the uprising had been sparked
by agents provocateurs. Rosa Luxemburg, too, knew that it was premature
and ill-considered. But she could not allow the masses to make their own
mistakes without interfering: she had to be with them, like a mother whose
children threaten to wade into a treacherous pool.” Henry Pachter, Weimar
Etudess (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982), pp. 13–14.
This was always just a twist on an old theme. Engels had already noted
that while the state is “as a rule, the state of most powerful, economically
dominant class . . . By way of exception, however, periods occur in which the
warring classes balance each other so nearly that the state power, as ostensible mediator, acquires for the moment, a certain degree of independence
of both. Such was the absolute monarchy of the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries, which held the balance between the nobility and the class of burghers; such was the Bonapartism of the First, and still more of the Second
French Empire, which played off the proletariat against the bourgeoisie and
the bourgeoisie against the proletariat. The latest performance of this kind,
in which ruler and ruled appear equally ridiculous, is the new German
Empire of the Bismarck nation: here capitalists and workers are balanced
against each other and equally cheated for the benefit of the impoverished
140
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
●
Stephen Eric Bronner
Prussian cabbage junkers.” Frederick Engels, “The Origins of the Family,
Private Property, and the State” in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected
Workss 3 vols. (Moscow, 1969), 3:328–29.
G. W. F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind,
d trans. J. B. Baillie (New York:
Harper, 1967), p. 599ff.
Again let me recommend the fine intellectual history by William David
Jones, The Lost Debate: German Socialist Intellectuals and Totalitarianism
(Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1999).
Exactly the opposite position is argued by the dean of left-wing German
historians of the Weimar period. See Arthur Rosenberg, Geschichte der
Weimarer Republikk (Frankfurt am Main: Europaische Verlagsanstalt, 1961),
pp. 210–11.
Stephen Eric Bronner, “Working Class Politics and the Nazi Triumph” in
Moments of Decision: Political History and the Crises of Radicalism (New
York: Routledge, 1992), pp. 44–55.
Alfred Doblin suggests that Luxemburg was actually suffering from nervous collapse in his novel, Karl und Rosaa (Munchen: Deutsche Taschenbuch
Verlag, 1978 ed.).
CHAPTER 9
Between Gospel and Church:
Resisting the Canonization of
Rosa Luxemburg
Amber Frost
I
n the interest of full disclosure, I am not an academic. My brief
flirtation with graduate school yielded some compelling work
in transnational feminisms, an extended sympathy to the most
vulgar of Marxists, and enough exposure to academia to solidify my
adamant position of avoidance whenever possible. My qualifications
(or lack thereof, some might argue) to participate in this project are
rooted in my presence among Marxist thinkers, far more than my
own voice.
What I am, in fact, is an activist and “satellite socialist.” My membership in Democratic Socialists of America (DSA) has most commonly called upon me to moderate this forum or lead that youth
workshop. Additionally, my employment for DSA is primarily secretarial duties—spreadsheets, correspondence, tracking, and mailings.
My exposure to Rosa Luxemburg was rendered from fairly autodidactic pursuits—reading groups in the back of anarchist bookstores,
generally attended by local punk rock anarchists and a local professor
or two.
As one of two or three self-identified socialists in that context, and
as a de facto housewife of DSA, my perspective on leftist discourse
142
●
Amber Frost
will likely be unique in the context of the New Politicss debate on
Luxemburg. While I understand there is some deficit to my consumption of her work outside of a classroom setting, I think that the
organic traditions of reading group deliberation from which I am
informed can refresh what is often an academic echo chamber, one
which I hope to deconstruct in the following piece.
* *
*
In the course of dialectics in practice, it often appears (especially from
my perspective, being one so frequently positioned as an arbiter to the
debate) that the most we can hope for is to finely tune our disagreements to as tiny a nuance as possible, then battle to the death over
the remaining minutia with the sort of passion usually only afforded
to deep-seated familial feuds. However objective we claim to be, the
tone and pacing of our rhetoric almost always seems to take on a
context of orthodoxy versus evolution, or reformism versus ideological purity—ironically, a dichotomy thoroughly explored by Rosa
Luxemburg herself. While not a generational divide in the sense of
physical time, this dichotomy of “traditional” versus “evolutionary”
is capable of descending into a sort of microsectarianism that yields
nothing productive.
This pattern often becomes increasingly ineffectual when we (on
the Left) attempt to evaluate the very architects of our political philosophy; in the case of Rosa Luxemburg, as with most of our revered
minds, we’re charged with rendering meaning from her words, adapting them to an ever-changing historical landscape. In the presence
of a plastic capitalism, adapted most recently to a particularly wily
neoliberal beast, how do we avoid the inherent canonization of a
(yes, fallible) figurehead, and the subsequent stagnation of her ideas,
especially when her thought was far from brittle and rigid?
My sympathies immediately line up with Paul Le Blanc when he
notes that “the comrades are—to a certain extent—arguing past each
other: too much learning, too much knowledge, too many fine-tuned
phrases getting in the way of identifying what’s really what in the
world and how they see the world.” Accusations of anti-intellectualism
are always railed at these sorts of criticisms, but I believe that in any
attempt to at least fashion “better disagreements,” and, at our highest
Between Gospel and Church
●
143
goal, better failures at synthesis, we must make room for the possibility
that participants are indulging in Freud’s “narcissism of minor differences,” and subsequently side-stepping more productive debate.
(I would also add that Le Blanc’s background as an activist and in
the party politics of revolutionary circles may be the reason for our
shared perspective on the debates. With all due respect and the warmest of affections to my comrades informed largely by their place on
the academic Left, as a working-class woman outside of the academy,
I perceive these Freudian tendencies as far more a result of their particular leftist cultural legacy, rather than the inevitable result of the
contentious debates, themselves.)
Dialectical discourse is a fumbling, sensitive business, so even when
undertaken with the comradeliest good faith, we inevitably risk talking past one another. Regarding Stephen Eric Bronner’s original piece
and the ensuing conversations, I find it most helpful to categorize
what I perceive as misallocated contention into a dual obstacle.
First is the question of anachronism —comrades must decide if an
ideological concept is relevant to our times before anything else. While
we sometimes believe that in the company of Marxists we would all
be acknowledging a certain reverence and legitimacy for the architectural staples, this has time and again proven to not always be the case.
From that point, we argue about interpretation and application of that
transferable relevant work—how can we decisively render malleable
praxis, avoiding the inherent risk of orthodoxy? I hope to address the
most conspicuous examples of this misdirection of dialogue.
First, while I’d argue that Bronner’s original piece doesn’t fully
explore Luxemburg’s thoughts on coalitions (which are incredibly well
developed), he leaps curiously to the Seattle World Trade Organization
protests of 1999, three years prior, as an example of an action that
“exerted real pressure on the Democratic Party, and momentarily
united competing groups in a spirit of internationalism.”
Bronner’s perspective on Seattle is cringingly rosy, and though I
cast no judgment on his inability to soothsay the ultimate futility of
the action, I find it difficult to rationalize his assessment of that protest as a successful model three years later. In fact, as I rifle through
the various utopian literature not yet yellowed from Occupy Wall
Street, I can remember steadfastly preparing myself for its failure,
even during its most inspiring heights.
144
●
Amber Frost
Granted, I tend toward optimism of the will, and pessimism of
the, well, everything else, but my lack of faith in Occupy (despite
my dedicated participation) and my initial evaluations of what would
prove to be its ultimate downfall were actually based heavily on the
Seattle uprising’s mistakes, not to mention the admissions of former
WTO protestors, themselves. So, when Bronner notes Luxemburg’s
prioritization of class consciousness over organizational development,
it appears as such a blatant gaffe to cite an event historically marked
with the recurring movement-building pitfalls of weak cohesion and
unsustainability. His interest in the actions feels like an attempt to
reverse-engineer a moment in history to relate to a particularly conflictual part of Luxemburg’s work.
One has to wonder if Bronner still sees the Battle of Seattle as an
effective model today, much the way Occupiers have yet to give up
the ghost and return to the drawing board in an attempt to, at least,
revise their strategies. David Camfield’s reply to Bronner touches on
this briefly in closing, as he assesses the “post-Seattle” moment as a
time to re-confirm bottom-up activism, though he isn’t particularly
clear on the legacy of the WTO protests, themselves.
Conversely, if Bronner’s concept of Seattle is overwhelmingly optimistic in terms of relevance, Alan Johnson’s foreboding intimations
of Laclau and Mouffe are a sky-is-falling alarmist response. With such
gusto and metaphors of Goths and the sack of Rome, he laments the
infection of post-Marxism in leftist circles as a cancerous (literally, his
words) abandonment of an authentic Marxism. (Were that I could use
such florid language without the stigma of feminine hysteria.) I think
it’s fair to say that Hegemony and Socialist Strategyy has not succeeded
in eviscerating the relevance of Marxism, no matter how many swings
it took—not even the anarchists in my old reading group embraced it
as a death knell to the romance of a workers’ revolution.
While I commiserate with Johnson’s emphasis on legitimating
theory (and admire the vigor of his prose, artfully accusatory and
stylistically reminiscent to Luxemburg herself), he seems to fall all too
squarely into what Raymond Williams warned against as the pitfall of
legitimating theory—that it might become “a series of self-alienating
options, in which our real political presence is as bystanders, historians or critics of the immense conflicts of other generations and other
Between Gospel and Church
●
145
places, with only marginal or rhetorical connections to the confused
and frustrating politics of our own time and place.”1
Johnson’s fear of post-Marxism is not only self-alienating, it implies
a lack of faith in the resilience of Marxism in the face of detractors
and assaults. The boogeymen of Laclau and Mouffe are of no more
threat to the refinement of a radical Left than Seattle was a boon,
and Bronner and Johnson’s respective sermonistic approaches to current political conditions leave behind the crux of what I perceive to
be their most compelling point of contention—the balance between
party-organizational concerns and the development of working-class
consciousness.
While, as Le Blanc points out, Bronner and Johnson seem to
mesh on the relationship of revolution and reform, in their move to
bring these ideas to some sort of here-and-now application, they both
feel tragically late to the dance. Bronner preaches the Seattle WTO
Protests as the harbinger of some grand fruition, and invests in grand
thought experiments on what Luxemburg’s opinions would be on
the new global economy (impossible to know, arguably extraneous).
Johnson responds by fretting about the ideological omens of postMarxist “cancers,” “rubble,” and “fetishes,” which, while a pestering
trend in the capricious, insular atmosphere of academic political theory, I’m sure, have yet to fling Marxism into irrelevance.
These respective red herrings, ill attempts at identifying political
and ideological developments, render the conversation to two ships
passing in the night. Foregoing functional discussion of applicability
of Luxemburg’s work, they instead careen onto loose ends of current
events or academic trends (sometimes not even that current) for dubious relevance.
*
*
*
Michael J. Thompson’s piece manages to avoid trendy pitfalls, and
engages deeply with the historical context of Luxemburg’s work, but
he proves hostile to addressing potential applications or praxis for
touchstone organizational concepts—specifically workers’ councils.
His aversion to this core concept of Luxemburg’s disregards so much
ground by simply adamantly refusing to engage with it. What’s more,
146
●
Amber Frost
he seems fairly unaware of the political landscape he’s working in,
other than his own small corner of study.
Starting with workers’ councils, he declares them undemocratic
and their efficacy limited—as if a limited efficacy renders them completely futile and unworthy of exploration. He doesn’t view them as a
model to be improved on, developed, or critiqued; he’s simply vehemently loath to even discuss them. He asserts this because he believes
“the ‘working class’ has itself grown increasingly heterogeneous with
respect to its interests as well as to its relation to capital.” While I criticize Bronner’s initial speculations of global economies as meandering,
Thompson seems to completely ignore the newly globalized economy
with his declaration of working-class heterogeneity, and he makes no
real attempt to clarify or argue the premise. Such broad strokes leave
his response divorced from the very connections the discussions hope
to make.
Thompson goes on about workers’ councils, but instead of citing
concrete dead ends in the model, he instead makes a flying leap to
gay marriage, saying, “There is no guarantee that individuals making up any workers’ council will, for instance, be inclined to allow
homosexuals to marry.”
First, the theoretical inability of a workers’ council to eschew heteronormativity in no way diminishes the potential value they have,
either in the real world or as a theoretical subject. Workers’ councils
will not solve peak oil or end racism either, but those are not valid
admonishments. Second, even bringing gay marriage into a conversation about democratizing politics and economics, as if the issue is
somehow inherently radical, ignores the incredibly problematic nature
of institutional marriage in a capitalist society. (In marriage, as it is
legally an economic arrangement, the rich share their wealth, and the
poor share their poverty.)
This is a subject which has been, and is still being, thoroughly
critiqued by socialist feminist and radical queer scholars and activists. Health care, immigration, taxation, housing access, child custody, and welfare—these benefits of marriage are material concerns,
and taking workers’ councils to task for failing to push for bourgeois
marriage completely misses the point. Comrade Thompson’s seeming
ignorance of this entire aspect of radical politics is troubling, to say
the least.
Between Gospel and Church
●
147
Far more egregious than the Seattle uprising or Hegemony and
Socialist Strategyy, Thompson has somehow managed to completely
ignore the ultimate goal of a radically restructured society, one in
which I believe it is almost unanimously understood that marriage
must be exculpated of its relationship to capital. This is not some
libertine cultural preaching for the evisceration of monogamy, but
when the inability to enforce an alienating institution of capitalism
in our most intimate family spheres is seen as evidence of inefficacy,
one has to question how well versed the speaker is in radical politics
outside his own.
(It’s worth mentioning that I’m somewhat sympathetic to the idea
of workers’ councils, while still remaining critical, especially in a
global economy where industrial factories are emerging in rural areas
of the developing world. I focus on them here not because I am particularly passionate about them, but because I see them as an example
of something being prematurely harshly dismissed. However, I can
find much more compelling criticisms of workers’ councils than their
imagined lack of support for something as procapitalist in institutional history as marriage.)
Now, I have been married, and I will probably be married again
(and then, maybe a few times after that—I like to keep busy), but
one need not be one of Thompson’s feared “anti-statists” to recognize that the legal (mostly economic) benefits of marriage should be
rights, and not privileges, and should not be granted on the basis
of state-authorized couplehood. The generally benevolent yet highly
liberal crusade for gay marriage is not inherently damagingg to queer
people, but when a radical organization (or political arrangement) is
criticized for (conceivably) not pushing for a liberal goal, I am forced
to ask what gay marriage will do for homeless queer youth or the
HIV-positive. Thompson’s reference to gay marriage represents an
extremely problematic ignorance of very rudimentary socialist feminism and/or radical queer theory.
Moreover, the very subject matter of the discussion lends itself to a
fairly scathing critique of marriage. Given Luxemburg’s own romantic history, it seems so little of a stretch to skew a bit vulgar-Marxist
when it comes to romantic love and prioritization of the material over
something as odd (and hopefully someday anachronistic) as state recognition of romantic love. In light of Luxemburg’s legal marriage to
148
●
Amber Frost
Gustav Lübeck for citizenship, and her simultaneous romance with
Leo Jogiches, marriage as a legal entity is ripe for critique in this
context—something Luxemburg navigated in spite off her feelings,
not according to them.
In Luxemburg’s love letters (which, given my leisurely literary
inclinations over my analytical/theoretical ones, I have read far more
? she says, in
diligently than What Does the Spartacus League Want?),
regards to her own affairs, “If I feel by intuition that he doesn’t love
me anymore, I will immediately fly away like a stricken bird.” This
romantic notion of cut-and-dried divorce flies in the face of institutional state marriage, which simply has no radical potential.
Thompson continues this troublingly rigid defense of state institutions, saying “To advocate workers’ councils and see the state as
nothing more than a tool of the interests of capital is to simultaneously emasculatee the very power socialism would have at its disposal
to work against the effects and tendencies of capital.” (The emphasis
is mine.)
I am not an anarchist, but socialists must engage in critiques of
the state, and it’s absurdly reactionary to maintain that harsh assessments of certain state powers are inherently “anti-statist.” To argue
that “emasculation” (an incredibly telling choice of words for a writer
who just prior reified marriage as a fundament of queer liberation) is
the risk presented by these sorts of arguments implies a threat that
is simply not there. This is a sort of stagnant, out-of-touch Marxist
castration anxiety I find all too common.
It’s important to continually refine and reassert the ideological differences between anticapitalist anarchists and socialists, but Thompson
appears to have visualized an anarchist “threat,” which I simply don’t
see. Even when Occupy Wall Street spewed forth an odd sort of (sometimes self-identified) anarcho-Leninist vanguard of its own (often to
incredibly effective ends), its potential menace to a socialist movement
is minimal—being paranoid over a group more marginal than our
own feels a bit absurd in an America with no mass radical movement.
* *
*
Thompson’s misidentification of radical premises and refusal of
engagement is the largest of the problems I seek to address. The
Between Gospel and Church
●
149
tendency to apply a legacy to current events in the hopes of illuminating the work (Bronner), and the tendency to invoke insular, trollish
academic trends as defilers of that legacy (Johnson), actually leave
us with very little to apply to our own lives and discussions, but I
find these penchants correctable with more consistent engagement
with the historical trajectory of movement building. Bronner and
Johnson veer, but they don’t abandon the original work or dismiss
the present.
Truly, I find Bronner’s proof-in-the-pudding approach incredibly admirable, and I think there’s a reason his essay elicited such
a response; canonization is a pitfall of leftist thought, and it takes
a commitment to praxis over rigid doctrine (one that apparently
labels one a post-Marxist pariah in some cases) to relevantly utilize
the work of a great mind like Rosa Luxemburg. His contention that
“the political moment must take priority over the economic moment
of analysis” has simply rendered him a little vulnerable to the au
courantt.
It is intellectually unfair, of course, to dismiss Bronner as nonanalytical when I have had a greater distance of hindsight, plus a similar
moment in Occupy, to declare his evaluation as obviously starry-eyed,
but this is simply the nature of discussing a ten-plus-year-old text that
attempted to divine the trajectory of a political moment. (I’m quite
sure I could do no better, and prefer to safely declare misjudgment
after the fact.) Likewise it is unfair to completely ignore Johnson’s
“post-Marxist” concerns as insular or paranoid—one can never truly
predict the trends of thought, and I admire his vigilance against the
dilution or perversion of our Marxism.
When we attempt to tackle concrete subject matter, applying theory
to our political moment, we have tendencies toward myopia and magnified memories. If one wants anecdotes of leftists doing this outside the academy, ask how many times I’ve carried a DSA banner
and been personally accused of hurling Luxemburg’s body into the
Landwehr Canal, myself. At the risk of folksiness, in my own evangelical Christian cultural context, the obstacles I identify (relevance
and praxis) are neatly summed up in the perpetual political question:
What is gospel, and what is merely “church?”
I have the utmost confidence in socialists’ ability to navigate these
habits and improve our discourse, especially as projects like this one
150
●
Amber Frost
continue to revisit and reinvigorate long-standing discussions, with
comradely good faith.
Note
1. Raymond Williams, Culture and Materialism: Selected Essayss (London:
Verso, 2006), p. 238.
CHAPTER 10
Where Do We Go from Here?
Rosa Luxemburg and the Crisis of
Democratic Capitalism
Chris Maisano
F
ive years into a global economic crisis that shows no sign of
abating, it’s become plainly obvious that the uneasy marriage
between capitalism and liberal democracy has been effectively
annulled. Citizenries throughout the world are outraged by increasing
inequality, unemployment, and poverty, but the political elites of the
established parties (from nominally center-left or Social Democratic
parties as well as the conservatives) have shown little interest in or
ability to respond effectively to their wishes. If anything, elites have
used the crisis as an opportunity to attack the last vestiges of the welfare state and the labor movement, pushing a politics of austerity that
further instantiates its insidious, self-reinforcing logic. From an elite
perspective, what state of affairs could possibly be better? Particularly
when the Left and the labor movement in almost every nation affected
by the crisis have shown themselves completely unable to mount effective opposition to these policies.
As Wolfgang Streeck has argued, democratic capitalism is a highly
unstable political-economic formation defined by an internal contradiction between two different principles of resource allocation.1 On the
one hand is the market’s desire for unimpeded capital accumulation,
152
●
Chris Maisano
and on the other is the demand for social entitlements and collective
goods placed on the state by democratic publics. In normal times,
these two tendencies exist in a state of tension, and while the demands
of the market tend to outweigh those of the people, democratic publics
are still typically able to defend important aspects of previous social,
economic, and political victories. This has been true even in the era
of neoliberalism, which has eroded but not completely dismantled the
welfare states of the advanced capitalist countries. But by the time
the current crisis hit in 2007–08, three decades of neoliberalism had
significantly fractured the social base of the labor movement and the
Left. Instead of providing a new opening for anticapitalist politics,
the crisis has (at least thus far) strengthened the hand of those forces
intent on restricting the scope of politics and enshrining the market
as the unquestioned regulative ideal of public life.
In country after country, we witness the ugly spectacle of the banks
and bond markets riding roughshod over the supposedly inviolable
principle of popular sovereignty. Over the course of the crisis, whenever democracy has threatened to challenge the market’s imperial
prerogatives, it is democracy that is consistently preempted. Greece
was the canary in the coalmine. In late 2011, then prime minister
George Papandreou moved to subject the European Union bailout
deal to a popular referendum. For this heresy he was promptly forced
out of power and replaced by a technocratic government led by neoliberal economists. At the same time a similar scenario unfolded in
Italy, where Silvio Berlusconi’s resignation paved the way for the
installation of a technocratic government with the economist Mario
Monti as prime minister. His program of tax increases, spending
cuts, and neoliberal labor market policies enraged Italians but earned
the confidence of international investors, who praised him as the
man who saved Italy from itself. Monti and his jerry-rigged party
were soundly defeated in the February 2013 elections, but when he
arrived as Italy’s representative at an EU summit meeting weeks later,
the assembled dignitaries welcomed him as something of a conquering hero, all but crowning him with a wreath of laurels as a Caesar
of neoliberalism.
The story is much the same across Europe and North America.
Politicians of all stripes are denounced as liars and thieves, electoral
turmoil ejects long-dominant parties from power, populist political
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
153
movements spring up at the margins—but the underlying arrangements remain in place much the same as before. In France, François
Hollande and the Socialists rode a wave of popular discontent into
the Elysée Palace for only the second time in the history of the Fifth
Republic. Hollande campaigned on a promise to hike taxes on the
rich and attack the power of finance, but his tax plan has failed and
his major legislative accomplishment has been the implementation of
a neoliberal “competitiveness pact” over the objections of the country’s most militant trade unions. In Italy, Monti has been ejected
from power but the broad Left completely abdicated its responsibility to present a coherent alternative to his program. The bellowing
comedian Beppe Grillo and his populist Five Star Movement stepped
into the breach, claiming the largest share of the votes and preventing
the formation of a new government. The Grand Coalition of centerleft and center-right parties that ultimately formed a government has
presided over a record-high jobless rate of 12.2 percent, with youth
unemployment also at an apex of 40.1 percent.2 In Germany and the
United Kingdom, the Left remains weak, divided, and marginalized,
and the return of either the Social Democrats or the Labor Party to
government would do little to undo the austerity programs of their
conservative counterparts. In Spain, where unemployment has reached
obscene levels, the only major challenge to the politics of austerity
has expressed itself in the form of a regional separatist movement in
wealthy Catalonia, not the articulation of a socialist alternative. In
the United States, popular opposition to austerity is widespread but
Democrats and Republicans, despite the bloodcurdling rhetoric and
ritual performances of extreme partisan polarization, differ mainly
over how far and how fast to implement welfare cuts. Recent opinion polls have shown Congress to be less popular than head lice and
venereal disease; in some polls, more Americans viewed the idea of
the country going Communist more favorably than the current lot of
mouth-breathers and bagmen who comprise that august body. Yet the
band plays on.
To be sure, the political conjuncture is not uniformly bleak.
Oppositional movements that carry the potential to build toward
a larger challenge to the system as a whole have sprung up across
the advanced capitalist countries. In Europe, we’ve seen SYRIZA
(Coalition of the Radical Left—Unitary Social Front) move from
154
●
Chris Maisano
the margins to the center of Greek politics as the postdictatorship
party system continues to disintegrate; the emergence of the Front
de Gauche in France, where Jean-Luc Mélenchon mounted a spirited
challenge to austerity politics in last year’s presidential campaign; the
surprising popular appeal of the Socialist Party in the Netherlands,
which polled strongly in the lead-up to recent parliamentary elections; and the enthusiastic response in the United Kingdom to a call
for a new leftist party to challenge not just the Conservative-Liberal
Democrat coalition government but the moribund Labor Party as
well. These electoral efforts have drawn strength from extraparliamentary movements demanding not just an end to austerity but an
entirely different way of doing politics, exemplified by the “movement of the squares” in Greece and the Spanish indignados.
s In the
United States, the crisis has not been so acute as to provoke ruptures
or realignments within the electoral system, but street-level resistance
to austerity has been widespread. The mass uprising in Wisconsin
against Governor Scott Walker’s attacks on labor rights was the dress
rehearsal for Occupy Wall Street, which spread like wildfire from
lower Manhattan to cities and towns around the country in late 2011
and 2012. These upsurges have even imbued certain sections of the
US labor movement with a fighting spirit that’s found expression in
national campaigns like OUR Walmart and recent strikes by fastfood workers in New York City.
To date, these movements have tended to reject parties, representation, and the state in totoo. The indignados,
s Occupiers, and others
have instead sought to instantiate direct forms of popular deliberation and action that operate completely outside existing structures
and seek to prefigure the new society in their internal organizational
practices. This should not be surprising. People today have very little
control over anything that happens in their lives. They feel like playthings of powerful forces that are not subject to even a modicum of
democratic accountability or control. This is what accounts for the
relentless focus of movements like Occupy on process and consensus.
In these spaces, where every issue or problem is hashed out to everyone’s satisfaction—or at least to the point where everyone will come
to accept what has been proposed—people gain a sense of agency.
This is why Occupy and its analogues have assiduously avoided establishing specific programs or demands, because doing so necessarily
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
155
assumes engagement with the state and other institutions that make
people feel like they have no power.
In their total rejection of the current mode of doing politics, the
partisans of “horizontalism” see clearly, but with only one eye. These
recent years have witnessed a remarkable degree of social ferment,
but these disparate protests have yet to translate into a long-term
project capable of harnessing power and building political capacities
for sustainable challenge to the rule of capital. The current ebbing
of Occupy’s fortunes, while disheartening, presents us with a crucial
opportunity to engage in critical reflection and analysis of where we
have been and where we might go from here.
*
*
*
Strangely enough, an esoteric debate over a long-dead Polish revolutionary that unfolded in the pages of New Politicss over a decade
ago seems like a fairly good place to start. In his 2001 essay “Red
Dreams and the New Millennium: Notes on the Legacy of Rosa
Luxemburg,” Stephen Eric Bronner employs his particular interpretation of Luxemburg’s theory and practice as a heuristic device to
approach the major issues of the day: globalization and its discontents, climate change, and the acrimonious intra-left debate over the
question of “humanitarian intervention.” This short piece inspired a
torrent of responses from a number of figures on the intellectual Left,
and while much of the debate concerned itself with exegetical questions over the appropriate understanding of Luxemburg’s thought
(and the intellectual legacy of Marxism generally), it anticipated a
number of contemporary controversies over which strategies, tactics,
and modes of organization the radical Left should employ to confront
the crisis of democratic capitalism.
The debate covered a wide range of issues in the field of Marxist
thought. For my purposes here, however, I’m particularly interested
in arguments over the state, the efficacy of workers’ councils, and
the problems of representation and leadership in revolutionary movements. Broadly speaking, we encounter two conflicting approaches
to these issues, with Bronner and Michael Thompson arguing for an
approach that appreciates the potentially liberatory qualities of the
republican state and gradualist programs of radical reform, and Alan
156
●
Chris Maisano
Johnson, David Camfield, Paul Le Blanc, and Barry Finger defending
a revolutionary councilist tradition that seeks to overthrow the republican state and replace it with a network of direct organs of popular
power.
On my reading, Bronner and Thompson clearly got the better of
the debate. As Bronner argues, historical experiments with alternative
forms of organization tend to indicate that workers’ councils cannot
either “deal with a complex economy or guarantee civil liberties,” and
that the administrative and coercive powers of some sort of state will
be required to radically transform the basic structures of the political
economy. It’s incredibly difficult to imagine a network of workers’
councils with the capacity to direct the conversion to a green economy
or take the financial system into public ownership, both of which
would require not just the repression of those who would fight such
measures but the application of technical expertise on a fairly massive scale. And as Thompson points out (following the critique by the
Austro-Marxists), workers’ councils were “insufficient to produce a
fully realized political democracy since they were composed of only
one strata of society.” While capitalist states are certainly guilty of
privileging the economic interests of the capitalist class over the common good, it’s not inevitable that states per see must fall victim to this
trap. Instead, socialists should work to privilege the political over the
economic and to fight for a republican state based on “the promotion
of the general interest at the expense of particular interest.”
I share the Bronner-Thompson conception of socialism as a living,
breathing movement that seeks to bring the future into the present
through what Ralph Miliband and Marcel Liebman called “revolutionary reformism.”3 But I agree with Bronner’s critics that he goes
too far to argue that “the institutional goal of the revolution initially
sought by Luxemburg, in short, has been realized.” The virtues of the
liberal republican state, such as they are, are hollowed out and vitiated
by the brutal realities of capitalist class power. The crisis of representation in ostensibly democratic and republican states demonstrates this
conclusively. The historical project of democracy still remains to be
completed within the framework of the republican state. We need a
different kind of state, a reallyy democratic republic.
Bronner concedes the point when he reminds himself that he had
previously called for the establishment of “‘secondary’ or ‘associative’
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
157
organizations that might provide a more direct form of democracy”
within the overall framework of a radically democratized republican
state. This is where the seemingly esoteric argument over councils
and republics becomes relevant to socialists and radicals in the age
of Occupy, where organizational questions of “horizontalism” and
“verticalism” have come to the fore. It’s also one of the places where
Luxemburg’s theoretical and practical legacy proves to be highly valuable to contemporary activists. Contrary to misconceptions propagated by Hannah Arendt and others, Luxemburg was not a one-sided
advocate of spontaneity and direct action against organization and
party. She spent most of her life engaged in the struggle to build
a revolutionary party and fully accepted the need for political representation, leadership, and discipline. In her writing and her organizational work, she strove to integrate those two perspectives—not
entirely successfully, but the attempt is an important part of her legacy. It’s a useful vantage point from which to assess the strengths and
weaknesses of Occupy and to formulate political strategies that might
point a way out of the crisis of democratic capitalism.
*
*
*
The media was quick to anoint David Graeber as Occupy’s leading
theoretician, but I would argue that that honor rightfully belongs to
Marina Sitrin. For years, she has articulated the theory and practice
of “horizontalism” that permeated Occupy’s various encampments.
After the breakup of the Zuccotti Park encampment, Sitrin participated in a symposium on the state of the contemporary US Left in
the pages of Dissentt. In a critique of Michael Kazin’s plea for the new
radicals to articulate a clear vision of a new society and a program
for how we might obtain it, Sitrin offers a concise statement of the
horizontalist rejection of demands, representation, program, and the
party form.4
I was willing to give this perspective a hearing during Occupy’s
early days, particularly because it seemed as if its adherents had succeeded where those of us on the socialist Left had failed, and miserably at that. Almost two years later, however, it seems curiously out of
touch. Sitrin’s vindication of horizontalism neatly captures a number
of weaknesses in its basic orientation that hindered the transformation
158
●
Chris Maisano
of Occupy into a political force capable of winning power for the
99%. Here I want to focus on three of them: the false dichotomy
between direct and representative democracy; the false opposition of
“bad” state versus “good” society; and the confusion of organization
and leadership with domination.
Democracy Is Direct and Representative
The fact that Occupy spoke first and foremost to the crisis of representation is probably the main reason why its message resonated
beyond the ranks of the perennial activists. All of the institutions
of contemporary society systematically deny those subject to them a
chance to articulate their interests, needs, or concerns. The fact that
the various encampments offered people a space in which to just speak
their minds, interminably if they wanted to, satisfied a widespread
need to be heard in public in a direct, unmediated fashion. This was
one of the most positive and liberating aspects of the encampments,
and Occupy suffered dramatically from their loss.
Where Sitrin and the horizontalists generally go astray is their construction of a false dichotomy between representative and direct forms
of democracy, as if they were mutually exclusive and couldn’t possibly
coexist within a single institutional space. In the many conversations
I had in Zuccotti Park and elsewhere, I found that the concept had
become an article of faith that prevented Occupy from addressing the
myriad weaknesses of its process. There was very little discussion of
the ways in which it frustrated the process of collective will formation,
particularly when the aspirations of a segment of the occupation ran
afoul of the tightly knit cadre group running things behind the scenes.
Any suggestion that the occupation might consider adopting certain
structures of representation or delegation opened one to denunciation
and charges of bad faith.
There’s no logical or practical reason why organs of direct democracy can’t be inscribed within a larger institutional configuration
that allows for representation and delegation at broader geographical levels or in policy areas that require a certain degree of technical expertise. This has been a perennial aspiration of revolutionary
movements in the modern era, which have typically sought to replace
the capitalist state with a commune of communes. This is the sort of
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
159
approach that seeks the establishment of what Staughton Lynd, in his
unjustly neglected book Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism,
calls “bicameralism from below.” Such a configuration would be
defined by a relationship of constructive tension in which representative structures are continually checked by autonomous organs of
direct popular participation and control.5 This strikes me as the only
reasonable approach to thinking about charting a way out of the crisis of representation and building new and truly democratic political
institutions.
Bad State/Good Society
The state has always been an object of fear and vilification in the
American political imagination, and the US Left has never really
occupied a space outside of this ideological consensus. Opposed to
the pernicious state is civil society, a virtuous realm of free association
untainted by the machinations of power or interest. So it’s no surprise that the horizontalist vision as articulated by Sitrin and others
has resonated so strongly in the contemporary US radical milieu. In
many ways, it represents a recrudescence of some of the most problematic aspects of the global justice movement, whose “activistism” was
grounded in a moral discourse that cast the state in one-dimensional
(i.e., repressive and authoritarian) terms.6
Sitrin sounds the refrain that has become so familiar in recent
years:
The point of reference of the movements is not the state or politics
conventionally defined. There is no desire to take over the state or
to create a new party . . . democracy is the crux of Occupy politics,
and democracy practiced in such a way so as to upend vertical
political relationships and expand horizontal ones . . . The question
for the future is not how to create a plan for what a better country will look like, but how to deepen and broaden the assemblies
taking place and how to enhance participatory democracy in the
process.7
The horizontalist rejection of the state in its current form is an impulse
that I share. But in completely rejecting engagement with state power,
160
●
Chris Maisano
e one that
horizontalists fail to grasp that another kind of state is possible,
allows for a significant amount of space for popular participation in
policy making and public administration. Recall the argument made
by Marx in his “Critique of the Gotha Programme,” in which he
reminded his erstwhile comrades in the German socialist movement
that “freedom consists in converting the state from an organ superimposed upon society into one completely subordinate to it.”8 Not only
is such a socialization of the state possible, it’s necessary. If we are to
adequately confront our overlapping social and ecological crises, the
task will no doubt require a significant mobilization of state power to
reshape production, investment, and social relations both nationally
and globally. Simply put, by rejecting the state in totoo, we leave the
most powerful institution in our society uncontested, leaving it safely
in the hands of the 1%.
Arendt or Luxemburg?
One of the chief ironies of Occupy’s encampment phase was that its
effectiveness was often attributed to its putative horizontalism. In
reality, this demonstrated the absolute need for a living movement
to have some sort of centralized, institutionall space to tie together its
disparate currents and tendencies. The encampments gave the movement an address and made it relatively easy for new recruits to rally to
the cause and maintain their attachments once they had done so.
In many ways, the encampments were a substitute for a prefiguration of the new kind of partyy we want to build: a broad formation that
allows for radicals of different persuasions to come together in a pluralistic and egalitarian institutional space. The encampments pointed
the way toward a new kind of organizational model that might allow
us to meld the horizontal with the vertical, to create an institutional
space that encourages the creation of a pluralistic and egalitarian
internal culture with a greater sense of common purpose and action.
The problem with the encampments was that they were strictly identified with specific patches of ground. Once the police decided they
had seen enough, those spaces were broken up and the processes they
engendered had no way to sustain themselves.
On the vexed question of organization and leadership, the present
moment leaves us with a choice: Will we be the followers of Hannah
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
161
Arendt or Rosa Luxemburg? Although many people in and around
Occupy characterized it as the latest instantiation of the anarchist
impulse, Arendt was the unacknowledged presiding spirit of Zuccotti
Park. The argument she advances in her classic work On Revolution
will sound familiar to anyone who was involved with Occupy.
According to Arendt, modern politics has become an instrumentalist
project devoted primarily to protecting the power and privileges of
interest groups and state bureaucrats. It closes off nearly all avenues
for popular participation and substitutes the expertise of elite technicians and party politicians for the direct action of the people. Arendt
also denounces the centrality of the “social question” in modern politics, because the intense conflicts that inevitably follow from it threatens her idealized, autonomous political space that she wished to keep
untainted by considerations of social or economic interests. But in
evacuating the social question from the political sphere, Arendt drains
politics of much of its substance and turns it into little more than a
forum for speech making and other modes of public performance, a
kind of public theater where one’s virtue is judged by others who are
similarly free from the need to go to work or do much of anything
else. Inevitably, political life becomes the province of a self-selected
hard core of actors, to the exclusion of those who can’t devote all their
time to politics.9
The similarities to the dynamic that prevailed in Zuccotti Park and
elsewhere should be immediately apparent. Arendt’s embrace of the
popular organs of the revolutionary tradition, from the various “societies” that sprung up during the radical phase of the French Revolution,
to Thomas Jefferson’s republic of wards, to the Paris Commune, the
r tee, is certainly admirable. But like
Russian soviets, and the German rä
the horizontalists of today, she makes a too-strict dichotomy between
these organizational forms and structures of leadership and representation, particularly the party.
Ironically, Arendt holds up Rosa Luxemburg as a leading avatar
of her preferred revolutionary tradition. This move is ironic because
Luxemburg, perhaps more than any other figure in the history of the
Left, understood the necessity of combining the horizontal and the
vertical, spontaneity and organization, mass movement and party.
Luxemburg is often mistakenly cast as an unalloyed devotee of
spontaneity, direct action, and insurrection. It’s certainly true that she
162
●
Chris Maisano
often spoke eloquently of the power of direct, unmediated expressions
of popular power, and this tendency constitutes an important aspect
of her political thought. But a close reading of her work, particularly
her classic pamphlet “The Mass Strike,” shows that Luxemburg sought
to encourage the construction of a more complex dynamic in the
internal organization of a revolutionary movement. For Luxemburg,
spontaneity, direct action, and mass participation are effective insofar as they further the project of building durable forms of political
organization capable of exercising leadership over the movement as a
whole.10
Horizontalism and verticalism, spontaneity and organization,
egalitarianism and leadership were not mutually exclusive categories
for Luxemburg. Properly understood, these dynamics should be put
into mutually constitutive relationships that could guide the development of a movement capable of challenging the combined forces of
the bourgeois state and capital. As Luxemburg observed, the chaotic,
spontaneous mass strikes that broke out across Russia during the years
leading up to the revolution of 1905 were “the starting point of a
feverish work of organization . . . from the whirlwind and the storm,
out of the fire and glow of the mass strike and the street fighting rise
again, like Venus from the foam, fresh, young, powerful, buoyant
trade unions.”11
Most of these strikes began as localized and rather limited struggles over wages and working conditions, but they developed (in conjunction with the agitational work of socialist parties) into general
confrontations with the ruling class. The parallels with the most successful movements in Europe and North America since the onset of
the crisis—the rise of SYRIZA in Greece and the Québec student
strike against higher education tuition hikes—are clear. By raising a set of seemingly limited and “reformist” demands that seek to
address the dire situation confronting their country, SYRIZA has
managed to attract growing numbers of Greek workers to their party
and put them on the verge of forming a government in the next election. CLASSE (the coalition of student unions that spearheaded the
struggle in Québec) began its campaign by raising relatively limited
demands around the question of education, but as it escalated its tactics, it managed to fashion a fully fledged social movement involving
many other sectors of the population, particularly in Montréal.
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
163
Both SYRIZA and CLASSE appear to have built unusually democratic and pluralistic institutional cultures, which has played no small
part in allowing them to establish legitimacy as the leading organizations in their respective movements. SYRIZA is a coalition of radical
left political formations from a diverse array of traditions ranging from
Eurocommunism to Maoism to Trotskyism to radical ecology. The
party makes its decisions on the basis of consensus, allowing member
parties to maintain a degree of autonomy while facilitating unity in
action. It has grounded itself in social struggles while also engaging in
electoral activity, making it practically the only Greek political formation that has any legitimacy in the eyes of the popular movements.12
In Québec, CLASSE was a loose coalition of student organizations with varying political orientations and traditions of militancy.
Initiated by ASSÉ , traditionally the most militant student union in
the province, CLASSE engaged in a painstaking project of education,
agitation, and outreach weeks and months leading up to the strike.
This work allowed CLASSE to pursue a militant strategy while maintaining the continued adherence of more moderate organizations and
individuals to the broader movement. The student movement also
adopted the general assembly as its basic unit of decision making, but
unlike Occupy’s chaotic and often impotent assemblies, theirs were
structured to allow for both mass participation and decisiveness in
action. Québec student leader Jérémie Bédard-Wien describes how
the strike’s assemblies worked:
It’s about getting people into the same space, and that space is
nothing like Occupy Wall Street general assemblies. It’s extremely
formalized. Every member of the union has the right to vote, to
propose motions, and to speak during those general assemblies, but
that’s it. Non-members do not even have the right to speak. There
is a chair, there is a note-taker, it’s all regulated by a very formal
code of procedures and the association’s bylaws. It’s very hard to
chair one of these meetings, you need to know the rules very well.
You have to keep order, and so on. And votes are taken for the most
part by majority. The strike was taken by majority, there was no
consensus. Consensus is not really democratic—it allows a small
group of people to block the process for hours on end if they want
to, and you cannot vote a strike by consensus, obviously.13
164
●
Chris Maisano
While Occupy has hitherto chosen to follow in the footsteps of Arendt,
SYRIZA and CLASSE have followed the example of Luxemburg.
Even accounting for the vast differences in political institutions and
political culture between Greece, Québec, and the United States, the
relative effectiveness of each approach seems immediately apparent.
SYRIZA and Québec students are moving forward while US radicals
are stuck trying to figure out why Occupy stalled, or explaining how
the energies unleashed in the course of the Wisconsin uprising gave
way to defeat, demobilization, and despair.
* *
*
It was always strange to me that Occupy adopted the name that it did.
I can’t think of many other social movements in history that named
themselves after their signature tactic rather than their social base or
their vision for a new society. The call for a “general strike” on May 1,
2012, unconnected to any particular social struggle or political campaign, brought to mind Luxemburg’s perplexity at the tendency of
certain militants to put tactics above strategy, process above program.
As she wrote in “The Mass Strike,”
It is just as impossible to “propagate” the mass strike as an abstract
means of struggle as it is to propagate the “revolution.” “Revolution”
like “mass strike” signifies nothing but an external form of the class
struggle, which can have sense and meaning only in connection
with definite political situations . . . If anyone were to undertake to
make the mass strike generally, as a form of proletarian action, the
object of methodological agitation, and to go house to house canvassing with this “idea” in order to gradually win the working class
to it, it would be as idle and profitless and absurd an occupation as
it would be to seek to make the idea of the revolution or of the fight
at the barricades the object of a special agitation.14
Occupy was correct in rejecting the one-off symbolic action and
adopting an ongoing, open-ended struggle as its basic tactic. But
because this tactic wasn’t part of a larger strategy grounded in a specific social struggle with clear demands, the loss of the encampments
meant the end of the activity. Occupy’s “if you build it, they will
Where Do We Go from Here?
●
165
come” approach to political activity succeeded brilliantly in jumpstarting a movement where everyone else had failed, but it wasn’t able
to sustain itself over the course of even a few months.
I close by turning once again to Luxemburg, whose keen grasp of
the dynamics of popular movements is deeply relevant to our time.
“Occupy” does not (or should not) signify a specific encampment or
even a specific tactic to be used in the course of mass struggle. As
Luxemburg observed, “It is absurd to think of the mass strike as one
act, one isolated action. The mass strike is rather the indication, the
rallying idea, of a whole period of the class struggle lasting for years,
perhaps for decades.”15
Change the phrase “mass strike” to “occupation,” and it becomes
difficult to determine whether these words were written in 1906 or
2013. The interlocking political, economic, and social dynamics that
summoned the occupations into existence and fueled the movement’s
grievances will not, and cannot, be solved within the parameters of the
present state of affairs. The cause of the 99% is the rallying point for a
generation, a movement worthy of our commitment, our struggle, and
even our joy. Our problems aren’t going away anytime soon. What’s
needed now is a refoundation of the Occupy movement in the light
of our weaknesses and the lessons taught by those who came before
us. The rich intellectual and practical legacy of Rosa Luxemburg is an
excellent place from which to begin again.
Notes
1. Wolfgang Streeck, “The Crises of Democratic Capitalism,” New Left Review
Vol. 71 (Sept.-Oct. 2011), pp. 5–29.
2. “Italy’s PM faces confidence vote,” Al Jazeera English, October 2, 2013,
http://www.aljazeera.com/news/europe/2013/10/italy-pm-faces-confi
dence-vote-201310273549447697.-html (accessed October 2, 2013).
3. Ralph Miliband and Marcel Liebman, “Beyond Social Democracy,” in
Socialist Register 1985/86,
6 ed. Ralph Miliband et. al. (Pontypool: Merlin
Press, 1985), pp. 476–89.
4. See Marina Sitrin, “Horizontalism and the Occupy Movements,” Dissent,
http://www.dissentmagazine.org/article/horizontalism-and-the-occupy
-movements (accessed April 7, 2013). Michael Kazin, “The Fall and Rise
of the U.S. Populist Left,” Dissent, http://www.dissentmagazine.org/article
/the-fall-and-rise-of-the-u-s-populist-left (accessed April 7, 2013).
166
●
Chris Maisano
5. Staughton Lynd, Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism (New York:
Pantheon, 1968), p. 171.
6. Liza Featherstone, Doug Henwood, and Christian Parenti, “‘Action Will
Be Taken: Left Anti-Intellectualism and Its Discontents,” Left Business
Observerr, http://www.leftbusinessobserver.com/Action.html (accessed
April 8, 2013).
7. Sitrin, “Horizontalism and the Occupy Movements.”
8. Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programmee (1875), http://www.marxists
.org/-archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/ch04.htm (accessed April 8, 2013).
9. Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (New York: Penguin, 2006). My reading
of Arendt’s politics is heavily indebted to the critique advanced by Joseph
Schwartz. See Joseph M. Schwartz, The Permanence of the Political: A
Democratic Critique of the Radical Impulse to Transcend Politicss (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), pp. 189–216.
10. “If, however, the direction of the mass strike in the sense of command over
its origin, and in the sense of the calculating and reckoning of the cost, is
a matter of the revolutionary period itself, the directing of the mass strike
becomes, in an altogether different sense, the duty of social democracy and
its leading organs. Instead of puzzling their heads with the technical side,
with the mechanism, of the mass strike, the social democrats are called upon
to assume political leadership in the midst of the revolutionary period.” Rosa
Luxemburg, “The Mass Strike,” in The Essential Rosa Luxemburg: Reform
or Revolution and The Mass Strikee, ed. Helen Scott (Chicago: Haymarket
Books, 2007), p. 149.
11. Ibid., pp. 134–35.
12. Antonis Davanellos, “Where Did SYRIZA Come From?” Socialist Worker,
r
May 17, 2012, http://socialistworker.org/2012/05/17/where-did-syriza-come
-from (accessed April 7, 2013).
13. Matt Porter and Maria Svart, “Québec Students Strike for Free Higher
t
Education: An Interview with Jérémie Bédard-Wien,” Democratic Left,
March 4, 2013, http://www.dsausa.org/quebec_students_strike (accessed
April 7, 2013).
14. Luxemburg, “The Mass Strike,” p. 118.
15. Ibid., p. 141.
CHAPTER 11
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg and
Working-Class Revolution
Michael Hirsch
M
y introduction to Rosa Luxemburg was familial. Readying
for a late soiree, I wore what was then late-teen de rigueur:
a sweatshirt, pea jacket, jeans, and boots. My father, a
German Social Democrat in his youth—more for the party’s wraparound social and cultural services than its particular ideology—
asked me if I was going out to meet Rosa Luxemburg. I didn’t know
who that was, but she sounded good.
She still sounds good.
Dad was an 11-year-old living in Germany when the murdered
Luxemburg’s corpse was fished out of Berlin’s Landwehr canal. He
was a 26-year-old exile when her remains were removed by the Nazis
from the Friedrichsfelde Cemetery. Too young in 1919 for him to
actually know much about the living Luxemburg or the comrades of
the German Revolution, it was Karl Liebknecht’s name and hers that
meant something honorable to his family and the millions like them
living in Berlin’s working-class districts, where support for socialists
of all factions was as common as breath.
Actress Barbara Sukowa, who played Luxemburg in the eponymous 1986 film, said of her that “Rosa was different from the characters I usually play—probably the only woman I’ve played who is not
168
●
Michael Hirsch
neurotic.” Director Margarethe von Trotta called her “the first victim
of National Socialism,”1 an apt observation.
Luxemburg, like Lenin, was an active revolutionary, attuned to
the flow of actual contemporary movements. Marx and Engels by
contrast were relatively shielded from the sensuous activities of real
social forces. The Communist Manifesto was written even before the
continent-wide eruptions of 1848; only Engels lived to see the end of
a decades-long recession, the first giant steps of Britain’s industrial
unions, and the explosion of support for socialism in Germany and
elsewhere, if not yet the imperial battles over colonies that led to the
First World War.
As Perry Anderson notes, neither Marx nor Engels “had bequeathed
any comparable corpus [to their work in political economy] of concepts
for the political strategy and tactics of the proletarian revolution.”2
That was Lenin’s genius. So even if Engels could write in the 1890
forward to the Manifestoo, quoting a leading trade union leader that
“‘Continental Socialism has lost its terrors for us”3 and with continental socialism recognizably Marxist in word if not always in deed,
it was also narrowly and not effectively political in the sense of connecting economic struggles to actual or potential offensives against
the state. Its ample social and cultural services were not a substitute
for agitation.
Luxemburg’s strengths lay in viewing history as an interactive process, not a dislocated series of events. She understood, long before
Edward Thompson, that social classes were relationships and not
categories or things. Luxemburg, with her long view that working
people had to be prepared—not just persuaded or anxious—to rule,
is an enigma for those conditioned to think revolutions are made by
clusters of dedicated operatives, rather than as an expression of a class
in formation evolving in experience, consciousness, collective action,
and social conditions.
Lenin is problematic if only read as the apostle of cadre efficiency
and professional revolutionaries indispensible in building a New
Jerusalem. While Lenin wrote in Left-Wing Communism: An Infantile
Disorderr that “the masses must have their own political experience,””4
that’s not the Lenin—fairly or unfairly—who was handed down to
posterity. Yet Luxemburg’s attraction to those of my New Left generation wasn’t just as an elective affinity for an intellectually vibrant,
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
169
singular, doomed individual; it was also in who she wasn’t. She wasn’t
the much abused Lenin, whom we accepted as the arch conspirator,
hypercentralist, veteran character assassin, ground-preparer for Stalin,
and a political strategist rarely appreciated by any but moist-eyed
sect acolytes. Lenin was a “hard” who would avoid musical concerts
because it made him “soft,” while Luxemburg, as her letters make
clear, was a fully formed person who could smell the bread laborers
baked and the roses grown at leisure. It was Luxemburg’s declaration
at the founding of the German Communist Party that “activity itself
educates the masses” that was a cardinal New Left principle.
As bodies grew older, passions cooler, and reading wider, we came
to know these takes were overly simple if not grossly unfair. While
each had historic differences that shouldn’t be minimized—the
charge that Lenin was at bottom more Jacobin than Marxist has some
truth, as does Luxemburg’s short-shrifting politics as public policy—
both encapsulated the truism voiced by Anatole France soon after
Luxemburg’s death, that in war “one thinks he is dying for his country, but he dies for the industrialists.” That’s something the Majority
Socialists denied as they invented reasons why German collapse on
the battlefield was bad for German workers and why class war had to
be suspended during wartime for the sake of a sacred union with the
old German order.
What Endures in Luxemburg’s Heritage?
The name “Rosa Luxemburg” today is known best by the general
German public for Berlin’s Rosa-Luxemburg-Platz, whose eponymous
subway stop in central Berlin caters to theatergoers, shoppers, and
visitors to Left Party headquarters. In the mainstream press, when
mentioned at all, she’s either reviled or condescended to. Typical was
the mind-numbing headline to an otherwise friendly review by Sheila
Rowbotham in the Guardian of a recently published collection of
Luxemburg’s letters, describing her in the teaser subhead as “an outspoken critic of Marxism”5 —something she assuredly was not.
What’s to be appreciated of Red Rosa today is her steadfast opposition to reform as a final goal (as opposed to seeing battles for reforms
as indispensible tactics, which she did). Her critique of capitalist
democracy and her deep respect for the ability of working people to
170
●
Michael Hirsch
engage in and win class struggles is as much relevant in the age of
neoliberalism as it was in the period of national cartels and imperial
rivalries. Her conception of socialism was a regime of liberty. In “The
Russian Revolution” she wrote:
Freedom is always and exclusively freedom for the one who thinks
differently. Not because of any fanatical concept of “justice” but
because all that is instructive, wholesome and purifying in political
freedom depends on this essential characteristic, and its effectiveness vanishes when “freedom” becomes a special privilege.6
For Luxemburg and her comrade Karl Liebknecht, opposition to the
First World War was not made on pacifist grounds or even prompted
by the need to attack the Majority Socialists for abandoning commonlyagreed-to internationalist principles. It was because support for the
war—including conscripted labor, a ban on strikes, fingering militants to the authorities, and a military dictatorship imposing a state of
siege—was an unholy peace treaty with the enemy at home, one that
strengthened capital. That policy could only result—should Germany
win the war—in a stronger reactionary social order and a weakened
working class.
In What Does the Spartacus League Want?? written within a month
before her death, Luxemburg set out her analysis:
The victory of the Spartakusbund stands not at the beginning but
at the end of the revolution. It is identical with the victory of the
millions of masses of the socialist proletariat. . . . The proletarian
revolution requires no terror for its aims; it hates and despises killing. It does not need these weapons because it does not combat
individuals but institutions, because it does not enter the arena with
naïve illusions whose disappointment it would seek to revenge. It is
not the desperate attempt of a minority to mold the world forcibly
according to its ideal, but the action of the great massive millions
of the people, destined to fulfill a historic mission and to transform
historical necessity into reality.7
The use of “historical mission” can be misleading. There is nothing preordained in the notion that workers, in the words of the
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
171
Manifesto, “have a world to win.” Or to lose. Goals don’t need to be
met to be goals; they only need to be necessary and achievable within
reason. Luxemburg’s counterpoising “socialism” and “barbarism”
as humanity’s only real choices was a departure from the orthodox
Marxism of Karl Kautsky and the leadership of the German Social
Democracy, who insisted that a scientifically grounded historical
materialism showed the classless society to be inevitable. What was
inevitable for Luxemburg was not the victory of an oppressed class
but economic crisis and the ensuing opportunities for that class.
What workers did, given economic and political collapse, was in
their own hands.
Bronner’s Luxemburg, and Hers
Steve Bronner deserves credit for his painstaking work in renewing
Luxemburg’s heritage. As a scholar, biographer, master educator, and
activist, he’s owed a debt. As early as 1980, in an essay penned in
memory of the martyred student leader Rudi Dutschke, Bronner
wrote with brio and intelligence about the socialist project and its
failures on both sides of the Iron Curtain.8 But at various points in
the debate in New Politicss over Luxemburg’s legacy, he writes what
reads like an implication that reforms in and of themselves—not just
as agitational targets and marks of success—can alter the structure of
capital and mollify its potential gravediggers such that revolution and
the destruction of a hegemonic owning class is a fool’s errand. Well,
we should all be such fools.
Bronner is right to label the “inevitable triumph of socialism” trope
(or for that matter post–Cold War end-of-history theorizing that capitalism itself is permanent) a teleology, a method that a priorii situates fixed ends as part of an overall design. Humans, as Marx said,
“make their own history, but not as they choose; they do not make it
under circumstances chosen by themselves, but under circumstances
directly encountered, given and transmitted from the past.” So “the
tradition of all the dead generations” may indeed “weigh like a nightmare on the brain of the living,”9 but humans have the capacity to
awaken from the worst nightmares. Luxemburg’s notion was that
humanity’s real choices are just two: socialism or barbarism. That
formulation, borrowed and amplified from Engels, is nott teleological.
172
●
Michael Hirsch
It is simply the logical outcome of an ongoing struggle that will leave
society either better or massively worse. Whatever the outcome, capitalist stability cannot survive.
Now Bronner may say, as he does to David Camfield, that a belief
in revolution and the working class as capitalism’s gravedigger, absent
objective justifications, is a wish if not a religious tenet because it
can’t be proven a posteriori. Fair enough! Marxism is not a divining
rod or an Ouija board. Projecting possible futures is what makes for
horseracing, not science. Still, I’ll bet on the prole horses. And why
not? Pascal’s wager on the existence of a god is based on a cost-benefit
analysis. Why not the same wager by capitalism’s critics?
But where I think Bronner strays is in downplaying the implications of the information we do have, that capital installs a social order
featuring growing concentrations of wealth and power by a few, fueled
by escalating exploitation in a rote drive for accumulation. (Just one
effect: decreased social mobility. In a study of 17 Organization of
Economic Cooperation and Development countries, the United States
came in a poor thirteenth, considerably behind Denmark, Norway,
Finland, and Canada and just outpacing the United Kingdom and
Italy.10)
The implication for me: such a social order is not merely heinous
but explosive. When the top 10 percent of US households in 2010
received 44.5 percent of all income and 76 percent of all wealth, the
capacity for the lower 90 percent to affect government policy is compromised, if not crippled.11 Those numbers suggest a plutocracy in
the making in the United States, and a likely unstable one. As the
rise of Hitler showed, barbarism is a ready candidate to replace bourgeois democracy when an established order fails. Does this necessarily
imply that the world proletariat can act with the degree of cohesion
and interest to make a revolution? No, but it certainly puts into question the viability of centuries of piecemeal reform or even a permanent stalemate between the classes.
And does Bronner really believe—as he suggests—that the proletariat is disaggregating? That it is so atomized that it resembles what
Marx said about the nineteenth-century peasantry, that they were a
sack of potatoes held together only by the sack? If anything, global
capital is recasting the working class as a world class, one that is “in
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
173
itself” if not (or not yet) “for itself.” Making the proletariat into a class
for itself and not just voters for the common good or masses to be
manipulated was precisely Luxemburg’s goal.
Then there’s the hobgoblin of critical mass. Will enough people
want socialism? Will enough working people act as one to move revolution from fantasy to fact? Posing the matter this way only restates the
problem; it doesn’t deal with it. From the standpoint of class struggle,
socialism is not an ethical ideal or a consumer choice; it’s a necessity
for survival as a culture and as a species.
Consider today’s alternatives: the Koch Brothers are only the most
visible of those corporate heads targeting our quintessentially moderate unions for extinction. Wal-Mart is a world-beater because it
severely underpays its employees, causing other retailers to compete
in a race to the bottom. The US auto industry survives only at the
expense of a drastically reduced workforce forced to accept heavy pay
cuts and drastically reduced pension and health benefits. Industrial
jobs are returning to the United States precisely because workers in
nonunion states are job-desperate and will work cheap.
What would the employer class do if a genuinely progressive
administration was elected or unions uniformly adopted social and
economic justice agendas that of necessity challenged the corporate
bottom line? Would shareholder buccaneer David Einhorn cease
his parasitic ways? Would a twenty-first century incarnation of Carl
Icahn operate a business as a public service rather than something to
dismantle and sell by the piece?
What is properly utopian isn’t the belief in the need for revolution
but the insistence that a class society, one built on manic accumulation and exploitation of labor power on a world scale, can survive
indefinitely.
In the comfort of relative affluence, all of us fine-tune Marxism
until its every kink is ironed out and every prediction reexamined
until only “method” remains. Or at least it remains as something
Marxists can agree on. That’s fair game. Even the ruthless criticism
of all things deserves critique. It’s what retrospection, the availability
of and access to documents, collegial input, and the lack of historical
urgency and the mixed blessings of polemical exchange allow. After
1914, Luxemburg had no such luxuries.
174
●
Michael Hirsch
So if thinking the exploited are capable of overturning the capitalist order, forestalling barbarism, and installing an egalitarian ethos
is unscientific, and in effect part of the sacred, then saying that they
cannot is profane. Marx referred to socialism as the end of prehistory,
not the end of strife or a return to innocence in the Garden of Eden.
I suspect Bronner agrees that capitalism cannot be reformed to
eliminate exploitation or resolve class conflict equitably, or even that a
regime of modest (let alone radical) reforms under capitalism is likely.
Bronner seems to think that the reforms he espouses would, even if
instituted, serve as the proverbial bird in the hand to check any revolutionary class-in-formation. To me, it’s an empty hand. By the most
optimistic measure, a progressive government committed to making
inroads into the wealth and security of the richest families and the
largest corporations, even if only to redistribute income, would be
undone. Its fall could be nonviolent, as was the exit of the first British
Labor government through a scandal manufactured by the permanent
staffs of the security services; or it could involve homicide and mass
murder, the weapons that exploded the Sukarno and Allende regimes
and massacred their supporters in Indonesia and Chile.
Another fault: Bronner, in response to Camfield, argues (albeit
only in a footnote) that the German Social Democratic leadership
was “constrained” in supporting the war and in acting as an agent for
big capital and the military. “One false step by the socialist leadership might have meant ruining the work of a generation,” Bronner
wrote in 1992,12 which is exactly what happened anyway, and within
14 years of the first Ebert government. As I will argue, the party had
ample choices besides being capital’s cat’s-paw. Perhaps the apparatus
of the party and the unions would not take the risk, but German
workers had options. Luxemburg showed that they did.
Bronner also fondly quotes his mentor Henry Pachter, “One cannot have socialism. One is a socialist.” If that means that socialism has
no use-by date, Pachter is right. If it means that there are no answers
to the key “social” questions of eradicating hunger and scarcity, he is
wrong. As Isaac Deutscher put it, even under socialism there will be
problems, including psychological pathologies. All that can be reasonably assumed is that “socialist man will be a better patient.”13
I do not take on Bronner easily. He is a hefty Luxemburg scholar,
and someone such as I who doesn’t read German opining on the
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
175
German Revolution—when key texts are not in translation, let alone
government documents and economic studies from the period that
could shed more light on what was possible for the emerging revolutionary movement of 1918—may be punching above his weight.
But then this exchange hinges on Bronner’s beef with revolutionary
romanticism and an idealized councilist polity. Certainly there’s a lot
to beef about. Supporters’ failure to articulate a theory of national
let alone international government based on the explosive yet fragile workers’ and soldiers’ councils is a weakness. It’s also a question
Luxemburg did not live to answer. Yet in his own way Bronner is ahistorical. Not only does he seem optimistic about spreading democracy
in a class-divided society, especially now—when austerity policies and
neoliberal regimes in the advanced capitalist nations are imbedding
plutocracies at rates not seen since the Gilded Age—but he shows
insufficient recognition for the necessity of working-class self-activity
as the key source of social change.
Of course workers’ councils are not cure-alls. Of course, valorizing any particular institutional form is shortsighted if not ahistorical. Of course reforms aimed at legislation that come with teeth and
not just gums is part of any socialist tool kit, but then so are the
quotidian acts of working people central to class struggle. Councils
when no one wants them? Bad idea! Councils set up by workers
themselves in opposition to the present order? Good idea! Councils
versus parliaments? Luxemburg certainly thought so—her support
for contesting elections to the National Assembly was strategic.
She believed workers were not ready for—or convinced of the need
for—self-rule, but then Bronner completely rules out dual power
and councils on the model of the Paris Commune or the soviets as
a challenge to a centralized and formal representative democracy.
“Where’s the agency for a social revolution,” he in effect asks, “if
there is no revolutionary class and thinking there will be is counterfactual if not delusional?”
If many radicals are overly sanguine about the ease in which councils could step in and replace existing governments, Bronner shows
in his interventions no reason to rule the possibility out. How else
to start a new society than to base it on the structures workers themselves create? I’m all for evening scores with vulgar Marxists, but why
at the expense of our class’s outstanding moments?
176
●
Michael Hirsch
Why the Failure of German Social Democracy to
Defend the “Social” Sphere?
So how did a mass socialist organization end up as a key enabler
of German capital? How did a party that could write in the Erfurt
Program, its 1891 founding document, that “the working class cannot
carry on its economic contests, and cannot develop its economic organization, without political rights” or “bring about the transference of
the means of production into the possession of the community, without having obtained political power,”14 within one generation become
a junior partner of the military and the big industrials, abandoning
any interest in transferring private property to community ownership? How did the party produce a Gustave Noske, a key Majority
Socialist, who would proudly name himself the “bloodhound”15 of
the counterrevolution after organizing the volunteer corps that murdered Luxemburg and Liebknecht in January 1919? There are a number of explanations:
●
●
●
There was the strength and stability of German capital even after
the collapse of the Central Command’s Western offensive, with
Victor Serge attesting that the German upper class was “the most
educated, the most organized, the most conscious bourgeoisie of
all.”16 In contrast to the Russian upper classes, this one was not
yet defeated internally or politically exhausted. Minor concessions and government titles dependent on military backing were
all it took to housebreak the SPD leadership.
There was also—and this is the Leninist explanation—no revolutionary party to shape opposition to the war and the Sacred
Union, turning the pacifist fight against the war into a battle
against capital, its instigator and benefactor. Luxemburg and the
radicals operated as a rump caucus in the SPD. By the time war
was declared, it was too late to form a coherent revolutionary
opposition capable of withstanding the military government’s
repression.
Then there was the hegemony of opportunists and careerists
not only in the SPD apparatus but in the national unions, marshaled against Marxists, including against Karl Kautsky, the
“pope” of Marxism, who could win no greater prize than militant language concessions at annual conferences before going on
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
177
to form the Independent Socialist Party of Germany (USPD).
Unlike in Moscow and St. Petersburg, where the Bolsheviks
had the backing of the majority of workers and the provisional
government twisted in the wind, the German revolutionaries
functioned as leaders and tacticians in comparative isolation,
though Liebknecht had in effect well-deserved rock-star status
among urban workers. Even the declaration of the Republic by
the Majority Socialists was prompted more by fear of the far left
than by a reading of the need to form a workers’ state. Philipp
Scheidemann, destined to be a future president only to be assassinated by the fascists in 1922, preempted Liebknecht’s call for a
workers’ and sailors’ government by proclaiming instead a labor
government—a move that ironically received no favor from
Fritz Ebert, who was then in tenuous and secret negotiations
with the army.
Instead of joining the revolution, the SPD leaders chose to either
co-opt or kill it. In the end, they did both, despite the clear intention of Luxemburg and her followers to “never assume governmental
power unless it is supported by the clear, unambiguous will of the
great majority of the proletariat in Germany, and in no other way
except with their conscious acceptance of the ideas, aims, and fighting methods of the Spartakusbund.”17 This statement sums up not
just Luxemburg’s repeated emphasis on building a class ready to rule
but her failure to think tactically given the conjuncture.
And the Majority Socialists had other choices. While Germany
was not the wreaked state and devastated civil society that was Russia
in 1917, it was far from stable, in the view of its own ruling elite. Then
Field Marshal Paul von Hindenburg was among those of the army
General Staff who met with the Kaiser’s cabinet to tell them that
“revolution was standing at the door, and we had the choice of meeting it with dictatorship or concessions. A parliamentary government
seemed to be the best weapon of defense”18 —especially for preserving
the highly political army and its Prussian offers corps, which the SPD
government did retain, as promised. Hindenburg would later admit
that the grand strategy of the government was, in the words of the
Kaiser’s secretary of state, “to forestall an upheaval from below by a
revolution from above.”19
178
●
Michael Hirsch
So committed were the socialist leaders to the policies of
Burgfreiden, the social peace to which all the Reichstag parties
yoked themselves for the war’s duration, and so tied to the rhetoric
of defending the sanctified fatherland that when the German Right
later blamed the war’s defeat on “traitorous” socialists in government
selling out an army “unbeaten in the field,” Ebert sued his “calumniators.” He did that, rather than what Pachter notes would have
been the more appropriate course, “boasting” that he had done a
public service by bringing the slaughter and the plainly lost war to
an end.20
So the SPD leaders weren’t victims of the warr21; they were its enablers
and its home guard inside the workers’ movement, actively and systematically fingering opponents, and saying that the class struggle was
the antithesis of the war’s beneficial aims. Like Luxemburg, Trotsky,
living in exile in Switzerland in 1914, knew better, writing in The War
and the Internationall that a German victory
can produce only one result—territorial acquisitions at the expense
of Belgium, France and Russia, commercial treaties forced upon
her enemies, and new colonies. The class struggle of the proletariat
would then be placed upon the basis of the imperialist hegemony
of Germany, the working class would be interested in the maintenance and development of this hegemony, and revolutionary
socialism would for a long time be condemned to the role of a
propagandist sect.22
Writing in the Junius Pamphlett the same year, Luxemburg notes:
Under the circumstances the question of victory or defeat becomes,
for the European working class, in its political exactly as in its
economic aspects, a choice between two beatings. It is therefore
nothing short of a dangerous madness for the French Socialists to
believe that they can deal a deathblow to militarism and imperialism, and clear the road for peaceful democracy, by overthrowing
Germany. Imperialism and its servant, militarism, will reappear
after every victory and after every defeat in this war. There can
be but one exception: if the international proletariat, through its
intervention, should overthrow all previous calculations.
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
179
She adds:
“The modern proletariat comes out of historical tests differently
[than did the bourgeoisie in its revolutions]. Its tasks and its errors
are both gigantic: no prescription, no schema valid for every case,
no infallible leader to show it the path to follow. Historical experience is its only schoolmistress. Its thorny way to self-emancipation
is paved not only with immeasurable suffering but also with countless errors. The aim of its journey—its emancipation depends on
this—is whether the proletariat can learn from its own errors. Selfcriticism, remorseless, cruel, and going to the core of things is the
life’s breath and light of the proletarian movement. The fall of the
socialist proletariat in the present world war is unprecedented. It
is a misfortune for humanity. But socialism will be lost only if the
international proletariat fails to measure the depth of this fall, if it
refuses to learn from it.23
As Arthur Rosenberg summed it up in 1928, writing as a former
member of the Reichstag Committee of Inquiry into the causes of
the German collapse during the First World War and challenging the
notion that the SPD caused the defeat by backstabbing the Kaiser’s
governments:
[The party leaders] contented themselves instead with emphasizing that Germany should not attempt any conquests and the
[hugely disproportional] electoral system in Prussia should be
reformed . . . [They] feared that if they took up a determined attitude
in opposition to the Government, the entire working class would rise
in rebellion, and the German defense collapse in consequence.24
So if the SPD leaders did any backstabbing, it wasn’t of those militarists prosecuting the war.
The Trade Union Apparatus as a Conservatizing Force
While Luxemburg was battling revisionism as an ideology, it was
alive and well in the party’s practice, the outcome of conservative
trade unions’ influence and a new breed of realpolitikk party officials
beholden to them. As Carl Schorske describes it, by the turn of the
180
●
Michael Hirsch
new century the unions ceased to be recruiting agencies for the SPD,
coming into their own as “great and wealthy organizations, offering
services in the field of social security which the state was unwilling
to provide. Inevitably, the interest of the unions and their members
became more and more closely identified with the existing economic
system.” It was what Robert Michels called “the replacement of agitators by the schooled official with specialized knowledge,” as he counterpoised “the glowing idealist to the lukewarm materialist” who was
interested less in the much vaunted final conflict for the broad proletariat as with the interim contract for the members.25
As early as 1905, the party at its Jena convention weighed in on
the importance of mass strikes even as the affiliated trade unions forbade members even broaching the subject. At the 1906 Mannheim
conclave, the unions even won veto power over party actions, even
as radical resolutions on war and socialism were routinely adopted.
A leading party paper bemoaned “the revisionism we killed in the
party rises again in greater strength in the trade unions.”26 In effect
the SPD had morphed, in deed if not yet in word, into a purely
reformist and accommodating party, even as by 1913, in the midst of
another cyclical economic crisis, the government employed police and
mass jailings to break strikes, imprison strike leaders, crack down on
boycotts, and even assault informational picketers.
With the war’s outbreak in 1914, the SPD joined the other parties
in offering the Kaiser’s government carte blanche to decide not only
military but also economic and political issues, what Schorske calls
“stagnation by consent” as opposed to the prewar’s “stagnation by
stalemate.” The ongoing state of siege meant the military only had
to answer to the Kaiser, leaving all the center parties as well as the
SPD as at best advisers and courtiers. For labor leaders, “Once they
accepted the primacy of foreign policy [they] assumed the function of
disciplining the labor movement in the interest of the state.”27
With the onset of the war and the sociological and ideological fissures in the party ruptured, no coherent organization emerged to do
what Luxemburg urged: turn the growing opposition to the war into
a war against the old order at home. Even the workers’ and soldiers’
councils, themselves products of mass strikes and harbingers of a
new social order, were too new and too loosely based to offer much
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
181
direction. There was, as Schorske puts it starkly, “no central leadership which, like Lenin’s in Russia, pursued a conscious strategy in
the interest of the single aim of the seizure of power, no cold political
planning in which the masses were viewed not solely as the subjects of
politics, but as its objects.”28
So the structure of the Spartakusbund itself—if not necessarily
the predilection of its leaders—militated against any strident sense
of timing or of tactics for the moment. What was so refreshing about
Luxemburg—her belief that revolutions had to be the work of masses
of people mobilizing in their own collective interests—was paralleled
by a shrunken sense of actually seizing the moment. It may be unfair
to associate her thinking with “spontaneity” (the word really means
that somebody else did the organizing), but it does suggest a failing
no less significant than Lenin’s fascination with maneuvers and his
substitution of the party for the class or Kautsky’s efforts to reconcile
the irreconcilable. Luxemburg had no organization or even infrastructure to coordinate antistate activities even as the Majority Socialists
were locked in as junior partners in the Wilhelmine state and later as
titular heads of the first Weimar government, wholly beholden to the
military tops. Not until August 1917 did left radicals formally reject
the division between unions and parties that had allowed the trade
union apparatus to determine practical party policy.
Paul Mattick Sr., a consistent advocate of council communism and
a fierce Lenin critic, argued that a parliamentary regime populated by
Social Democrats collaborating with German capital
was the immediate and only goal of German Social Democracy.
Its reluctance to extend the revolution into the economic sphere
was even more pronounced in the trade union leadership, which
set itself in opposition “to any socialist experiment and any form
of socialization at a time when the population required work and
food,” as though the socializations would come at the expense of
providing work and food. The close wartime cooperation between
the trade unions and private industry was reinforced, in order
to prevent and break strikes and to combat the politicization of
the workers via the factory councils in largescale enterprises. In
brief, the old labor movement in its entirety became an unabashed
182
●
Michael Hirsch
counter-revolutionary force within a revolution that had [placed]
political power in its hands.29
Luxemburg Today
How to build a society that isn’t piratical and vampire-like is a question
confronting socialists in Europe and the United States. In response
to the austerity measures demanded by Germany and the European
Union officials, the PIIGS countries (Portugal, Italy, Ireland, Greece,
and Spain) are walking two paths: their governments are capitulating
while resistance movements are growing. These movements may not
be enough.
In Greece, SYRIZA, a leftist party that is poised to win the next
election (it garnered 27 percent of the popular vote in 2012) faces
exactly the political divide that marked German socialism in
Luxemburg’s time: either govern through a deal with big capital—in
these cases not even national capital—or rule from the left without
the sort of organic institutional support the Bolsheviks initially had or
that Luxemburg thought was necessary to rule. A radical restructuring of the Greek economy would be the perfect pretext for a military
coup, even a fascist uprising, unless SYRIZA in government has not
only a voting majority in parliament but workers and soldiers mobilized in its defense. (It may in fact have that basis in labor support,
with 29 general strikes waged from 2008 through the first quarter
of 2013, far higher than in the other PIIGS countries, which are also
seeing general strikes against austerity.30)
I don’t worry about SYRIZA; I worry with it. I hope it does take
office in the next election. At best, SYRIZA can serve as a living
model demonstrating how a progressive government in a capitalist
state is handicapped by forces arrayed against it. At worst, it consists
of dead men (and women) walking. But if it governs by placating the
EU through a rhetorically kinder variation on austerity measures at
the expense of its working-class base, it risks either losing the next
election or physical extinction from an emboldened right. Or both.
And like socialists in the German Revolution, its leaders risk either
becoming enablers of murder or getting murdered themselves if they
don’t take steps to create dual power. They may in fact be doing so.
If they are, both Luxemburg and Lenin have things to tell them.
Contra Bronner on Luxemburg
●
183
Notes
1. Quoted in Jan Benzel, “Rosa Luxemburg: More Than a Revolutionary,” New
York Timess (May 31, 1987), http://www.nytimes.com/1987/05/31/movies
/rosa-luxemburg-more-than-a-revolutionary.html-?pagewanted=2 (accessed
April 18, 2013).
2. Perry Anderson, Considerations on Western Marxism (London: Verso, 1976),
p. 11.
3. Quoted in Karl Korsch, “Introduction to the Critique of the Gotha
Programme,” in Marxism and Philosophyy (1922), http://www.marxists.org
/archive/korsch/1922/gotha.htm (accessed April 18, 2013).
4. V.
V I. Lenin, Left-Wing Communism: An Infantile Disorder (1920), http://
www.-marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1920/lwc/ch10.htm (accessed
April 18, 2013).
5. Sheila Rowbotham, “The Revolutionary Rosa Luxemburg,” The Guardian,
March 4, 2011, http://www.guardian.co.uk/books/2011/mar/05/rosa-luxem
burg-writer-activist-letters (accessed April 19, 2013).
6. Rosa Luxemburg, The Russian Revolution (1918), http://www.marxists.org
/archive/luxemburg/1918/russian-revolution/ (accessed April 18, 2013).
7. Rosa Luxemburg, What Does the Spartacus League Want?? (1918), http://
www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1918/12/14.htm (accessed April 18,
2013).
8. Stephen Eric Bronner, “The Socialist Project,” Social Researchh (Spring
1980), pp. 11–35.
9. Karl Marx, The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonapartee (1852), http://www.marx
-ists.org/archive/marx/works/1852/18th-brumaire/ch01.htm (accessed April
18, 2013).
10. Lawrence Mishel et al., The State of Working America, 12th edition (Ithaca:
ILR Press, 2012), p. 9.
11. Ibid., pp. 80–84.
12. Stephen Eric Bronner, Moments of Decision: Political History and the Crises
of Radicalism (New York: Routledge, 1992), p. 22.
13. Isaac Deutscher, On Socialist Man (New York: Merit Publishers, 1967),
p. 21.
14. The Erfurt Program (1891), http://www.marxists.org/history/international
/social-democracy/1891/erfurt-program.htm (accessed April 18, 2013).
15. Quoted in Marcel Liebman, The Russian Revolution (New York: Random
House, 1970), p. 345.
16. Victor Serge, Year One of the Russian Revolution (1930), http://www.marx
-ists.org/archive/serge/1930/year-one/ch10.htm (accessed April 18, 2013).
17. Luxemburg, What Does the Spartacus League Want?
18. Quoted in Ruth Fischer, Stalin and German Communism (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1948), p. 54.
184
●
Michael Hirsch
19. Quoted in Pierre Broué, The German Revolution, 1917–1923 (Chicago:
Haymarket, 2006), p. 130.
20. Henry Pachter, The Fall and Rise of Europee (New York: Praeger Publishers,
1975), p. 98.
21. In his aside to Camfield, Bronner suggests that the Majority Socialists’ support for the war was based in part on their being realists “constrained” by
bad times, presumably to live to fight another day. As I argue, there were
ample alternatives to the SPD’s direction. Both structural and careerist reasons better explain their morphing into the Kaiser’s policemen. They lived
indeed, but not in order to “fight the power.”
22. Leon Trotsky,
y The War and the Internationall (1915), http://www.marxists
.org/archive/trotsky/1914/war/part2.htm#ch05 (accessed April 18, 2013).
23. Rosa Luxemburg, The Junius Pamphlet: The Crisis of German Social Democracy
(1915), http://www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1915/junius/ (accessed
April 18, 2013).
24. Arthur Rosenberg, Imperial Germany: The Birth of the German Republic,
1871–19188 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1970), pp. 117, 170.
25. Carl Schorske, German Social Democracy, 1905–1917
7 (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1955), p. 14.
26. Ibid, pp. 51–52.
27. Ibid, p. 293.
28. Ibid, pp. 323–24.
29. Paul Mattick, Marxism: Last Refuge of the Bourgeoisie?? (Armonk: M. E.
Sharpe, Inc., 1983), p. 269.
30. Joseph Choonara, “The Class Struggles in Europe,” International Socialism
No. 138 (Spring 2013), p. 49.
APPENDIX
Reflections on Red Rosa: An Interview
with Stephen Eric Bronner
Conducted by Jason Schulman
You have been interested in Rosa Luxemburg since the beginning of
your academic career. What makes her such a fascinating figure?
Yes, it’s true: Rosa Luxemburg has been with me, so to speak, from the
beginning. My edition and translation of her political letters appeared
in 1979 and my short biography Rosa Luxemburg: A Revolutionary
for Our Timess was published in 1980—and it remains in print. Few
historical figures speak especially to young radicals in such a direct
fashion. Rosa (as everyone called her) was a charismatic personality,
a woman, and a Jew, who must have been a sparkling orator. She
was the first woman to receive a doctorate in political economy from
the University of Zurich and she was probably the finest theoretician of the socialist labor movement prior to the First World War.
Rosa had an independent and wide-ranging intellect. She was fascinated by nature, she studied botany in her spare time, and she was
steeped in history and the classics of literature. She also must have
exhibited a kind of personal warmth that is difficult to convey. Rosa
had her lovers and her circle of intimate and extraordinarily loyal
female friends—she also had an innate sympathy for animals. Make
no mistake: Rosa was ambitious and impatient, sometimes dogmatic
186
●
Appendix
in her judgments, patronizing with her friends, sometimes difficult
and self-righteous. Too often her ideals made her blind to existing
political realities. Not even her critics, however, questioned Rosa’s
bravery and her passionate dedication to democracy and socialism.
Luxemburg was a genuinely honorable woman, a true role model,
whose life and work has inspired generations of radicals and—I
believe—will continue to do so.
You seem to treat Rosa more critically in your initial essay than some
might have expected. Or am I wrong? What makes her more relevant today than other socialist theorists—specifically other classical
Marxists—of her era?
My opening essay to this volume argues that Rosa’s political concerns
are more relevant than ever, but that they need to be addressed in new
terms for a new context. What Leszek Kolakowski termed the “golden
age of Marxism” has passed. There is no longer a socialist party that
claims our virtually unqualified loyalty or a meaningful international
organization representing workers. Class consciousness is no longer
the primary form of self-identification. There is no longer the same
agreement on the agent of historical transformation or about the prospects for a capitalist breakdown—and there is no longer the same
confidence in the ultimate triumph of the proletariat. We should not
turn Luxemburg’s writings into holy writ. In her time, when “orthodoxy” was the name of the game, she worried greatly over “the stagnation of Marxism.” She criticized Marx’s views on any number of
topics. We should approach Luxemburg in roughly the same way that
she approached Marx: appreciative, critical, yet aware that we are in a
new historical epoch.
What makes Rosa relevant? She embodies the alternative to
Communist authoritarianism as well as social democratic technocracy. Her most famous line—“freedom is only freedom for the one
who thinks differently”—appears in her critique of the Russian
Revolution. Her claim that reform is akin to the “labor of Sisyphus”
(thereby infuriating union bureaucrats) has a particular relevance for
a period marked by austerity and the rise of the far right. More forcefully than any of her contemporaries, Rosa challenged the illusion
that reforms mechanically build on one another to produce a kind of
Appendix
●
187
irreversible progress. Her internationalist and cosmopolitan convictions are also important for interpreting globalization and confronting
narrow forms of identity politics. Above all, however, Rosa recognized
the connection between political democracy and the struggles of the
working class. Her views on mass mobilization illuminate not merely
the dynamics behind the Arab Spring but also the fall of Communism.
In fact, there is hardly a competing contemporary theory that can
account for recent transnational political developments sparked by
unplanned uprisings from below. Better than anyone else, Rosa provides a starting point for what I call “the underground tradition” of
libertarian socialism.
What do you make of the aura that surrounds Luxemburg and the
Spartacus Revolt of 1919? What was its unrealized potential, its mistakes, and its importance for Rosa’s enduring appeal?
1919 witnessed an unrealized opportunity to combine workers’ councils with republican democracy and, speaking historically, Rosa’s death
symbolizes that failed attempt. The Spartacus Revolt still captures the
radical imagination but, in fact, two revolutions were taking place in
Germany in that year. The ill-fated Weimar Republic was proclaimed
on November 9, 1918, the product of what became known as the
“aborted revolution.” It was immediately attacked from the right and
the left. The new regime lacked legitimacy and its leaders lacked charisma. Conservatives, monarchists, and proto-Nazis instantly united
in opposing the regime. Even liberals seemed more often swayed by
exigency than conviction in supporting the Weimar Republic. As
for the far left, it was appalled by the new regime’s refusal to purge
the imperial judiciary and the military, nationalize large-scale capitalist firms, or liquidate the estates of the arch-reactionary Prussian
aristocrats. Yet the great majority of the working class supported the
Weimar Republic until the bitter end. Its members feared a repeat of
the Communist seizure of power and bloody civil war—if the victorious powers of the First World War did not decide to intervene first,
crush the revolutionaries and the republic, and set up a puppet regime.
A significant proletarian minority, however, remembered the “great
betrayal” by the SPD in 1914 when it endorsed Germany’s entry into
the First World War. Along with supporters of the workers’ councils
188
●
Appendix
that briefly arose in Munich, Vienna, and elsewhere, Spartacus sought
to break with the old labor movement tout courtt. Its members were
inspired by the Bolshevik Revolution and Lenin’s slogan, “All Power
to the Soviets!” Led by Luxemburg and Karl Liebknecht, Spartacus
soon formed the nucleus of what in 1919 would become the German
Communist Party (KPD). To most the choice seemed clear: participate in the first parliamentary elections or support the insurgents calling for workers’ councils and a “soviet” Germany. Rosa called upon
those on the left of the SPD to participate in the elections. She recognized the obvious: the protean Communist Party and the ultra-left
were too weak (and would remain too weak) to overthrow the new
republic. When her proposal for electoral participation was defeated,
however, feelings of solidarity led her to side with the revolutionary workers. This idealistic gesture led to her death at the hand of
proto-Nazi troops on January 15, 1919. But it also turned Rosa into
a martyr—and her legend grew even while her politics, so to speak,
went underground.
Why do you think that Luxemburg devoted no resources to building a tendency or an organized left fraction within German Social
Democracy after her split with Karl Kautsky in 1910? In retrospect do
you think she should have done so?
Organizing a “Bolshevik” fraction, which is what Lenin did in the
tiny Russian Social Democratic Party, would have been impossible in
a mass party with a strong bureaucratic and cultural apparatus like
the SPD. A (minority) tendency formed around Luxemburg (with her
approval)—but I’m not sure how much more she could have done
other than split. And that she was unwilling to do. Was her break with
Kautsky prudent? Probably not: on the occasion of the (second) mass
strike debate in 1910, Kautsky along with Bernstein and other oldtimers argued that it should be employed only as a “defensive” tactic
when democracy and the functioning of the party was threatened—
ironically it was actually used that way in 1920 when a defensive mass
strike called by the Social Democrats defeated the reactionary Kapp
Putsch. Luxemburg and her friends, however, wished to use the mass
strike as an “offensive” weapon to transform society. As for the true
right-wing Social Democrats, they insisted that “the mass strike is
Appendix
●
189
mass nonsense.” Rosa’s decision to split the once unified left-wing of
the SPD made it much easier for the rightwing to take over the party
and lead it into supporting the First World War. In any event, the
overwhelming majority of the SPD opposed Luxemburg’s politics:
it was that simple. Yet she remained remarkably loyal to the party.
She opposed an organizational split even after 1914; she criticized the
proposed creation of a new Communist International; and, had she
lived, she certainly would have condemned Lenin’s “21 Points” and
his demand for conformity with the Bolshevik party model. Why
did she stress unity? I think Rosa basically agreed with Marx that
the ability of capital to exercise its power depends upon the degree of
organizational and ideological disunity among workers.
Could you elaborate on that? What are the implications for Luxemburg’s
theoretical and practical legacy?
Rosa Luxemburg died at the historical moment when socialism
split into three competing understandings in theory and practice:
Communist authoritarianism, socialist republicanism, and the direct
democracy associated with workers’ councils. She has been claimed
(and then discarded) at different times by all three. She was very
briefly the first leader of the KPD and she had worked with Lenin on
various projects including the Second International’s famous peace
resolution of 1907. By the same token, Luxemburg grew up in the
atmosphere of the prewar SPD and she had battled for a parliamentary republic like her other Social Democratic comrades. Yet Rosa
also experienced firsthand the Revolution of 1905 with its workers’
councils—Trotsky would later call 1905 the “dress rehearsal” for
1917—and she soon became the great advocate of the mass strike.
Now, from the standpoint of today, Communist authoritarianism has
been discredited; socialist republicanism has lost its radical character;
and workers’ councils legitimately appear utopian. Many insist upon
identifying “socialism” exclusively with one form or the other. But
Rosa never did. And, in fact, Marx never did either. Under present
circumstances, given what has transpired among the competing conceptions, it only fosters sectarianism and dogmatism to insist upon an
analytic definition of socialism or the specifically democratic institutional form it should take. Instead, I consider socialism as a regulative
190
●
Appendix
ideal (rather than a finished program of institutional arrangement)
that is predicated on a class politics with what will remain an unfinished commitment to political democracy, economic justice, and cultural cosmopolitanism. In this sense, quoting Henry Pachter, “one
cannot have socialism, one is a socialist.”
You were criticized for claiming that “Luxemburg foresaw how the
Communist repression of bourgeois democracy in 1917 would unleash
a dynamic of terror ultimately paralyzing the soviets and undermining
public life (in Russia) as a whole.” Do you think that your critics would
have been softer on you had you used the term “parliamentary democracy,” or even “liberal democracy,” instead of “bourgeois democracy”?
I don’t know. Liberals and Social Democrats might wince at my use of
the term “bourgeois democracy,” but my critics in the debate were neither liberals nor traditional Social Democrats. Most of them are leftwing libertarian Marxists committed to workers’ councils and some
of them view Lenin through the lens of the soviet. In any case, historically, Marxists and Leninists mostly employed this class designation
for the “provisional government” of Russia that emerged in February
1917. More importantly, the Communist International used the three
terms you mentioned interchangeably as it officially denied support
for republican regimes struggling against political reaction during the
1920s. My point was to highlight Luxemburg’s insistence upon maintaining a plausible relation between means and ends. She understood
all too well that revolutionary terror has historically tended to take on
a life of its own. Once unleashed it becomes difficult to put the genie
back in the bottle. Many on the Left still have not learned that terror
is—employing a phrase from Max Weber—like ideology, “not a taxicab that you can stop at the corner and say ‘I want to get off.’”
What do you see as “Luxemburgist” about the Arab Spring of 2011?
Too many radicals and progressives were overly preoccupied with the
establishmentarian fixation on elites, conspiracies, leaders, and the
media spectacle of the Arab Spring. They tended to ignore the question of political agency and the dynamics of the revolutionary chain
reaction that rocked the world first in Tunisia and then in Jordan,
Appendix
●
191
Algeria, Albania, Bahrain, Libya, Sudan, Syria, Yemen, and—of
course—Egypt. As the mass actions of 2011 were underway I wrote a
short piece, “Rosa in Cairo” that noted how this transnational set of
uprisings fit the analysis offered in The Mass Strike, the Party, and the
Trade Unionss. Of course, Luxemburg’s pamphlet was itself inspired by
a series of spontaneous protests that began in Baku in 1902, spread to
Kiev, Odessa, and St. Petersburg, and ultimately engulfed the entire
Russian Empire in 1905. The mass strike first expressed itself locally
in the towns and cities through the actions of workers and then spread
to the countryside; liberal political aims unified the working masses
with progressive elements of the ruling class and, ultimately, brought
about the first parliament in Russian history. Unfortunately, however, the dramatic character of the spontaneous uprisings tended to
obscure the years of underground work by unionists and political
activists. Something similar took place during the Arab Spring. All
the uprisings were spontaneous and yet, especially in Egypt, where
3,000 strikes and protests had taken place since 2004, they were also
mostly anchored in ongoing activities. Parties emerged organically,
if chaotically, from the struggle, while the revolts were transnational
and diverse expressions of a single process. Also, in keeping with
Luxemburg’s view, the radical goal everywhere was for a secular parliamentary republic that would provide civil liberties and a measure
of economic justice. Rosa placed special emphasis upon the formation
of a democratic consciousness and what I would call a cosmopolitan
pedagogy whereby one exploited community learns from another in
an ongoing revolutionary process. Luxemburg saw in the mass strike a
way to actualize the socialist movement as well as the untapped democratic capacities of the disenfranchised and the exploited.
How do you understand the economic analysis Luxemburg provided
in The Accumulation of Capital (1913)? What does this imply for
her politics?
Putting it very crudely, Luxemburg argued that production outstrips
consumption under capitalism, which (as an open system) transgresses
national boundaries. To this extent, indeed, she agreed with Marx.
But Rosa did not think that he had sufficiently explained why investment would continue if the system is marked by underconsumption.
192
●
Appendix
Without ongoing investment, of course, the capitalist system would
immediately collapse. According to Luxemburg, therefore, an outlet
for those overproduced commodities (including excess capital) must
exist within the system itself. That outlet is imperialism. Or, to put it
another way, the existence of precapitalist territories makes it possible
for capitalism to function. In contrast to Lenin, therefore, imperialism
is not the “last stage of capitalism,” or a derivative by-product, but is
rather endemic to the survival of capitalism. Increasingly, international
competition for control of these territories will, by the same logic, produce increasingly international wars. Crisis will follow crisis and war
will follow war as, inevitably, precapitalist territories are transformed
into capitalist states. An absolute limit to capitalist expansion appears.
With no outlet for its commodities, no way of dealing with overproduction, and thus no reason for capitalists to reinvest, the system will
implode. Her structural analysis provided a useful “scientific” foundation for her radical politics. Given the recurring crises of capitalism,
and its future breakdown, reform can only prove a palliative and the
movement must retain its revolutionary posture. Her economic analysis also justified her internationalist criticisms first of Marx regarding
national self-determination for Poland and then Lenin with respect to
the “right of national self-determination.” Of course, it also offers an
explanation for the First World War and her principled condemnation of it in the Junius Pamphlett (1915). The Accumulation of Capital
remains useful in making sense of globalization and perhaps even
postcolonialism. But national conflicts still exist. Nor is every capitalist nation militarist or imperialist (and certainly not militarist and
imperialist all the time). Is there an absolute limit for capitalist accumulation? I’m not sure it matters. More important is the ethical and
practical struggle against those reactionary trends that Rosa contested
all her life: provincial nationalism, militarism, imperialist arrogance,
and the neoliberal demands of corporate capital.
What do you think Luxemburg would have to say to contemporary
radical movements like Occupy Wall Street or left-wing parties like
SYRIZA?
Rosa would surely have welcomed Occupy and SYRIZA. Both
after their fashion attempt to link together the disenfranchised and
Appendix
●
193
exploited elements of the population with an eye on class aims.
Admittedly OWS was purely a movement that opposed electoral politics, and never wished to turn itself into a party, while SYRIZA is a
political party whose electoral activity requires forms of compromise
opposed by more radical elements of the Greek movement against
austerity. In spite of her support, therefore, Luxemburg would probably have had her critique of both. In works like The Mass Strikee,
she sought to develop a (dialectical) relationship between decentralized and centralized forms of politics. As I mentioned previously, she
also did not believe that extraelectoral activity somehow invalidated
electoral participation especially when workers’ rights and political
democracy are being threatened from the far right by mass organizations like the Republican/Tea Party in the United States and the
fascist Golden Dawn in Greece. Radical organizers of OWS may have
envisioned a new “horizontal” form of political organization, which
was theoretically underdeveloped and had no mass support, but the
movement actually played a pivotal role in electoral politics by throwing the Tea Party off the front pages, energizing demoralized progressives and the Obama administration, and changing the laissez-faire
public discourse with its slogan “We are the 99%!” Someone like Rosa
would surely have seen that the “horizontal” vision of radicals within
OWS did not deal with any of the long-standing problems associated
with workers’ councils or make direct democracy particularly attractive or salient in an age of globalization. Luxemburg would also have
insisted upon making people aware that the threat facing Greece and
southern Europe is not simply economic austerity and hardship for
workers but the erosion of democracy and the representative character
of republicanism. No party can fight for such political goals without
reaching out to the masses and the radical elements inspiring so many
of them.
Some have accused Luxemburg of championing spontaneity. At times
she seems to argue that unorganized workers are spontaneously revolutionary, only held back by the conservatism of their leaders. What do
you think?
Luxemburg was a critic of bureaucratic reformism from the time of
her participation in the “revisionism debate” of 1898 and, a few years
194
●
Appendix
later, she chastised Lenin in Organizational Questions of Russian Social
Democracyy (1904) for placing the party over the proletariat as the revolutionary agent. It’s true that both Eduard Bernstein and Lenin—
each in his own way—insisted that the proletariat left on its own
was capable only of trade union consciousness. But it is important to
remember that Luxemburg’s critique of reformism was undertaken
in the context of defending the revolutionary character of the SPD
and, whatever her other reservations about Lenin, she never questioned his revolutionary commitments. Luxemburg’s primary concern was that (bureaucratic) party leaders would underestimate the
innovative democratic capacities of the working class and the need to
educate its members with respect to the revolutionary process. Or, to
put it another way, strengthening the democratic self-administrative
capacities of the proletariat required some form of centralized political
organization. Luxemburg most clearly articulated her position in the
The Mass Strikee. There she spoke of heightening that “creative tension” between different parts of the revolutionary process. Luxemburg
argued that the party, the unions, and the mass movement all had different functions: the party would develop a general program, educate
the workers in the means and purposes of the struggle; the unions
would articulate the economic demands of the proletariat as a whole;
and, spurred by the contradictions of capitalist accumulation, the
masses would provide the energy to keep the revolutionary process
moving forward. Today, perhaps, it is more a matter of radicals working with existing organizations and movements in order to generate
what I termed a “class ideal” that can identify programs and practices capable of benefiting working-class elements in all existing social
movements without privileging any. In any event, Luxemburg sought
to illuminate the dialectic between organization and spontaneity in
the revolutionary process. She never relinquished that idea.
Some consider Luxemburg’s theory as fatalistic or teleological. But she
also famously posed the choice between “socialism or barbarism.” How
do you reconcile these two positions? Or can they be reconciled?
Rosa’s critics used to joke that her politics rested on moving from
defeat to defeat to final victory. Of course, this is a caricature. But,
I think, she assumed that socialism would ultimately triumph even
Appendix
●
195
while barbarism was inscribed within the structure of capitalism. As
with most deterministic ideologies, whether predestination for the
burgeoning bourgeoisie according to Max Weber or the “inevitable”
victory of the proletariat according to Marx, Luxemburg’s economic
theory inspired action. It’s worth remembering that the greatest mass
labor movement in history was inspired not by preoccupations with
“consciousness” but rather by economic determinism or “scientific
socialism.” Such an outlook gave workers confidence and let them
believe they were on the right side of history. As her friend Wilhelm
Liebknecht—among the great organizers of late nineteenth-century
Social Democracy—put the matter: “I can see the socialist future
appearing as present.” Rosa believed that too. She may have highlighted the choice between “socialism or barbarism” with the outbreak of the war but to claim that she was agnostic regarding the
outcome of the struggle between them betrays a lack of historical
understanding—and a distorted view of Luxemburg. It would reduce
her Marxism to a revolutionary variant of the “ethical socialism”
that she had condemned during the revisionism debate. No less than
Marx, Luxemburg believed in the ultimate victory of the working
class. “Order Reigns in Berlin,” Rosa’s famous last article, written
for Die Rote Fahnee (Red Flagg), recognizes the defeat of the Spartacus
rebellion. Nevertheless, she ends with a quotation from the radical
poet (befriended by Marx and Engels) Ferdinand Freilingrath—“The
Revolution will ‘raise itself up again clashing,’ and to your horror it
will proclaim to the sound of trumpets; ‘I was, I am, I shall be.’” That
may still be the case for the revolution; it is surely the case for Rosa
Luxemburg.
Contributors
Stephen Eric Bronnerr is currently Distinguished Professor (II) of
Political Science and director of Global Relations at the Center for the
Study of Genocide, Conflict Resolution, and Human Rights, as well
as a member of the Executive Committee of the Center for Middle
Eastern Studies at Rutgers University. The senior editor of Logos: A
Journal of Modern Society & Culture,
e Professor Bronner’s works have
been translated into a dozen languages. They include: Socialism
Unbound: Principles, Practices, Prospectss (Columbia University Press,
2011); Camus: Portrait of a Moralistt (University of Chicago Press,
2009); Critical Theory: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford University
Press, 2011); Of Critical Theory and Its Theoristss (Routledge, 2002), A
Rumor about the Jews: Anti-Semitism, Conspiracy, and the “Protocols of
Zion”” (Oxford University Press, 2003); Reclaiming the Enlightenment:
Toward a Politics of Radical Engagementt (Columbia University Press,
2006); Blood in the Sand: Imperial Fantasies, Rightwing Ambitions,
and the Erosion of American Democracyy (University Press of Kentucky,
2005); Peace Out of Reach: Middle Eastern Travels and the Search for
Reconciliation (University Press of Kentucky, 2007); and Modernism at
the Barricades: Aesthetics, Politics, Utopiaa (Columbia University Press,
2012). He is chair of the Executive Committee of US Academics for
Peace, an advisor to Conscience International, and the recipient of the
2011 ME Peace Prize from the Middle East Political Network based
in Jerusalem.
David Camfield was a graduate student in Social and Political
Thought at York University at the time his article was written. He
now teaches Labour Studies at the University of Manitoba, and is
198
●
Contributors
the author of Canadian Labour in Crisis: Reinventing the Workers’
Movementt (Fernwood Publishing, 2011).
Barry Fingerr is an editorial board member of New Politicss and a former shop steward and activist with the Public Employees Federation.
Amber Frostt is a writer and musician living in Brooklyn, NY. She has
been active with the Democratic Socialists of America since 2007.
Michael Hirsch is a veteran labor journalist, editorial board member of
New Politicss and Democratic Left,
t and contributor to the Encyclopedia
of American Strikess. A former sociology professor and steelworker, his
writing has appeared in the Village Voice,
e Crain’s New York Businesss,
Labor Notess, the New Statesman, the New York Observerr, and other
venues. He formerly worked as a staff writer for a public sector union
s
and currently blogs for Talking Union and New Politics.
Alan Johnson has worked at Edge Hill University, England, in the
Social Sciences since 1991. He was made a reader in 2001 and a professor in 2007. His research has mostly been about the intellectual
history of the Left and social movements. He was an editorial board
member at Socialist Organiserr in the 1980s, at Historical Materialism
(1999–2003) and New Politicss (1999–2003). He has been involved in
supporting Iraqi trade unions since 2003, coauthoring Hadi Never
Died: Hadi Saleh and the Iraqi Trade Unionss (TUC, 2006) with
Abdullah Muhsin. In 2005 he founded the online quarterly journal
Democratiyaa and edited 16 issues until its merger with the US journal
Dissentt in 2009. He blogs at the UK Guardian’s Comment Is Freee and
at the new transatlantic blog created by the merger of Democratiya
and Dissent,
t Arguing the Worldd. He coauthored the Euston Manifesto
and has been involved with the “Progress” think tank, especially its
Progressive Internationalism policy group. He is currently on the editorial board of Dissentt.
Paul Le Blancc is professor of History at La Roche College in
Pittsburgh, PA. He has written widely on history and social issues,
edited the Revolutionary Studies series published by Humanities
Press and Humanity Books, and is an associate editor of The
International Encyclopedia of Revolution and Protest: 1500 to the
Presentt (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009). His books include Marx, Lenin, and
Contributors
●
199
the Revolutionary Experience: Studies of Communism and Radicalism
in the Age of Globalization (Routledge, 2006); Black Liberation and
the American Dream: The Struggle for Racial Justice and Economic
Justice—Analysis, Strategy, Readingss (Humanity Books, 2003); U.S.
Labor in the Twentieth Century: Fragmentation and Insurgency,
y ed. with
John Hinshaw (Humanity Books, 2000); Rosa Luxemburg: Reflections
and Writings,
s ed. (Humanity Books, 2000); A Short History of the
U.S. Working Classs (Humanity Books, 1999); From Marx to Gramsci
(Humanities Press, 1996); and Lenin and the Revolutionary Party
(Humanities Press, 1990).
Chris Maisano is a Brooklyn-based union researcher and writer. He
is a contributing editor of Jacobin magazine and former managing
t the publication of the Democratic Socialists
editor of Democratic Left,
of America.
Jason Schulman is adjunct assistant professor of Political Science at
Lehman College, City University of New York. He is on the editorial
boards of New Politicss and Democratic Leftt and is also the recipient of
the Labor Historyy Best Dissertation Award for 2009.
Michael J. Thompson is associate professor of Political Science at
William Paterson University where he offers classes in political theory, political sociology, political psychology, and history of political
thought. His areas of research are in political and social theory, moral
philosophy, political psychology, Critical Theory, German Idealism,
Classical political thought, and Western Marxism. He is also the
founder and executive editor of Logos: A Journal of Modern Society &
Culturee. His books include Islam and the West: Critical Perspectives
on Modernity,
y ed. (Rowman and Littlefield, 2003); The Politics of
Inequality: A Political History of the Idea of Economic Inequality in
Americaa (Columbia University Press, 2007); The Politics of Inequality: A
Political History of the Idea of Economic Inequality in Americaa (Columbia
University Press, 2007); Confronting the New Conservatism: The Rise of
the Right in America, ed. (NYU Press, 2007); Fleeing the City: Studies in
the Culture and Politics of Antiurbanism, ed. (Palgrave, 2009); Rational
Radicalism and Political Theory: Essays in Honor of Stephen Eric Bronner,
r
ed. (Lexington Books, 2010); and Georg Lukács Reconsidered: Essays in
Politics, Philosophy, and Aesthetics,
s ed. (Continuum, 2011).
Index
Abramovich, Rafael, 110
Accumulation of Capital,
l The
(Luxemburg), 2, 3, 13, 45–6,
191, 192
“‘Action Will Be Taken’: Left
Anti-Intellectualism and Its
Discontents” (Featherstone,
Henwood, and Parenti), 166
Acts of Resistance: Against the Tyranny
of the Markett (Bourdieu), 139
Adler, Freidrich, 110
Adler, Max, 70
Adler, Viktor, 131
Administering Civil Society
(Neocleous), 47
Adorno, Theodor, 85, 96, 139
Afghanistan, 2, 80
Al Jazeera online newspaper, 165
Albania, 191
Algeria, 62, 191
Alien and Sedition Acts, 105
alienation, 5, 15, 40, 41, 55, 61
Allende, Salvador, 174
“American Century,” 80
American Economic Review
w journal, 97
anarchism, 8, 95
Anderson, Perry, 168, 183
anticapitalism, 45, 55, 148, 152
anti-Stalinism/anti-Stalinists, 1, 25, 60.
see alsoo Stalinism/Stalinist
Appleman Williams, William, 80
Arab Spring, 187, 190–1
Arendt, Hannah, 29, 37, 62, 73, 74,
131, 133, 157, 160–1, 164, 166
Argentina, 8, 28
Aristotle, 95
ASSÉ, 163
Augustine of Hippo (St. Augustine), 69
Austria, 9, 133, 134
Austrian Social Democracy, 111, 131
Austro-Marxism (Bottomore and
Goode, eds.), 96
authenticity, 6, 22, 56, 57, 63, 64, 69,
76, 123, 136, 144
Authenticity and Potentiality
(Bronner), 70
authoritarianism, 3, 12, 14, 16, 18,
44, 52, 53, 60, 103, 107, 109,
111, 113, 115, 123, 125, 129,
132, 135, 136, 159, 186, 189
autonomism, 8
Bacon, Sir Francis, 63
Bahrain, 191
Baku (mass strikes of 1902), 14, 191
Basso, Lelio, 9
Bauer, Otto, 110, 132
Bebel, August, 131
Bédard-Wien, Jérémie, 163, 166
Before Stalinism (Farber), 25
202
●
Index
Belated Feudalism (Orren), 97
Belgium, 178
Bellofiore, Riccardo, 10
Benzel, Jan, 183
Bergamo (Italy), 2
Berlin Alexanderplatzz (Doblin), 64
Berlin (Germany), 1, 3, 19, 49, 139,
167, 169, 195
Berlusconi, Silvio, 152
Bernstein, Eduard, 5, 25, 29, 31, 36,
40, 41, 43, 51, 58, 65, 66, 68,
69, 71, 100, 122, 127, 131, 134,
139, 188, 194
“Beyond Social Democracy”
(Miliband and Liebman), 165
black bloc, 8
Bloch, Ernst, 132, 139
Blum, Leon, 126, 132
Bolshevik Revolution, 7, 52, 110,
112–14, 188. see also Russian
Revolution (1917)
Bolsheviks/Bolshevism, 7, 14, 25,
32–3, 41–2, 52, 54, 60, 104,
110, 112–17, 132, 134, 177,
182, 188, 189. see also Leninism/
Leninists
Bonapartism, 110, 139
Bonefeld, Werner, 47
Borkenau, Franz, 133
Bourdieu, Pierre, 130, 139
bourgeois democracy, 15, 25,
40–2, 55, 105–6, 114, 130,
172, 190. see also liberal
democracy
bourgeoisie, 55, 68, 87, 89, 111, 116,
139, 176, 179, 195
Brazil, 28
Brecht, Bertolt, 126
Brenner, Robert, 3
Bronner, Stephen Eric, 3–7, 10,
21–36, 39–46, 67–71, 74–5,
79–83, 85–96, 99–118, 138,
140, 143–9, 155–6, 171–5
on bourgeois democracy/liberal
democracy, 5, 15, 25, 40–2,
52–4, 62, 65, 121, 125, 128,
129, 130–3, 135, 138
on capitalism, 12, 13, 14, 16, 17,
50, 51, 59, 65, 121, 124, 136,
137, 191–2, 195
on civil liberties, 15, 16, 53, 61,
125, 129, 135, 191
on the class ideal, 65, 70, 120,
129, 194
on Communism/Communists, 15,
16, 17, 52, 54, 59, 60–1, 132–6,
186. 187, 188, 189–90
on cosmopolitan pedagogy, 191
on critical theory, 57, 60, 63, 69
on democratic consciousness, 191
on Eduard Bernstein, 51, 58, 65,
66, 68, 69, 71, 122, 127, 131,
134, 188, 194
on ethics/ethical socialism, 17, 51,
55, 59, 64, 67, 120, 123, 127–8,
134, 192, 195
on Georg Lukács, 50, 56–7, 69,
70–1, 124, 132, 138
on the German Communist Party
(KPD), 11, 54, 132, 139, 188–9
on the German Social Democratic
Party (SPD), 52, 58, 68, 134,
187–9, 194
on Henry Pachter, 65, 190
immanent critique of Marx and
Luxemburg, 6, 56–7, 119–20,
122, 126
on the Independent Social
Democratic Party of Germany
(USPD), 68, 69
on internationalism, 12, 18, 56,
60, 64, 66, 123, 126, 187, 192
on Karl Kaustky, 14, 50, 61, 68,
70, 132, 133, 134, 139, 188
on Karl Korsch, 56–7, 62, 65, 69,
70, 132
Index
on Karl Marx, 12, 13, 50, 56, 57,
62, 63, 66, 67, 69, 121, 122,
123, 124, 126, 127, 130, 131,
186, 189, 191, 192, 195
on Lenin/Leninism, 14, 51, 52,
59–61, 66, 70, 119, 123, 124,
125, 127, 128–30, 134–6, 188,
189, 192, 194
on libertarian socialism, 12, 137,
187, 190
on Marxism, 12, 14, 16, 50–1,
55–8, 62–4, 69, 70, 120, 127,
131, 133, 139, 186, 195
on reformism, 55, 64, 137, 193–4
on revolution, 12–14, 16, 17, 50–5,
58, 59–66, 68, 121, 122–5,
127–31, 133–6, 185–95
on Rosa Luxemburg, 11–19,
49–54, 56, 57, 58–61, 65–6, 69,
119, 122, 123, 124, 125, 126,
127, 131, 134, 139, 140, 185–95
on the rule of law, 53, 54, 135, 136
on the Russian Revolution (1905),
13–14, 52, 121, 189, 191
on the Russian Revolution (1917),
14–16, 54, 69, 132, 134, 136,
186
on Social Democrats/social
democracy, 13–14, 17, 50, 52,
60, 64, 68, 69, 125, 128, 131,
132, 134, 136, 138, 139, 186,
188, 189, 190, 194, 195
on socialism, 12, 15, 16–17, 50, 53,
59, 60, 62, 63–6, 119, 121, 124,
127–9, 131, 136–8, 186, 187,
189–90, 194–5
on “socialism or barbarism,” 12,
16, 59, 128, 137, 195
on soviets/workers’ councils, 15,
16, 52–4, 54, 61–2, 65, 66, 68,
69, 120, 122, 124, 125, 127,
131–2, 134, 136, 137, 138,
187–90, 193
●
203
on ultra-leftism, 52, 60, 125, 128,
135, 188
on the Weimar Republic, 52, 140,
187
Broué, Pierre, 184
Bukharin, Nikolai, 115
bureaucracy, 15, 41, 45, 54, 104, 110,
115, 117, 132, 133
bureaucratic collectivism, 110, 133
Burgfreiden, 178
Canada, 172
Capital (Das Kapital) (Marx), 3, 28,
95, 124
“Capital Ideas” (Schmidt), 9
capitalism, 1, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 12, 13,
14, 16, 17, 23, 24–5, 30–2, 35,
40–1, 43, 45–6, 50, 51, 59, 65,
76, 77, 78, 79, 81, 86, 89, 91,
92, 94–6, 101–3, 105, 108, 110,
117–8, 121, 124, 136, 137, 142,
147, 151, 155, 157, 171, 172, 174,
191–2, 195
capitalist democracy, 44, 124, 128,
138, 169
Catalonia (Spain), 153
Change The World without Taking
Powerr (Holloway), 10
Chile, 174
China, 2, 9, 28, 60, 113, 135
Choonara, Joseph, 184
civil liberties, 15, 16, 28, 53, 61, 103,
107, 125, 129, 135, 156, 191
Civil Rights Movement, 94
class ideal, the, 65, 70, 120, 129, 194
class struggle, 5, 33, 81, 104, 113,
118, 124, 164, 165, 170, 173,
175, 178
“Class Struggles in Europe, The”
(Choonara), 184
Class Struggles in France, 1848–1850,
Thee (Marx), 69
CLASSE, 162–4
204
●
Index
Cliff, Tony, 9
COINTELPRO, 105
Communism/Communists, 1, 2, 3,
15, 16, 17, 25, 27, 41, 52, 54, 59,
60–1, 73–4, 81, 111, 112, 115,
118, 132–6, 153, 169, 181, 186.
187, 188, 189–90
Communist Manifesto, Thee (Marx and
Engels), 83, 168, 169
Communist Party of Germany
(KPD), 1, 11, 54, 132, 139,
188–9
Communist (Third) International
(Comintern), 1, 16, 57, 73, 189,
190
Complete Works of Rosa Luxemburg,
Volume 1, Thee (Hudis, ed.), 10
Conservative Party (United
Kingdom), 154
Considerations on Western Marxism
(Anderson), 184
Constituent Assembly (Russia 1918),
25, 42, 46, 53–4, 61, 175
Corrigan, Philip, 47
cosmopolitan pedagogy, 4, 9, 191
council communism, 181
Crack Capitalism (Holloway), 10
“Crises of Democratic Capitalism,
The” (Streeck), 165
Critical Models: Interventions and
Catchwordss (Adorno), 139
critical theory, 57, 60, 63, 69, 110
Of Critical Theory and Its Theorists
(Bronner), 69
Critique of the Gotha Programme
(Marx), 131, 160, 166
Crosland, Tony, 31
Cuba, 60, 62, 113, 135
Culture and Materialism: Selected
Essayss (Williams), 150
“Current Relevance of Rosa
Luxemburg’s Thought, The”
(Trincado), 9
Dan, Theodore, 110
Davanellos, Antonis, 166
democracy, 1, 4, 5, 8, 12, 15, 26,
28, 33, 39, 41, 42, 50, 53, 56,
62, 65, 73, 86–90, 94, 96, 101,
103–8, 110, 111, 112, 117, 120,
128, 129, 130–1, 133, 137, 152,
156–7, 158, 159, 175, 178, 186,
187, 188, 189–90, 193
democratic centralism, 8, 125
democratic consciousness, 4, 9, 191
Democratic Leftt magazine, 166
Democratic Party (United States), 17,
143, 153
Democratic Socialists of America
(DSA), 141, 149
Denmark, 172
determinism, 22, 32, 195
Deutscher, Issac, 174, 183
Dickens, Charles, 16, 31, 67, 34, 137
dictatorship of the proletariat, 14, 29,
41–2, 52, 87, 104, 132
Dictatorship of the Proletariat
(Kautsky), 87, 132
Die Rote Fahne (Red Flag newspaper),
195
Dies Committee, 105
direct democracy, 89, 158, 189, 193
Discourses of Extremityy (Geras), 36
Dissentt magazine, 157, 165
Doblin, Alfred, 140
Draper, Hal, 5
Dunayevskaya, Raya, 9
Dutschke, Rudi, 171
Ebert, Friedrich, 58, 68, 139, 174,
177, 178
Economics of Global Turbluence, The
(Brenner), 3
economism, 14, 25, 40, 51
Egypt, 191
Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis
Bonaparte, Thee (Marx), 183
Index
Einhorn, David, 173
Eisner, Kurt, 68
Engels, Friedrich, 9, 12, 29, 69, 78,
91, 104, 139–40, 168, 171, 195
Enigma of Capital and the Crises of
Capitalism, Thee (Harvey), 3
Erbschaft dieser Zeitt (Bloch), 139
Erfurt Program (1891), 176, 183
Essential Rosa Luxemburg, The
(Scott, ed.), 166
ethics/ethical socialism, 6, 17, 26,
51, 55, 59, 64, 67, 91, 96, 101,
102, 120, 123, 127–8, 134, 173,
192, 195
Eurocommunism, 163
European Socialists Respond to Fascism
(Horn), 68
European Union (EU), 130, 152, 182
Failure of a Revolution: Germany
1918–19199 (Haffner), 69
Failure of Illiberalism, Thee (Stern), 68
Falklands War, 34
Fall and Rise of Europe, Thee (Pachter),
184
“Fall and Rise of the U.S. Populist
Left, The” (Kazin), 165
Farber, Samuel, 25
fascism, 52, 111, 128, 131
Featherstone, Liza, 166
Fifth Republic (France), 153
Financial Times, 3
Finland, 172
First International, 83, 97
First World War, 1, 7, 14, 18, 26, 34,
43, 52, 68, 80, 107, 131, 134,
168, 170, 179, 185, 187, 189, 192
Fischer, Ruth, 183
Five Star Movement, 153
Flounder,
r Thee (Grass), 135
Fourth International, 127
France, 9, 43, 69, 89, 90, 113, 126,
153, 154, 178
●
205
France, Anatole, 169
Frankfurt School, 51, 56
Freikorps (Volunteer Corps), 1, 11
Freilingrath, Ferdinand, 195
French Popular Front, 126
French Revolution (1789), 133, 161
Freud, Sigmund, 143
Friedrichsfelde Cemetery (Germany),
167
Frölich, Paul, 9, 46–7, 139
From Marx to Gramscii (Le Blanc), 78
Fromm, Erich, 133
Front de Gauche, 154
Future of Socialism, Thee (Crosland), 31
Gardner, Lloyd, 80
gay marriage, 89, 146–7
General Agreement On Tariffs And
Trade (GATT), 109
Genoa (Italy), 82
Geras, Norman, 6, 9, 23–5, 36,
41–2, 46, 58
German Communist Party (KPD), 1,
11, 54, 132, 139, 169, 188–9
German Revolution (1918–23), 7, 47,
52–3, 68, 133–4, 167, 176–9,
182, 184, 188–9
German Revolution, 1917–1923, The
(Broué), 184
German Social Democratic Party
(SPD), 1, 2, 3, 5, 7, 37, 50, 52,
58, 67, 68, 134, 171, 176–80,
181, 184, 187, 188. see also
Majority Socialists
German Social Democracy, 1905–1917
(Schorske), 67, 184
Germany, 1, 3, 9, 15, 41, 46, 52, 54,
55, 58, 68, 69, 80, 107, 111–12,
113–14, 132, 133–4, 153, 167,
168, 170, 177–9, 182, 184, 187–8
Geschichte der Weimarer Republik
(Rosenberg), 69
Gindin, Sam, 47
206
●
Index
Global Capital, National State and the
Politics of Moneyy (Bonefeld and
Holloway), 47
“Global Capitalism and the Left”
(Panitch), 10
globalization, 2, 8, 18, 95, 124, 155,
187, 192, 193
Golden Dawn, 193
Goldner, Loren, 70
“Goodbye to the Working Class?”
(Kellogg), 37
Gorz, André, 137
Goths (of East Germany), 22
Graeber, David, 157
Gramsci, Antonio, 22, 58, 78
Grand Coalition (Italy), 153
Grass, Gunther, 135
Great Arch, Thee (Corrigan and
Sayer), 47
Greece, 154, 162, 164, 182, 193
Greenfield, Gerard, 44
Grillo, Beppe, 153
Guangzhou (China), 2, 9
Guardian (UK), 169, 183
Gulf War (1991), 34
Haase, Hugo, 68
Haffner, Sebastian, 69
“Hands off Rosa Luxemburg!”
(Trotsky), 9
Harvey, David, 2, 3
Hegel, G. W. F., 56, 63, 89, 90, 92,
93, 120, 121, 122, 126, 133,
135, 137, 140
Hegemony and Socialist Strategy
(Laclau and Mouffe), 22, 58,
144, 147
Heidegger, Martin, 63
Henwood, Doug, 166
Hilferding, Rudolf, 95, 110
historical materialism, 22, 66, 70,
108, 133, 136, 171
Historical Materialism journal, 9, 55
History and Class Consciousness
(Lukács), 56, 69, 70, 71
Hitler, Adolf, 110, 126
Hollande, François, 153
Holloway, John, 10
Hook, Sidney, 37, 62, 70
horizontalism, 7, 155, 157, 158,
159–61, 162, 165, 166, 193
“Horizontalism and the Occupy
Movements” (Sitrin), 165, 166
Horkheimer, Max, 51, 128, 133
Horn, Gerd-Rainer, 68
House Un-American Activities
Committee (HUAC), 105
Howard, Dick, 9–10
Howe, Irving, 74
Hudis, Peter, 9, 10
Hungary, 133
Husserl, Edmund, 63
Huysmans, Camille, 131
Ichan, Carl, 173
Ideas in Action (Bronner), 70, 74
Imagining the Possiblee (Bronner), 138
Imperial Germany: The Birth of the
German Republic, 1871–1918
(Rosenberg), 184
imperialism, 2, 13, 77, 79, 82, 123,
178, 192
Independent Social Democratic
Party of Germany (USPD), 47,
68, 69, 177
India, 28
indignadoss (Spain), 154
Industrial Development of Poland, The
(Luxemburg), 12
Intellectual Origins of American
Radicalism (Lynd), 159
International Monetary Fund (IMF),
109, 130
International Socialism journal, 37, 184
internationalism, 4, 5, 6, 9, 12, 18,
32, 33–4, 39, 56, 60, 64, 66, 78,
Index
79, 81, 109, 114, 123, 126, 143,
170, 175, 187, 192
Introduction to Political Economy
(Luxemburg), 3
Ireland, 182
Italian Social Democracy, 111
Italy, 2, 111, 133, 152, 153, 165, 172,
182
Jacobin magazine, 10
James, C. L. R., 7
Japan, 9
Jaurès, Jean, 131
Jefferson, Thomas, 161
Jena (Germany), 180
Jogiches, Leo, 148
Jones, William David, 68, 140
Jordan, 190
July Revolution of 1848, 53
Junius Pamphlet, Thee (Luxemburg),
13, 178, 184, 192
Kaiser Wilhelm II, 177, 179, 180, 184
Kant, Immanuel, 19, 63, 92–3, 121
Kapp Putsch (1920), 188
Karl Kautsky and the Socialist
Revolution, 1880–1938
(Salvadori), 37
Karl und Rosaa (Doblin), 140
Kausalitaet und Teleologie im Streit
um die Wissenschaftt (Adler), 70
Kautsky, Karl, 14, 30, 37, 41, 50, 61,
68, 69, 70, 87, 110, 113, 132, 133,
134, 139, 171, 176, 181, 188
Kazin, Michael, 157, 165
Kellner, Douglas, 69
Kellog, Paul, 37
Kelly, Christine A., 70
Kernpunkte der materialischen
Geschichtsauffassung
(Korsch), 70
“Keynesian consensus,” 8
Kierkegaard, Søren, 57, 120
●
207
Kiev (Ukraine), 191
Koch Brothers, 173
Kolakowski, Leszek, 51, 186
Kolko, Gabriel, 80
Korsch, Karl, 26, 56–7, 62, 65, 69,
70, 100, 110, 132, 183
Kosovan conflict, 34
Kronstadt Rebellion (1921), 52
Kuroń, Jacek, 5
labor movement, 6, 7, 11, 13, 14,
15, 16, 17, 27, 36, 43, 54, 64,
66, 68, 81, 82, 93, 97, 102, 118,
124, 128, 131, 137, 151, 152,
180, 181, 182, 185, 188, 195.
see also trade unions
Labor Party (United Kingdom), 31,
36, 153, 154, 174
Laclau, Ernesto, 22, 57, 70, 144–5
Lafargue, Paul, 65
LaFeber, Walter, 80
Landwehr Canal, 149, 167
Laurat, Lucien, 110
Lavoisier, Antoine, 95
Lebowitz, Michael A., 46
Left Communists, 115
Left Mensheviks, 30, 116
Left Party (Die Linke), 169
Left Social-Revolutionaries, 135
Left-Wing Communism: An Infantile
Disorderr (Lenin), 183
Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg,
g The
(Geras), 9, 23, 36, 46
legitimating theory, 22–3, 36, 57, 144
“Lenin and Rosa Luxemburg”
(Shachtman), 9
Lenin and the Revolutionary Party
(Le Blanc), 78
Lenin, V. I., 5, 9, 14, 25–6, 27, 30,
33, 51, 52, 59–61, 78–9, 112,
114–16, 123, 124, 125, 127, 131,
134–6, 168–9, 181, 182, 183,
188, 189, 190, 192, 194
208
●
Index
Leninism/Leninists, 3, 8, 23,
59–60, 66, 70, 76, 78, 109–11,
113–14, 119, 123, 125, 127–9,
135–6, 148, 176, 190. see also
Bolsheviks/Bolshevism
Lerner, Abba, 95, 97
Letters of Rosa Luxemburg,
g Thee (Alder,
Hudis, and Laschitza, eds.), 2, 9
Letters of Rosa Luxemburg,
g The
(Bronner, ed.), 21
Levi, Paul, 52
liberal democracy, 5, 53, 104–5,
107, 112, 121, 125, 128, 129,
138, 151, 190. see also bourgeois
democracy
Liberal Democrats (United
Kingdom), 154
liberalism, 28, 36, 52, 86, 91, 92–6,
97, 111, 131
libertarian Marxism, 190
libertarian socialism, 12, 137, 187, 190
Libya, 191
Liebknecht, Karl, 1, 167, 170, 176,
177, 188
Liebknecht, Wilhelm, 50, 131, 195
Liebman, Marcel, 156, 165, 183
Literature of Revolution (Geras), 36
Lithuania, 1
Logoss online journal, 85, 119
Lost Debate, Thee (Jones), 68, 140
Lowenthal, Richard, 133
Lübeck, Gustav, 148
Lukács, Georg, 26, 50, 56–7, 69,
70–1, 100, 110, 124, 132, 138
Luxemburg, Rosa, 1–9, 10, 11–19,
21–2, 23–26, 27, 28–9, 31,
32, 33, 34, 36, 37, 39–46, 47,
49–54, 56, 57, 58–61, 65–6, 69,
100, 102, 104, 106, 108, 112,
114, 117, 119, 122, 123, 124,
125, 126, 127, 131, 134, 139,
140, 141, 142, 143, 144, 145,
147, 149, 155, 156, 157, 160–2,
164–5, 167–71, 173–5, 176, 177,
178–9, 180–1, 182, 183, 184,
185–95
belief in the ultimate “breakdown”
of capitalism, 12, 24, 45, 59
on the mass strike, 2, 14–15, 24,
36, 58, 131, 162, 164, 165, 166,
180, 188–9, 191, 193, 194
on national self-determination, 12,
32, 60, 192
on proletarian/socialist democracy,
6, 24, 41–2, 58
on the Russian Revolution (1917),
2, 4, 15, 37, 41–2, 46, 54, 134,
170, 183, 186
as (secular) Jew, 1, 11, 185
on Social Democratic revisionism,
2, 14, 40, 50–1, 69, 127, 193,
195
on “socialism or barbarism,” 6,
7, 12, 16, 25, 31, 59, 128, 171,
194–5
and spontaneity, 7, 27, 73, 157,
161–2, 181, 193–4
on working-class self-administration,
15, 194
“Luxemburg versus Lenin” (Mattick), 9
Lynd, Staughton, 159, 166
Machiavelli, Niccolò, 19
Majority Socialists. seee German
Social Democratic Party (SPD)
Malaysia, 28
Mandel, Ernest, 35, 36
Mannheim (Germany), 180
Maoism/Maoists, 111, 113, 163
Marx, Karl, 2–3, 9, 12, 13, 21, 22,
27, 28, 29, 35, 39, 40, 50, 56, 57,
62, 63, 66, 67, 69, 78, 89–90,
91, 92, 93, 95, 102, 104, 121,
122, 123, 124, 126, 127, 130,
131, 160, 166, 168, 171, 172,
174, 186, 189, 191, 192, 195
Index
Marxism and Democracyy (Laurat), 110
Marxism and Philosophy (Korsch) 57,
70, 183
Marxism: Last Refuge of the
Bourgeoisie?? (Mattick), 184
Marxism/Marxists, 1, 2, 3, 4, 6, 8,
12, 14, 16, 21–3, 26–7, 29–30,
32, 33, 34, 35, 36, 39, 42, 50–1,
55–8, 62–4, 69, 70, 73, 75,
78–9, 81, 91, 92, 100, 113, 120,
127, 131, 133, 139, 141, 143,
144, 145, 149, 155, 169, 171,
172, 173, 175, 176, 183, 184,
186, 195
analysis of capitalism, 5, 81, 124
Austro-Marxism/Austro-Marxists,
110, 156
base and superstructure model, 94
classical Marxism, 39, 81, 186
critical Marxism, 100, 110
European labor/socialist
movement, 102, 168
golden age of Marxism (1889–1914),
16, 42, 51, 186
Marxist political theory, 30
Marxist political tradition, 74
orthodox Marxism, 57, 70, 139, 171
scientific status of Marxism, 6, 16,
26–7, 50, 62–3, 91, 120, 127,
171, 172, 192, 195
vulgar Marxism, 94, 147, 175
Western Marxism, 63, 69, 183
Marxists, Thee (Mills), 73
Mass Strike, the Party, and the Trade
Unions, Thee (Luxemburg), 2, 14,
162, 164, 166, 191, 193, 194
Mattick, Paul, 9, 181, 184
McCarthyism, 105
Mehring, Franz, 122
Mélenchon, Jean-Luc, 154
Mensheviks, 1, 30, 116
Mexico, 8
Michels, Roberto, 125, 180
●
209
Miliband, Ralph, 156, 165
militarism, 1, 3, 13, 125, 178, 179, 192
Mill, John Stuart, 95
Mills, C. Wright, 73
Mishel, Lawrence, 183
Modzelewski, Karol, 5
Moments of Decision (Bronner), 68,
74, 140, 183
Montesquieu, 133
Monthly Review
w magazine, 46
Monti, Mario, 152, 153
Montréal (Canada), 162
Moody, Kim, 47
Morgan, David W., 68
Morris, William, 35
Moscow (Russia), 177
Mouffe, Chantal, 22, 57, 70, 144–5
Munich (Germany), 188
national liberation, 5, 18
national self-determination, 12,
32–3, 60, 62, 66, 99, 123, 192
nationalism, 13, 16, 18, 33, 60, 192
Nazis/Nazi Germany, 68, 80, 132,
133, 140, 167–8, 187, 188
Negative Dialecticss (Adorno), 96
Neocleous, Mark, 47
neoliberalism, 3, 8, 11, 17, 31, 39, 43,
44, 45, 64, 89, 101, 126, 142,
152, 153, 170, 175, 192
Netherlands, 154
Nettl, J. P., 46, 74
Neumann, Franz, 133
New Economic Policy (NEP), 116,
117
New Imperialism, Thee (Harvey), 2
New Left (1960s), 2, 9–10, 168–9
New Left Projectt online journal, 10
New Left Review
w journal, 165
New Politicss magazine, 4, 5–6, 10,
49, 55, 70, 75, 85, 100, 119, 142,
155, 171
New York City (United States), 154
210
●
Index
North American Free Trade
Agreement (NAFTA), 109
North Atlantic Treaty Organization
(NATO), 33–4, 109
Noske, Gustav, 68, 176
Occupy Wall Street (OWS), 7, 8,
143–4, 148, 149, 154–5, 157–8,
159, 160–1, 163, 164–5, 166, 192
Odessa (Ukraine), 191
Open Door Policy, 80
operative theory, 22–3, 57
“Order Reigns in Berlin”
(Luxemburg), 195
Organizational Questions of
Russian Social Democracy, The
(Luxemburg), 2, 125, 194
Origins of the Family, Private
Property, and the State, The
(Engels), 139–40
Origins of Totalitarianism, The
(Arendt), 37
Our Political Taskss (Trotsky), 96
OUR Walmart, 154
Pachter, Henry, 65, 68, 69, 70, 71,
74, 136, 139, 174, 178, 184, 190
Palestinian refugees, 130
Palmer Raids, 105
Panitch, Leo, 8, 10
Parenti, Christian, 166
Paris Commune, 14, 15, 52, 87, 90,
104, 107, 161, 175
Permanence of the Political,
l The
(Schwartz), 166
Phenomenology of Mind,
d The
(Hegel), 140
Philippines, 80
piqueteros, 8
Plekhanov, Georgi, 50
Poland, 1, 12, 192
Political Writings, 1919–29
(Lukács), 69
“Politics as a Vocation” (Weber), 60
Pollack, Friedrich, 133
Porter, Matt, 166
Portugal, 182
positivism, 26, 62, 92
post-Marxism, 22, 36, 144–5
Poverty of Theory, Thee (Thompson), 37
Prague (Czech Republic), 82
proletarian democracy, 6, 24, 58.
see also socialist democracy
proletariat, 12, 13, 14, 16, 24, 27–8,
29, 32, 41, 42, 43, 50, 52, 67,
70, 87, 104, 113, 116, 130, 132,
139, 170, 172–3, 177, 178–9,
180, 186, 194, 195.
see also working class
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 122
Prussia, 179
Québec (Canada), 162–3, 166
“Québec Students Strike for Free
Higher Education” (Porter and
Svart), 166
queer theory, 7, 147
Quest for Evolutionary Socialism, The
(Steger), 139
“Rank and File Strategy: Building a
Socialist Movement in the
U.S., The” (Moody), 47
Reagan, Ronald, 36
“Reclaiming a Socialist Vision”
(Lebowitz), 46
Red Pepperr magazine, 10
Reform or Revolution (Luxemburg), 2,
14, 40, 43, 46, 47, 166
reformism, 55, 30, 43, 64, 93, 94,
112, 118, 137, 142, 156, 162,
180, 193–4. see also revisionism
reification, 57, 94, 136, 137
Renner, Karl, 87
Republican Party (United States),
153, 193
Index
republicanism, 4, 6, 14, 28, 29–30,
32, 43, 44, 52, 54, 60, 61, 62,
65, 68, 87, 88, 90, 91, 105, 111,
155–7, 187, 189, 190
revisionism (social democratic), 2,
5, 14, 40–1, 43, 50, 51, 65–6,
69, 71, 75, 100–1, 179–80, 193,
195. see also reformism
revolution, 2, 4, 6, 7, 9, 12–14, 16,
17, 23, 24, 25, 26, 28, 29, 30,
34, 35, 36, 37, 40, 41–2, 43, 46,
47, 50–5, 58, 59–66, 68, 73,
90, 94, 104, 107–8, 109, 110,
111, 112, 113–14, 115–17, 121,
122–5, 127–31, 133–6, 144,
145, 156, 161, 162, 164, 166,
167, 168, 170, 171, 172, 173,
175, 177, 179, 181, 182, 185–95
On Revolution (Arendt), 161, 166
“Revolutionary Rosa Luxemburg,
The” (Rowbotham), 183
revolutionary socialism/socialists,
23, 25, 30, 78–9, 80, 81, 82, 83,
104, 106, 107, 110, 131, 178
Revolutionary Theoryy (Korsch), 69
“Right To Be Lazy, The”
(Lafargue), 65
Rome, 22, 144
“Rosa in Cairo” (Bronner), 10
Rosa Luxemburgg (Cliff), 9
Rosa Luxemburg: A Reappraisal
(Basso), 9
Rosa Luxemburg: A Revolutionary for
Our Timess (Bronner), 3, 21, 36,
69, 185
Rosa Luxemburg Foundation
(Berlin), 19
Rosa Luxemburg: Her Life and Work
(Frölich), 9, 46–7
“Rosa Luxemburg: More Than a
Revolutionary” (Benzel), 183
Rosa Luxemburg Reader,
r Thee (Hudis
and Anderson, eds.), 2
●
211
Rosa Luxemburg Speakss (Waters, ed.),
37, 46, 69
Rosa Luxemburg, Women’s Liberation,
and Marx’s Philosophy of
Revolution (Dunayevskaya), 9
Rosa-Luxemburg-Platz (Germany),
169
Rosenberg, Arthur, 69, 140, 179, 184
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 15, 58
Rowbotham, Sheila, 169, 183
Russia, 9, 15, 29, 46, 52, 54, 87, 110,
112, 113–14, 116, 117, 162, 177,
178, 181, 190
Russian Civil War, 115, 135, 187
Russian Empire, 13, 14, 191
Russian Revolution (1905), 2, 13–14,
24, 41, 87, 52, 113, 121, 162,
189, 191
Russian Revolution (1917), 14–16,
26, 30, 41–2, 54, 69, 109–10,
111, 118, 132, 134, 136, 186.
see also Bolshevik Revolution
Russian Revolution, Thee (Liebman),
183
Russian Revolution, Thee (Luxemburg),
2, 4, 15, 37, 41–2, 46, 170, 183,
186
Russian Social Democratic (Labor)
Party, 188. see also Bolsheviks,
Mensheviks
Rwanda, 33–4, 80
Salvadori, Massimo, 37
Schmidt, Ingo, 10
Schorske, Carl E., 67, 179, 180, 181,
184
Schwartz, Joseph M., 166
Scott, Helen, 166
Seattle, Washington (United States),
6–7, 17, 46, 82, 143–4, 145, 147
Second French Empire, 139
Second (Socialist) International, 26,
27, 40, 42, 43, 73, 83, 91, 92, 189
212
●
Index
Second World War, 80, 110
Selected Political Writings of Rosa
Luxemburg (Howard, ed.), 10, 37
Serge, Victor, 176, 183
Shachtman, Max, 9, 25
Sierra Leone, 80
Silesius, Angelus, 69–70
Sitrin, Marina, 157, 158, 159, 165,
166
Smith, Adam, 95
Social Democratic Party of Germany
(SPD). see German Social
Democratic Party
Social Democrats/social democracy,
2, 8, 13–14, 17, 27, 30, 41, 44,
50, 52, 60, 64, 68, 69, 74, 91,
100, 110, 111, 112, 113, 125,
128, 131, 132, 134, 136, 138,
139, 151, 153, 165, 166, 167,
171, 174, 176, 181, 184, 186,
188, 189, 190, 194, 195
Social Democracy of the Kingdom
of Poland and Lithuania
(SDKPiL), 1
Social Researchh journal, 183
socialism, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 9, 12, 15,
16–17, 24, 25, 27, 28, 29, 30, 31,
32, 34, 35, 36, 39, 40, 41, 43,
46, 47, 50, 53, 59, 60, 62, 63–6,
73, 75, 76–7, 78, 79, 81, 86,
88, 89, 90, 91–2, 94–5, 100–2,
105–6, 108, 109, 110, 111,
112–13, 114, 115, 119, 121, 124,
127–9, 131, 136–8, 148, 156,
168, 170, 171, 173, 174, 178,
179, 180, 182, 186, 187, 189–90,
194–5. see also ethical socialism,
revolutionary socialism
Socialism in History: Political Essays of
Henry Pachterr (Bronner, ed.), 71
Socialism Unboundd (Bronner), 60, 67,
69, 70, 71, 74, 139
“Socialism with Sober Senses:
Developing Workers’ Capacities”
(Gindin), 47
socialist democracy, 41–2.
see also proletarian democracy
socialist feminism, 7, 146, 147
On Socialist Man (Deutscher), 183
Socialist Party (Netherlands), 154
“Socialist Project, The” (Bronner), 183
Socialist Registerr journal, 47, 165
Socialist Strategy for Western Europe,
A (Mandel), 37
Socialist Studies / Études socialistes
journal, 9
socialists, 5, 6, 7, 22, 23, 25, 26,
30, 34, 61, 64, 68, 78–9, 80,
81, 82, 83, 88, 93, 104, 105,
106, 107, 110, 112, 115, 128,
131, 137, 138, 141, 148, 149,
156, 157, 167, 178, 182.
see also revolutionary socialists
South Africa, 28
South Korea, 28
soviets (workers’ councils), 5, 6, 15,
16, 25, 28–9, 41, 43, 46, 47,
52–4, 54, 61–2, 65, 66, 68, 69,
86–90, 96, 99, 100, 105, 107,
111, 120, 122, 124, 125, 127,
131–2, 134, 136, 137, 138,
145–6, 147, 148, 155–7, 161,
175, 181, 187–90, 193
Soviet Union, 16, 54, 61, 114
1918 constitution of, 115
Second All-Russian Congress of, 116
Spain, 153, 182
Spanish Civil War, 107
Spanish-American War, 80
Spartacus League (Spartakusbund),
1, 28, 37, 54, 139, 148, 170, 177,
181, 183, 188
Spartacus Revolt (1919), 1, 11, 15, 52,
68, 111, 187, 195
Index
St. Petersburg (Russia), 87, 177, 191
Stalin and German Communism
(Fischer), 183
Stalin, Josef, 1, 25, 59–60, 110, 117,
169
Stalinism, 2, 3, 9, 25, 27, 28, 44, 45,
66, 110–11, 113, 114, 118, 133
Stalinist bureaucracy, 110, 132, 133
State and Revolution (Lenin), 115
State of Working America, The
(Mishel et al, eds.), 183
Steger, Manfred B., 139
Steinberg, Issac, 135
Stern, Fritz, 68
Streeck, Wolfgang, 151, 165
Sukowa, Barbara, 167
Sunkara, Bhaskar, 10
Svart, Maria, 166
SYRIZA, 153, 162, 163, 164, 166,
182, 192–3
Tale of Two Cities, A (Dickens), 67, 71
Tangled Up in Red, White and Blue
(Kelly), 70
teleology, 4, 6, 7, 12, 17, 21, 22, 23,
24, 27, 32, 46, 53, 56, 59, 64,
91, 92, 102, 113, 120, 121, 124,
127, 135, 138, 171, 194
terror (Bolshevik/Communist), 15,
25, 41, 54, 59, 61, 112, 115, 134,
136, 190
Thailand, 28
Thatcher, Margaret, 36, 126
Thompson, E. P. (Edward), 37, 168
Towards the Understanding of Karl
Marxx (Hook), 26, 37, 62, 70
trade unions, 2, 7, 14, 28, 36, 44, 61,
78, 82, 87, 91, 95, 103, 115, 116,
117, 153, 162, 168, 173, 174,
176, 179–80, 181, 186, 191, 194
conservatism of leadership of,
179–80, 181, 186
●
213
Trincado, Estrella, 2, 9
Trotsky, Leon, 9, 14, 25–6, 35, 51,
78, 87, 96, 115, 178, 184, 189
Trotskyism/Trotskyists, 8, 133, 163
Turkey, 28
Two Souls of Socialism, Thee (Draper), 5
UNESCO, 130
unions. see trade unions
United Kingdom (UK), 153, 154, 172
United Nations Relief and Works
Agency, 130
United Nations (UN), 5, 31, 65, 109,
130
United States (US), 2, 9, 26, 31, 44,
70, 76, 79, 80, 153, 154, 164,
172, 173, 182, 193
US Left, 22, 159
University of Zurich, 185
USA Patriot Act, 105
utopianism, 14, 16, 28, 50, 51, 63,
65, 73, 74, 90, 100, 102, 131,
138, 143, 173, 189
Utopie-Kreativv journal, 19
verticalism, 157, 162
Vico, Giambattista, 70
von Hindenburg, Paul, 177
von Trotta, Margarethe, 168
Walker, Governor Scott, 154
War and the International,
l The
(Trotsky), 184
Washington, D.C. (United States), 82
Weber, Max, 60, 133
Weimar Etudess (Pachter), 68, 69, 70,
139
Weimar Republic, 52, 140, 187
Western Marxism. see Marxism
What Does the Spartacus League
Want?? (Luxemburg), 28, 37,
148, 170, 183
214
●
Index
“Where Did SYRIZA Come From?”
(Davanellos), 166
“Why We Loved the Zapatistas”
(Sunkara), 10
Williams, Raymond, 22, 23, 56, 144,
150
Wisconsin (United States), 154, 164
workers’ councils. seee soviets
working class, 5, 6, 7, 14, 15, 22,
25, 27–8, 32, 34, 37, 40, 41,
43, 44, 45–6, 47, 51, 66, 68,
75, 77–8, 79, 81, 82–3, 87–8,
90, 97, 101, 102–3, 104, 105,
106, 108, 109, 111, 112,
113–14, 117–18, 122, 123,
124, 125, 132, 134–5, 136,
140, 143, 145, 146, 164, 167,
170, 172, 175, 176, 178, 179,
182, 187, 194, 195.
see also proletariat
“Working-Class Politics in the
Canadian State 2000” (New
Socialist Group), 47
World Bank, 109
World Trade Organization (WTO),
95, 109, 143
Year One of the Russian Revolution
(Serge), 183
Zapatistas, 8, 10
Zuccotti Park, 157–8, 161