The Philosophical Implications of Set Theory in Infinity
Carson Lam Kai Shun
[email protected]
University of Hong Kong
Faculty of Science, Department of Mathematics
Abstract: What does the term “Infinity” mean? There are mathematical, physical and metaphysical definitions of the concept of limitlessness. This study will focus on the scription of the
three philosophical foundations of mathematics – formalism, intuitionism and logicism – in set
theory. Examples will also be provided of the concept of infinity for these three schools of thought.
However, none of them cannot prove whether there is an infinite set or the existence of infinity. It
forms the foundational crisis of mathematics. Further elaboration on these schools of philosophy
leads to the ideas of actual, potential and absolute boundlessness. These correspond to three basic
aforementioned definitions of infinity. Indeed for example, by using Basic Metaphor Infinity,
cognitive mechanisms such as conceptual metaphors and aspects, one can appreciate the transfinite
cardinals’ beauty fully (Nũńez, 2005). This implies the portraiture for endless is anthropomorphic.
In other words, because there is a connection between art and mathematics through infinity, one can
enjoy the elegance of boundlessness (Maor, 1986). Actually, in essence this is what mathematics is:
the science of researching the limitless.
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2815293
1. Introduction
What is the concept of infinity? According to the Encyclopaedia Britannica, one may refer
to infinity as the concept about something which is endless, unlimited, or without bounds 1. In 1657,
English mathematician John Wallis introduced the common symbol “∞” for infinity. One can
categorise the concept according to three schools of thought:
1. Mathematically: the number of points on a continuous line; or
the size of endless sequence in counting numbers: 1,2,3,….
2. Physically: whether the number of stars are infinite; or
whether the universe will last forever.
3. Meta-Physically: the discussion of God1.
It is therefore important to begin investigating the term “Infinity” with these definitions in mind.
Moreover, in the 19th century, Georg Cantor proposed what he called “transfinite numbers” from
set theory. This in turn caused a great dispute between himself and Leopold Kronecker. Thus, one
needs to understand how the philosophical implications for infinity in modern set theory.
2. Literature Review
In order to resolve the conflict between Cantor and Kronecker, one needs first to understand
the arguments behind them. The following sections will describe their differing perceptions in the
foundations of mathematical philosophy concerning infinity.
2.1 Cantor's Formalization of Infinity
What is Cantor's mathematical definition of infinity? He developed the idea through set
algebra and proposed what can be termed as “Infinity Arithmetic”. Indeed, Cantor tried earlier to
formalize his ideas and that connected infinity and infinite sets 2. The origin of Cantor’s ideas and
their subsequent development will be explained in more depth in the following paragraph.
2.1.1 Origin of Cantor's Theory – Galileo's Paradox
Galileo Galilei (1564 – 1642) was a Physicist, mathematician and astronomer 3. He noticed
that there are equally as many natural numbers as there are perfect squares of natural numbers
(Velickovic, 2010). One can draw one-to-one correspondence. For example:
1 is assigned to 1,
2 is assigned to 22 = 4,
3 is assigned to 32 = 9…..etc.
It should be noted that f is said to be one-to-one if x1≠ x2 ⇒ f(x1)≠ f(x2), however there may exist y∈Y
but one cannot find an x∈X and f(x) = y. Therefore, the number of X ≤ the number of Y. However,
the set of square natural numbers is properly contained in the set of all natural numbers (Velickovic,
2010). That is the number of Y ≤ the number of X. Therefore, one may conclude the number of X =
number of Y. There must be a one-to-one and onto mapping (bijection) between these two sets of
numbers3. To be more precise, one will have the following (as described by Velickovic, 2010):
Definition 2.1.1.1: For any given two sets X and Y
One may write X ≼Y if there exists an injection from X to Y; One may write X ≈ Y if there
exists a bijection between X and Y.
1
http://global.britannica.com/topic/infinity-mathematics#toc252429
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity
3
http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/%7Eschectex/courses/infinity.pdf
2
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2815293
X ≼Y
X ≈Y
Surjective mapping
This leads to the following theorem:
Theorem 2.1.1.2 (Cantor - Bernstein): Suppose
4
X ≼Y and Y ≼ X , then X ≈ Y .
Brief Proof (Rao, 2009): This means that there is an injection mapping from X to Y. Also there is an
injection mapping from Y to X. Hence by definition, for every element in Y, there is at most one
pre-image element in X such that f(x) = y. i.e. number of X ≤ number of Y. Similarly for every
element in X, there is at most one pre-image element in Y s.t. g(y) = x. i.e. the number of elements
in Y ≤ the number of elements in X. Thus, the number of X = number of Y. There must be a
bijection mapping between X and Y. Details of the proof will be shown as follows 5.
Proposition 2.1.1.3: X is infinite iff X ≈ X / { x } , for any x ∈ X .
Definition 2.1.1.4: X is countable if X ≈ ℕ .
The author notes that a set X is countable if one can find a bijection between X and ℕ
or some subset of ℕ . Thus one may conclude that for any finite set X is countable (when a
bijection exists between X and subset {0, 1, 2,…..m-1} where m = size of X) (Rao, 2009).
2.1.2 Cantor's Transfinite Number
As previously mentioned, the number of elements in a set is important in
determining the countable properties of it. Thus, one has the following circumscriptions:
Definition 2.1.2.1: The number of elements in a set X is defined as cardinality and denoted as |X|.
Where the cardinal is called the transfinite number.
Definition 2.1.2.2 (Bulatov, 2012): | ℕ | is denoted by ˳א.
Theorem 2.1.2.3 (Cantor): The set of rational numbers ℚ is countable.
Proof (Schechter, 2002, Rao, 2009; Velickovic, 2010): It is obvious that ℕ ⊂ ℚ .The
n
| ℕ | ≤ | ℚ |. Therefore our goal is to prove ℚ ⊂ ℕ or| ℚ |≤ | ℕ |. One may erect a
f: ℚ → ℕ with the later diagram of a spiral transmits the concept of this function:
4
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bijection,_injection_and_surjection
http://math.gmu.edu/~tlim/bernstein.pdf
5
One may further construct the following ordered pairs:
(1, 1), (2, 1), (1, 2), (1, 3), (2, 2), (3, 1)…..
then write each pair as a fraction:
1 / 1, 2 / 1, 1 / 2, 1 / 3, 2 / 2, 3 / 1…..
before deleting those repeated pair and mapping them to 1, 2 , 3 , 4, 5…..
1 / 1, 2 / 1, 1 / 2, 1 / 3, 3 / 1…..
↓
↓
↓
↓
↓
1
2
3
4
5…..
Obviously, the above mapping is an injection between ℚ and ℕ and hence | ℚ |≤ | ℕ |.
Onewi
l
lha
v
e ℚ ≼ℕ The
r
e
f
or
e
,wi
t
ht
he
or
e
m 2.1.1.2, one will get ℚ ≈ ℕ a
ndby
de
ini
t
i
on2.1.1.4, ℚ is countable. It seems straightforward but the violation found was so
amazing such that Cantor said "I see this result, but just cannot believe it!” (Maor, 1986: p.83)
Thus, the members of the set fraction's collection is dense, but the number of members and
the difference in the distance of natural numbers are equal (Maor, 1986). Studying this, Cantor
decided to give a label to the collection of a countable number, which is called them a power of ˳א. (
אis pronounced as "aleph", the first Hebrew letter). A collection of power ˳אand natural numbers
have the same number, so are countable (Maor,1986).
In addition, from the above proof, one may ask (as did Cantor): “Are all infinite sets
countable?” (Maor, 1986: p.84) To answer this question, this study suggests using the following
theorem below:
Theorem 2.1.2.4 (Cantor): The set of real numbers ℝ is uncountable.
Proof: (Rao, 2009, Maor, 1986) On the contrary, suppose there is a bijection f: ℕ → ℝ [0, 1].
One can enumerate the infinite list in general as follows :
r1 = 0.a1a2a3…..
r2 = 0.b1b2b3…..
r3 = 0.c1c2c3…..
……………….
where ai, bi, ci is selected from ℕ
Then one may choose those diagonals such that where it forms a new real number r = 0.a 1b2c3…..
Now consider the real number “s” obtained by modifying every digit of r, say by replacing each
digit xi with xi+2 mod 10. This study claims that “s” will not appear in the above list of infinite real
numbers. Conversely, suppose that “s” existed, and it was the n th number in the list. Then r is
differed from s in the nth digit xn: the nth digit of s is the nth digit of r plus 2 mod 10. That is s ≠ rn
for any rn in [0, 1]. Hence “s” is a real number but obviously not in the range of f. This will
contradict the fact that f is a bijection. ℝ is therefore uncountable. Cantor used the letter “C” to
represent the power אfor set rational numbers (Maor, 1986).
In such a way, Cantor developed hierarchical orders for infinity. For example, the power א
named C in such a set is higher than the hierarchy of set with power ˳א. However, there will not be
an infinite set with hierarchy of power lower than ;˳אeven if one tries to form a set of ℕ 2 and
deleted all the non- ℕ 2, the result remains the same (Maor, 1986).
2.1.3 The Arithmetic of Transfinite Cardinal Number
Consider the subsets of set S = {a, b, c}, one can have {a}, {b}, {c}, {a, b}, {a, c}, {b, c}
together with empty set { } and the original set {a, b, c} (Maor, 1986). In total there are eight
subsets from the set which contains three elements. One calls the collection of these subsets power
set P(S). There are 23 such subsets. The result can be extended to any finite set consisting of n
elements and has 2n elements for the power set P(N). Similarly, Cantor expanded the consequence
to the infinite sets. When one considers the power set P(inf) of any infinite set, the numbers of
elements of such a set P(inf) is greater than that of original set. This way of thinking was
revolutionary and unbelievable in Cantor's time (Maor, 1986).
Cantor came to a conclusion: If one starts from any finite or infinite set S, one can create a
new set P(S) which has more elements than set S (Maor, 1986). By repeating this process, one can
make more new power set. Thus, one can have infinitely hierarchical infinite sets, each new power
set introduces a larger new set with larger א. Cantor used 2 ˳א,
4 ˳אwhere in the hierarchy, those sets with same cardinal number are with one to one
correspondence, while those sets with different numbers cannot be one to one (Maor, 1986).
The cardinal number ˳א,
2 ˳א,
(22) ˳א,
Cantor named transfinite cardinal numbers. In the case of a finite set, the hierarchical relationship
is: n < 2n < (22)n <….. .When one expands these transfinite cardinal numbers, one will have
< ˳א
2 < ˳א
(22)… < ˳א..
Hence, by extending the above comparison, Cantor established so called arithmetic transfinite
cardinal numbers which have some strange rules:
1 + ˳א˳ = א,
ℵ
0
+ ℵ
ℵ
0
. ℵ
0
0
= ℵ
= ℵ
0
0
To conclude, Cantor tried to develop those philosophies concerning infinite sets of different sizes 2.
Nevertheless, his formalism caused a great deal of controversy with Kronecker's Finitism – an
extreme case of intuitionism. This will be discussed more in depth in the next section.
2.2 Kronecker's Finitism & Intuitive Objections to Transfinite Number
Kronecker's Finitism is a form of mathematical philosophy that accepts the presence of only
finite mathematical objects 6. It is therefore best understood when one compares it to the
conventional philosophy of mathematics where infinite mathematical objects (e.g., infinite sets) are
considered as reasonable. The major concept of finitistic mathematics is asserting the non-existence
of infinite objects, e.g. infinite sets. One will consider all natural numbers as existing. However, the
set of all natural numbers is thought to be non-existing as a mathematical object. Therefore any
quantification over infinite domains is not relevant. One of the most famous mathematical theories
in finitism is Skolem's primitive recursive arithmetic 6.
Indeed one can prove the non-existence of infinite sets through the following counter example 7:
6
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Finitism
Consider a set S = {66454517, 3, 507}, one can rewrite it as: 66454517
03
507
1. Construct a number from a diagonal where one will take the “units” digit from the first number,
i.e. “7” in this case.
2. Next one gets the “tens” digit from the following number by adding a zero before “3”.
3. Continue the recursive process, one will have “507” which is just in the set S.
4. The last step is to change each digit in the “found” number to any other digit. For example, 5
changes to 9, 0 changes to 1 and 7 could change to 1 also.
5. The result is “911”.
However, the number is not in the set. This counter example tells us that one cannot have a
complete set of ALL natural numbers as one will always find some numbers not in the set.
Cantor's proof assumes that “infinitely many” is a valid idea and is employed in disproving the
above counter argument. According to Cantor, one can always create a number that is not in the set
S but has “infinitely many” digits. Hence the created number is not a natural one and consequently
must not be in the set S.
Even if one accepts that “infinitely many” is valid, the counter example is still true. This is
because some digits created by the aforementioned recursive process have a finite number of digit
places away from the lowest-value digit. At the same time, other digits must have an infinite
number of places away from the lowest-value digit. Obviously, there is an inconsistency which
should not occur since the recursive process is uniform. Therefore, finitism demonstrates that
Cantor's formalization of an infinite set is invalid and only finite sets exist.
These serious criticisms were one of the reasons why Cantor became gloomy (Maor, 1986).
His former teacher, famous mathematician Leopold Kronecker, tried to attack transfinite numbers
even more. In fact, Kronecker was very conservative and was not only resisting the concept of the
infinite, but also commenting on those mathematical theories based on natural numbers. The reason
for these attacks was not purely academic but also due to jealousy. He saw his student' s reputation
becoming greater than his own. Sadly, Cantor died in a mental hospital in 1918 (Maor, 1986).
To summarize, through Kronecker's finitism (the non-existence of infinite sets) and an
intuitive recursive process, one can illustrate that there are no Cantor transfinite numbers and hence
all philosophies mentioned in section 2.1 fail. After reviewing the relation between infinite sets and
formalism and intuitionism, this study will proceed to discuss Dedekind and logicism in the next
section.
2.3 Dedekind's Infinite set & Logicism
According to Dedekind8:
“A set X is infinite if only if it is equivalent to a proper subset of itself 8.”
Given sets S and T, they are said to be equivalent if only if there exists a bijection
f: S → T
between elements of S and those of T9.
7
http://www.extremefinitism.com/blog/infinity-and-infinite-sets-the-root-of-the-problem/
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Infinite_Set_Equivalent_to_Proper_Subset
9
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Definition:Set_Equivalence
8
Proof:
Case I: “if”8 part
Let X be an infinite set. Since every infinite set has countably infinite subset 10, thus one can
possibly construct one from X.
Suppose S = {a1, a2, a3, ….} is a countably infinite subset of X.
One can create a partition of S into:
S1 = {a1, a3, a5, ….} and S2 = {a2, a4, a6, ….}
In addition, assume that there exists a bijection established between S and S 1 s.t.
an
an-1
One can further extend the bijection between:
S ∪ ( X ∖ S ) = X and S1 ∪ ( X ∖ S ) = X ∖ S 2
One can demonstrate that a bijection can be created between T and one of its proper subset
T ∖ S 2 . Hence one can conclude if X is infinite, then it is equivalent to one of its proper subsets.
Case II: “only if”8 part
On the contrary, suppose X is equivalent to one of its proper subsets, say X 0,
i.e. X 0 ⊂ X and there exists a bijection f: X → X0. Nevertheless, there is no bijection between
finite set and its proper subset11. Therefore X must be infinite.
Indeed Dummett (1991, p.49), offered a critique of Dedekind's Infinite set theory:
“Dedekind's philosophy of mathematics was that mathematical objects are 'free creations of the
human mind'. The idea, widely shared by his contemporaries, was that abstract objects are actually
created by the operations of our minds. This would seem to lead to a solipsistic conception of
mathematics; but it is implicit in this conception that each subject is entitled to feel assured that
what he creates by means of his own mental operations will coincide, at least in its properties, with
what others have created by means of analogous operations. For Frege, such an assurance would be
without foundation: for him, the contents of our minds are
wholly subjective; since there is no means of comparing them, I cannot know whether my idea is
the same as yours.”
After reviewing the three categories of philosophy, one finds that none of them can fully
explain the concept of infinity in mathematics. Further work should be done between
mathematicians and philosophers to create a model for it (Lam, 2016). However, one should still
appreciate the beauty in the method of the various proofs about infinity in these schools. In addition
to these proofs, there are also daily examples of teaching infinity through mathematical philosophy;
these will be discussed in detail in the next section.
3. Examples of teaching infinity using Mathematical Philosophy
During the course of everyday learning at university, the present author has encountered
several different concepts of infinity in mathematics. These will now be discussed one by one
through the application of mathematical philosophy.
3.1 Teaching Calculus Using the Concept of Limit in Formalism
One of the most famous examples in teaching the idea of infinity is calculus. It allows one to
teach formally the concept of a limit. To begin, one should understand the well-known Paradoxes of
motion:
10
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Infinite_Set_has_Countably_Infinite_Subset
11
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/No_Bijection_between_Finite_Set_and_Proper_Subset
“Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 meters, for example. If we suppose that each
racer starts running at some constant speed (one very fast and one very slow), then after some finite
time, Achilles will have run 100 meters, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point. During this
time, the tortoise has run a much shorter distance, say, 10 meters. It will then take Achilles some
further time to run that distance, by which time the tortoise will have advanced farther; and then
more time still to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles
reaches somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has farther to go. Therefore, because there are an
infinite number of points Achilles must reach where the tortoise has already been, he can never
overtake the tortoise12.”
Long before Cantor, Zeno's paradoxes (Zeno of Elea, 490 – 425 BC) shows how poor
people’s understanding was of the concept of infinity:
“There is no motion, because to get anywhere you’d first have to get halfway, and before
that you’d have to get a quarter of the way, etc.” (Schechter, 2002: p.3)
The figure above shows one of Zeno's Paradoxes (Maor,
1986, p.34). It is used to tell us how worst is the knowing
of infinity earlier on Cantor.
Nowadays, one can explain Zeno's Paradox as:
1/ 2 + 1/ 4 + 1/ 8 + 1/ 16 + 1/ 32 + ….. = 1
which is an infinite series with the sum equal to the limit of finite partial sums.
Indeed, one will never get 1. The infinite series should be rewritten as:
…..+ 1/ 32 + 1/ 16 + 1/ 8 + 1/ 4 + 1/ 2 = 1
This means that one will have infinitely many steps before one gets ½ way or gets 1/ 4 way. If each
step takes 1 second, one will never get anywhere (Schechter, 2002).
Nevertheless, when one take an in-depth look at the infinite series, if there is a sufficient
number of items with common ratio equals to “1/ 2”, then the sum of the series can be approached
arbitrarily closer to 1 (Maor, 1986). Suppose the runner has a constant speed “s”, then the time
needed between two points is directly proportional to the distance travelled. Therefore, the total
period required for the whole journey is the sum of the series multiplied by the constant “s”. Hence
only limited time is used for the travelling and this solves the controversy. The ancient Greek did
not believe the infinite series to have a convergence to a limit (Maor, 1986).
Really for the sequence 1, 1/ 2, 1/ 4, …., 1/ n, the limit is zero (Maor, 1986). As n increases,
the value in the sequence becomes smaller and tends to zero but will never equal zero. It means if
one has sufficiently large n, the sequence an can approach arbitrarily close to zero. For
12
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zeno%27s_paradoxes
example, if one needs an to be smaller than one in a thousand, then one requires n to be larger than
one thousand. Similarly, one can make a n even as close as one in ten billions (Maor, 1986).
However, those mathematicians did not like such kind of lengthy explanation. They
preferred a simpler description (Maor, 1986):
an→ L when n→ ∞ or
lim a n = L
n→ ∞
lim 1/n = 0.
Thus, one can represent the sequence by 1/ n→ 0 when n→ ∞ or n→
∞
lim
a
n
is a kind of symbol under mathematical rules meaning “limiting value of….”
The term
n→ ∞
when n tends to infinity. It obviously connects the ideas of endlessness and formalism. To be more
precise, an abstract definition of limit may be as follows:
Suppose there exists a finite value “a”, then for any given positive integer ε, there is always a
positive integer N(ε) such that n > N, |xn – a| < ε, then one says the sequence {xn} is with limit “a”;
lim x n = a; xn→ a (Fudan, 1978).
n→ ∞
After viewing the example for origin, linking and teaching concepts between limit (a kind of
infinity as well as calculus) and formalism, one may proceed to the inferior part.
3.2 Using Geometry to learn infinity mathematics intuitively
Consider the following function (Maor, 1986):
y=1/x
where the diagram is likely described as below:
The above figure on the left shows a hyperbola (positively branch). Suppose it is rotating around the
x-axis, then it becomes a hyperbolic rotator as shown on the right. If one integrates the surface area
from x = 1 to infinity of the rotator, the area is infinitely large. To be more precise, one can show
that when calculate the corresponding surface area from x = 1 to some value greater than 1 such as t
and letting “t” tend to infinity, there will be no bound to the area. However, the corresponding
rotator's volume will tend to a certain limited value. In other words, there is a limit in volume for
the infinite 3D figure. If one wants to paint on the surface of the 3D figure, the job cannot be
finished as one needs an infinite amount of paint. On the other hand, if one paints the surface inside
of the rotator, then it is finite. This paradox cannot find a simple explanation and tells us that when
anything is related to the concept of infinity, one's intuition can produce errors (Maor, 1986).
Furthermore, relationships exist between these paradoxes and so-called “Morbid Functions”.
For example, one considers y = sin(1/x) which has some special properties (Maor, 1986):
1. When x approaches to zero, the graph of the function's oscillation becomes larger, thus it can
never be depicted completely. If one compares it with the hyperbola's graph, there is also a
“discontinuity” when x = 0. However, the difference is that this function's graph will not tend to
infinity but only the oscillation frequency becomes infinite.
2. If one considers the related function y = xsin(1/x), the singular point x = 0 will disappear and
hence the function becomes continuous.
3. Consider the function y = f(x) where
1
when
x∈ℚ
-1
when
x∉ℚ
f(x)=
Then for the upper line y = 1, there are an uncountably number of holes since ℝ is uncountable.
On the other hand, for y = -1, there are a countable number of holes as ℚ is countable. This
special function discontinues everywhere and leads to controversies. As a result, the concept of
“continuous” is redefined (Maor, 1986).
To conclude, from Jones et al. (2004: p.5), “We define ‘geometrical intuition’ as a skill to
create and manipulate geometrical figures in the mind, to see geometrical properties, to relate
images to concepts and theorems in geometry, and decide where to start when solving problems in
geometry. We suggest that tasks that require students to imagine and manipulate geometrical figures
can link geometrical intuition more directly with geometrical theory, and involve active use of
imagination skills.”
3.3 Applying Contradictory logicism in studying infinity algebra
When one is concerned with contradiction in infinity, one might refer to an analogy
proposed by philosopher William Lane Craig who was involved in the calculations of certain kinds
of infinite sets:
“Imagine that one has an infinite number of marbles in his possession and he wants to give other
some of them. In addition, suppose one (say A) wants to give other one (say B)an infinite number of
marbles.” (Sewell, 2010: p.18)
Case I: One (A) could do that by giving all marbles to the other one (B). Hence, A will have zero
marbles left for himself. i.e. ℵ 0 - ℵ 0 = 0
Case II: Alternatively, A gives B all the odd numbered marbles. Then A will still have an infinite
number left for himself and B will also have an infinite set too. i.e. ℵ 0 - ℵ 0 = ℵ 0
Obviously, the above two cases show contradictory results (0 and ℵ 0). However, subtraction and
dividing sets of equal amounts should not produce them. These collisions cast doubt on the idea that
infinite can be treated as a coherent notion (Sewell, 2010). Nevertheless, other philosophers such as
Morrision and Gumiski believe that there are discrepancies between subtracting infinite sets in
transfinite mathematics (which will normally result in absurdities). The “removal” of one infinite
set from another does not happen in the present real world (Sewell, 2010). In addition, the present
author notes that the aforementioned paradox leads to the logical contradiction of an infinite set
being both “divisible” and yet “not divisible” which results in both a mathematical and a logical
contradiction.
Note: The above two graphs are adopted from Maor, 1986: p.111.
In reality, there cannot be infinite set of marbles or an infinite set of anything (Sewell, 2010). Thus,
this may lead to the concept of indefiniteness which can resolve the problem.
After discussing the views and examples from the three categories of philosophy of
mathematical infinity, one turns to the philosophical implications.
4. Discussions – Types of Infinity and their philosophical implications
For each kind of mathematical philosophy, there are matters of corresponding philosophical
significance such as the countability of numbers, the start of the universe and the big bang as well
as the existence of God.
4.1 Cantor's Theory implies Actual Limitless – Countability of Numbers
What is actual limitlessness? One usually refers to the concept as an ongoing process which
is repeated over and over but it is conceived as being “completed” or as having a final resultant state
(Núñez, 2005). For instance, one can contemplate the sequence of regular polygons with an
increasing number of sides where the distance from the centre to any of the vertices remains
constant. Indeed, one always begins with a triangle, then a square, a pentagon, a hexagon and so on
endlessly until it completes a circle. This is because after each iteration, there is an increase in one
to the number of sides, the side' s length becomes smaller but the distance “r” between the centre of
the polygon and the vertices remains the same. As one continues the process, the area and the
perimeter of the polygon gets closer and closer to the value in πr2 and 2πr respectively. The circle
actually has all the prototypical properties that circles must have but conceptually it is a polygon.
“The main theme of Cantor’s Grundlagen is that there are multiple actual infinities, because there is
a realm of an actual, but increasable infinite known as the transfinite.” (Newstead, 2009: p.536).
This is the reason why it is proposed here that there is a connection between actual limitlessness and
Cantor's Theory of transfinite numbers. Through these cardinals, one can tell the countability of
“Natural”, “Rational” and even “Real” numbers as mentioned earlier.
4.2 Kronecker's Disagreement suggests Potential Boundless – Big Bang Theory
On the contrary, potential boundless means “a non-terminating process (such as "add 1 to
the previous number") produces an unending "infinite" sequence of results, but each individual
result is finite and is achieved in a finite number of steps 13.” It is proposed here that this definition is
related to Kronecker's finitism as well as Skolem's primitive recursive arithmetic. In fact, according
to Craig14, what the past is made up of a series of events (E1, E2…En). Usually, one refers to “the
past” as the set of all these events. Hence, the past cannot be an actual infinity. If one begins with a
single event and adds one another gradually, one will get never get an actual infinite number of
events. What one ends up with is a set whose number of constituents becomes ever larger and tends
towards infinity but never actually reaches it 14. This is defined as a “potential infinity”. Therefore, it
appears to the present author that there must be a beginning of time.What is entailed by “potential
boundlessness” is the Big Bang theory and thus a “Start of the Universe”.
Recently, some astronomers has combined observations and mathematical models in order
to develop a workable theory of how the Universe came to be 15. According to the theory, our
universe previously existed as a “singularity” 13.7 billion years ago 16. Singularities are thought to
be “black holes” with intense gravitational pressure where finite matter is crushed into infinite
density. Our Universe is believed to have started as an infinitely hot, infinitesimally small, infinitely
dense, something – a singularity. Beyond initial shape, the singularity seemingly inflated (the so
called “Big Bang”), cooled and expanded, and began changing from being extremely small and
13
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Actual_infinity
http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/danaher20141015
15
http://science.nasa.gov/astrophysics/focus-areas/what-powered-the-big-bang/
16
http://www.big-bang-theory.com
14
extremely hot, to the current temperature and size of the universe. The process is ongoing and
human beings are a part of it - incredible creatures who are living on a unique planet, circling with a
beautiful star. The planet is also clustered with some hundred billion other stars in a galaxy soaring
through the cosmos. All of this happening inside an expanding universe that began as an
infinitesimal singularity which appeared out of nowhere and for reasons unknown. This is one
suggestion what the Big Bang theory is16.
4.3 Dedekind's Concept Describes Absolute Endlessness - The Existence of God
What is the definition of absolute endlessness? Some philosophers believe that the class V
of all sets, the mindscape, the cosmos, and God are all examples of what “absolute” is 17. Indeed, one
may define the term “absolute” in the sense of “non-relative, non-subjective” 17. The absolute itself
exists together with the highest form of completeness. In actual, there is a relationship between the
limitlessness of God and mathematical infinity. As St. Gregory said, “No matter how far our mind
may have progressed in the contemplation of God, it does not attain to what He is, but to what is
beneath Him.” (Rucker, 2013: p.44) In such a case, one is now in the rudiments of the infinite
dialectic process since one is trying to establish an image of the whole mindscape. The dialectic
process happens in the following way:
1. First of all, one collects a group of thoughts into a single thought T.
2. When one is in a conscious state of mind T, a new thought is then constructed that one has not yet
accounted for previously.
3. One’s mindscape is improved for thought including the elements of T plus T itself.
In mathematically symbolic term, one may consider the nth thought Tn, one can define
inductively: To = ∅ and Tn + 1 = Tn U {Tn}, for any sets A and B. AUB means the set of all the sets
that are members of A or of B. Nevertheless, one may have another inductive definition: Tn = {Tm:
m < n}, which means “Tn is the set of all Tm such that m is less than n."17 However, T plus “T” is not
always different from the thought T. In the case of a mind M, it is already fully self-aware, and
therefore M plus “M” is no different from M. i.e. M U {M} = M. Rucker (2013) discusses in detail
“absolute” in terms of the rational and mystical. Indeed, during 1887 one of Cantor's friend, Richard
Dedekind, issued a proof and claimed that the mindscape is infinite. Dedekind's word for mindscape
was Gedankenwelt, which liberally means “thought-world”. By continuing the repetitive process,
Dedekind proved the infinitude of the mindscape:
{s, s is a possible thought, s is a possible thought is a possible thought, . . .}
Therefore, this shows that the class of all sets, the mindscape and the class of all true propositions
are all infinite. In similar terms, one can tell whether God is endless. There are comments about
God’s existence in Rucker’s work, however, this author believes in the existence of God and His
“Absolute”.
5. Conclusions – Infinity acts as a link between Art and Mathematics
After reviewing, providing examples and discussing infinity, the question remains “What is
the role of limitlessness? This study finds that it acts as a connection between art and mathematics.
For example, one can appreciate the beauty of transfinite cardinals and hence imply the portrait of
infinity has human face (Nũńez, 2005):
17
https://math.dartmouth.edu/~matc/Readers/HowManyAngels/InfinityMind/IM.html
1. Aspectual systems consist of continuative and iterative processes, those ideal and non-ideal
structures with a starting status and completion status and so on.
2. Conceptual Metaphors such as in the case of Cantor’s Metaphor Same Number As Is Pairability.
3. Conceptual Blending such as the use of multiple implicit Basic Mappings of infinity in Cantor’s
proofs.
Indeed, Cantor’s theories and proofs often worked against the mainstream mathematicians’
thought, and hence why he surprised many people (Carey, 2005). His idea also caused discomfort
among certain mathematics professionals. Meschkowski so eloquently wrote, “Cantor’s theorem is
thus a beautiful example of a mathematical paradox, of a true statement which seems to be false to
the uninformed” (quoted. in Dauben, 1979).
Nevertheless, what a mathematician focuses on with infinity is that “Mathematics takes us
into the region of absolute necessity to which not only the actual world, but every possible world,
must conform.” (Egner et al., 2009: p.229)
From a philosopher’s point of view: “Mathematics is an ideal world and an eternal edifice of
truth…. .In the contemplation of its serene beauty man can find refuge from the world full of evil
and suffering.”(Copleston, 1966: p.438)
From the astronomer James Jeans (1877-1946), “God is a mathematician” and most
mathematicians say “God made the numbers. All the rest is made by human.” (Peat, 2009: p.28)
In a nutshell, it is suggested here that mathematics is the science of studying infinity. When
one is talking about its daily applications, these may include calculating the gravitational force for
infinite mass, determining whether infinity exists in our physical universe, infinite regression
arguments, computing such as arithmetic overflow and division by zero etc 18. Below is a poem that
can best depict boundlessness:
"L'ininito" ( Giacomo Leopardi)19
This lonely hill was always dear to me,
and this hedgerow, which cuts off the view
of so much of the last horizon.
But sitting here and gazing, I can see
beyond, in my mind’s eye, unending spaces,
and superhuman silences, and depthless calm,
till what I feel
is almost fear. And when I hear
the wind stir in these branches, I begin
comparing that endless stillness with this noise:
and the eternal comes to mind,
and the dead seasons, and the present
living one, and how it sounds.
So my mind sinks in this immensity:and foundering is sweet in such a sea.
(Translated by Jonathan Galassi)
18
19
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity#Physics
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/L%27infinito
References:
Bulatov, A. (2012), Bijection and Cardinality: Discrete Mathematics.
http://people.math.gatech.edu/~ecroot/2406_2012/cantor2.pdf
Carey, P.H. (2005), Beyond Infinity: Georg Cantor and Leopold Kronecker's Dispute over
Transfinite Numbers., Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation.
http://hdl.handle.net/2345/481
Copleston, F.C., (1966). A History of Philosophy: Bentham to Russell. Search Press.
Dauben, J. W. Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1979.
Dummett, M.A.E., (1991), Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics, Harvard University Press.
Egner, R., Denonn, L. (2009). The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell, Routledge Classic, London
and New York.
Fudan University (1978), Department of Mathematics, Mathematical Analysis (Chinese Simplified
Version), Commercial Press (商務印書館)
Jones, K., Fujita, T., Yamamoto, S., (2004). GEOMETRICAL INTUITION AND THE LEARNING
AND TEACHING OF GEOMETRY, 10th International Congress on Mathematical Education
(ICME-10). Copenhagen, Denmark;
http://eprints.soton.ac.uk/14687/1/Fujita_Jones_Yamamoto_ICME10_TSG10_2004.pdf
Maor, B.E. (1986), To Infinity and Beyond: A Cultural History of Infinite (Chinese Version),
BookZone (天下文化)
Newstead, A. (2009), Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind, American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 83, No. 4.
http://philpapers.org/archive/NEWQOI.pdf
Nũńez, R.E (2005), Creating mathematical infinities: Metaphor,
blending, and the beauty of transfinite cardinals, Department of Cognitive Science, University of
California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093-0515, USA, ScienceDirect,
http://www.cogsci.ucsd.edu/~nunez/web/TransfinitePrgmtcs.pdf
Peat, E.D. (2002), From Certainly to Uncertainly: The Story of Science and Ideas in the twentieth
Century, Joseph Henry Press, Washington, D.C.
Rao, S. Tse, D. (2009), Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory, Note 20.
https://web.stanford.edu/~dntse/classes/cs70_fall09/n20_fall09.pdf
Rucker, R. (2013). Infinity and the Mind: the Science and Philosophy of the Infinite. Princeton
Science Library.
Schechter, E. (2002), Georg Cantor: The man who tamed infinity, Vanderbilt University
http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/%7Eschectex/courses/infinity.pdf
Sewell, K.K. (2010), THE CASE AGAINST INFINITY.
http://philpapers.org/archive/SEWTCA
Velickovic, B. (2010), The Mathematical Theory of Infinity, Sino-European Winter School in
Logic, Language and Computation, Equipe de Logique Université de Paris Diderot.
http://www.math.helsinki.fi/logic/sellc-2010/ws/guangzhou-boban.pdf