VERA TRIPODI
Singular Terms and Inferential Criteria
1
1.1 “The syntactic priority thesis” and Inference
At the heart of Frege’s philosophy of mathematics lies “the
thesis of the priority of the syntactic over ontological categories”
that Crispin Wright explains so:
(SPT) «The question whether a specific expression is a candidate
to refer to an object is entirely a matter of the sort of the syntactic
role which it plays in whole sentences».1
This thesis is strictly connected to the Fregean Argument that,
following Hale, runs as follows:
(1) «If a range of expression functions as singular terms in true
statements, then there are objects denoted by expressions belonging to
that range;
(2) Numerals, and many other numerical expressions besides, do so
function in many true statements (of both pure and applied
mathematics);
Hence:
(3) There exist objects denoted by those numerical expressions (i.e.
there are numbers) ».2
I thank Prof. Cesare Cozzo, Valeria Giardino and Gianluca Paronitti for
helpful comments on earlier draft of this paper.
1
Wright, 1983 51.
2
Hale 1987 11.
VERA TRIPODI
In general, the Fregean Argument establishes that an expression
refers to an object if:
(i) such an expression functions in certain sentence as a singular
term;
(ii) sentences in which it functions in this way are true.
According to Frege, linguistic categories are prior to ontological
categories: in order to explain what sort of thing an expression refers
to, we need to explain what sort of expression it is. In order to
understand the sort of thing to which the expression might refer, we
need to understand how that expression functions in the sentence of
which it is a part. The logical kind of an expression determines the
ontological kind of its referent. More specifically, Fregean use of the
ontological term “object” corresponds to his use of the linguistic term
“proper name”: the primary use of a singular term in a sentence is to
pick out a determinate object for which the term stands in the same
way as a proper name stands for its bearer. As we can see, it is essential
to the Fregean programme to characterize formally the class of singular
terms. In Fregean ontology, syntactic criteria for singular term-hood
are provided by inferential test for distinguishing the behaviour and
the role of such terms in natural languages from terms that belong to
other logical categories.
Dummett’s point of view is a defence of the Fregean programme.
At the centre of Dummett’s defence is a version of Frege’s famous
dictum according to which «only in the context of a sentence does a
word have any reference».3 According to Dummett, it is possible to
characterize the logical kind of singular terms in «wholly linguistic
terms»4 and to give clear and exact criteria for them by relating to their
functioning within the language.
Dummett suggests, in Frege. Philosophy of Language ,5 five criteria
that are supposed to discriminate singular terms from expressions of
other kind. These criteria are not based merely on conditions of
grammatical correctness, because the place that a genuine singular
3
4
5
2
Frege 1988, § 62.
Dummett 1981, 57.
Ibid., chapter 4.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
term stands in a sentence can be occupied by other expression that
expresses generality (such as “everything”, “nothing”, etc.). Thus,
Dummett’s criteria are inferential criteria and are based on the
speaker’s recognition of “the sentence as well-formed” and the
«correctness or incorrectness of certain patterns of inference»6 at the
intuitive level. So, given what Dummett says, any sentence that
contains a singular term must admit a particular inference.
1.2 Dummett’s Criteria
Dummett’s purpose is to describe the character of singular terms
in general. His criteria reflect the idea that some simple patterns of
inference are valid when singular terms occupy certain positions in
their premises or conclusions. In fact, these criteria furnish a means by
which we decide whether a given expression is to be considered as a
singular term as it occurs in a particular sentence, and not whether
some expression is or is not (considered in itself) a singular term. I first
introduce the first three criteria all together and analyse them
separately, then I explain the remaining two.
Let t be an expression of a language, in this case the English
language, which occurs in many different sentences. According to the
first three conditions, t is a singular term only if:
(i) For any sentence “A(t)”, the inference from “A(t)” to “there is
something such that A(it)” is valid;
(ii) For any sentences “A(t)” and “B(t)”, the inference from “A(t)
and B(t)” to “there is something such that A(it) and B(it)” is valid;
(iii) For any sentences “A(t)” and “B(t)”, the inference from “it is
true of t that A(it) or B(it)” to “A(t) or B(t)” is valid.
Criterion (I):
The first criterion rules out those expressions that contains terms as
“nothing”, “nobody”, “no-one” and expressions like “no philosophers”
or “no Italian”.
6
Ibid, 58.
3
VERA TRIPODI
Examples.
From “Nothing is wise”, it is not possible to infer “There is
something such that it is wise”.
From “Tom loves Mary”, it is possible to infer “There is someone
that loves Mary”.
Criterion (II):
The second criterion rules out “something”, “somebody”,
“some sheep” or many occurrences of indefinite substantival
phrases such as “a policeman” when they occur in grammatical
subject or object position.
Examples.
(i) «From “Something is red” and “Something is not red”, it is not
possible to infer “There is something such that it is red and it not red”».7
(ii) «From “A policeman struck me” and “A policeman arrested
me”, it is not possible to infer “There is something such that he
struck me and he arrested me”».8
(iii) «From “I struck a policeman” and “I insulted a policeman”, it
is not possible to infer “There is someone such that he struck me
and he arrested me”».
But this criterion fails to exclude an expression like “a
policeman” or “a poet” when it occurs in complement position as
predicates.
Examples.
(i) «From “Henry is a policeman” and “Peter is not a policeman”, it
is possible to infer “There is something such that Henry is it and
Peter is not it”».9
(ii) «From “Richard was born a poet” and “Henry has become a
poet”, it is possible to infer “There is something such that Richard
was born it and Henry has become it”».10
7
Wetzel 1990, 241.
Hale 1979, 288.
9
Dummett 1981, 61.
8
4
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
Criterion (III):
The third criterion excludes “everything”, “everybody” and
“every sheep” and plural nouns, but it is not sufficient to exclude
“undetected murders” as in the following example:
Example.
«From “it is true of undetected murders either that they are very rare
or that they do not take place at all”, it is possible to infer “Either it
is true that undetected murders are very rare or it is true that
undetected murders never take place at all”».11
1.3 Some problems posed by Dummett’s criteria
According to Dummett, these criteria establish only necessary
conditions for an expression’s being a singular term. Nevertheless, as
Dummett points out, these criteria require some emendations. In
fact, even if they are sufficient to exclude various expressions
whenever they stand in place of genuine singular terms, they are not
sufficient to exclude indefinite noun phrases when they occur where
singular terms cannot be. More explicitly, they do not exclude some
expressions (e.g., “undetected murders” or “a policeman”) when they
function as ordinary predicates (e.g. “Harry is a policeman”) and
when they occur in sentences in which they are the subjects of
second-level predicates (e.g. “Undetected murders are rare”). As
Crispin Wright suggests, these first three criteria proposed by
Dummett characterize at best a class of sentences as one in which a
given expression occurs as an expression of level n, with predicates of
level n+1. Nevertheless, they don’t distinguish a class of sentences in
which an expression of, e.g., level 2, is predicated of an expression of
level 1 from one in which an ordinary predicate is predicate of a
singular term (an expression of level 0).
Hence, we need some supplementary tests which allows us (i)
to distinguish a difference in function or semantic role between
those expressions that can refer to a particular object and those
10
Ibid., 60.
Dummett writes about this example that it is «slightly unnatural but
clearly intelligible». See Ibid., 1981, 60.
11
5
VERA TRIPODI
which can not and (ii) to distinguish first-order from second (and
higher) order generality.
1.4 Criterion IV: Aristotle’s dictum
We need some further guide for distinguishing between firstlevel from second-level generality. According to Dummett, we can
explain this difference only by means of the idea that «a proper
name is standing for an object about which we are asserting that
the predicate is true of it is».12 We have to explain the difference
among different levels of expression and to clarify the difference
between «generalization over objects from generalization over all
the things that might be true of a first-level quality».13
The criterion proposed by Dummett is the following:
Criterion (IV) «Suppose that we have a sentence “S(t,u)” involving
two expressions “t” and “u” both of which pass the tests for
[singular terms] which we have already laid down. We now inquire,
which respect to “t”, whether we may assert “There is something
such that S(it, anything) if and only if it is not the case that S(t, that
thing)”: if we may, then “t” is not a [singular term]. Likewise, with
respect to “u”, we enquire whether we may assert “There is
something such that S(anything, it) if and only if it is not the case
that S(that thing, u)”: if we may, then “u” is not a [singular term]».14
This criterion is based on Aristotle’s dictum that «a quality has a
contrary but a substance does not».15 As Dummett points out, «for
any predicate, there is another predicate which is true of just those
objects of which the original predicate is false, and false of just those
objects of which the original predicate is true».16 The underlying idea
is that «we can not assume that, given any object, there is another
object of which just those predicates are true which were false of the
original object, and conversely».17
12
13
14
15
16
17
6
Ibid., 66.
Ibid., 66.
Ibid., 64
Ibid., 63.
Ibid., 64.
Ibid.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
Dummett’s thought is that, given any sentence from which a
predicate is extracted, it is possible to extract from its negation, that is “it
is not the case that Ft”, another predicate which is its contrary, that is
“not-F”. Given any predicate as “wise”, it is possible to introduce an
another predicate as “stupid” and to stipulate that – for every proper
name “a” – “a is stupid” is to have the same truth-value as “It not the
case that a is wise”. Nevertheless, given any proper name as “Socrates”, it
not possible to introduce another proper name as “Not-Socrates” and
stipulate that for every predicate “F()”, “F(Not-Socrates)” is to have the
same truth-value as “It is not the case that F(Socrates)”. So, the idea is
that whereas for any given predicate there is always a contrary predicate
applying to a given object just in case the original predicate fails to apply,
there is not, for a singular term, anything corresponding to this.
The Aristotelian criterion, therefore, allows us to explain the
difference between a proper name and a predicate as a difference
between levels of expression. But, as Dummett observes, this criterion
is not straightforward since its use involves a “double generality”.
The Aristotelian criterion, hence, allows us to rule out from the
class of singular terms every predicate that occurs in a sentence as
predicate. For example, this criterion eliminates the predicate “man” in
“Plato is a man”, but it doesn’t eliminate “undetected murders” in
“Undetected murders are rare”.18 The reason is that «there is nothing of
which just those things are true which are false of undetected murders, i.
e., something which is frequent just in case undetected murders are rare,
on the decrease just in case undetected murders are increasing or
constant, etc.».19
But, since it fails to distinguish between different levels of
generality, the Aristotelian criterion does not exclude expressions like
“undetected murders” when they function as grammatical subject and
some second-level predicate is predicated of them (e.g. “undetected
murders” in “Undetected murders are rare”). We need, therefore,
another criterion that allows us to distinguish from singular terms an
expression like “undetected murders” when occurs as ordinary predicate
18
19
Ibid., 67.
Ibid., 67.
7
VERA TRIPODI
and, specifically, to distinguish when this expression serves to provide a
first or a second level of generality.
1.5 Criterion V: the difference between first-order and second-order
generality
A characteristic of our natural languages is that they involve
expressions that can indifferently be used to express first-level (over
objects) and second-level generality (over properties or relations). For
example, the expression “something” can be used to express
generalization over things and over properties.
The principal fault of the first three of Dummett’s criteria is that in
their formulation the expression “something” expresses a first-level and
second-level generality. We have, therefore, to propose a test for
distinguishing the two different forms of generality.
According to Dummett, valid inferences that - on the basis of the
first three criteria - qualify adjectives and indefinite noun phrases as
proper names are inferences in which the expression “something” in the
conclusion expresses second-level generality. So, the inference from
“Jones is a policeman” to “There is something such that Jones is it” is a
valid inference that expresses a generalization over things that Jones
would be or over a property Jones might be instantiate.
To solve this problem, Dummett proposes an additional criterion,
which Hale calls “the specification test”,20 for distinguishing first-order
from second-order quantification and formulates it as follows:
Criterion (V) «An expression expresses a second- or higher- level of
generality “if a point may be reached where a demand for specification
is still grammatically well constructed, but is nevertheless rejected as
illegitimate».21
Dummett’s idea is quite simple: any existentially quantified
sentence allows request for further specification. But the problem
is that natural languages comprise ambiguous sentences that are
20
21
8
Hale 2001, 37.
Dummett 1981, 68.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
subject to different readings: a first-order and a second-order
reading. Dummett’s thought is that, when the generality is of
second level, «the answer to a request for specification is treated as
complete» 22 and the request for further specification is rejected.
Example of second level generality:
«From “Ten years ago undetected murders were very common” and from
“Now undetected murders are rare”, it possible to infer “There is
something which ten years ago was very common and now is rare”».23
According to the specification test, “something” in the conclusion of
this inference supplies to express a generality of second level. As
Dummett observes, if someone says “There is something which ten years
ago was very common and now is rare”, someone can properly ask me
“What is it that ten years ago was very common and now is rare?” and
she may receive the answer “undetected murders”. But she can’t
properly ask further “Which undetected murders?”, because the request
for further specification clearly indicates a misunderstanding of my
original assertion and can properly be rejected as illegitimate.
Here is an example of first level generality.
Example of first level generality:
«If I say “George dropped something on his toe”, someone may ask
“what was is that George dropped on his toe?” and I may reply “a
hammer”. If she asks further “Which hammer?”, I can’t reject his
request further specification as illegitimate because the question has
an answer even if I don’t know what it is.»24
Hence, according to Dummett, the generality, involved in all
his criteria relating to inference, shall be of first level.
Unfortunately, as Bob Hale remarks, this test is flawed in
opaque contexts. Here is a counterexample.
Counter-example:
«If I say, “Edward believes that someone is leaking official secret”,
someone may ask me “whom does he believe to be leaking official
22
23
24
Ibid.
Ibid., 69.
Ibid., 67.
9
VERA TRIPODI
secrets?” and I may reply “a member of his department”. The
request for a further specification, “which member?”, may have an
answer and in the same time may be rejected as illegitimate because
it may betray a misunderstanding of the character of the belief
attributed to Edward.»25
In the quantification involved in the formulation of Edward’s
belief, “someone” expresses a first-level generality. It is possible to
express this sentence, using the quantifier-variable notation, as follows:
“Edward believes that (x)(x is leaking official secret). This
paraphrases is different from that of a sentence involving a higher-level
quantification like “There is something that George is but Henry is
not”, that we might write it as “(F) (F(George) but ¬F(Henry)).
To overcome this obstacle, as Hale illustrates, it is not necessary
to introduce the general distinction between first and second level of
generality occurrences of “something”. Indeed it is sufficient to apply
the idea that «the quantifier contained in applications of those
conditions should be first-order».26 Therefore, Hale proposes to
emendate criterion V as follows:
«a is a proper name only if the conclusion of an inference of the sort
described in criterion (1) and (2) is not such that a point may be
reached where a grammatically well-formed request for
specification can be rejected as illegitimate ».
2 FURTHER DIFFICULTIES
2.1 Wetzel’s objections
How can we recognize the validity of patterns of those inferences
by means of which we could decide whether it is a singular term or
not? As I pointed out earlier, Dummett maintains that his criteria are
based on the capacity of recognizing the correctness or incorrectness
of inferences “at the intuitive level”. If Dummett is right, what does it
mean that we can recognize the correctness of certain patterns of
25
26
10
Hale 1979, 291.
Wright 1983, 62.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
inference solely on our intuitions? Several philosophers don’t accept
Dummett’s thesis in this respect. In her recent paper,27 Linda Wetzel
maintains that this thesis is problematic in some points. More
specifically, according to Wetzel, the thesis according to which “the
recognition of simple patterns of inference is at the intuitive level” is
absurd because it presupposes at the outset what should be explained
(the notion of singular term) and because it seems to maintain the
idea that a valid inference is one that preserves syntactic property.
In my opinion, Wetzel’s point of view is not quite correct.
Nevertheless, in order to determinate the validity of Dummett’s
programme, it is crucial to analyze Wetzel’s objections and the
reasons why, according to her, Dummett’s thesis is absurd. More
specifically, I first examine Wetzel’s accusation about the supposed
circularity of Dummett’s criteria and why the role that Dummett
ascribes to the inference should not be in contrast with the “syntactic
priority thesis” but also incompatible with Dummett’s theory of
meaning. In the next paragraph, using an argument proposed by Bob
Hale, I explore what is the correct way to understand Dummett’s
thesis and argue that Wetzel’s accusation is unjustified.
(i) Inference and Our Intuitions
First, let us examine the thesis according to which the
recognition of simple patterns of inference at the intuitive level is
senseless and in contrast with the “syntactic priority thesis”.
According to Wetzel, if this thesis were taken as involving merely the
observation that we are intuitively able to pick out what we consider
as the general notion of singular term, it would be absurd and in
contrast with the fact that we have liable different intuitions about
what is a singular term and whether a expression passes our tests.
Examined in this prospective, letting recognition of the crucial
patterns of inference be at intuitive level «leaves too much room for
27
See Wetzel 1990.
11
VERA TRIPODI
one’s ontological intuitions to colour the results».28 In philosophy of
mathematics, for example, a realist and a nominalist have different
intuitions about numerical terms and about which phrase has an
“existential import”. Suppose, for example, that we have to establish
whether the expression “two” in “Two is a prime number” is a
singular term. Criterion (I) is a test to decide whether a given phrase
has an “existential import”. According to a realist, since she assumes
that by definition a singular term always denotes something, “two”
has an “existential import” and it is a singular term. On the contrary,
a nominalist would refuse this point of view.
So, the notion of inference, to which Dummett appeals to,
presupposes a certain general notion of singular term. For this reason,
the thesis about “the recognition of simple patterns of inference at the
intuitive level” is, according to Wetzel, not quite plausible because it
fails to furnish a general notion of singular terms. The result of all this
is, according to Wetzel, that Dummett’s criteria are circular and fail
to delimitate formally the class of singular terms.
Wetzel defends a new approach to ontology that is different from
that of Frege because based on «more give and take between syntax
and ontology».29 As Frege points out in his analysis of number’s
definition, we can consider numbers as objects because we are forced
to recognize numerical terms as proper names. At the same time, the
approach defended by Wetzel is different from the approach - that
Dummett ascribes to Geach - according to which ontological
categories are prior to linguistic categories. According to Geach, we
first apprehend that a linguistic term stands for a certain entity (i.e., to
which ontological category it belongs), then we can assign that
expression to an adequate logic category in accordance with the
category of the entity it stands for. Therefore, we can consider
numerical terms as singular terms because we are forced to count
numbers as objects. Wetzel’s suggestion is to assume a strategy that is
midway between Frege’s approach and Geach’s approach. Such an
approach is able to explain the relationship between syntax and
28
29
12
Ibid., 252.
Ibid., 254.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
ontology in terms of a development so that «sometimes our
ontological intuitions inform our view of syntax and sometimes
syntactic principles determine our view of ontology».30
But, if Wetzel is right, the account of the relation of inference
proposed by Dummett in the formulation of his criteria doesn’t meet
the requirements of the “Syntactic Priority Thesis” for singular
termhood. Examined in this prospective, Dummett’s criteria fail to
furnish a general and language-neutral notion of singular terms, which
would be the original aim of the “Syntactic Priority Thesis”, and the
notion of valid inference, to which Dummett appeals to, cannot be
considered as a good guide to what there is because it fails to assure
the adequate generality to our recognitions of a correct inference since
it is based on linguistic notion that should be explained.
I think that Wetzel’s objections are also correlated to the
accusation of a certain form of linguistic and ontological relativism
which can be tracked back to Crispin Wright.31 This accusation states
that the linguistic relativism concerning singular terms infects also the
objects that, in Frege’s framework, are thought of as their non-linguistic
correlatives. Linguistic relativism puts in danger the Fregean notion of
object. As I explained earlier, even if Dummett does not explicitly state
it, his criteria are to be thought of as relative to a particular language,
because any general and language-neutral characterization of singular
terms is impossible. The point is that, if we don’t have a languageneutral notion of a singular term, it is impossible for a Fregean to supply
any language-neutral notion of object and to defend his idea of
“International Platonism”. We could not defend a general notion of
object but at best, as Wright observes, we shall be able to explain the
notion of an English-object, a German-object, an Italian-object, and so
forth. The linguistic relativism in Dummett’s criteria, as Wright notes,
puts in danger also the possibility to apply them to other languages,
because they could be subject to the indeterminacy a là Quine and
«minefield concerning translation».32
30
31
32
Ibid., 254.
Wright 1983, 62-64.
Ibid., 64.
13
VERA TRIPODI
Nevertheless, if Linda Wetzel were right, the challenge itself to
distinguish singular terms from other expressions would be absurd.
Actually, it is easy to undermine Wetzel’s objection. Dummett’s
criteria, in spite of the objection voiced by Wetzel, are not circular
because they are based on a pre-theoretical notion of valid inference
that is shared by speakers. As I discussed earlier, according to
Dummett, the assigning of an expression to the adequate logic
category depends on some simple feature of its use and the application
of syntactic criteria for singular term-hood requires the capacity to
distinguish a valid inference from an invalid one. Dummett’s definition
of singular term tells us that an expression is a singular term if it
functions in a “particular way” in inferential processes, which are
accepted as valid by speakers, of drawing a conclusion from premises.
So, the point is what we mean with the expression “accepted as valid”.
What does it mean that an inference is “accepted as valid”? Does the
expression “accepted as valid” mean “accepted as valid by the
community of speakers” or “accepted as valid by the theorist”? What
is it that establishes the validity of an inference?
It’s obvious that we have to distinguish between the theorist’s
point of view and the community’s point of view and between a
theoretical notion and pre-theoretical notion of valid inference. So,
even if Dummett does not expressly explain whether his criteria are
intended to be semantic or syntactic, what he probably means is that
the inference is not considered in semantic term, but in terms of what
kinds of inference are accepted as valid by speakers. In order to be able
to apply the criteria for singular terms, we need to be able to
distinguish a valid inference from an invalid one. For this reason, we
need to assume that the speaker understands the distinction between
singular terms and other expressions if she understands the validity of
certain patterns of inference. Therefore, it is in this sense –that we
need the notion of inference to explain the notion of singular term
without appeal to semantic notions. Nevertheless, what speakers
accept as valid concerns the community's shared sense of a certain
expression and not something that is theoretically maintained as
correct. It’s evident that the application of Dummett’s criteria
requires that a speaker understands the concepts used in their
14
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
formulation, in particular the quantifier “something”. It’s also evident
that what Dummett means with the expression “inferences accepted
as valid” is “inference that the community recognize as valid”.
Consequently, Wetzel’s analysis clearly indicates a misunderstanding
of Dummett’s use of the expression “inferences accepted as valid” and
can properly be rejected as illegitimate. Examined in this prospective,
Wetzel’s view according to which Dummett’s criteria are circular can
be considered not justified. As to the question of the indeterminacy à
la Quine, we can observe that that difficulty is (at least in theory) not
so hard to overcome if we can arrive at a sort of isomorphism among
translations of different languages.
Now let us examine the second objection concerning the validity of
inference. Validity is a semantic notion: an inference is valid if it
impossible that its premises are true and its conclusion is false, i.e. if it
preserves the truth. In order to evaluate whether an inference is valid, we
have to know certain semantic facts, that is to say we have to know in
what conditions its premises and its conclusion are true. Wetzel is not
convinced that it is possible to know the conditions in which a sentence
as “Middlemarch was written by George Eliot” is true «without already
knowing if Middlemarch was a singular term or a predicate».33 In order
to establish if “Middlemarch” passes Criterion II, we have to investigate
if the following inference which goes from “Middlemarch was written by
George Eliot” and “Middlemarch was written by Marian Evans” to “There
is something that it was written by Marian Evans and it was written by
George Eliot” is valid. Supposing that “Marian Evans” and “George
Evans” are rigid designators, this inference is valid because it impossible
that its premises are true e its conclusion is false. Nevertheless, according
to Wetzel, to determine if this inference is valid, we would have to know
someway that George Eliot is Marian Evans or that “George Eliot” is
co-referential with “Marian Evans”. But, requiring this kind of
knowledge would make the Frege-Dummett programme delimitate
singular terms circularly, because it supposes that only linguistic analysis
can establish what objects there are and not. According to Wetzel, this is
a problematic point to which Dummett doesn’t give a solution.
33
Wetzel, 1990, 253.
15
VERA TRIPODI
(ii) Inference and the Analysis of Proposition
On the basis of what Wetzel says, an opponent to Dummett’s
programme could argue that if the thesis that “we can recognize the
validity of an inference at intuitive level” were taken as involving that
intuitively we pick out what we regard as the general notion of valid
inference, it would be in conflict with the idea that the capacity of
recognizing the validity of certain inferences depends on our being able
to provide some sort of differentiation and to recognize the validity of
inferential rules. If this is right, Dummett’s thesis “we can recognize if an
inference is correct at intuitive level” should be also incompatible with
one of his former claim: the recognition of valid (or invalid) inference
requires at the same time also a capacity to construe a sentence as
divisible in a particular way (the capacity, for example, to extract and to
discern complex first or higher-order predicates within a sentence or
functional expressions within a complex term). The argument against
Dummett is the following. If we examine these criteria carefully, we see
that they are not based on an intuitive recognition. According to
Dummett, in order to settle the validity of an inference in which a
sentence may be involved in premises or conclusion, it is essential that
we are aware that «the constituents in which the sentence may be
analysed may be complex incomplete expressions which we form from
the sentence itself by omitting some other expression or expressions
from it».34 Sentences are constructed in stages (step-by-step). A
complex predicate is thought of as formed from a sentence by omitting
some occurrences of a proper name. Therefore, it is essential to give «an
account of inference in which it and some sentence involving the
attachment of a sign of generality to the complex predicate in question
both figure».35 An atomic sentence like “Socrates is wise” may be
analysed in two different ways: as composed of the proper name
“Socrates” and the incomplete first-level predicate “ is wise” or as
composed of the first-level predicate inserted into the argument-place of
another incomplete expression “ (Socrates)”. According to Dummett,
it is also necessary to distinguish between two different notions of
34
35
16
Dummett, 1981, 65.
Ibid., 29.
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
predicate: «as it is required for Frege’s account of the expression of
generality»36 and «as required in explaining the structure of atomic
sentences».37 These two different notions of predicate reflect the idea
that a predicate may be playing two different roles in a sentence. If we
need to characterize the general form of an atomic sentence, the notion
of simplex predicate is necessary and sufficient. For example: “Socrates is
wise” is composed of the proper name “Socrates” and the incomplete
first-level predicate “ is wise”. Otherwise, it is not possible to
considerate a sentence like “Someone is wise” as composed of the
expression “Someone” and the predicate “ is wise”. The sentences
“Someone is wise” and “Socrates is wise” have two different logical
forms. We need this notion to give «an account of inference in which it
and some sentence involving the attachment of a sign of generality to
the complex predicate in question both figure».38 The notion of
complex predicate is necessary not to explain the way in which its
constituents determine the sense of an atomic sentence, but to explain
certain inferential uses of sentences. This kind of analysis allows us «to
explain the general scheme of inference»39 to which we appeal and
«state the general principle to which we are appealing when we
recognize an inference»40 (e.g., from “Brutus killed Caesar” and
“Anyone who killed Caesar is an honourable man” to the conclusion,
“Brutus is an honourable man”). Complex predicates are necessary to
explain the generality expressed by sentences.
Examined in this prospective, the validity of an inference, given
what Dummett says, seems to be based on a particular analysis of the
proposition and not on the recognition of correctness or
incorrectness of some patterns of inferences “at the intuitive level”.
The recognition of the validity of inference seems to require that a
speaker possess an understanding of the concepts used in their
formulation, specifically an understanding of the quantifier
“something”. If that were right, the validity of inference would
36
37
38
39
40
Ibid., 27.
Ibid.
Ibid., 29.
Ibid.
Ibid.
17
VERA TRIPODI
depend on the possibility to preserve some syntactic and not semantic
property. This is the subject of the next paragraph.
2.2 Hale’s defence of the Frege-Dummett programme
Hale tries to defend Dummett against the accusation of
linguistic and ontological relativism with the following argument.
Hale states that it is necessary, in order to defend the
syntactic priority thesis and to give an adequate characterization of
singular terms, to distinguish between two different questions:
(i) What is it for an inference to be valid?
(ii) Which inferences are valid? How can they be recognized as
such?
Appealing to the “principle of necessary preservation of truth”,
Hale argues that it is possible to give a general answer to the question
(ii): an inference is valid if it is impossible for its premise (or premises)
to be true while the conclusion is false. From a logical point of view,
we need an account of language only as it relates to truth, because the
notion of the validity of an inference relates precisely to truth. To
satisfy this purpose, it is sufficient to provide an account of the
structure of the sentence by a specification of its truth-conditions as
connected with that structure.
Nevertheless, this answer is neutral from a linguistic point of view
and it does not supply an adequate guide for discriminating a valid
inference from another. To do that, what we need is some guide
which is strictly connected to a specific language and that makes use of
information about the truth-conditions of a sentence of that particular
language. According to Hale, the validity of inference thought of as
language-relative is neither a threat nor an obstacle, because it is on
the basis of this general account of (ii) that we can pick out and
construe criteria for recognizing valid inference expressed in one
particular language.
Likewise, Hale states, the relation between (i) and (ii) is similar
to the relation between the following questions:
(iii) What is for an expression to function as a singular term?
18
SINGULAR TERMS AND INFERENTIAL CRITERIA
(iv) How these expressions, which play such a function, have to
be recognized?
It is possible to give a general answer to question (iii): the primary
function of a singular term is to refer and to identify an object. Several
philosophers accept this general thesis. But this thesis is still not
sufficient to pick out singular terms from other linguistic expressions. It
is necessary to formulate specific tests for different languages. Even in
this case, our choice in formulating inferential tests for singular termhood is suggested by our «general conception of a singular term as one
whose function is to identify an object».41 Hale’s idea is that we are
guided by general answer to (iii) to pick out singular terms in a unitary
sense. It is the general answer to question (iii) that regulates the
selection of specific sets of criteria for different languages.
The point is that, Hale notes, the recognition of the validity of
inference requires that a speaker possess an understanding of the
concepts used in their formulation (specifically an understanding of
the quantifier “something”), but a speaker can possess such
understanding and at the same time lack «any general criterion by
means of which he could decide, for any arbitrary expression of the
language, whether if is a quantifier or not».42
So, according to Hale, Dummett seems to establish the following
analogy. Understanding a sentence requires knowing its truthconditions and the capacity to evaluate the inference in which that
sentence figures, but, generally, possession of this knowledge doesn’t
demand a capacity to explain how the truth-conditions are
determined. Likewise, the recognition of an inference as valid doesn’t
require the capacity to furnish a theoretical account of the particular
form it has. Hence, according to Hale, judging whether an inference
is valid doesn’t require an ability to explain why it is so.
To sum up: I’m not pessimist about the possibility of explaining
the inference relation as Dummett suggests and, in spite of the
objections voiced by Wetzel, I’m convinced that Hale succeeds in
defending Dummett against the accusation that his criteria are
circular and in conflict with the “syntactic priority thesis”.
41
42
Hale, 1987, 44.
Hale, 1979, 289.
19
VERA TRIPODI
References
Dummett 1981:
M. DUMMETT, Frege Philosophy of Language,
Cambridge (Mass.) 1981.
Frege 1988:
G. FREGE, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine
logisch-mathematische Untersuchung über den
Begriff der Zahl, Hamburg 1988.
Hale 1987:
B. HALE, Abstract Objects, Oxford 1987.
Hale 1979:
B. HALE, Strawson, Geach and Dummett on Singular
Terms and Predicates, «Synthese», 42 (1979), 275295.
Hale 2001:
B. HALE, Singular Terms (1), in B. HALE - C.
WRIGTH [ed. by], The Reason’s Proper Study.
Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of
Mathematics, Oxford 2001, 31-47.
Hale 2001:
B. HALE, Singular Terms (2), in B. HALE - C.
WRIGTH [ed. by], The Reason’s Proper Study.
Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of
Mathematics, Oxford 2001, 48-71.
Wetzel 1990:
L. W ETZEL, Dummett’s Criteria for Singular
Terms, «Mind», 99 (1990), 239-254.
Wright 1983:
C. WRIGHT, Frege’s Conception of Numbers as
Objects, Aberdeen 1983.
20