Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
14 pages
1 file
This paper is an intellectual history of Nietzsche and Frege's analysis of Plato's theory of forms.
Логико-философские штудии, 2021
Even though Frege is a major figure in the history of analytic philosophy, it is not surprising that there are still issues surrounding his views, interpreting them, and labeling them. Frege’s view on numbers is typically termed as ‘Platonistic’ or at least a type of Platonism (Reck 2005). Still, the term ‘Platonism’ has views and assumptions ascribed to it that may be misleading and leads to mischaracterizations of Frege’s outlook on numbers and ideas. So, clarification of the term ‘Platonism’ is required to portray Frege’s views more accurately (Reck 2005). This clarification gives us a better picture of what Frege is interested in and what he does not emphasize. Moreover, in such a clarifying process, we find that Frege draws significant influence from Rudolf Hermann Lotze, who is frequently called a Neo-Kantian (Vagnetti 2018). In Lotze’s major work, Logik, Lotze has a central focus on validity, in its most general form as he used it, that investigates various related topics, i.e., concepts, language, etc. (Vagnetti 2018; Lotze 1888). Furthermore, we observe that Frege’s work is so similar to Lotze, that it seems questionable to call his outlook ‘Platonism’. Therefore, attributing ‘Platonism’ to Frege may be a slight misnomer. This paper’s entirety is mostly a synthesis of a variety of articles related to Frege, Lotze, and their respective outlooks and the original works of Frege and Lotze that I use to support the view that the term ‘Platonism’ is a slight issue when predicated to Frege. As such, I include an overview of Frege’s treatment in other work that highlights the usage of the term ‘Platonism’ and how broad its uses tend to be utilized (Balaguer 2006; Burge 1992). In sum, it is observed that the general label ‘Platonism’ becomes less appropriate when we consider Lotze in the picture and contrast Lotze alongside Mr. Frege. Overall, this paper is just an explanatory one of Mr. Frege, the Platonist, and the issues of applying the term ‘Platonism’ onto him as his views are seemingly more of a segue from Lotze.
History and Philosophy of Logic, 2008
Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock's critical introduction to the philosophy of Gottlob Frege is based on 25 years of teaching Frege's philosophy at the University of Puerto Rico. It developed from an earlier publication by Rosado Haddock on Frege's philosophy which was, however, only available in Spanish. This introduction to Frege is meant to steer a path between the two main approaches to Frege studies: on the one hand, we have interpretations of Frege which portray him as a Neo-Kantian and thus as some kind of Idealist, on the other, we have writings like those of Dummett in which Frege is portrayed as a type of "philosophical Adam", i.e. as completely separated from his philosophical tradition. Rosado Haddock succeeds in placing Frege's thinking into a (slightly) broader philosophical context-mainly by reference to his contemporary Edmund Husserl-while also avoiding a (Neo-) Kantian reading of Frege's work. The structure of the book (which contains less than 150 pages of prose) follows chronologically Frege's writing. In this way, Rosado Haddock leads the reader through the whole of Frege's philosophy while highlighting important changes and developments in Frege's thought from the Begriffsschrift to his Grundgesetze and other later writings. Chapter 1 introduces us to the core philosophical themes of Frege's Begriffsschrift with a special emphasis on Frege's notions of "conceptual content" and "judgeable content". Here, Rosado Haddock, anticipates further discussion and points towards changes and developments of Frege's core notion of "identity", "function" and "content". Chapter 2 and 3 focus on Frege's Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Chapter 2 discusses Frege's methodological principles as outlined in Frege's introduction and his criticisms of psychological, naturalistic and Kantian approaches to the philosophy of mathematics. Chapter 3 focuses exclusively on Frege's own Logicist account of arithmetic while emphasising differences between Frege's views and Kantian or Neo-Kantian views. Chapter 4 and 5 are concerned with Frege's highly influential papers published in 1891-2, "Funktion und Begriff", "Über Sinn und Bedeutung" and "Über Begriff und Gegenstand" while also drawing on other relevant material from Frege's Nachlass, his correspondence and his magnum opus Grundgesetze der Arith
History and Philosophy of Logic, 2003
One particular topic in the literature on Frege’s conception of sense relates to two apparently contradictory theses held by Frege: the isomorphism of thought and language on one hand and the expressibility of a thought by different sentences on the other. I will divide the paper into five sections. In (1) I introduce the problem of the tension in Frege’s thought. In (2) I discuss the main attempts to resolve the conflict between Frege’s two contradictory claims, showing what is wrong with some of them. In (3), I analyze where, in Frege’s writings and discussions on sense identity, one can find grounds for two different conceptions of sense. In (4) I show how the two contradictory theses held by Frege are connected with different concerns, compelling Frege to a constant oscillation in terminology. In (5) I summarize two further reasons that prevented Frege from making the distinction between two conceptions of sense clear: (i) the antipsychologism problem and (ii) the overlap of traditions in German literature contemporary to Frege about the concept of value. I conclude with a hint for a reconstruction of the Fregean notion of ‘thought’ which resolves the contradiction between his two theses
Phenomenological Reviews, 2019
Brill’s Companion to German Platonism explores how Plato was interpreted and appropriated by some of the leading thinkers of the history of German philosophy, from Nicholas of Cusa to Hans Georg Gadamer. The book includes fifteen chapters, each of them devoted to one author or school, written by outstanding scholars. While most of the contributions deal with the reception of Plato’s epistemology and ontology, some others also—or only—address the long-disputed issue of how to interpret Plato’s philosophy. Since it is not possible to discuss all the topics in this almost four-hundred page volume, the review is limited to discussing how Plato’s most famous and controversial doctrine, the so-called theory of forms, was interpreted by German philosophers. More specifically, I will pay special attention to what we might call—to use the terminology suggested by the editor—the ‘transcendental interpretation’ of Plato’s theory of ideas. In the following lines, I focus on how this reading emerged and was developed by German philosophers in their various ways of endorsing, modifying, or rejecting Plato’s thought.
This lecture was designed as an introduction to Plato's theory of Forms. Reference is made to key passages of Plato's dialogues, but no guidance on further reading is offered, and numerous controversies about the theory's interpretation are left in the background. An initial sketch of the theory's origins in the inquiries of Plato's teacher Socrates is followed by an explanation of the Forms' primary characteristic, Plato's metaphysical separation of them from the sensible world. Other aspects discussed include the Forms' metaphysical relation to sensible particulars, their 'selfpredication', and the range of items that have Forms. Finally, the envisaged structure of the world of Forms is illustrated by a look at Plato's famous Cave simile.
Summary of Frege's "The Thought" with remarks on connections to Platonism, Meinong, and Berkeley
1 My purpose in this essay is to set forth something of the philosophical discussion among Plato, Aristotle, Plotinus, and Aquinas concerning Forms and First Principles and to add to that discussion which is continued in my own thought and, here, to the purpose of supplying supporting argument in favor of the Platonic theory of Forms and against the refutations and attacks upon it of Aristotle and my beloved brother, Saint Thomas Aquinas. To this end, what is required is a sufficient theory of act and potency so as to apply, in a metaphysics of pure act esse, analogically to both Uncreated Being and created being which is new ontology of universal pure act esse.
Quaestiones Disputatae, 2019
In chapter 4 of What is Philosophy?, Hildebrand asserts the existence of Platonic Forms. I argue that his position in that text is similar to Plato’s in Timaeus 51d, insofar as both philosophers insist that knowledge in the strict sense requires the existence of ideal Forms. The steps and theoretical scaffolding of each argument is explained, noting both how they overlap and how they differ. Ultimately, while Hildebrand affirmed some of Plato’s most distinctive insights, he also disagreed with him enough to significantly improve upon his theory of ideal being.
Continental Philosophy Review, 2011
This essay focuses on and attempts to uncover the truly radical character of Nietzsche's early "philological" work, specifically asking after the benefit he claims the study of classical culture should have for our present, late-modern historical moment. Taking up his study of the Pre-Platonic thinkers in 1873's Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter der Griechen, the first section analyzes Nietzsche's statement that history's principle task is the uncovering of Persönlichkeiten. I argue that it is not at all the subjective character of a psychologized individual that Nietzsche has in mind, but rather the moment of persönliche Stimmung or 'being attuned' to the world, which grounds and gives rise to thinking. In the second section, I show that the phusis or 'nature' to which the thinker is exposed in this attunement is comparable to the tension between the Dionysian and Apollonian natural forces in tragic poetry, as Nietzsche understands it. This dynamic conception of phusis does not provide a metaphysical substrate or an objectively real ground to which we might return via that Greeks, but is rather essentially phenomenal, i.e. it is nothing other than the movement into and out of appearance, which always entails and requires its reception by the human being to whom it appears. In the final section of the essay, this origin proves for Nietzsche not to be located in a distant past moment. Rather, it is the abyssal origin of the tradition that is always already effective in our present moment, informing our contemporary conceptions of our world and ourselves.
The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology , 2019
Environmental Chemistry Letters, 2020
Revista de Administração de Empresas, 2000
Sociology Compass, 2024
„Dilema Veche”, nr. 1008 (din 3 august – 9 august 2023), p. 21
The Career Development Quarterly, 1998
Crossroads. A Journal of English Studies
arXiv: Number Theory, 2019
American Journal of Physiology-Cell Physiology, 2004
1ο Διεθνές Συνέδριο για την ιστορία και τον πολιτισμό της Θεσσαλίας, Περιφέρεια Θεσσαλίας, Λάρισα, 9-11/11/2006, πρακτικά, τόμος ΙΙ, 2008
COLECCIÓN CATÁLOGOS RAZONADOS, 2020
Nuclear Instruments and Methods in Physics Research Section A: Accelerators, Spectrometers, Detectors and Associated Equipment, 2019
The Scientific World Journal, 2021