Bibliography
Lehmann, Hans-Thies.
Postdramatic Theatre. Translated
by Karen Jürs-Munby. Abingdon:
Routledge, 2006.
Endnotes
1
Hans-Thies Lehmann,
Postdramatic Theatre,
trans. Karen Jürs-Munby
(Abingdon: Routledge, 2006).
NONPHILOSOPHY
AND ART
PRACTICE
(OR, FICTION
AS METHOD)
Simon O’Sullivan
– 270 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
In the following essay I want to introduce François Laruelle’s
non-philosophy—or what he has more recently referred to as nonstandard philosophy—with a particular eye to its relevance for
art practice, when this latter term is very broadly construed.1
Although at times this essay involves more questions than answers
(and, indeed, proceeds through its own circuits and overlaps), at
stake is the mapping out of a speculative and synthetic practice
of thought, which might also be described as the deployment of
fiction as method. My essay is concerned in part with those modes
of thinking—art included—that occur away from the legislative
and more standard frameworks of Philosophy and Art History. To
move away from these frameworks is to call for a practice that
involves forcing encounters and compatibilities and, ultimately,
for experimentation with a terrain beyond typical ideas of self
and world. In terms of using fiction as a method more specifically
I am especially interested in how the performance of fictions
can operate to show us the edges of our own reality, and in the
diagram as itself a form of speculative fictioning. My essay ends
by drawing some of these different threads together, and laying
out six propositions or applications of non-philosophy to—or
indeed as—art practice.
time necessarily attempting to explain everything within its
purview. Indeed, each subsequent philosophy must offer up its
own exhaustive account of the real, “trumping” any previous
philosophy in an endless game of one-upmanship. John Ó Maoilearca
puts this particular pretension more strongly, suggesting that
philosophy itself is a form of “thought control” that attempts
to define the very act of thinking through its particular
transcendent operations (more on these below).2
1. Deinitions and Diagrams
From these few sentences we can already extract two key
characteristics (or distinct articulations, perhaps) of nonphilosophy:
In his work on non-philosophy (comprising over twenty-five
books to date and periodized into five distinct phases of
development) Laruelle claims to have identified and demarcated
a certain autocratic (and arrogant) functioning of philosophy:
that it tends to position itself as the highest form of thought
(enthroned above all other disciplines), while at the same
– 272 –
Non-philosophy pitches itself against this particular apparatus
of capture. Not as an anti-philosophy (as, for example, in
Jacques Lacan’s characterization of psychoanalysis), nor as
simply an “outside” to philosophy (at least as this is posited
by philosophy). Indeed, non-philosophy does not turn away from
philosophical materials exactly, but rather reuses or, we
might say, retools them. As Ray Brassier, among many others,
has pointed out (following Laruelle’s own suggestion), the
“non” here is more like that used in the term “non-Euclidean
geometry”: it signals an expansion of an already existing
paradigm; a recontextualization of existing material (in this
case conceptual) and the placing of these alongside newer
“discoveries.”3
1. It involves an attitude and orientation toward philosophy that
also implies a kind of practice (or, at any rate, a particular
“use” of philosophical materials). Laruelle also calls this a
performance, as well as, crucially, a science: non-philosophy
– 273 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
is the “science of philosophy” in this sense. (Brassier’s
writings on Laruelle attend specifically to this more “formal”
articulation of non-philosophy.)
2. Non-philosophy might be said to name other forms of thought—
other practices, we might say—besides the philosophical
(again, when these are not simply positioned and interpreted
by philosophy), while in the same gesture naming a general
democratization of all thinking (Ó Maoilearca would be the key
exponent of this second articulation, hence the title of his
recent book “on” Laruelle, All Thoughts are Equal).
I want to take each of these two articulations in turn, but before
that a further brief word about non-philosophy and the real.4
For Laruelle, as I have already intimated, philosophy involves a
particular take on—or an account, explanation, or interpretation
of—the real. Non-philosophy, on the other hand, is a form of
thought that proceeds from the real, or, at a pinch, alongside
it: rather than positing a real, it assumes its always already
“givenness” as a presupposition or axiom. For non-philosophy this
real is itself radically foreclosed to thought, at least as this
is typically understood (it cannot be “explained” or interpreted
in this sense), and as such we might say that the third key
articulation of non-philosophy is that it implies a form of
gnosis or even “spiritual” knowledge.5 In fact, alongside its
formidable complexity there is a sense in which non-philosophy
can be immediately grasped in an almost banal or at least naïve—
sense. I will be returning to this and adding some qualifications
below.
– 274 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
i. The science of philosophy
For Laruelle all philosophy involves a common function—or
invariant—that he names “decision.” Put simply, philosophy sets
up a binary that then dictates its subsequent operations. It is
always “about” a world that, in fact, it has itself determined,
posited as its object. In Laruelle’s terms (in Brassier’s
somewhat technical reading) this is “an act of scission”
producing a dyad between a conditioned datum and a conditioning
faktum.6 This decisional structure involves a further move:
philosophy’s “auto-positioning” as ultimate arbiter over the
two terms. Philosophy offers a certain perspective and higher
synthesis—a “unity of experience”—over both conditioning
factors and what is conditioned.7 Philosophy’s cut, we might
say, produces a particular subject and world, and then offers a
perspective (now seemingly the only permissible or coherent one)
from which to think them both.
We might also call this complex set of operations philosophy’s
ideological character: the real causes—or, at least, in the
last instance, determines—philosophy, but the latter is then
abstracted out and seen as itself cause of the real (hence, its
production of the world). The connections to two of Laruelle’s
key precursors, Karl Marx and especially Louis Althusser, are
explicit, but we might also note that this perspective bears some
resemblance to Lacan’s theorization of the retro-formation of the
subject (which must come to reverse the “illusion” of the ego and
assume its own causality), as well as Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari’s own materialist account of the subject as residuum
in Anti-Oedipus (a subject that misrecognizes itself as prior to
the process—the syntheses of the unconscious—that produced it).8
– 275 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Indeed, in a relatively recent summary of non-philosophy Laruelle
himself suggests that non-philosophers are very close to both the
political militant and the analyst.9
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
outside perspective). Non-philosophy, for Laruelle, must attempt
its task from within philosophy’s own interpretive circles (we
might note, again, the connections with deconstruction as a
process always already occurring “within” Western metaphysics).
The decisional mechanism is not restricted to philosophy as a
discipline (or discourse), but impacts on our thinking more
generally (we are all philosophical subjects in this sense). We
might note here the resonances with Jacques Derrida’s “diagnosis”
of a logocentrism that is determinate in philosophy (at least in
the Western tradition), but also in other forms of apparently non
philosophical thought (the lack of hyphen here denotes the non
Laruellian sense of these terms). Commentators have variously
suggested that non-philosophy (this time in Laruelle’s sense)
is a less convincing deconstruction (as in Andrew McGettigan’s
critical overview of Laruelle) as well as, indeed, a more radical
operation that itself repositions deconstruction as simply
another form of philosophy (as in Brassier’s own overview).10
Whatever the understanding, it seems clear that Derrida is the
“near enemy” of Laruelle, but also (at least to this reader) that
non-philosophy, although clearly indebted to Derrida, involves
something more affirmative (at least potentially) than the
melancholy science of deconstruction.
To backtrack for a moment: as mentioned above, for Laruelle,
non-philosophy is not another take on the real (or, indeed,
a sufficient explanation of it), but proceeds from the real.
For Laruelle it names a more radical immanence—arising from a
suspension of decision—that is specifically other to the world
produced by philosophy (whatever the claims of the latter about
its own immanence might be).11 Again, non-philosophy is a thinking
from a real that is itself indifferent to that thinking (there
is no reverse causality (or “reciprocal determination”) in this
sense). On the one hand, then, this real is very simple: it is
just “this,” immediately graspable, almost pre-cognitive (and,
for Brassier, uninteresting—and empty—in this respect). And yet,
as Robin Mackay points out in his own introduction to Laruelle,
it is in fact not self-evident at all (at least to the typical
“subject” that is in and of the “world”).12 Indeed, how could it
be self-evident to a subject who has been produced by the very
philosophical operation (the decisional structure) in question?
Non-philosophy is, then, an attempt to practice philosophy (at
least of a kind) without the aforementioned auto-positioning.
Crucially, it does not involve a straightforward disavowal of the
philosophical gesture (again, it is not non philosophy in this
more straightforward sense); nor does it involve recourse to an
“outside” that might then be simply folded back in by philosophy
(as I suggested above, all philosophy claims to supersede previous
interpretations, to really get to the real “from” a more radical
In its own operations, non-philosophy (at least in this
particular articulation) does use concepts, but only after
these have been untethered from their properly philosophical
function, their auto-positioning. Laruelle also calls this autopositioning the “Principle of Sufficient Philosophy”: simply put,
philosophy’s claim to truth—or as Anthony Paul Smith puts it,
“philosophy’s faith in itself before the Real.”13 This “explains”
some of the complexity of non-philosophy, in that it can read
– 276 –
– 277 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Fig. 1. The ventriloquism of non-philosophy
like philosophy (it cannot but be very close to the philosophy
it writes on) and also must use neologisms and other unfamiliar
terms—not only a new vocabulary but, at times, also a new syntax—
in order to articulate its non-philosophical operations away from
already existing philosophical language.
We could perhaps also diagram these relations between philosophy
and non-philosophy, in relation to the real, as a set of circuits,
as in in Fig. 1:
The arrows in the diagram suggest the direction of determination
(as in the real determining both non-philosophy and philosophy)
but also demark a direction of operation (as in philosophy
interpreting the real, and non-philosophy “ventriloquizing,” or
speaking through philosophy). To jump ahead slightly, we might also
call this ventriloquism of philosophy by non-philosophy a kind of
fictioning, insofar as the “explanatory” power of philosophy (its
various claims about the real) is transformed into something else:
models with no necessary pretensions to truth (I have attempted
to suggest this in the above diagram with the broken line inner
circuit). Certainly, in his more recent writings (as we shall see)
Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is concerned with just such
a mutation of philosophy, which he calls “philo-fictions.”
We might also note again the connections to Marx and Althusser
here: philosophy as a particular ideology (with its truth claims)
and, thus, non-philosophy as a form of ideology critique. The
apparent “real” world of philosophy—from the perspective of
non-philosophy—is itself revealed as a fiction, determined (in
the last instance) by a more radical immanence that has not been
determined by philosophy at all (indeed, this real is, precisely,
– 278 –
1.
2.
3.
4.
The real;
Philosophy;
Non-Philosophy;
Fictioning
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Fig. 2 The lattening of non-philosophy
(or “change in vision”)
undetermined). Crucially, however (and following Mackay once
more), one cannot draw a simple line of demarcation here between
ideology/philosophy and a science that “demystifies” them. This
would act simply to produce a further binary that philosophy
could then reach across and ultimately subsume; it would be to
produce yet another philosophical circuit, a further structure
of decision. Hence the importance of what Laruelle will call
“superposition,” an act of placing the two alongside one another,
as it were (I will return very briefly to this in section 2).
To see all this from a slightly different perspective—more
topologically, or even “non-topologically”—we might suggest that
non-philosophy involves a kind of “flattening” of philosophy’s
auto-positioning and a concomitant undoing of its Principle of
Sufficient Philosophy (again, its pretension of being able to
account for all of the real). We might then draw a second diagram,
as in Fig. 2:
This diagram foregrounds the particular “change in vision” (to
use a Laruellian phrase) that non-philosophy entails, a kind of
“dropping down” of philosophical perspective and, with that, what
we might call a rejigging of foreground and background relations.
Here, it is as if the conceptual material has been laid out on
a tabletop. This is not exactly a move from three dimensions to
two, but rather a flatness in which there are no supplementary
dimensions (to use Deleuzian terminology).14 The “view from above”
is replaced by something more immanent and, as such, partial (in
fact, Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is less an overview
than like a line, a clinamen, that touches on different “models”
of thought). It is this radical change in perspective that
enables a different treatment of philosophy.
– 280 –
1.
2.
3.
4.
Philosophy (view from above);
Non-philosophy (as dropping down);
Philo-fictions (and other modes of thought);
Non-philosophy (as clinamen)
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
To jump ahead again slightly we might note an immediate and
obvious connection with art practice here, insofar as nonphilosophy becomes a practice that involves a manipulation
of material (and even the construction of a different kind of
conceptual “device” that allows for this “shift” in view). We
might however also note four brief reservations before moving on
to the second—and somewhat looser—articulation of non-philosophy.
The first reservation concerns whether Laruelle’s diagnosis
of all philosophy is correct. Are there forms of philosophy
that do not proceed by decision in the sense Laruelle uses the
term? This, ultimately, is where Brassier marks the limits of
Laruelle’s method.15 An attendant (and stronger) critique is that
the operation of reducing all philosophy to decision (albeit
articulated in numerous ways) denies the specificity of different
philosophies and indeed can produce a kind of solipsism; this
is McGettigan’s take.16 A third reservation is whether nonphilosophy involves anything other than a kind of “turf war”
among philosophers (after all, generally speaking, non-philosophy
is read by philosophers). A fourth and final reservation concerns
what, precisely, a concept does when untethered from the
Principle of Sufficient Philosophy. This, for me, is really the
key question (and the most productive), and it is something I will
return to explicitly in section 2 below.
untethered from its Principle of Sufficient Philosophy, becomes
just one mode of thinking alongside a whole host of others:
artistic, but also the scientific, even, perhaps, the animal
(again, this is the democratization of thought, which is most
thoroughly tracked through in Ó Maoilearca’s work “on” Laruelle).17
Non-philosophy gives us an interesting way in which to (re)position
philosophy and its materials (as laid out above)—a radically
different point of view, as it were—but it also offers up a
corollary perspective on how different forms of thought invariably
coexist and, indeed, might interact. This is to posit a radical
horizontality (or, in Félix Guattari’s terms, “transversality”)
that operates between heterogeneous practices. In this change
of vision philosophy is brought down to earth, operating more
as fiction than as a claim to truth (it is positioned as a model
among others). In the same gesture, other forms of thought (for
example art), in their turn, are given some philosophical (or at
any rate non-philosophical) worth, insofar as they are no longer
unfavorably compared with a philosophy enthroned above them.
ii. Other modes of thought
In the second diagram above (Fig. 2) we might note the possibility
that the “flattened” philosophical materials—the philo-fictions—
can be positioned alongside other forms of non philosophical
thought (note the lack of hyphen again here). Philosophy, when
– 282 –
This second articulation of non-philosophy (as naming different
kinds of thinking) is less explored by Laruelle (although I will
look below at two recent texts by him on the kind of thinking that
photography, for example, might perform). This might well be, as
Brassier suggests, because non-philosophy, in one respect anyway,
has very little to say about these other forms of thought; it does
not involve yet another (philosophical) take on the different
terrains “outside” philosophy that it can then appropriate via
its own definitions of the latter.18
It is worth remarking, however, that these other forms of
thinking have themselves been theorized elsewhere (there is
– 283 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
plenty of material out there on art, the animal, and so on).19
The question, it seems to me, is whether these theorizations
have hitherto always been philosophical in character (proceeding
from decision), and, if so, what might a non-philosophical
theorization (one not proceeding from decision) of, say, art
be like? There is also the supplementary question as to whether
these other non philosophical forms of thinking “need” an
account—from philosophy or non-philosophy—in the first place.
After all, the work of artists, scientists, and so forth is
already occurring without the help of philosophy (although my own
essay does not attend to this directly, there is also the more
radical thesis I gestured to above that animals, for example,
already think in some respects).
It seems to me that this is one of the most interesting areas
of inquiry in relation to non-philosophy and art practice.
The diagnosis of how philosophy or theory captures objects and
practices (or, in fact, defines them as such in the first place)
is important, but more compelling is how non-philosophy might
reconfigure what counts as a theory of art and how it might
contribute—however obliquely—to an understanding of how art itself
works in practice, on the ground as it were (that is, when it is
not explained, interpreted, or simply defined by philosophy). Two
questions, then: what kind of framework does non-philosophy offer
for thinking about art; and, what kind of thinking is art?
In fact, the above two questions—of theory and practice, we
might say—are connected insofar as the change in perspective
announced by non-philosophy (the “dropping down”) produces both
a reconfiguration of what a theory (of art, for example) might
be and a different understanding of what thought (understood
– 284 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
as a practice) might consist in (in passing we might also note
that this implies that practice always already involves its
own “theory”—it does not necessarily need a further layer of
reflection—just as it also implies that theory can itself be its
own kind of (speculative) practice).20 I will return to some of
these questions in section 3.
To return more directly to Laruelle, and pull back slightly,
a more general question concerns what other practices could
follow from non-philosophy’s particular shift in perspective.
What different kinds of thought does it make possible in its
very redefinition of thinking? To a certain extent this is
precisely a work of experimentation and, indeed, construction.
The possibility of what Mackay calls “non-standard worlds” that
arise from this shift and radical change in perspective cannot
be predicted—or even, perhaps, articulated in typical (read:
philosophical) language.21 In relation to this we might note
Laruelle’s interest in poetics, or forms of writing—fictions—
that are not for philosophers (it is pretty clear from even a
cursory look at Laruelle’s corpus that the readership of his
major works needs to be well-versed in philosophy).22 Might this
more poetic and experimental register involve an untethering from
decision? Indeed, what forms of writing, we might ask, are really
adequate to, and appropriate for, the properly non-philosophical
subject? This question is of especial relevance when we consider
that, typically, syntax and narrative are generally a kind of
handmaiden to philosophy; I will return to this below.
To start to bring to an end this brief reflection on what I have
called the second articulation of non-philosophy (the flattening)
we might suggest a couple more questions. The first concerns how
– 285 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
Laruelle’s account of different models and of an “algebra of
thought” differs from, for example, someone like Guattari and his
own theory of metamodelization. In fact, it seems to me that there
might well be a highly productive encounter to be forced between
non-philosophy and schizoanalysis, not least as the latter
could itself be understood as a kind of “non-psychoanalysis.”23
To return to an earlier criticism, we might also ask whether
Laruelle’s thinking implies a certain homogenization, but also
(and almost despite itself) a further overview, at least of a
kind, “on” other forms of thought: non-philosophy as just the
latest novel philosophy, as it were. Although non-philosophy
does not involve the same auto-positioning as philosophy, it does
posit a kind of view from elsewhere, or, perhaps, a view on a view
(as exemplified in my own diagrams of its operations). In fact, as
I suggested in section i above, it seems to me that the latter—the
perspective of any view from above—must also be dropped down in a
further flattening (it is in this sense that non-philosophy can
only ever be one form of thinking; one perspective among others).
kind of overview (or, indeed, any clinamen that “touches” other
forms of thought). It would be a radical “non” that announces the
necessity of always re-localizing any global view. This “non”
does not name a terrain as such (external to philosophy), or
indeed any kind of steady state or consistent practice, but the
continuing refusal of any superior or global position—or what we
might also call a radical parochialism.
To give this another inflection, we might also note that these
different perspectives or models are also “lived” out in the
world. They are, we might say, performed (hence, again, the
connection between non-philosophy and schizoanalysis). Which is
to say that the realm of non-philosophical work is not only the
tabletop—and the abstract (non) philosophical plane—but also life
and practice more generally. (In this respect it is especially
the connection of Guattari’s abstract modeling to concrete
practice—for example, at La Borde—that marks out schizoanalysis
as its own kind of non philosophy.) Could we then posit a more
radical non philosophy? This would perhaps name forms of thinking
that do not “refer” to philosophy and its materials, or to any
– 286 –
All this speculation aside (and it has to be said that thinking
about non-philosophy breeds this kind of speculation, with
its various loops and nestings), there is also clearly a key
issue here—another reason that what I have called the second
articulation of non-philosophy is less explored by Laruelle.
Indeed, following on from some of my comments above, we might
note that the practice of non-philosophy can never be simply a
question of mapping out a terrain outside philosophy, as this
will then simply be co-opted by philosophy (as its material). Is
this, ultimately, the limit of non-philosophy as a particular
practice? Like deconstruction before it (at least from one
perspective), non-philosophy—as a take on the structure and
workings of philosophy—is delimited by the very thinking it
pitches itself “against.” Non-philosophy can operate as a kind of
trap for thought even as it diagnoses philosophy as itself a trap.
2. Interlude: Philo- to Photo-Fiction
I want now to briefly turn to Laruelle’s writings on what he calls
“photo-fiction,” which in many ways address—and bring together—
the two articulations of non-philosophy outlined above. Indeed,
for Laruelle a way of thinking the relationship of philosophy
– 287 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
to non-philosophy is through photography and its relationship
to what he calls non-photography. Here photography contains
its own Principle of Sufficient Photography, or, again, makes
a particular claim to truth. Indeed, photography (at least at
first glance) is an accurate and faithful “picture of the world”;
it is, we might say, a graphic example of those standard modes
of thought that Laruelle writes against. Outlining a possible
non-photographic practice is then also a way of outlining a nonphilosophical practice.
part of the real) instead of (or besides) its representational
function. In each case the conceptual and photographic materials
are positioned as fictions—or what Laruelle, in this essay, calls
photo-fictions and philo-fictions.
In his essay “What Is Seen in a Photo?” Laruelle pitches his own
take on the photograph against any “theory” of photography that
positions the former as a double of the world. Indeed, the task
is to think the photograph as non-representational (however
counterintuitive that might be).24 For Laruelle this requires
a certain stance or posture of the photographer—and with this
the instantiation of a very particular kind of relation to the
real—which then, in turn, entails the production of a different
kind of knowledge (one that does not arise from representation).
To “see” the photograph (and photographer) in this way means
both the suspension of a certain privileging of perception and
the interruption of the paradigm of “being-in-the-world.” In
this problematization of phenomenology—and refusal of yet more
philosophical “interpretive circles”—Laruelle suggests that
science and scientific experiences of the world might operate
as a guide insofar as the latter proceed through a pragmatic
and experimental engagement with the real (or, at least, with
a demarcated “section” of it). So, just as non-philosophy
involves a particular take on philosophy, a use of it as material
(untethered from its interpretive function), so non-photography
will involve a use of the photograph as material (as very much
– 288 –
In a more recent essay that develops this idea of photo-fiction,
Laruelle tackles the philosophical discourse of aesthetics
more directly, tracking a move from aesthetics (understood as
a philosophical account of art’s self-sufficiency or truth)
to what he calls, generally, art-fictions. These latter are
associated with the practice of a “non-aesthetics,” an aesthetics
not tied to a Principle of Sufficient Philosophy but instead
arising from what he suggests, again, is a more a scientific
paradigm involving the positing of models.25 On the face of
it, this later essay is less about art practice—photography or
otherwise—and more about philosophy (as instantiated in the
discourse of aesthetics) and how one might reposition it. Indeed,
there is still a minimal aesthetics at work in Laruelle’s own
account, at least of sorts (an account of what art “is”). That
said, Laruelle’s own claim is that these photo/philo-fictions
operate between photography and philosophy, with each discipline
surrendering its own “auto-finalized form” or “auto-teleology.”26
The two disciplines undergo a reduction of sorts (“in the sense
of phenomenological reduction”27)—or are themselves flattened—
and are brought together in what Laruelle calls the matrix,
or generic, “in which photo and fictions (a philosophy or
conceptuality) are under-determined, which is to say, deprived of
their classical finality and domination.”28
The generic—a kind of image or “space” of thought that is nonhierarchical (or radically horizontal, to return to a term I used
– 289 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
above)—is then this other strange realm (of the real) that is
un- or under-determined. Laruelle will also call this leveling
out an algebra of philosophy/photography. This horizontality is
important, as without it—as I mentioned above—non-philosophy
becomes just one more superior philosophical position (and thus
is itself open to further “nesting” by the positing of other
outside perspectives). Indeed, one might suggest that Laruelle’s
own non-philosophy is itself simply another form of thought
among others; although, as I also mentioned above, Laruelle
does suggest that non-philosophy has a specificity as a line—a
clinamen—that “touches” these other fictions.
In “Photo-Fiction, A Theoretical Installation” Laruelle is
concerned with building a new conceptual or theoretical apparatus
that would be capable of producing these strange photo-fictions
or models of the real. These are forms of thought (broadly
construed) that are less explanatory or interpretive of the world
as it is, and more speculative in character. Might we suggest,
then, that it is this experimental nature of photo-fictions that
characterizes them as a form of art practice?
As I intimated above, this strange kind of non-photographic
apparatus is also necessarily a phenomenologically reduced one:
it “pictures” what happens to experience when not tied to a self/
interpreter, or when such experience is not “processed” through
representation. We might also say the fictions that are produced
by it are somehow weaker (again, they are “undetermined”),
untethered as they are from a certain pretension. This is a more
modest form of thought, perhaps, but it is also one that has the
potential to expand the very idea—and working out—of what thought
is and might become (it is in this sense that Laruelle’s “non”
– 290 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
announces a turn from hermeneutics to something more heuristic).
The key for Laruelle in all this is photo-fiction’s break with
representation and mimesis and, with that, the production of a
certain kind of freedom (he writes, for example, of the jouissance
to be found at the end of “photo-centrism”).29 In themselves these
photo-fictions imply and, it seems to me, help produce a new kind of
subject (if we can still call it this), or what Laruelle calls (in
a nod to Kant’s notion of a non-empirical transcendental subject)
“Subject = X.”30 They also imply a new terrain (or, as I suggested
above, a new realm) to be “discovered”—or constructed—“beyond”
the “world” of philosophy/photography.31 Laruelle turns to quantum
mechanics here (and indeed in much of his recent writings),
where he finds the tools adequate and appropriate to this
experimental reorganization or reconstruction of the world (outside
representation). Such a “new” scientific theory does not involve
yet more binaries, but rather a “superpositioning” in which a third
state is produced by the addition (or “superposing”) of two previous
states. Superpositioning is a way of dealing with the paradox I
mentioned above of non-philosophy as both theory of thought and
just one mode of thinking itself—indeed, it is precisely quantum
science’s break with representational “accounts” of matter and the
universe that makes it so useful for non-philosophy. We might even
say that non-philosophy, in this sense, is quantum philosophy—and
that the Subject = X is the quantum-subject.
3. Non-Art Practice
I want now to develop some of the above in six different, more
specific “applications” of non-philosophy to art practice.32
– 291 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
In particular I want to test Laruelle’s method when it comes to
thinking through a non philosophical discipline with its own
logics and history, but also, more particularly, in relation to
an understanding of performance as its own kind of “non-art” (or
what David Burrows has called “performance fiction”).33
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
conceptual resources (given that the normal (philosophical) rules
are suspended).34 Philosophy (or non-philosophy) becomes a more
synthetic—and, again, speculative—practice in this sense (rather
than an analytic inquiry). More radically, this kind of practice
opens up the different space of and for thinking that I mentioned
above.
i. Diagrammatics
ii. Art as model
Diagrammatics might be a name for the practice of
recontextualization, reorganization, and general manipulation
of philosophical materials that have been untethered from their
properly philosophical function or discourse. I have already
laid out some of the aspects of this kind of practice above, but
in relation to art more explicitly we might note the possibility
that concepts be refigured diagrammatically. In a simple sense
they can be drawn, but more generally to diagram suggests a
different “imaging” or even performance of concepts. In fact,
art practice has always involved a take on philosophy (and theory
more broadly) that resonates with this—a “use” of philosophical
materials as material.
A key question here is what these philosophical materials “do”
when untethered in this way: what is their explanatory power
(if that still has a meaning here)? Or, to put this another way,
can this be anything different from the use of philosophy as
illustration, or “caption”? (Laruelle himself uses the latter
term when writing of philo-fictions.) What, we might ask, does
the treatment of philosophy in this way allow us to think?
One answer is that it might, for example, suggest surprising
and productive connections and conjunctions between different
– 292 –
Non-philosophy might also name the multiplicity of thinking—the
other kinds of thought—that subsists alongside the philosophical
and the conceptual more broadly. Indeed, there is the important
question, here, of the role of affect in art practice, and whether
this more pathic register might also be understood as a kind
of non-conceptual thinking—a different kind of non philosophy,
perhaps. Again, some of this terrain has been laid out above, but
in relation to art practice it seems to me that with this second
aspect we are moving into more productive territory. Indeed, art
practice has long been involved in non-conceptual explorations,
just as it has also involved its own particular take on conceptual
material (without the help of non-philosophy). A question
rephrased from one asked above might also be posed here: what does
non-philosophy in its democratizing aspect bring to art practice?
Certainly it brings philosophy (and aesthetics) down from its
throne, makes it more of a model among others; and, in the same
gesture, art’s own models are given a certain status beyond being
simple fiction (at least when this is opposed to truth). But
what does this modeling allow beyond such democratization? As I
mentioned above, very little is said about this area—the other
forms of thought besides philosophy—“within” non-philosophy
– 293 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
itself. Again, it seems to me that this is partly because a
certain deconstructive logic is at play: any form of thinking, as
thinking, is always already determined by the cut that produces
the world and the subject that thinks.35
“decision” (however that might manifest)? Insofar as art involves
representation (a “picturing of the world”) then the answer is
clearly yes (and the above comments on photography would have
relevance here—although work would need to be done to lay out
how this particular structure operates in art practice more
generally). But in this sense we might also say that modern art
has already been through its own “non” “revolution” with the move
from figuration to abstraction (Malevich and Pollock representing
the twin apotheoses of this tendency in Western painting).37
But perhaps we might rephrase this, and also put it in more
positive terms: non-philosophy cannot but use the stuff of the
world and thus must use it differently, untethering it from the
world (in the sense of a world determined by philosophy). In terms
of art one thinks of William Burroughs and his cut-ups, which
open up a different space-time. Indeed, narratives—the logical
sequencing of sentences (cause and effect), familiar syntax,
and so forth—which the cut-ups slice into and rearrange are key
determining factors of the world. Non-philosophy in this expanded
sense might then also be a form of non-narrative, or even a form
of non-fiction (in which the “non” names a widening of context to
include those formal experiments that go beyond simple narrative,
as well as a use of language beyond its representational
function). Such art will need to be “read,” or at least maintain
a minimum consistency of sense. Again, experiments in writing
non-narrative fictions (or, at least, in playing with narrative
schema) would be instructive here.36
iii. Non-art (and art history)
Another (and perhaps more appropriate) thinking through of
non-philosophy in relation to art would be an examination of
whether art performs its own auto-positioning and has its own
kind of principle that doubles the Principle of Sufficient
Philosophy: does art also involve a certain kind of invariant
– 294 –
In fact, with the further move beyond abstraction to objecthood
we have practices that, in their relationship to representation,
“mirror” the relation between non-philosophy and philosophy.
Certainly Minimalism, for example, was involved in something
else “beyond” representation, in that it was the production
of objects, assemblages, and so forth that were not “about”
the real, but part of it (and in writers such as Donald Judd
and Robert Smithson we have a clear articulation of this
logic—the radical break their practices announce—as well
as an indication of the importance of fiction, as a mode of
writing, in articulating it).38 We need only add that this shift
in perspective also necessarily changes the perspective on
previous art, such that it is then seen as representation but
also as itself object (what else could it be?). We might also
note Marcel Duchamp’s idea of the “reciprocal readymade,” which
involves using (representational) art as material for everyday
objects.39 Contemporary practices that refer back to—or reuse—
art, untethered from its previous representational functioning,
would also be important here (what is sometimes called “secondorder practice”), but so would those practices that, for example,
repeat or restage previous performances. It is also in this
– 295 –
ALMOST EVERY
MODERN MOVEMENT
INVOLVED THIS
DISAVOWAL OF
A PREVIOUS
DEFINITION—
THE PERFORMANCE
OF A FORCEFUL
“NO” ECHOING
THROUGHOUT TIME
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
sense that, today, abstract art is itself figural (it involves
the referencing of previous abstractions). There is a similar
structure to non-philosophy’s use of philosophy in these kinds of
practice, but we might also note that there is equally a similar
limit, insofar as such practices involve a nesting of art within
art (ad infinitum). I will return to this.
We might also gesture here to the history of the avant-garde more
generally and their refusal of previous categories of art. Almost
every modern movement involved this disavowal of a previous
definition—the performance of a forceful “No” echoing throughout
time (and manifestos embody this recurring motif, perhaps most
explicitly foregrounded in Dada, which further involved a refusal
of “good sense”). There was also, with the avant-gardes, a
concomitant drive to bring art into life. Indeed, in terms of nonart, a recurring feature of the avant-garde is the incorporation
of non-artistic material in order to disrupt representation.
From the readymade to Arte Povera to the happening, art has also
been—at least in its initial impulse—non-art. Here it is surely
Duchamp who best exemplifies the refusal of representation, just
as it is Allan Kaprow who gestures to the very limits of the frame
(and who does most to collapse or “blur” the art/life boundary).
All this amounts to saying that from one perspective art history
gives us an account of how art has always been thought in relation
to something outside itself.
There is a lot more to be said about this relationship between
art and non-art, especially in relation to Laruelle’s own ideas
about how an anti-philosophy (as opposed to non-philosophy)
invariably sets up an “outside” that then gets incorporated in
a renewed “definition” (hence my interest in the reciprocal
– 297 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
readymade, which does not look “outside” art (it is not an antiart) but uses art as its material). There is also the issue of
art practice traversing this edge, often moving toward non-art
status, only to hold back at the last moment, as it were, in
order to maintain an artistic status (again, it seems to me that
a certain deconstructive logic is at play with these practices
that oscillate between art and non-art). A question here might
be, then, what does an understanding of non-art (in Laruelle’s
sense) bring to the table given this particular history of modern
art? One answer might be that it allows a radical rethinking of
the whole question of the avant-garde and of the art/non-art
dialectic. To recall: Laruelle’s non-philosophy does not posit an
outside; indeed, it is not an avant-garde position in this sense.
Perhaps if we follow Laruelle, then, we are not so much exploring
a territory beyond accepted definitions, but reconfiguring the
very terrain of art and life (in terms of superpositioning). Once
again it would seem that non-philosophy (and non-art) has this
double face: on the one hand it allows a certain practice outside
the laws and logics of the discipline it seeks to undermine (it
is, as Laruelle calls it, “heretical”), but on the other it cannot
but be caught by these very forms (insofar as it must work within
and with them).40
as it were, a structuring invariant, whatever a given practice
might claim. Such is the strategy of Suhail Malik, who calls
for an “exit” from a Contemporary Art that is the handmaiden of
contemporary neoliberalism.41 Here the very “openness” of the
work of art is seen as profoundly ideological. In relation to this
recent critique of contemporary art, we might also note that there
has long been a “tradition” of radical (or “social”) art history
as a form of ideology critique that is intent on demystifying the
aesthetic and ideological functioning of art, and especially of
“Art History,” by giving a properly historical account of art
objects—might we even call this a kind of non-Art History (the
capitals denoting a certain disciplinary self-sufficiency)?
To return to some of my earlier comments about Althusser and
ideology, another take on the conjunction of non-philosophy
and art might be that non-philosophy can help to diagnose and
critique “Contemporary Art” as a whole. It might help to identify
a particular logic at work—for example, indeterminacy—that is,
But, to return to Malik, this is also a complex matter insofar
as we might say that contemporary art (note: no capitals)
is a practice that has itself been untethered from a certain
programmatic account (namely, modernism). Contemporary art is
already characterized by a radical democratization: this, for
example, would be Jean-François Lyotard’s take (on “art in the
age of postmodernity”), or indeed Rosalind Krauss’s (on our
“post-medium condition”).42 From this perspective it would be
Malik who is reinstating a certain program—we might even say
decision—about what art should do. Of course, it is always
possible to position the other’s point of view as the ideological
one (witness the Adorno/Lukács debates around autonomy versus
realism43), but it does seem to me that positioning art as
ideology critique—or as simply critical—and at the same time
dismissing practices that are not committed to this critique,
cannot but limit our understanding of art and indeed of its
terrain of operation (rather than, for example, opening it up to
further adventures).
– 298 –
– 299 –
iv. Ideology critique
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Nevertheless, a key question arising from this particular
perspective is whether there is indeed a non-art practice that
utilizes art as its material, but untethers it from its dominant
logics (whatever these might be); and, if so, whether this is
something different to what art already does. It seems clear,
here, that it is the definition of art that determines its “non”
(and, as such, if the dominant logics are indeed indeterminacy,
or perhaps representation, then this will define non-art as nonrepresentation and determinate). A further question is whether
art—or non-art—can itself escape these interminable circuits of
definition and redefinition. Can it offer a different kind of
knowledge “outside” art as it is typically understood?44
v. Performance ictions
Leading on from the above, and changing perspective a little,
there is also the compelling gnostic “account” that nonphilosophy gives of the real that I mentioned at the beginning of
this essay. At the end of the conference on “Fiction as Method”
(the progenitor of this book), Tim Etchells performed a “re-mix”
of the previous speaker, M. John Harrison, and his compelling
reading of one of his own short stories.45 Both presentations—
one a piece of fiction, the other a performance—were somewhat
different to the previous papers. Indeed, if the latter had
generally been about fiction as method (albeit involving creative
as well as critical approaches and interventions), here, in both
of these last contributions to the conference, we were presented
with fiction as method itself. With both it was as if the whole
conference assemblage had somehow tipped—and phase-shifted—from
being “about” the real to being “of” (or alongside) it.
– 300 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
For me this experience resonates with the radical immanence of
non-philosophy. Indeed, as I also mentioned above, there is
something surprising—and yet at the same time obvious—about
Laruelle’s idea of a form of thought that is from the real
rather than yet another interpretation of it. As I hope I have
made clear, art practice is often involved in this other kind
of presentation. The conference, however, made the difference
between the two perspectives—or gestures—suddenly very apparent.
Indeed, performance in general has this quality of producing
difference through a cut. It is non-representation par excellence
insofar as in its very liveness it offers an “experience” of life
“outside” representation.46 However, there is also the question
here as to whether at least some kind of minimal framing is
required to make it art, or else it becomes “just life” (this,
again, is the edge that Kaprow traverses). In fact, it seems to
me that a life might well need some framing—a performance, as it
were—in order for it be taken out of the frame within which it is
usually experienced/perceived (what Laruelle calls the world).
Counter-intuitively, art practice, as performance, can be more
real than life because it is framed (at least minimally).
The models and fictions referred to earlier in this essay
demonstrate ways of sidestepping more typical, often unseeable,
frames of reference. They offer one set of approaches to enabling
ourselves to think of art practice as the production of fictions
that allow—almost as a side effect—for a glimpse of the real
(or, to refer again to the conference, it is the very difference
between the two fictional worlds—our typical world and the world
an art practice can present—that allows for a small part of the
real to leak through). Again, unless a fiction is produced, the
– 301 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
danger is that a practice merely presents a piece of the world as
it surrounds us on an everyday basis, without any difference (as
is the case with art practices that simply archive what exists
without transforming it). It is, then, through the performance
of a fiction that art can foreground the always already fictional
status of a world it is different from.
vi. The iction of a self
Performance art aside, it seems to me that non-philosophy is
also at its most interesting and compelling when it is thought
in relation to a life that is lived differently, or in relation
to Michel Foucault’s suggestion (though for different reasons)
that “everyone’s life become a work of art.”47 This is to “apply”
non-philosophy to expanded practices beyond the gallery, but also
to think about aesthetic practices, in more general terms, in
relation to what Guattari called the production of subjectivity
(and to the expanded ethico-aesthetic paradigm that is implied by
this).
Indeed, as I have gestured toward above, we might want to ask
whether the very structure of typical subjectivity—and of a
“self”—is not itself the product of a certain philosophical
decision (broadly construed), one that is lived on a day-to-day
basis.48 A non-philosophical take on subjectivity will involve a
diagnosis of such a positioning (again, typical subjectivity),
but, for me, more interesting is that it might point to the
possibility of being in the world without a fixed sense of a
typical self (with all the attendant issues this unfixity can
bring). Laruelle seems to be suggesting something similar in
– 302 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
his “A New Presentation of Non-Philosophy,” not least when he
suggests that non-philosophy might be the only “chance for an
effective utopia.”49
This effective utopia would mean living life away from those
forms that have caught and restrict it: it is to refuse
philosophy, especially in its key operation of producing the
fiction of a (separate) self—or, rather, its positing of the
latter as not a fiction but as a truth (the self as product
of a certain decision that is then occluded, hidden from that
subject). Non-philosophy might then be about untethering the
self from its auto-positioning, its own enthronement (and as
such it has something very specific to offer recent accounts and
critiques of the “Anthropocene”).
In fact, it seems that what follows from this insight is not
the “dissolving” of the self, but, we might say, a holding of it
in a lighter, more contingent manner—as, precisely, a fiction
(and, insofar as the self is the anchor point for numerous other
fictions—the different worlds through which a self moves—then
these too are seen as fictions). Crucially, this might also
mean the possibility of producing other fictions of the self
(or other fictions of non-self), and with that the exploration
of other ways of being in the world.50 Although there is not the
space here to go into Laruelle’s own writings on this other kind
of subject, we might note his concept of the “generic human,”
or “stranger,” which he describes as a “radical ordinariness”
that is nevertheless at odds with the world (and which we always
already are, over and above any “assumed” subjectivity).51
A compelling final question—which I have gestured towards
– 303 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
throughout my essay—is what this terrain “outside” the self might
be like and if, indeed, it can be explored. Mackay writes well on
this discovery of the generic “beneath” the subject produced by
philosophy and how we might begin to experience and experiment
with it (for it is not a given, but, to echo Deleuze and Guattari,
needs to be constructed, piece by piece).52 It is perhaps with
this grand vision of the work of non-philosophy that we begin to
see the more profound connections with, and radical implications
for, what might be call a non-art practice. This, then, is
the experimental exploration—but also the construction and
performance—of new worlds and new kinds of non-subjects adequate
and appropriate to them. Or, more simply: fiction as method.
Bibliography
Adorno, Theodor, Walter Benjamin,
Ernst Bloch, Bertolt Brecht, and
Georg Lukàcs. Aesthetics and
Politics. Translated by Ronald
Taylor. London: NLB, 1977.
Beech, Amanda. “Art and Its
‘Science’.” In Speculative Aesthetics.
Edited by Robin Mackay, Luke
Pendrell, and James Traford.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2014.
Brassier, Ray. “Axiomatic Heresy:
The Non-Philosophy of François
Laruelle.” Radical Philosophy, no.
121 (September/October 2003):
24–35.
–––. Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment
and Extinction. Basingstoke:
Palgrave, 2007.
–––. “The View from Nowhere.”
Identities: Journal of Politics,
Gender and Culture 8, no. 2
(Summer 2011): 7–23.
Burrows, David. “Performance
Fictions.” In Performance Fictions.
Edited by David Burrows, 47–70.
Birmingham: Article Press, 2010.
Burrows, David, and Simon
O’Sullivan. Mythopoesis–MythScience–Mythotechnesis:
Fictioning in Contemporary Art.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, forthcoming.
Deleuze, Gilles. Diference and
Repetition. Translated by Paul
Patton. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1994.
– 304 –
– 305 –
–––. “Immanence: A Life.” In Pure
Immanence: Essays on A Life.
Translated by Anne Boyman,
25–33. New York: Zone Books,
2011.
–––, and Félix Guattari. AntiOedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Translated by
Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and
Helen R. Lane. London: Athlone
Press, 1984.
–––. What Is Philosophy?
Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and
Graham Burchell. London: Verso,
1994.
Foucault, Michel. “On the
Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview
of Work in Progress.” In Ethics:
Subjectivity and Truth. Essential
Works of Foucault, 1954–1984.
Edited by Paul Rabinow. Translated
by Robert Hurley, 253–80. London:
Penguin, 2000.
Judd, Donald. “Speciic Objects.”
In Art in Theory, 1900–1990.
Edited by Charles Harrison and
Paul Wood, 809–13. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1992.
Krauss, Rosalind. A Voyage on the
North Sea: Art in the Age of the
Post-Medium Condition. London:
Thames and Hudson, 1999.
Laruelle, François. “Fragments of
an Anti-Guattari.” Linguistic Capital.
Translated by Charles Wolfe.
Accessed January 7, 2017. https://
linguisticcapital.iles.wordpress.
com/2013/03/laruelle_fragmentsof-an-anti-guattari.pdf.
–––. From Decision to Heresy:
Experiments in Non-Standard
Thought. Translated by Robin
Mackay. Falmouth: Urbanomic,
2012.
–––. “‘I, the Philosopher, am Lying’:
A Reply to Deleuze.” Translated
by Taylor Adkins, Ray Brassier,
and Sid Littleield. In The NonPhilosophy Project: Essays by
François Laruelle. Edited by
Gabriel Alkon and Boris Gunjevic,
40–74. New York: Telos, 2012.
–––. “A New Presentation of
Non-Philosophy.” Organisation
Non-Philosophique Internationale.
Accessed August 23, 2017. http://
www.onphi.net/corpus/32/a-newpresentation-of-non-philosophy.
–––. “Photo-Fiction, A Theoretical
Installation.” In Photo-Fiction:
A Non-Standard Aesthetics.
Translated by Drew S. Burk, 11–24.
Minneapolis, MN: Univocal, 2012.
–––. “What Is Seen in a Photo?” In
The Concept of Non-Photography.
Translated by Robin Mackay, 1–28.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2011.
Lyotard, Jean-François.
“Philosophy and Painting in the
Age of Their Experimentation:
Contribution to an Idea of
Postmodernity”. Translated by
Mária Minich Brewer and Daniel
Brewer. In The Lyotard Reader.
Edited by Andrew Benjamin,
181–195. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1989.
– 306 –
Mackay, Robin. “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided.” In From
Decision to Heresy: Experiments in
Non-Standard Thought. Translated
by Robin Mackay, 1–32. Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2012.
O’Sullivan, Simon. “From Science
Fiction to Science Fictioning: SF’s
Traction on the Real.” Foundation:
The International Review of
Science Fiction 46.1 No. 126 (2017):
74–84.
–––. “Strata: A Geophotographic
Fiction.” In Robert Smithson: The
Collected Writings. Edited by
Jack Flam, 75–77. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press,
1996.
Malik, Suhail. On the Necessity of
Art’s Exit from Contemporary Art.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2017.
–––, “Memories of a Deleuzian:
To Think Is Always to Follow the
Witches Flight.” In A Thousand
Plateaus and Philosophy. Edited
by Henry Somers-Hall, Jef Bell,
and James Williams, 172–88.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, 2018.
Srnicek, Nick. “Capitalism and the
Non-Philosophical Subject.” In
The Speculative Turn: Continental
Materialism and Realism. Edited
by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek,
and Graham Harman, 164–81.
Melbourne: re.press, 2011.
McGettigan, Andrew. “Fabrication
Defect: François Laruelle’s
Philosophical Materials.” Radical
Philosophy, no. 175 (September/
October 2012): 33–42.
Metzinger, Thomas. The Ego
Tunnel: The Science of the Mind
and the Myth of the Self. New York:
Basic Books, 2009.
Nauha, Tero. Schizoproduction:
Artistic Research and Performance
in the Context of Immanent
Capitalism. Helsinki: University of
the Arts, 2016.
Ó Maoilearca, John. All Thoughts
are Equal: Laruelle and Nonhuman
Philosophy. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 2015.
–––, John, and Anthony Paul
Smith. “Introduction: The NonPhilosophical Inversion: Laruelle’s
Knowledge Without Domination.”
In Laruelle and Non-Philosophy.
Edited by John Ó Maoilearca
and Anthony Paul Smith, 1–18.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, 2012.
–––. On the Production of
Subjectivity: Five Diagrams
of the Finite–Ininite Relation.
Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2012.
Paul Smith, Anthony. François
Laruelle’s “Principles of NonPhilosophy”: A Critical Introduction
and Guide. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2016.
Schmid, Anne-Françoise. “The
Madonna on the Craters of the
Moon: An Aesthetic Epistemology.”
Accessed January 7, 2017. https://
www.urbanomic.com/document/
the-madonna-on-the-cratersof-the-moon-an-aestheticepistemology.
Smithson, Robert. “Entropy and
the New Monuments (1966).” In
Robert Smithson: The Collected
Writings. Edited by Jack Flam,
10–23. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press, 1996.
– 307 –
Tilford, Keith. “Laruelle, Art
and the Scientiic Model.”
Accessed January 7, 2017. http://
keithtilford.com/wp-content/
uploads/2015/05/Tilford_Keith.pdf.
1
The following account is
heavily indebted to a number
of other introductions to
Laruelle’s thought, including:
Ray Brassier, “Axiomatic
Heresy: The Non-Philosophy
of François Laruelle,”
Radical Philosophy, no. 121
(September/October 2003):
24–35; Ray Brassier, Nihil
Unbound: Enlightenment
and Extinction (Basingstoke:
Palgrave, 2007); Robin
Mackay, “Introduction: Laruelle
Undivided,” in François
Laruelle, From Decision
to Heresy: Experiments in
Non-Standard Thought, trans.
Robin Mackay (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2012), 1–32; John
Ó Maoilearca and Anthony
Paul Smith, “Introduction: The
Non-Philosophical Inversion:
Laruelle’s Knowledge Without
Domination,” in Laruelle and
Non-Philosophy, ed. John Ó
Maoilearca and Anthony Paul
Smith (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2012),
1–18; John Ó Maoilearca, All
Thoughts are Equal: Laruelle
and Nonhuman Philosophy
(Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press, 2015);
and Anthony Paul Smith,
François Laruelle’s “Principles
of Non-Philosophy”: A
Critical Introduction and
Guide (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
– 308 –
They are the great destroyers
of the forces of philosophy
and the state, which band
together in the name of
order and conformity. The
spiritual haunt the margins
of philosophy, gnosticism,
mysticism, and even of
institutional religion and
politics.” François Laruelle,
“A New Presentation of NonPhilosophy,” Organisation
Non-Philosophique
Internationale, accessed
August 23, 2017, http://www.
onphi.net/corpus/32/anew-presentation-of-nonphilosophy.
University Press, 2016). These
and other secondary texts are
referenced throughout (often
in endnotes), but I also want to
be clear at the outset that my
understanding of Laruelle, and
in particular the laying out of
the tenets of non-philosophy
in section 1 of my essay, is
based on these rather than
any exhaustive reading of
Laruelle’s own books (and
as such constitutes only an
initial foray into what, for me,
is new territory). Any errors in
understanding are, of course,
my own.
Endnotes
2
3
4
5
Ó Maoilearca, All Thoughts
are Equal, 1.
6
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
25.
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
26.
7
Ibid.
8
See especially Gilles Deleuze
and Félix Guattari, AntiOedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, trans. Robert
Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen
R. Lane (London: Athlone
Press, 1984), 16–22.
9
Laruelle, “A New
Presentation.”
10
Andrew McGettigan,
“Fabrication Defect: François
Laruelle’s Philosophical
Materials,” Radical Philosophy,
no. 175 (September/October
2012): 33–42; Ray Brassier,
“Axiomatic Heresy.”
Although I have used a
lowercase “r” here and
throughout, Laruelle invariably
has Lacan’s sense of the
Real in mind—as that which
is “outside” the symbolic
register and which indeed is
resistant to it (although, as
we shall see, Laruelle makes
his own modiications to this
topology).
As Laruelle remarks in
relation to the “character” of
non-philosophers: “they are
also related to what I would
call the “spiritual” type—
which it is imperative not to
confuse with “spiritualist.” The
spiritual are not spiritualists.
– 309 –
11
As, for example, Laruelle
will argue, in Deleuze’s
philosophy (see for example
François Laruelle, “‘I, the
Philosopher, Am Lying’: A
Reply to Deleuze,” trans.
Taylor Adkins, Ray Brassier,
and Sid Littleield, in The
Non-Philosophy Project:
Essays by François Laruelle,
ed. Gabriel Alkon and Boris
Gunjevic (New York: Telos,
2012), 40–74. Is this claim,
however, entirely correct? In
his last essay, “Immanence:
A Life,” Deleuze is very
careful to distinguish his
concept of immanence from
one that is immanent “to”
something (which would
necessarily involve a form
of transcendence): Gilles
Deleuze, “Immanence: A Life,”
in Pure Immanence: Essays
on A Life, trans. Anne Boyman
(New York: Zone Books, 2011),
25–34. Deleuze does attend,
however, to how a “point of
view” on this immanence
cannot but involve a certain
kind of abstraction and
“folding back,” but it is not
entirely clear, at least to this
reader, whether this can
be understood as simply
a decisional structure in
Laruelle’s terms. A more
detailed comparison on
this point will need to wait
for another time, but we
might note here Deleuze’s
own sympathy (albeit with
reservations) with Laruelle’s
non-philosophical project, as
evidenced by the footnote
to the latter at the very end
of What is Philosophy?
(Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari, What is Philosophy?
trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Graham Burchell (London:
Verso, 1994), 234 n.16). For
my own take on Deleuze
(and Guattari) as a form of
non philosophy see Simon
O’Sullivan, “Memories of a
Deleuzian: To Think Is Always
to Follow the Witches Flight,”
in A Thousand Plateaus
and Philosophy, ed. Henry
Somers-Hall, Jef Bell, and
James Williams (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press,
2018), 172–88.
12
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided,” 2.
13
Smith, François Laruelle’s
“Principles,” 26. Indeed, Smith
is especially attuned to the
arrogance of Philosophy—
and, not least, its connection
to a “wider” European
colonial attitude (hence the
importance of non-philosophy
in the decolonization of
thinking). In his Francois
Laruelle’s “Principles of
Non-Philosophy”: A Critical
Introduction and Guide he
is also keen to maintain
and defend the category
of the human (albeit that
this is not the human of a
straightforward humanism,
but of a more generic
– 310 –
“force-of-thought”) against
those other readers of
Laruelle—Smith has Brassier
especially in mind—who
are intent on dismantling
the latter or hastening its
demise. Might we say then
that Smith attends to the
ongoing importance of
phenomenology (especially
Martin Heidegger and
Michel Henry) for Laruelle’s
non-philosophy (though in
a “reduced” form), whereas
Brassier is interested
(see note 15 below) in a
reading that efectively
rids non-philosophy of
any phenomenological
residue (hence the focus
on abstraction). These two
positions revolve around
diferent attitudes to
alienation and reason. For
Brassier, alienation enables
freedom via the constructs
of reason (hence the
Promethean character of
his writing); for Smith nonphilosophy promises a kind
of overcoming of alienation
(and a limiting of reason) for
a human that is always more
than simply a rational animal.
14
See, for example, Deleuze
and Guattari’s discussion of
the rhizome in A Thousand
Plateaus, and in particular
the third “Principle of
Multiplicity”: “The point is that
a rhizome never allows itself
to be overcoded, never has
available a supplementary
dimension […]. All multiplicities
are lat in the sense that
they ill or occupy all of
their dimensions.” Deleuze
and Guattari, A Thousand
Plateaus, 9.
15
In Nihil Unbound Brassier
suggests that the
philosophical operation
that Laruelle lays out as a
universal invariant decision—
which Brassier describes
a “quasi-spontaneous
philosophical compulsion”
(Nihil Unbound, 119)—
is, rather, the hallmark
of a particular kind of
philosophy that inds its
terminus in Heidegger and
deconstruction. Indeed,
for Brassier it is only by
understanding Laruelle in this
way—as ofering something
to philosophy (basically the
suspension of the decisional
mechanism that in itself
might allow for a diferent
kind of thinking)—that
the radical implications of
Laruelle’s thought can be
laid out. Brassier argues
that this must also involve
the extraction from out
of Laruelle’s own account
of non-philosophy (and
especially of the human
as locus of the real) of a
“de-phenomenologized
conception of the real as
‘being-nothing’” (ibid., 118);
hence the title of Brassier’s
book.
– 311 –
16
McGettigan, “Fabrication
Defect.”
17
As Ó Maoilearca remarks
at the beginning of his
book: “Non-philosophy is a
conception of philosophy
(and all forms of thought)
that allows us to see them
as equivalent according
to a broader explanatory
paradigm. It enlarges the
set of things that can count
as thoughtful, a set that
includes existing philosophy
but also a whole host of
what is presently deemed
(by standard philosophy) to
be non-philosophical (art,
technology, natural science).”
Ó Maoilearca, All Thoughts
are Equal, 9.
18
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
27.
19
Again, we might note
the connections with
deconstruction as a
particular kind of practice
here; a diagnosis of Western
metaphysics, but also—more
elusively, perhaps—a gesture
to forms of thinking that are
irreducible to this.
20
On this point see Keith
Tilford’s unpublished essay
on the implications of nonphilosophy for art: Keith
Tilford, “Laruelle, Art, and the
Scientiic Model,” accessed
January 7, 2017, http://
keithtilford.com/wp-content/
uploads/2015/05/Tilford_
Keith.pdf. Tilford makes
an especially compelling
distinction (though not
one I use in my own essay)
between “theories” (based on
decision) and “models” (which
are, precisely, revisable).
21
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided,” 8.
22
See for example the texts
gathered together in
“Appendix I” at the end of
Laruelle, From Decision to
Heresy, 353–408.
23
24
25
As in Guattari’s
metamodelization of Lacanian
concepts. For Laruelle’s
own non-philosophical
response to Guattari and
schizoanalysis (and, not
least, the collaboration
with Deleuze) see François
Laruelle, “Fragments of an
Anti-Guattari,” Linguistic
Capital, accessed 7 January
2017, trans. Charles Wolfe,
https://linguisticcapital.iles.
wordpress.com/2013/03/
laruelle_fragments-of-an-antiguattari.pdf.
François Laruelle, “What Is
Seen in a Photo?” in The
Concept of Non-Photography,
trans. Robin Mackay
(Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2011),
1–28.
François Laruelle, “PhotoFiction, A Theoretical
Installation,” in Photo-Fiction:
A Non-Standard Aesthetics,
– 312 –
trans. Drew S. Burk
(Minneapolis, MN: Univocal,
2012), 11–24.
26
Ibid., 16.
27
Ibid., 14.
28
Ibid., 16.
29
Ibid., 18–19.
January 7, 2017, https://www.
urbanomic.com/document/
the-madonna-on-the-cratersof-the-moon-an-aestheticepistemology. For Schmid
there is no “birds-eye view” on
this terrain, and, as such, no
one model (of either science
or art), but rather a diversity
of models in superposition.
For Schmid this also implies
a new understanding of the
object, which is no longer
given as such but must be
invented (might we even say
ictioned?). Schmid gives this
expanded practice the name
“integrative object,” involving
as it does a kind of synthesis
of heterogeneity, one that
proceeds “piece by piece.”
30 Ibid., 15–17.
31
Ibid., 15.
32
I am aware that this idea
of an “application” is highly
problematic in relation to nonphilosophy; my comments
below attempt to address this
particular limitation. I would
also point the interested
reader to the writings of
Anne-Françoise Schmid, who
develops a more sustained
inquiry into the implications
of non-philosophy for art
history and practice. In her
article “The Madonna on
the Craters of the Moon:
An Aesthetic Epistemology”
Schmid follows Laruelle in
making a case for a generic
epistemology and, indeed, a
generic aesthetics that might
operate as an “intermediary”
between science and art, but
also between diferent art
practices (or even between
diferent elements within a
practice): Anne-Françoise
Schmid, “The Madonna on
the Craters of the Moon: An
Aesthetic Epistemology,”
Urbanomic, accessed
33
34
35
David Burrows, “Performance
Fictions,” in Performance
Fictions, ed. David Burrows
(Birmingham: Article Press,
2010), 47–70.
My own book On the
Production of Subjectivity
includes examples of this kind
of diagrammatic treatment of
conceptual material. Simon
O’Sullivan, On the Production
of Subjectivity: Five Diagrams
of the Finite–Ininite Relation
(Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2012).
Nick Srnicek suggests
something similar in his
own take on a politics (and
a certain aporia) that leads
from non-philosophy: any
form of typical intervention
in the world cannot but be
– 313 –
determined by that world (or,
again, takes place within the
horizon of decision): Nick
Srnicek, “Capitalism and the
Non-Philosophical Subject,”
in The Speculative Turn:
Continental Materialism and
Realism, ed. Levi Bryant, Nick
Srnicek, and Graham Harman
(Melbourne: re.press, 2011),
164–81. Non-philosophy can
in this sense open a view from
elsewhere (or, for Srnicek, it
can open up a kind of noncapitalist space), but it cannot
ofer any content (Brassier’s
reading of Laruelle’s method
puts this necessary abstract
character and formal
inventiveness in more positive
terms as the very work of
non-philosophy: Brassier,
“Axiomatic Heresy”).
36
In relation to this—and to
an idea of “ictioning”—see
my essay “From Science
Fiction to Science Fictioning:
SF’s Traction on the Real,”
Foundation: The International
Review of Science Fiction
46.1, No. 126 (2017): 4–84.
We might also note once
again Laruelle’s own writing
experiments here.
37
In relation to this it is worth
noting Deleuze’s compelling
observation (in the chapter
on “The Image of Thought”
in Diference and Repetition)
that philosophy needs to go
through a similar revolution
to modern art. Gilles Deleuze,
Diference and Repetition,
trans. Paul Patton (New York:
Columbia University Press,
1994), 129–67.
38
39
In relation to the irst of these,
see, for example, Donald
Judd, “Speciic Objects,” in
Art in Theory, 1900–1990,
ed. Charles Harrison and
Paul Wood (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1992), 809–13; and
Robert Smithson, “Entropy
and the New Monuments,”
in Robert Smithson: The
Collected Writings, ed. Jack
Flam (Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press, 1996),
10–23. In relation to the
second, see Robert Smithson,
“Strata: A Geophotographic
Fiction,” in Robert Smithson:
The Collected Writings, ed.
Jack Flam (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press,
1996), 75–77.
My thanks to Nadja MillnerLarsen for alerting me to
the logic of the reciprocal
readymade.
40 See for example François
Laruelle, “Non-Philosophy
as Heresy,” in Laruelle, From
Decision to Heresy, 257–84.
41
42
Suhail Malik, On the
Necessity of Art’s Exit from
Contemporary Art (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2017).
See Jean-François
Lyotard, “Philosophy and
Painting in the Age of Their
– 314 –
Experimentation: Contribution
to an Idea of Postmodernity,”
trans. Mária Minich Brewer
and Daniel Brewer, in The
Lyotard Reader, ed. Andrew
Benjamin (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1989), 181–95; and
Rosalind Krauss, A Voyage
on the North Sea: Art in the
Age of the Post-Medium
Condition (London: Thames
and Hudson, 1999).
43
Theodor Adorno et al.,
Aesthetics and Politics, trans.
Ronald Taylor (London: NLB,
1977).
44
This is the question that
Amanda Beech asks in her
own take on Laruelle and on
what she sees as problems
with an art practice invested
in freedom, immediacy,
diference, contingency,
and so forth. For Beech,
besides this critique of
typical operating procedures
and logics of contemporary
art, at stake is the outlining
of a diferent practice—or
Science—of the image,
one that embraces its
representational/mediatory
character in its own kind of
“critical-political project”; or,
in the terms of Laruelle’s own
“non-diferential space of
the generic matrix”: “What is
the distinction between the
paradigm of art as we know
it, and another category of art
that we could imagine in this
new coniguration?” Amanda
Beech “Art and Its ‘Science’,”
in Speculative Aesthetics, ed.
Robin Mackay, Luke Pendrell,
and James Traford (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2014), 15.
45
Fiction as Method conference,
Goldsmiths, University of
London, October 17, 2015.
46
Performance, as Tero Nauha
has articulated, can be a
practice that is alongside the
real and as such might be
thought of as an “advent” (as
opposed to an event that gets
“recaptured” by philosophy).
Nauha also makes a
convincing case, following
Laruelle, for performance
as a heretical practice
(pitched against the “law”
of representation): see Tero
Nauha, Schizoproduction:
Artistic Research and
Performance in the Context
of Immanent Capitalism
(Helsinki: University of the
Arts, 2016).
47
Michel Foucault, “On the
Genealogy of Ethics:
An Overview of Work
in Progress,” in Ethics:
Subjectivity and Truth.
Essential Works of Foucault,
1954–1984, ed. Paul Rabinow,
trans. Robert Hurley (London:
Penguin, 2000), 261.
48
Smith writes well on how a
certain decisional structure
produces the philosophical
subject (as separate from
an object—the real—that it
– 315 –
cannot know except through
itself) and how the nonphilosophical subject—as
“force-of-thought”—might
be understood, instead, as
always already a part of,
or a clone of, the real (see
Smith, François Laruelle’s
“Principles,” 45–61).
49
To continue the quote
from note 5, above: “nonphilosophy is also related
to Gnosticism and scienceiction; it answers their
fundamental question—which
is not at all philosophy’s
primary concern—“Should
humanity be saved? And
how?” And it is also close
to spiritual revolutionaries
such as Müntzer and certain
mystics who skirted heresy.
When all is said and done,
is non-philosophy anything
other than the chance for an
efective utopia?” Laruelle, “A
New Presentation.”
50
David Burrows and I attend
more fully to this in our
forthcoming book: David
Burrows and Simon O’Sullivan,
Mythopoesis–Myth-Science–
Mythotechnesis: Fictioning in
Contemporary Art (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press,
forthcoming).
51
One of the other key
thinkers in relation to this
area is the neuroscientist
and philosopher Thomas
Metzinger and his thesis of
the “ego tunnel” as productive
of what he calls the “myth”
of the self. See Thomas
Metzinger, The Ego Tunnel:
The Science of the Mind and
the Myth of the Self (New
York: Basic Books, 2009).
We might also turn again to
Brassier’s recent writings on a
certain kind of “nemocentric”
subject that is “produced”
through neuroscientiic
understandings of our place
in the world. In both of these
cases it is a question of
exploring a kind of nonsubject whose processes of
re-presenting the world (or
modeling) are opaque rather
than transparent (and thus
open to examination). Ray
Brassier, “The View from
Nowhere,” Identities: Journal
of Politics, Gender and Culture
8, no. 2 (Summer 2001): 7–23.
52
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided.”
BEYOND
PLATO’S
CAVE:
ESCAPING
FROM THE
CITIES
OF THE
INTERIORITY
Justin Barton
– 316 –
Bibliography
Lehmann, Hans-Thies.
Postdramatic Theatre. Translated
by Karen Jürs-Munby. Abingdon:
Routledge, 2006.
Endnotes
1
Hans-Thies Lehmann,
Postdramatic Theatre,
trans. Karen Jürs-Munby
(Abingdon: Routledge, 2006).
NONPHILOSOPHY
AND ART
PRACTICE
(OR, FICTION
AS METHOD)
Simon O’Sullivan
– 270 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
In the following essay I want to introduce François Laruelle’s
non-philosophy—or what he has more recently referred to as nonstandard philosophy—with a particular eye to its relevance for
art practice, when this latter term is very broadly construed.1
Although at times this essay involves more questions than answers
(and, indeed, proceeds through its own circuits and overlaps), at
stake is the mapping out of a speculative and synthetic practice
of thought, which might also be described as the deployment of
fiction as method. My essay is concerned in part with those modes
of thinking—art included—that occur away from the legislative
and more standard frameworks of Philosophy and Art History. To
move away from these frameworks is to call for a practice that
involves forcing encounters and compatibilities and, ultimately,
for experimentation with a terrain beyond typical ideas of self
and world. In terms of using fiction as a method more specifically
I am especially interested in how the performance of fictions
can operate to show us the edges of our own reality, and in the
diagram as itself a form of speculative fictioning. My essay ends
by drawing some of these different threads together, and laying
out six propositions or applications of non-philosophy to—or
indeed as—art practice.
time necessarily attempting to explain everything within its
purview. Indeed, each subsequent philosophy must offer up its
own exhaustive account of the real, “trumping” any previous
philosophy in an endless game of one-upmanship. John Ó Maoilearca
puts this particular pretension more strongly, suggesting that
philosophy itself is a form of “thought control” that attempts
to define the very act of thinking through its particular
transcendent operations (more on these below).2
1. Deinitions and Diagrams
From these few sentences we can already extract two key
characteristics (or distinct articulations, perhaps) of nonphilosophy:
In his work on non-philosophy (comprising over twenty-five
books to date and periodized into five distinct phases of
development) Laruelle claims to have identified and demarcated
a certain autocratic (and arrogant) functioning of philosophy:
that it tends to position itself as the highest form of thought
(enthroned above all other disciplines), while at the same
– 272 –
Non-philosophy pitches itself against this particular apparatus
of capture. Not as an anti-philosophy (as, for example, in
Jacques Lacan’s characterization of psychoanalysis), nor as
simply an “outside” to philosophy (at least as this is posited
by philosophy). Indeed, non-philosophy does not turn away from
philosophical materials exactly, but rather reuses or, we
might say, retools them. As Ray Brassier, among many others,
has pointed out (following Laruelle’s own suggestion), the
“non” here is more like that used in the term “non-Euclidean
geometry”: it signals an expansion of an already existing
paradigm; a recontextualization of existing material (in this
case conceptual) and the placing of these alongside newer
“discoveries.”3
1. It involves an attitude and orientation toward philosophy that
also implies a kind of practice (or, at any rate, a particular
“use” of philosophical materials). Laruelle also calls this a
performance, as well as, crucially, a science: non-philosophy
– 273 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
is the “science of philosophy” in this sense. (Brassier’s
writings on Laruelle attend specifically to this more “formal”
articulation of non-philosophy.)
2. Non-philosophy might be said to name other forms of thought—
other practices, we might say—besides the philosophical
(again, when these are not simply positioned and interpreted
by philosophy), while in the same gesture naming a general
democratization of all thinking (Ó Maoilearca would be the key
exponent of this second articulation, hence the title of his
recent book “on” Laruelle, All Thoughts are Equal).
I want to take each of these two articulations in turn, but before
that a further brief word about non-philosophy and the real.4
For Laruelle, as I have already intimated, philosophy involves a
particular take on—or an account, explanation, or interpretation
of—the real. Non-philosophy, on the other hand, is a form of
thought that proceeds from the real, or, at a pinch, alongside
it: rather than positing a real, it assumes its always already
“givenness” as a presupposition or axiom. For non-philosophy this
real is itself radically foreclosed to thought, at least as this
is typically understood (it cannot be “explained” or interpreted
in this sense), and as such we might say that the third key
articulation of non-philosophy is that it implies a form of
gnosis or even “spiritual” knowledge.5 In fact, alongside its
formidable complexity there is a sense in which non-philosophy
can be immediately grasped in an almost banal or at least naïve—
sense. I will be returning to this and adding some qualifications
below.
– 274 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
i. The science of philosophy
For Laruelle all philosophy involves a common function—or
invariant—that he names “decision.” Put simply, philosophy sets
up a binary that then dictates its subsequent operations. It is
always “about” a world that, in fact, it has itself determined,
posited as its object. In Laruelle’s terms (in Brassier’s
somewhat technical reading) this is “an act of scission”
producing a dyad between a conditioned datum and a conditioning
faktum.6 This decisional structure involves a further move:
philosophy’s “auto-positioning” as ultimate arbiter over the
two terms. Philosophy offers a certain perspective and higher
synthesis—a “unity of experience”—over both conditioning
factors and what is conditioned.7 Philosophy’s cut, we might
say, produces a particular subject and world, and then offers a
perspective (now seemingly the only permissible or coherent one)
from which to think them both.
We might also call this complex set of operations philosophy’s
ideological character: the real causes—or, at least, in the
last instance, determines—philosophy, but the latter is then
abstracted out and seen as itself cause of the real (hence, its
production of the world). The connections to two of Laruelle’s
key precursors, Karl Marx and especially Louis Althusser, are
explicit, but we might also note that this perspective bears some
resemblance to Lacan’s theorization of the retro-formation of the
subject (which must come to reverse the “illusion” of the ego and
assume its own causality), as well as Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari’s own materialist account of the subject as residuum
in Anti-Oedipus (a subject that misrecognizes itself as prior to
the process—the syntheses of the unconscious—that produced it).8
– 275 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Indeed, in a relatively recent summary of non-philosophy Laruelle
himself suggests that non-philosophers are very close to both the
political militant and the analyst.9
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
outside perspective). Non-philosophy, for Laruelle, must attempt
its task from within philosophy’s own interpretive circles (we
might note, again, the connections with deconstruction as a
process always already occurring “within” Western metaphysics).
The decisional mechanism is not restricted to philosophy as a
discipline (or discourse), but impacts on our thinking more
generally (we are all philosophical subjects in this sense). We
might note here the resonances with Jacques Derrida’s “diagnosis”
of a logocentrism that is determinate in philosophy (at least in
the Western tradition), but also in other forms of apparently non
philosophical thought (the lack of hyphen here denotes the non
Laruellian sense of these terms). Commentators have variously
suggested that non-philosophy (this time in Laruelle’s sense)
is a less convincing deconstruction (as in Andrew McGettigan’s
critical overview of Laruelle) as well as, indeed, a more radical
operation that itself repositions deconstruction as simply
another form of philosophy (as in Brassier’s own overview).10
Whatever the understanding, it seems clear that Derrida is the
“near enemy” of Laruelle, but also (at least to this reader) that
non-philosophy, although clearly indebted to Derrida, involves
something more affirmative (at least potentially) than the
melancholy science of deconstruction.
To backtrack for a moment: as mentioned above, for Laruelle,
non-philosophy is not another take on the real (or, indeed,
a sufficient explanation of it), but proceeds from the real.
For Laruelle it names a more radical immanence—arising from a
suspension of decision—that is specifically other to the world
produced by philosophy (whatever the claims of the latter about
its own immanence might be).11 Again, non-philosophy is a thinking
from a real that is itself indifferent to that thinking (there
is no reverse causality (or “reciprocal determination”) in this
sense). On the one hand, then, this real is very simple: it is
just “this,” immediately graspable, almost pre-cognitive (and,
for Brassier, uninteresting—and empty—in this respect). And yet,
as Robin Mackay points out in his own introduction to Laruelle,
it is in fact not self-evident at all (at least to the typical
“subject” that is in and of the “world”).12 Indeed, how could it
be self-evident to a subject who has been produced by the very
philosophical operation (the decisional structure) in question?
Non-philosophy is, then, an attempt to practice philosophy (at
least of a kind) without the aforementioned auto-positioning.
Crucially, it does not involve a straightforward disavowal of the
philosophical gesture (again, it is not non philosophy in this
more straightforward sense); nor does it involve recourse to an
“outside” that might then be simply folded back in by philosophy
(as I suggested above, all philosophy claims to supersede previous
interpretations, to really get to the real “from” a more radical
In its own operations, non-philosophy (at least in this
particular articulation) does use concepts, but only after
these have been untethered from their properly philosophical
function, their auto-positioning. Laruelle also calls this autopositioning the “Principle of Sufficient Philosophy”: simply put,
philosophy’s claim to truth—or as Anthony Paul Smith puts it,
“philosophy’s faith in itself before the Real.”13 This “explains”
some of the complexity of non-philosophy, in that it can read
– 276 –
– 277 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Fig. 1. The ventriloquism of non-philosophy
like philosophy (it cannot but be very close to the philosophy
it writes on) and also must use neologisms and other unfamiliar
terms—not only a new vocabulary but, at times, also a new syntax—
in order to articulate its non-philosophical operations away from
already existing philosophical language.
We could perhaps also diagram these relations between philosophy
and non-philosophy, in relation to the real, as a set of circuits,
as in in Fig. 1:
The arrows in the diagram suggest the direction of determination
(as in the real determining both non-philosophy and philosophy)
but also demark a direction of operation (as in philosophy
interpreting the real, and non-philosophy “ventriloquizing,” or
speaking through philosophy). To jump ahead slightly, we might also
call this ventriloquism of philosophy by non-philosophy a kind of
fictioning, insofar as the “explanatory” power of philosophy (its
various claims about the real) is transformed into something else:
models with no necessary pretensions to truth (I have attempted
to suggest this in the above diagram with the broken line inner
circuit). Certainly, in his more recent writings (as we shall see)
Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is concerned with just such
a mutation of philosophy, which he calls “philo-fictions.”
We might also note again the connections to Marx and Althusser
here: philosophy as a particular ideology (with its truth claims)
and, thus, non-philosophy as a form of ideology critique. The
apparent “real” world of philosophy—from the perspective of
non-philosophy—is itself revealed as a fiction, determined (in
the last instance) by a more radical immanence that has not been
determined by philosophy at all (indeed, this real is, precisely,
– 278 –
1.
2.
3.
4.
The real;
Philosophy;
Non-Philosophy;
Fictioning
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Fig. 2 The lattening of non-philosophy
(or “change in vision”)
undetermined). Crucially, however (and following Mackay once
more), one cannot draw a simple line of demarcation here between
ideology/philosophy and a science that “demystifies” them. This
would act simply to produce a further binary that philosophy
could then reach across and ultimately subsume; it would be to
produce yet another philosophical circuit, a further structure
of decision. Hence the importance of what Laruelle will call
“superposition,” an act of placing the two alongside one another,
as it were (I will return very briefly to this in section 2).
To see all this from a slightly different perspective—more
topologically, or even “non-topologically”—we might suggest that
non-philosophy involves a kind of “flattening” of philosophy’s
auto-positioning and a concomitant undoing of its Principle of
Sufficient Philosophy (again, its pretension of being able to
account for all of the real). We might then draw a second diagram,
as in Fig. 2:
This diagram foregrounds the particular “change in vision” (to
use a Laruellian phrase) that non-philosophy entails, a kind of
“dropping down” of philosophical perspective and, with that, what
we might call a rejigging of foreground and background relations.
Here, it is as if the conceptual material has been laid out on
a tabletop. This is not exactly a move from three dimensions to
two, but rather a flatness in which there are no supplementary
dimensions (to use Deleuzian terminology).14 The “view from above”
is replaced by something more immanent and, as such, partial (in
fact, Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is less an overview
than like a line, a clinamen, that touches on different “models”
of thought). It is this radical change in perspective that
enables a different treatment of philosophy.
– 280 –
1.
2.
3.
4.
Philosophy (view from above);
Non-philosophy (as dropping down);
Philo-fictions (and other modes of thought);
Non-philosophy (as clinamen)
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
To jump ahead again slightly we might note an immediate and
obvious connection with art practice here, insofar as nonphilosophy becomes a practice that involves a manipulation
of material (and even the construction of a different kind of
conceptual “device” that allows for this “shift” in view). We
might however also note four brief reservations before moving on
to the second—and somewhat looser—articulation of non-philosophy.
The first reservation concerns whether Laruelle’s diagnosis
of all philosophy is correct. Are there forms of philosophy
that do not proceed by decision in the sense Laruelle uses the
term? This, ultimately, is where Brassier marks the limits of
Laruelle’s method.15 An attendant (and stronger) critique is that
the operation of reducing all philosophy to decision (albeit
articulated in numerous ways) denies the specificity of different
philosophies and indeed can produce a kind of solipsism; this
is McGettigan’s take.16 A third reservation is whether nonphilosophy involves anything other than a kind of “turf war”
among philosophers (after all, generally speaking, non-philosophy
is read by philosophers). A fourth and final reservation concerns
what, precisely, a concept does when untethered from the
Principle of Sufficient Philosophy. This, for me, is really the
key question (and the most productive), and it is something I will
return to explicitly in section 2 below.
untethered from its Principle of Sufficient Philosophy, becomes
just one mode of thinking alongside a whole host of others:
artistic, but also the scientific, even, perhaps, the animal
(again, this is the democratization of thought, which is most
thoroughly tracked through in Ó Maoilearca’s work “on” Laruelle).17
Non-philosophy gives us an interesting way in which to (re)position
philosophy and its materials (as laid out above)—a radically
different point of view, as it were—but it also offers up a
corollary perspective on how different forms of thought invariably
coexist and, indeed, might interact. This is to posit a radical
horizontality (or, in Félix Guattari’s terms, “transversality”)
that operates between heterogeneous practices. In this change
of vision philosophy is brought down to earth, operating more
as fiction than as a claim to truth (it is positioned as a model
among others). In the same gesture, other forms of thought (for
example art), in their turn, are given some philosophical (or at
any rate non-philosophical) worth, insofar as they are no longer
unfavorably compared with a philosophy enthroned above them.
ii. Other modes of thought
In the second diagram above (Fig. 2) we might note the possibility
that the “flattened” philosophical materials—the philo-fictions—
can be positioned alongside other forms of non philosophical
thought (note the lack of hyphen again here). Philosophy, when
– 282 –
This second articulation of non-philosophy (as naming different
kinds of thinking) is less explored by Laruelle (although I will
look below at two recent texts by him on the kind of thinking that
photography, for example, might perform). This might well be, as
Brassier suggests, because non-philosophy, in one respect anyway,
has very little to say about these other forms of thought; it does
not involve yet another (philosophical) take on the different
terrains “outside” philosophy that it can then appropriate via
its own definitions of the latter.18
It is worth remarking, however, that these other forms of
thinking have themselves been theorized elsewhere (there is
– 283 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
plenty of material out there on art, the animal, and so on).19
The question, it seems to me, is whether these theorizations
have hitherto always been philosophical in character (proceeding
from decision), and, if so, what might a non-philosophical
theorization (one not proceeding from decision) of, say, art
be like? There is also the supplementary question as to whether
these other non philosophical forms of thinking “need” an
account—from philosophy or non-philosophy—in the first place.
After all, the work of artists, scientists, and so forth is
already occurring without the help of philosophy (although my own
essay does not attend to this directly, there is also the more
radical thesis I gestured to above that animals, for example,
already think in some respects).
It seems to me that this is one of the most interesting areas
of inquiry in relation to non-philosophy and art practice.
The diagnosis of how philosophy or theory captures objects and
practices (or, in fact, defines them as such in the first place)
is important, but more compelling is how non-philosophy might
reconfigure what counts as a theory of art and how it might
contribute—however obliquely—to an understanding of how art itself
works in practice, on the ground as it were (that is, when it is
not explained, interpreted, or simply defined by philosophy). Two
questions, then: what kind of framework does non-philosophy offer
for thinking about art; and, what kind of thinking is art?
In fact, the above two questions—of theory and practice, we
might say—are connected insofar as the change in perspective
announced by non-philosophy (the “dropping down”) produces both
a reconfiguration of what a theory (of art, for example) might
be and a different understanding of what thought (understood
– 284 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
as a practice) might consist in (in passing we might also note
that this implies that practice always already involves its
own “theory”—it does not necessarily need a further layer of
reflection—just as it also implies that theory can itself be its
own kind of (speculative) practice).20 I will return to some of
these questions in section 3.
To return more directly to Laruelle, and pull back slightly,
a more general question concerns what other practices could
follow from non-philosophy’s particular shift in perspective.
What different kinds of thought does it make possible in its
very redefinition of thinking? To a certain extent this is
precisely a work of experimentation and, indeed, construction.
The possibility of what Mackay calls “non-standard worlds” that
arise from this shift and radical change in perspective cannot
be predicted—or even, perhaps, articulated in typical (read:
philosophical) language.21 In relation to this we might note
Laruelle’s interest in poetics, or forms of writing—fictions—
that are not for philosophers (it is pretty clear from even a
cursory look at Laruelle’s corpus that the readership of his
major works needs to be well-versed in philosophy).22 Might this
more poetic and experimental register involve an untethering from
decision? Indeed, what forms of writing, we might ask, are really
adequate to, and appropriate for, the properly non-philosophical
subject? This question is of especial relevance when we consider
that, typically, syntax and narrative are generally a kind of
handmaiden to philosophy; I will return to this below.
To start to bring to an end this brief reflection on what I have
called the second articulation of non-philosophy (the flattening)
we might suggest a couple more questions. The first concerns how
– 285 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
Laruelle’s account of different models and of an “algebra of
thought” differs from, for example, someone like Guattari and his
own theory of metamodelization. In fact, it seems to me that there
might well be a highly productive encounter to be forced between
non-philosophy and schizoanalysis, not least as the latter
could itself be understood as a kind of “non-psychoanalysis.”23
To return to an earlier criticism, we might also ask whether
Laruelle’s thinking implies a certain homogenization, but also
(and almost despite itself) a further overview, at least of a
kind, “on” other forms of thought: non-philosophy as just the
latest novel philosophy, as it were. Although non-philosophy
does not involve the same auto-positioning as philosophy, it does
posit a kind of view from elsewhere, or, perhaps, a view on a view
(as exemplified in my own diagrams of its operations). In fact, as
I suggested in section i above, it seems to me that the latter—the
perspective of any view from above—must also be dropped down in a
further flattening (it is in this sense that non-philosophy can
only ever be one form of thinking; one perspective among others).
kind of overview (or, indeed, any clinamen that “touches” other
forms of thought). It would be a radical “non” that announces the
necessity of always re-localizing any global view. This “non”
does not name a terrain as such (external to philosophy), or
indeed any kind of steady state or consistent practice, but the
continuing refusal of any superior or global position—or what we
might also call a radical parochialism.
To give this another inflection, we might also note that these
different perspectives or models are also “lived” out in the
world. They are, we might say, performed (hence, again, the
connection between non-philosophy and schizoanalysis). Which is
to say that the realm of non-philosophical work is not only the
tabletop—and the abstract (non) philosophical plane—but also life
and practice more generally. (In this respect it is especially
the connection of Guattari’s abstract modeling to concrete
practice—for example, at La Borde—that marks out schizoanalysis
as its own kind of non philosophy.) Could we then posit a more
radical non philosophy? This would perhaps name forms of thinking
that do not “refer” to philosophy and its materials, or to any
– 286 –
All this speculation aside (and it has to be said that thinking
about non-philosophy breeds this kind of speculation, with
its various loops and nestings), there is also clearly a key
issue here—another reason that what I have called the second
articulation of non-philosophy is less explored by Laruelle.
Indeed, following on from some of my comments above, we might
note that the practice of non-philosophy can never be simply a
question of mapping out a terrain outside philosophy, as this
will then simply be co-opted by philosophy (as its material). Is
this, ultimately, the limit of non-philosophy as a particular
practice? Like deconstruction before it (at least from one
perspective), non-philosophy—as a take on the structure and
workings of philosophy—is delimited by the very thinking it
pitches itself “against.” Non-philosophy can operate as a kind of
trap for thought even as it diagnoses philosophy as itself a trap.
2. Interlude: Philo- to Photo-Fiction
I want now to briefly turn to Laruelle’s writings on what he calls
“photo-fiction,” which in many ways address—and bring together—
the two articulations of non-philosophy outlined above. Indeed,
for Laruelle a way of thinking the relationship of philosophy
– 287 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
to non-philosophy is through photography and its relationship
to what he calls non-photography. Here photography contains
its own Principle of Sufficient Photography, or, again, makes
a particular claim to truth. Indeed, photography (at least at
first glance) is an accurate and faithful “picture of the world”;
it is, we might say, a graphic example of those standard modes
of thought that Laruelle writes against. Outlining a possible
non-photographic practice is then also a way of outlining a nonphilosophical practice.
part of the real) instead of (or besides) its representational
function. In each case the conceptual and photographic materials
are positioned as fictions—or what Laruelle, in this essay, calls
photo-fictions and philo-fictions.
In his essay “What Is Seen in a Photo?” Laruelle pitches his own
take on the photograph against any “theory” of photography that
positions the former as a double of the world. Indeed, the task
is to think the photograph as non-representational (however
counterintuitive that might be).24 For Laruelle this requires
a certain stance or posture of the photographer—and with this
the instantiation of a very particular kind of relation to the
real—which then, in turn, entails the production of a different
kind of knowledge (one that does not arise from representation).
To “see” the photograph (and photographer) in this way means
both the suspension of a certain privileging of perception and
the interruption of the paradigm of “being-in-the-world.” In
this problematization of phenomenology—and refusal of yet more
philosophical “interpretive circles”—Laruelle suggests that
science and scientific experiences of the world might operate
as a guide insofar as the latter proceed through a pragmatic
and experimental engagement with the real (or, at least, with
a demarcated “section” of it). So, just as non-philosophy
involves a particular take on philosophy, a use of it as material
(untethered from its interpretive function), so non-photography
will involve a use of the photograph as material (as very much
– 288 –
In a more recent essay that develops this idea of photo-fiction,
Laruelle tackles the philosophical discourse of aesthetics
more directly, tracking a move from aesthetics (understood as
a philosophical account of art’s self-sufficiency or truth)
to what he calls, generally, art-fictions. These latter are
associated with the practice of a “non-aesthetics,” an aesthetics
not tied to a Principle of Sufficient Philosophy but instead
arising from what he suggests, again, is a more a scientific
paradigm involving the positing of models.25 On the face of
it, this later essay is less about art practice—photography or
otherwise—and more about philosophy (as instantiated in the
discourse of aesthetics) and how one might reposition it. Indeed,
there is still a minimal aesthetics at work in Laruelle’s own
account, at least of sorts (an account of what art “is”). That
said, Laruelle’s own claim is that these photo/philo-fictions
operate between photography and philosophy, with each discipline
surrendering its own “auto-finalized form” or “auto-teleology.”26
The two disciplines undergo a reduction of sorts (“in the sense
of phenomenological reduction”27)—or are themselves flattened—
and are brought together in what Laruelle calls the matrix,
or generic, “in which photo and fictions (a philosophy or
conceptuality) are under-determined, which is to say, deprived of
their classical finality and domination.”28
The generic—a kind of image or “space” of thought that is nonhierarchical (or radically horizontal, to return to a term I used
– 289 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
above)—is then this other strange realm (of the real) that is
un- or under-determined. Laruelle will also call this leveling
out an algebra of philosophy/photography. This horizontality is
important, as without it—as I mentioned above—non-philosophy
becomes just one more superior philosophical position (and thus
is itself open to further “nesting” by the positing of other
outside perspectives). Indeed, one might suggest that Laruelle’s
own non-philosophy is itself simply another form of thought
among others; although, as I also mentioned above, Laruelle
does suggest that non-philosophy has a specificity as a line—a
clinamen—that “touches” these other fictions.
In “Photo-Fiction, A Theoretical Installation” Laruelle is
concerned with building a new conceptual or theoretical apparatus
that would be capable of producing these strange photo-fictions
or models of the real. These are forms of thought (broadly
construed) that are less explanatory or interpretive of the world
as it is, and more speculative in character. Might we suggest,
then, that it is this experimental nature of photo-fictions that
characterizes them as a form of art practice?
As I intimated above, this strange kind of non-photographic
apparatus is also necessarily a phenomenologically reduced one:
it “pictures” what happens to experience when not tied to a self/
interpreter, or when such experience is not “processed” through
representation. We might also say the fictions that are produced
by it are somehow weaker (again, they are “undetermined”),
untethered as they are from a certain pretension. This is a more
modest form of thought, perhaps, but it is also one that has the
potential to expand the very idea—and working out—of what thought
is and might become (it is in this sense that Laruelle’s “non”
– 290 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
announces a turn from hermeneutics to something more heuristic).
The key for Laruelle in all this is photo-fiction’s break with
representation and mimesis and, with that, the production of a
certain kind of freedom (he writes, for example, of the jouissance
to be found at the end of “photo-centrism”).29 In themselves these
photo-fictions imply and, it seems to me, help produce a new kind of
subject (if we can still call it this), or what Laruelle calls (in
a nod to Kant’s notion of a non-empirical transcendental subject)
“Subject = X.”30 They also imply a new terrain (or, as I suggested
above, a new realm) to be “discovered”—or constructed—“beyond”
the “world” of philosophy/photography.31 Laruelle turns to quantum
mechanics here (and indeed in much of his recent writings),
where he finds the tools adequate and appropriate to this
experimental reorganization or reconstruction of the world (outside
representation). Such a “new” scientific theory does not involve
yet more binaries, but rather a “superpositioning” in which a third
state is produced by the addition (or “superposing”) of two previous
states. Superpositioning is a way of dealing with the paradox I
mentioned above of non-philosophy as both theory of thought and
just one mode of thinking itself—indeed, it is precisely quantum
science’s break with representational “accounts” of matter and the
universe that makes it so useful for non-philosophy. We might even
say that non-philosophy, in this sense, is quantum philosophy—and
that the Subject = X is the quantum-subject.
3. Non-Art Practice
I want now to develop some of the above in six different, more
specific “applications” of non-philosophy to art practice.32
– 291 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
In particular I want to test Laruelle’s method when it comes to
thinking through a non philosophical discipline with its own
logics and history, but also, more particularly, in relation to
an understanding of performance as its own kind of “non-art” (or
what David Burrows has called “performance fiction”).33
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
conceptual resources (given that the normal (philosophical) rules
are suspended).34 Philosophy (or non-philosophy) becomes a more
synthetic—and, again, speculative—practice in this sense (rather
than an analytic inquiry). More radically, this kind of practice
opens up the different space of and for thinking that I mentioned
above.
i. Diagrammatics
ii. Art as model
Diagrammatics might be a name for the practice of
recontextualization, reorganization, and general manipulation
of philosophical materials that have been untethered from their
properly philosophical function or discourse. I have already
laid out some of the aspects of this kind of practice above, but
in relation to art more explicitly we might note the possibility
that concepts be refigured diagrammatically. In a simple sense
they can be drawn, but more generally to diagram suggests a
different “imaging” or even performance of concepts. In fact,
art practice has always involved a take on philosophy (and theory
more broadly) that resonates with this—a “use” of philosophical
materials as material.
A key question here is what these philosophical materials “do”
when untethered in this way: what is their explanatory power
(if that still has a meaning here)? Or, to put this another way,
can this be anything different from the use of philosophy as
illustration, or “caption”? (Laruelle himself uses the latter
term when writing of philo-fictions.) What, we might ask, does
the treatment of philosophy in this way allow us to think?
One answer is that it might, for example, suggest surprising
and productive connections and conjunctions between different
– 292 –
Non-philosophy might also name the multiplicity of thinking—the
other kinds of thought—that subsists alongside the philosophical
and the conceptual more broadly. Indeed, there is the important
question, here, of the role of affect in art practice, and whether
this more pathic register might also be understood as a kind
of non-conceptual thinking—a different kind of non philosophy,
perhaps. Again, some of this terrain has been laid out above, but
in relation to art practice it seems to me that with this second
aspect we are moving into more productive territory. Indeed, art
practice has long been involved in non-conceptual explorations,
just as it has also involved its own particular take on conceptual
material (without the help of non-philosophy). A question
rephrased from one asked above might also be posed here: what does
non-philosophy in its democratizing aspect bring to art practice?
Certainly it brings philosophy (and aesthetics) down from its
throne, makes it more of a model among others; and, in the same
gesture, art’s own models are given a certain status beyond being
simple fiction (at least when this is opposed to truth). But
what does this modeling allow beyond such democratization? As I
mentioned above, very little is said about this area—the other
forms of thought besides philosophy—“within” non-philosophy
– 293 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
itself. Again, it seems to me that this is partly because a
certain deconstructive logic is at play: any form of thinking, as
thinking, is always already determined by the cut that produces
the world and the subject that thinks.35
“decision” (however that might manifest)? Insofar as art involves
representation (a “picturing of the world”) then the answer is
clearly yes (and the above comments on photography would have
relevance here—although work would need to be done to lay out
how this particular structure operates in art practice more
generally). But in this sense we might also say that modern art
has already been through its own “non” “revolution” with the move
from figuration to abstraction (Malevich and Pollock representing
the twin apotheoses of this tendency in Western painting).37
But perhaps we might rephrase this, and also put it in more
positive terms: non-philosophy cannot but use the stuff of the
world and thus must use it differently, untethering it from the
world (in the sense of a world determined by philosophy). In terms
of art one thinks of William Burroughs and his cut-ups, which
open up a different space-time. Indeed, narratives—the logical
sequencing of sentences (cause and effect), familiar syntax,
and so forth—which the cut-ups slice into and rearrange are key
determining factors of the world. Non-philosophy in this expanded
sense might then also be a form of non-narrative, or even a form
of non-fiction (in which the “non” names a widening of context to
include those formal experiments that go beyond simple narrative,
as well as a use of language beyond its representational
function). Such art will need to be “read,” or at least maintain
a minimum consistency of sense. Again, experiments in writing
non-narrative fictions (or, at least, in playing with narrative
schema) would be instructive here.36
iii. Non-art (and art history)
Another (and perhaps more appropriate) thinking through of
non-philosophy in relation to art would be an examination of
whether art performs its own auto-positioning and has its own
kind of principle that doubles the Principle of Sufficient
Philosophy: does art also involve a certain kind of invariant
– 294 –
In fact, with the further move beyond abstraction to objecthood
we have practices that, in their relationship to representation,
“mirror” the relation between non-philosophy and philosophy.
Certainly Minimalism, for example, was involved in something
else “beyond” representation, in that it was the production
of objects, assemblages, and so forth that were not “about”
the real, but part of it (and in writers such as Donald Judd
and Robert Smithson we have a clear articulation of this
logic—the radical break their practices announce—as well
as an indication of the importance of fiction, as a mode of
writing, in articulating it).38 We need only add that this shift
in perspective also necessarily changes the perspective on
previous art, such that it is then seen as representation but
also as itself object (what else could it be?). We might also
note Marcel Duchamp’s idea of the “reciprocal readymade,” which
involves using (representational) art as material for everyday
objects.39 Contemporary practices that refer back to—or reuse—
art, untethered from its previous representational functioning,
would also be important here (what is sometimes called “secondorder practice”), but so would those practices that, for example,
repeat or restage previous performances. It is also in this
– 295 –
ALMOST EVERY
MODERN MOVEMENT
INVOLVED THIS
DISAVOWAL OF
A PREVIOUS
DEFINITION—
THE PERFORMANCE
OF A FORCEFUL
“NO” ECHOING
THROUGHOUT TIME
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
sense that, today, abstract art is itself figural (it involves
the referencing of previous abstractions). There is a similar
structure to non-philosophy’s use of philosophy in these kinds of
practice, but we might also note that there is equally a similar
limit, insofar as such practices involve a nesting of art within
art (ad infinitum). I will return to this.
We might also gesture here to the history of the avant-garde more
generally and their refusal of previous categories of art. Almost
every modern movement involved this disavowal of a previous
definition—the performance of a forceful “No” echoing throughout
time (and manifestos embody this recurring motif, perhaps most
explicitly foregrounded in Dada, which further involved a refusal
of “good sense”). There was also, with the avant-gardes, a
concomitant drive to bring art into life. Indeed, in terms of nonart, a recurring feature of the avant-garde is the incorporation
of non-artistic material in order to disrupt representation.
From the readymade to Arte Povera to the happening, art has also
been—at least in its initial impulse—non-art. Here it is surely
Duchamp who best exemplifies the refusal of representation, just
as it is Allan Kaprow who gestures to the very limits of the frame
(and who does most to collapse or “blur” the art/life boundary).
All this amounts to saying that from one perspective art history
gives us an account of how art has always been thought in relation
to something outside itself.
There is a lot more to be said about this relationship between
art and non-art, especially in relation to Laruelle’s own ideas
about how an anti-philosophy (as opposed to non-philosophy)
invariably sets up an “outside” that then gets incorporated in
a renewed “definition” (hence my interest in the reciprocal
– 297 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
readymade, which does not look “outside” art (it is not an antiart) but uses art as its material). There is also the issue of
art practice traversing this edge, often moving toward non-art
status, only to hold back at the last moment, as it were, in
order to maintain an artistic status (again, it seems to me that
a certain deconstructive logic is at play with these practices
that oscillate between art and non-art). A question here might
be, then, what does an understanding of non-art (in Laruelle’s
sense) bring to the table given this particular history of modern
art? One answer might be that it allows a radical rethinking of
the whole question of the avant-garde and of the art/non-art
dialectic. To recall: Laruelle’s non-philosophy does not posit an
outside; indeed, it is not an avant-garde position in this sense.
Perhaps if we follow Laruelle, then, we are not so much exploring
a territory beyond accepted definitions, but reconfiguring the
very terrain of art and life (in terms of superpositioning). Once
again it would seem that non-philosophy (and non-art) has this
double face: on the one hand it allows a certain practice outside
the laws and logics of the discipline it seeks to undermine (it
is, as Laruelle calls it, “heretical”), but on the other it cannot
but be caught by these very forms (insofar as it must work within
and with them).40
as it were, a structuring invariant, whatever a given practice
might claim. Such is the strategy of Suhail Malik, who calls
for an “exit” from a Contemporary Art that is the handmaiden of
contemporary neoliberalism.41 Here the very “openness” of the
work of art is seen as profoundly ideological. In relation to this
recent critique of contemporary art, we might also note that there
has long been a “tradition” of radical (or “social”) art history
as a form of ideology critique that is intent on demystifying the
aesthetic and ideological functioning of art, and especially of
“Art History,” by giving a properly historical account of art
objects—might we even call this a kind of non-Art History (the
capitals denoting a certain disciplinary self-sufficiency)?
To return to some of my earlier comments about Althusser and
ideology, another take on the conjunction of non-philosophy
and art might be that non-philosophy can help to diagnose and
critique “Contemporary Art” as a whole. It might help to identify
a particular logic at work—for example, indeterminacy—that is,
But, to return to Malik, this is also a complex matter insofar
as we might say that contemporary art (note: no capitals)
is a practice that has itself been untethered from a certain
programmatic account (namely, modernism). Contemporary art is
already characterized by a radical democratization: this, for
example, would be Jean-François Lyotard’s take (on “art in the
age of postmodernity”), or indeed Rosalind Krauss’s (on our
“post-medium condition”).42 From this perspective it would be
Malik who is reinstating a certain program—we might even say
decision—about what art should do. Of course, it is always
possible to position the other’s point of view as the ideological
one (witness the Adorno/Lukács debates around autonomy versus
realism43), but it does seem to me that positioning art as
ideology critique—or as simply critical—and at the same time
dismissing practices that are not committed to this critique,
cannot but limit our understanding of art and indeed of its
terrain of operation (rather than, for example, opening it up to
further adventures).
– 298 –
– 299 –
iv. Ideology critique
– FICTION AS METHOD –
Nevertheless, a key question arising from this particular
perspective is whether there is indeed a non-art practice that
utilizes art as its material, but untethers it from its dominant
logics (whatever these might be); and, if so, whether this is
something different to what art already does. It seems clear,
here, that it is the definition of art that determines its “non”
(and, as such, if the dominant logics are indeed indeterminacy,
or perhaps representation, then this will define non-art as nonrepresentation and determinate). A further question is whether
art—or non-art—can itself escape these interminable circuits of
definition and redefinition. Can it offer a different kind of
knowledge “outside” art as it is typically understood?44
v. Performance ictions
Leading on from the above, and changing perspective a little,
there is also the compelling gnostic “account” that nonphilosophy gives of the real that I mentioned at the beginning of
this essay. At the end of the conference on “Fiction as Method”
(the progenitor of this book), Tim Etchells performed a “re-mix”
of the previous speaker, M. John Harrison, and his compelling
reading of one of his own short stories.45 Both presentations—
one a piece of fiction, the other a performance—were somewhat
different to the previous papers. Indeed, if the latter had
generally been about fiction as method (albeit involving creative
as well as critical approaches and interventions), here, in both
of these last contributions to the conference, we were presented
with fiction as method itself. With both it was as if the whole
conference assemblage had somehow tipped—and phase-shifted—from
being “about” the real to being “of” (or alongside) it.
– 300 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
For me this experience resonates with the radical immanence of
non-philosophy. Indeed, as I also mentioned above, there is
something surprising—and yet at the same time obvious—about
Laruelle’s idea of a form of thought that is from the real
rather than yet another interpretation of it. As I hope I have
made clear, art practice is often involved in this other kind
of presentation. The conference, however, made the difference
between the two perspectives—or gestures—suddenly very apparent.
Indeed, performance in general has this quality of producing
difference through a cut. It is non-representation par excellence
insofar as in its very liveness it offers an “experience” of life
“outside” representation.46 However, there is also the question
here as to whether at least some kind of minimal framing is
required to make it art, or else it becomes “just life” (this,
again, is the edge that Kaprow traverses). In fact, it seems to
me that a life might well need some framing—a performance, as it
were—in order for it be taken out of the frame within which it is
usually experienced/perceived (what Laruelle calls the world).
Counter-intuitively, art practice, as performance, can be more
real than life because it is framed (at least minimally).
The models and fictions referred to earlier in this essay
demonstrate ways of sidestepping more typical, often unseeable,
frames of reference. They offer one set of approaches to enabling
ourselves to think of art practice as the production of fictions
that allow—almost as a side effect—for a glimpse of the real
(or, to refer again to the conference, it is the very difference
between the two fictional worlds—our typical world and the world
an art practice can present—that allows for a small part of the
real to leak through). Again, unless a fiction is produced, the
– 301 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
danger is that a practice merely presents a piece of the world as
it surrounds us on an everyday basis, without any difference (as
is the case with art practices that simply archive what exists
without transforming it). It is, then, through the performance
of a fiction that art can foreground the always already fictional
status of a world it is different from.
vi. The iction of a self
Performance art aside, it seems to me that non-philosophy is
also at its most interesting and compelling when it is thought
in relation to a life that is lived differently, or in relation
to Michel Foucault’s suggestion (though for different reasons)
that “everyone’s life become a work of art.”47 This is to “apply”
non-philosophy to expanded practices beyond the gallery, but also
to think about aesthetic practices, in more general terms, in
relation to what Guattari called the production of subjectivity
(and to the expanded ethico-aesthetic paradigm that is implied by
this).
Indeed, as I have gestured toward above, we might want to ask
whether the very structure of typical subjectivity—and of a
“self”—is not itself the product of a certain philosophical
decision (broadly construed), one that is lived on a day-to-day
basis.48 A non-philosophical take on subjectivity will involve a
diagnosis of such a positioning (again, typical subjectivity),
but, for me, more interesting is that it might point to the
possibility of being in the world without a fixed sense of a
typical self (with all the attendant issues this unfixity can
bring). Laruelle seems to be suggesting something similar in
– 302 –
– NON-PHILOSOPHY AND ART PRACTICE –
his “A New Presentation of Non-Philosophy,” not least when he
suggests that non-philosophy might be the only “chance for an
effective utopia.”49
This effective utopia would mean living life away from those
forms that have caught and restrict it: it is to refuse
philosophy, especially in its key operation of producing the
fiction of a (separate) self—or, rather, its positing of the
latter as not a fiction but as a truth (the self as product
of a certain decision that is then occluded, hidden from that
subject). Non-philosophy might then be about untethering the
self from its auto-positioning, its own enthronement (and as
such it has something very specific to offer recent accounts and
critiques of the “Anthropocene”).
In fact, it seems that what follows from this insight is not
the “dissolving” of the self, but, we might say, a holding of it
in a lighter, more contingent manner—as, precisely, a fiction
(and, insofar as the self is the anchor point for numerous other
fictions—the different worlds through which a self moves—then
these too are seen as fictions). Crucially, this might also
mean the possibility of producing other fictions of the self
(or other fictions of non-self), and with that the exploration
of other ways of being in the world.50 Although there is not the
space here to go into Laruelle’s own writings on this other kind
of subject, we might note his concept of the “generic human,”
or “stranger,” which he describes as a “radical ordinariness”
that is nevertheless at odds with the world (and which we always
already are, over and above any “assumed” subjectivity).51
A compelling final question—which I have gestured towards
– 303 –
– FICTION AS METHOD –
throughout my essay—is what this terrain “outside” the self might
be like and if, indeed, it can be explored. Mackay writes well on
this discovery of the generic “beneath” the subject produced by
philosophy and how we might begin to experience and experiment
with it (for it is not a given, but, to echo Deleuze and Guattari,
needs to be constructed, piece by piece).52 It is perhaps with
this grand vision of the work of non-philosophy that we begin to
see the more profound connections with, and radical implications
for, what might be call a non-art practice. This, then, is
the experimental exploration—but also the construction and
performance—of new worlds and new kinds of non-subjects adequate
and appropriate to them. Or, more simply: fiction as method.
Bibliography
Adorno, Theodor, Walter Benjamin,
Ernst Bloch, Bertolt Brecht, and
Georg Lukàcs. Aesthetics and
Politics. Translated by Ronald
Taylor. London: NLB, 1977.
Beech, Amanda. “Art and Its
‘Science’.” In Speculative Aesthetics.
Edited by Robin Mackay, Luke
Pendrell, and James Traford.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2014.
Brassier, Ray. “Axiomatic Heresy:
The Non-Philosophy of François
Laruelle.” Radical Philosophy, no.
121 (September/October 2003):
24–35.
–––. Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment
and Extinction. Basingstoke:
Palgrave, 2007.
–––. “The View from Nowhere.”
Identities: Journal of Politics,
Gender and Culture 8, no. 2
(Summer 2011): 7–23.
Burrows, David. “Performance
Fictions.” In Performance Fictions.
Edited by David Burrows, 47–70.
Birmingham: Article Press, 2010.
Burrows, David, and Simon
O’Sullivan. Mythopoesis–MythScience–Mythotechnesis:
Fictioning in Contemporary Art.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, forthcoming.
Deleuze, Gilles. Diference and
Repetition. Translated by Paul
Patton. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1994.
– 304 –
– 305 –
–––. “Immanence: A Life.” In Pure
Immanence: Essays on A Life.
Translated by Anne Boyman,
25–33. New York: Zone Books,
2011.
–––, and Félix Guattari. AntiOedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Translated by
Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and
Helen R. Lane. London: Athlone
Press, 1984.
–––. What Is Philosophy?
Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and
Graham Burchell. London: Verso,
1994.
Foucault, Michel. “On the
Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview
of Work in Progress.” In Ethics:
Subjectivity and Truth. Essential
Works of Foucault, 1954–1984.
Edited by Paul Rabinow. Translated
by Robert Hurley, 253–80. London:
Penguin, 2000.
Judd, Donald. “Speciic Objects.”
In Art in Theory, 1900–1990.
Edited by Charles Harrison and
Paul Wood, 809–13. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1992.
Krauss, Rosalind. A Voyage on the
North Sea: Art in the Age of the
Post-Medium Condition. London:
Thames and Hudson, 1999.
Laruelle, François. “Fragments of
an Anti-Guattari.” Linguistic Capital.
Translated by Charles Wolfe.
Accessed January 7, 2017. https://
linguisticcapital.iles.wordpress.
com/2013/03/laruelle_fragmentsof-an-anti-guattari.pdf.
–––. From Decision to Heresy:
Experiments in Non-Standard
Thought. Translated by Robin
Mackay. Falmouth: Urbanomic,
2012.
–––. “‘I, the Philosopher, am Lying’:
A Reply to Deleuze.” Translated
by Taylor Adkins, Ray Brassier,
and Sid Littleield. In The NonPhilosophy Project: Essays by
François Laruelle. Edited by
Gabriel Alkon and Boris Gunjevic,
40–74. New York: Telos, 2012.
–––. “A New Presentation of
Non-Philosophy.” Organisation
Non-Philosophique Internationale.
Accessed August 23, 2017. http://
www.onphi.net/corpus/32/a-newpresentation-of-non-philosophy.
–––. “Photo-Fiction, A Theoretical
Installation.” In Photo-Fiction:
A Non-Standard Aesthetics.
Translated by Drew S. Burk, 11–24.
Minneapolis, MN: Univocal, 2012.
–––. “What Is Seen in a Photo?” In
The Concept of Non-Photography.
Translated by Robin Mackay, 1–28.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2011.
Lyotard, Jean-François.
“Philosophy and Painting in the
Age of Their Experimentation:
Contribution to an Idea of
Postmodernity”. Translated by
Mária Minich Brewer and Daniel
Brewer. In The Lyotard Reader.
Edited by Andrew Benjamin,
181–195. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1989.
– 306 –
Mackay, Robin. “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided.” In From
Decision to Heresy: Experiments in
Non-Standard Thought. Translated
by Robin Mackay, 1–32. Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2012.
O’Sullivan, Simon. “From Science
Fiction to Science Fictioning: SF’s
Traction on the Real.” Foundation:
The International Review of
Science Fiction 46.1 No. 126 (2017):
74–84.
–––. “Strata: A Geophotographic
Fiction.” In Robert Smithson: The
Collected Writings. Edited by
Jack Flam, 75–77. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press,
1996.
Malik, Suhail. On the Necessity of
Art’s Exit from Contemporary Art.
Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2017.
–––, “Memories of a Deleuzian:
To Think Is Always to Follow the
Witches Flight.” In A Thousand
Plateaus and Philosophy. Edited
by Henry Somers-Hall, Jef Bell,
and James Williams, 172–88.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, 2018.
Srnicek, Nick. “Capitalism and the
Non-Philosophical Subject.” In
The Speculative Turn: Continental
Materialism and Realism. Edited
by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek,
and Graham Harman, 164–81.
Melbourne: re.press, 2011.
McGettigan, Andrew. “Fabrication
Defect: François Laruelle’s
Philosophical Materials.” Radical
Philosophy, no. 175 (September/
October 2012): 33–42.
Metzinger, Thomas. The Ego
Tunnel: The Science of the Mind
and the Myth of the Self. New York:
Basic Books, 2009.
Nauha, Tero. Schizoproduction:
Artistic Research and Performance
in the Context of Immanent
Capitalism. Helsinki: University of
the Arts, 2016.
Ó Maoilearca, John. All Thoughts
are Equal: Laruelle and Nonhuman
Philosophy. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 2015.
–––, John, and Anthony Paul
Smith. “Introduction: The NonPhilosophical Inversion: Laruelle’s
Knowledge Without Domination.”
In Laruelle and Non-Philosophy.
Edited by John Ó Maoilearca
and Anthony Paul Smith, 1–18.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, 2012.
–––. On the Production of
Subjectivity: Five Diagrams
of the Finite–Ininite Relation.
Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2012.
Paul Smith, Anthony. François
Laruelle’s “Principles of NonPhilosophy”: A Critical Introduction
and Guide. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2016.
Schmid, Anne-Françoise. “The
Madonna on the Craters of the
Moon: An Aesthetic Epistemology.”
Accessed January 7, 2017. https://
www.urbanomic.com/document/
the-madonna-on-the-cratersof-the-moon-an-aestheticepistemology.
Smithson, Robert. “Entropy and
the New Monuments (1966).” In
Robert Smithson: The Collected
Writings. Edited by Jack Flam,
10–23. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press, 1996.
– 307 –
Tilford, Keith. “Laruelle, Art
and the Scientiic Model.”
Accessed January 7, 2017. http://
keithtilford.com/wp-content/
uploads/2015/05/Tilford_Keith.pdf.
1
The following account is
heavily indebted to a number
of other introductions to
Laruelle’s thought, including:
Ray Brassier, “Axiomatic
Heresy: The Non-Philosophy
of François Laruelle,”
Radical Philosophy, no. 121
(September/October 2003):
24–35; Ray Brassier, Nihil
Unbound: Enlightenment
and Extinction (Basingstoke:
Palgrave, 2007); Robin
Mackay, “Introduction: Laruelle
Undivided,” in François
Laruelle, From Decision
to Heresy: Experiments in
Non-Standard Thought, trans.
Robin Mackay (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2012), 1–32; John
Ó Maoilearca and Anthony
Paul Smith, “Introduction: The
Non-Philosophical Inversion:
Laruelle’s Knowledge Without
Domination,” in Laruelle and
Non-Philosophy, ed. John Ó
Maoilearca and Anthony Paul
Smith (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2012),
1–18; John Ó Maoilearca, All
Thoughts are Equal: Laruelle
and Nonhuman Philosophy
(Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press, 2015);
and Anthony Paul Smith,
François Laruelle’s “Principles
of Non-Philosophy”: A
Critical Introduction and
Guide (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
– 308 –
They are the great destroyers
of the forces of philosophy
and the state, which band
together in the name of
order and conformity. The
spiritual haunt the margins
of philosophy, gnosticism,
mysticism, and even of
institutional religion and
politics.” François Laruelle,
“A New Presentation of NonPhilosophy,” Organisation
Non-Philosophique
Internationale, accessed
August 23, 2017, http://www.
onphi.net/corpus/32/anew-presentation-of-nonphilosophy.
University Press, 2016). These
and other secondary texts are
referenced throughout (often
in endnotes), but I also want to
be clear at the outset that my
understanding of Laruelle, and
in particular the laying out of
the tenets of non-philosophy
in section 1 of my essay, is
based on these rather than
any exhaustive reading of
Laruelle’s own books (and
as such constitutes only an
initial foray into what, for me,
is new territory). Any errors in
understanding are, of course,
my own.
Endnotes
2
3
4
5
Ó Maoilearca, All Thoughts
are Equal, 1.
6
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
25.
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
26.
7
Ibid.
8
See especially Gilles Deleuze
and Félix Guattari, AntiOedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, trans. Robert
Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen
R. Lane (London: Athlone
Press, 1984), 16–22.
9
Laruelle, “A New
Presentation.”
10
Andrew McGettigan,
“Fabrication Defect: François
Laruelle’s Philosophical
Materials,” Radical Philosophy,
no. 175 (September/October
2012): 33–42; Ray Brassier,
“Axiomatic Heresy.”
Although I have used a
lowercase “r” here and
throughout, Laruelle invariably
has Lacan’s sense of the
Real in mind—as that which
is “outside” the symbolic
register and which indeed is
resistant to it (although, as
we shall see, Laruelle makes
his own modiications to this
topology).
As Laruelle remarks in
relation to the “character” of
non-philosophers: “they are
also related to what I would
call the “spiritual” type—
which it is imperative not to
confuse with “spiritualist.” The
spiritual are not spiritualists.
– 309 –
11
As, for example, Laruelle
will argue, in Deleuze’s
philosophy (see for example
François Laruelle, “‘I, the
Philosopher, Am Lying’: A
Reply to Deleuze,” trans.
Taylor Adkins, Ray Brassier,
and Sid Littleield, in The
Non-Philosophy Project:
Essays by François Laruelle,
ed. Gabriel Alkon and Boris
Gunjevic (New York: Telos,
2012), 40–74. Is this claim,
however, entirely correct? In
his last essay, “Immanence:
A Life,” Deleuze is very
careful to distinguish his
concept of immanence from
one that is immanent “to”
something (which would
necessarily involve a form
of transcendence): Gilles
Deleuze, “Immanence: A Life,”
in Pure Immanence: Essays
on A Life, trans. Anne Boyman
(New York: Zone Books, 2011),
25–34. Deleuze does attend,
however, to how a “point of
view” on this immanence
cannot but involve a certain
kind of abstraction and
“folding back,” but it is not
entirely clear, at least to this
reader, whether this can
be understood as simply
a decisional structure in
Laruelle’s terms. A more
detailed comparison on
this point will need to wait
for another time, but we
might note here Deleuze’s
own sympathy (albeit with
reservations) with Laruelle’s
non-philosophical project, as
evidenced by the footnote
to the latter at the very end
of What is Philosophy?
(Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari, What is Philosophy?
trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Graham Burchell (London:
Verso, 1994), 234 n.16). For
my own take on Deleuze
(and Guattari) as a form of
non philosophy see Simon
O’Sullivan, “Memories of a
Deleuzian: To Think Is Always
to Follow the Witches Flight,”
in A Thousand Plateaus
and Philosophy, ed. Henry
Somers-Hall, Jef Bell, and
James Williams (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press,
2018), 172–88.
12
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided,” 2.
13
Smith, François Laruelle’s
“Principles,” 26. Indeed, Smith
is especially attuned to the
arrogance of Philosophy—
and, not least, its connection
to a “wider” European
colonial attitude (hence the
importance of non-philosophy
in the decolonization of
thinking). In his Francois
Laruelle’s “Principles of
Non-Philosophy”: A Critical
Introduction and Guide he
is also keen to maintain
and defend the category
of the human (albeit that
this is not the human of a
straightforward humanism,
but of a more generic
– 310 –
“force-of-thought”) against
those other readers of
Laruelle—Smith has Brassier
especially in mind—who
are intent on dismantling
the latter or hastening its
demise. Might we say then
that Smith attends to the
ongoing importance of
phenomenology (especially
Martin Heidegger and
Michel Henry) for Laruelle’s
non-philosophy (though in
a “reduced” form), whereas
Brassier is interested
(see note 15 below) in a
reading that efectively
rids non-philosophy of
any phenomenological
residue (hence the focus
on abstraction). These two
positions revolve around
diferent attitudes to
alienation and reason. For
Brassier, alienation enables
freedom via the constructs
of reason (hence the
Promethean character of
his writing); for Smith nonphilosophy promises a kind
of overcoming of alienation
(and a limiting of reason) for
a human that is always more
than simply a rational animal.
14
See, for example, Deleuze
and Guattari’s discussion of
the rhizome in A Thousand
Plateaus, and in particular
the third “Principle of
Multiplicity”: “The point is that
a rhizome never allows itself
to be overcoded, never has
available a supplementary
dimension […]. All multiplicities
are lat in the sense that
they ill or occupy all of
their dimensions.” Deleuze
and Guattari, A Thousand
Plateaus, 9.
15
In Nihil Unbound Brassier
suggests that the
philosophical operation
that Laruelle lays out as a
universal invariant decision—
which Brassier describes
a “quasi-spontaneous
philosophical compulsion”
(Nihil Unbound, 119)—
is, rather, the hallmark
of a particular kind of
philosophy that inds its
terminus in Heidegger and
deconstruction. Indeed,
for Brassier it is only by
understanding Laruelle in this
way—as ofering something
to philosophy (basically the
suspension of the decisional
mechanism that in itself
might allow for a diferent
kind of thinking)—that
the radical implications of
Laruelle’s thought can be
laid out. Brassier argues
that this must also involve
the extraction from out
of Laruelle’s own account
of non-philosophy (and
especially of the human
as locus of the real) of a
“de-phenomenologized
conception of the real as
‘being-nothing’” (ibid., 118);
hence the title of Brassier’s
book.
– 311 –
16
McGettigan, “Fabrication
Defect.”
17
As Ó Maoilearca remarks
at the beginning of his
book: “Non-philosophy is a
conception of philosophy
(and all forms of thought)
that allows us to see them
as equivalent according
to a broader explanatory
paradigm. It enlarges the
set of things that can count
as thoughtful, a set that
includes existing philosophy
but also a whole host of
what is presently deemed
(by standard philosophy) to
be non-philosophical (art,
technology, natural science).”
Ó Maoilearca, All Thoughts
are Equal, 9.
18
Brassier, “Axiomatic Heresy,”
27.
19
Again, we might note
the connections with
deconstruction as a
particular kind of practice
here; a diagnosis of Western
metaphysics, but also—more
elusively, perhaps—a gesture
to forms of thinking that are
irreducible to this.
20
On this point see Keith
Tilford’s unpublished essay
on the implications of nonphilosophy for art: Keith
Tilford, “Laruelle, Art, and the
Scientiic Model,” accessed
January 7, 2017, http://
keithtilford.com/wp-content/
uploads/2015/05/Tilford_
Keith.pdf. Tilford makes
an especially compelling
distinction (though not
one I use in my own essay)
between “theories” (based on
decision) and “models” (which
are, precisely, revisable).
21
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided,” 8.
22
See for example the texts
gathered together in
“Appendix I” at the end of
Laruelle, From Decision to
Heresy, 353–408.
23
24
25
As in Guattari’s
metamodelization of Lacanian
concepts. For Laruelle’s
own non-philosophical
response to Guattari and
schizoanalysis (and, not
least, the collaboration
with Deleuze) see François
Laruelle, “Fragments of an
Anti-Guattari,” Linguistic
Capital, accessed 7 January
2017, trans. Charles Wolfe,
https://linguisticcapital.iles.
wordpress.com/2013/03/
laruelle_fragments-of-an-antiguattari.pdf.
François Laruelle, “What Is
Seen in a Photo?” in The
Concept of Non-Photography,
trans. Robin Mackay
(Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2011),
1–28.
François Laruelle, “PhotoFiction, A Theoretical
Installation,” in Photo-Fiction:
A Non-Standard Aesthetics,
– 312 –
trans. Drew S. Burk
(Minneapolis, MN: Univocal,
2012), 11–24.
26
Ibid., 16.
27
Ibid., 14.
28
Ibid., 16.
29
Ibid., 18–19.
January 7, 2017, https://www.
urbanomic.com/document/
the-madonna-on-the-cratersof-the-moon-an-aestheticepistemology. For Schmid
there is no “birds-eye view” on
this terrain, and, as such, no
one model (of either science
or art), but rather a diversity
of models in superposition.
For Schmid this also implies
a new understanding of the
object, which is no longer
given as such but must be
invented (might we even say
ictioned?). Schmid gives this
expanded practice the name
“integrative object,” involving
as it does a kind of synthesis
of heterogeneity, one that
proceeds “piece by piece.”
30 Ibid., 15–17.
31
Ibid., 15.
32
I am aware that this idea
of an “application” is highly
problematic in relation to nonphilosophy; my comments
below attempt to address this
particular limitation. I would
also point the interested
reader to the writings of
Anne-Françoise Schmid, who
develops a more sustained
inquiry into the implications
of non-philosophy for art
history and practice. In her
article “The Madonna on
the Craters of the Moon:
An Aesthetic Epistemology”
Schmid follows Laruelle in
making a case for a generic
epistemology and, indeed, a
generic aesthetics that might
operate as an “intermediary”
between science and art, but
also between diferent art
practices (or even between
diferent elements within a
practice): Anne-Françoise
Schmid, “The Madonna on
the Craters of the Moon: An
Aesthetic Epistemology,”
Urbanomic, accessed
33
34
35
David Burrows, “Performance
Fictions,” in Performance
Fictions, ed. David Burrows
(Birmingham: Article Press,
2010), 47–70.
My own book On the
Production of Subjectivity
includes examples of this kind
of diagrammatic treatment of
conceptual material. Simon
O’Sullivan, On the Production
of Subjectivity: Five Diagrams
of the Finite–Ininite Relation
(Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2012).
Nick Srnicek suggests
something similar in his
own take on a politics (and
a certain aporia) that leads
from non-philosophy: any
form of typical intervention
in the world cannot but be
– 313 –
determined by that world (or,
again, takes place within the
horizon of decision): Nick
Srnicek, “Capitalism and the
Non-Philosophical Subject,”
in The Speculative Turn:
Continental Materialism and
Realism, ed. Levi Bryant, Nick
Srnicek, and Graham Harman
(Melbourne: re.press, 2011),
164–81. Non-philosophy can
in this sense open a view from
elsewhere (or, for Srnicek, it
can open up a kind of noncapitalist space), but it cannot
ofer any content (Brassier’s
reading of Laruelle’s method
puts this necessary abstract
character and formal
inventiveness in more positive
terms as the very work of
non-philosophy: Brassier,
“Axiomatic Heresy”).
36
In relation to this—and to
an idea of “ictioning”—see
my essay “From Science
Fiction to Science Fictioning:
SF’s Traction on the Real,”
Foundation: The International
Review of Science Fiction
46.1, No. 126 (2017): 4–84.
We might also note once
again Laruelle’s own writing
experiments here.
37
In relation to this it is worth
noting Deleuze’s compelling
observation (in the chapter
on “The Image of Thought”
in Diference and Repetition)
that philosophy needs to go
through a similar revolution
to modern art. Gilles Deleuze,
Diference and Repetition,
trans. Paul Patton (New York:
Columbia University Press,
1994), 129–67.
38
39
In relation to the irst of these,
see, for example, Donald
Judd, “Speciic Objects,” in
Art in Theory, 1900–1990,
ed. Charles Harrison and
Paul Wood (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1992), 809–13; and
Robert Smithson, “Entropy
and the New Monuments,”
in Robert Smithson: The
Collected Writings, ed. Jack
Flam (Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press, 1996),
10–23. In relation to the
second, see Robert Smithson,
“Strata: A Geophotographic
Fiction,” in Robert Smithson:
The Collected Writings, ed.
Jack Flam (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press,
1996), 75–77.
My thanks to Nadja MillnerLarsen for alerting me to
the logic of the reciprocal
readymade.
40 See for example François
Laruelle, “Non-Philosophy
as Heresy,” in Laruelle, From
Decision to Heresy, 257–84.
41
42
Suhail Malik, On the
Necessity of Art’s Exit from
Contemporary Art (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2017).
See Jean-François
Lyotard, “Philosophy and
Painting in the Age of Their
– 314 –
Experimentation: Contribution
to an Idea of Postmodernity,”
trans. Mária Minich Brewer
and Daniel Brewer, in The
Lyotard Reader, ed. Andrew
Benjamin (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1989), 181–95; and
Rosalind Krauss, A Voyage
on the North Sea: Art in the
Age of the Post-Medium
Condition (London: Thames
and Hudson, 1999).
43
Theodor Adorno et al.,
Aesthetics and Politics, trans.
Ronald Taylor (London: NLB,
1977).
44
This is the question that
Amanda Beech asks in her
own take on Laruelle and on
what she sees as problems
with an art practice invested
in freedom, immediacy,
diference, contingency,
and so forth. For Beech,
besides this critique of
typical operating procedures
and logics of contemporary
art, at stake is the outlining
of a diferent practice—or
Science—of the image,
one that embraces its
representational/mediatory
character in its own kind of
“critical-political project”; or,
in the terms of Laruelle’s own
“non-diferential space of
the generic matrix”: “What is
the distinction between the
paradigm of art as we know
it, and another category of art
that we could imagine in this
new coniguration?” Amanda
Beech “Art and Its ‘Science’,”
in Speculative Aesthetics, ed.
Robin Mackay, Luke Pendrell,
and James Traford (Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2014), 15.
45
Fiction as Method conference,
Goldsmiths, University of
London, October 17, 2015.
46
Performance, as Tero Nauha
has articulated, can be a
practice that is alongside the
real and as such might be
thought of as an “advent” (as
opposed to an event that gets
“recaptured” by philosophy).
Nauha also makes a
convincing case, following
Laruelle, for performance
as a heretical practice
(pitched against the “law”
of representation): see Tero
Nauha, Schizoproduction:
Artistic Research and
Performance in the Context
of Immanent Capitalism
(Helsinki: University of the
Arts, 2016).
47
Michel Foucault, “On the
Genealogy of Ethics:
An Overview of Work
in Progress,” in Ethics:
Subjectivity and Truth.
Essential Works of Foucault,
1954–1984, ed. Paul Rabinow,
trans. Robert Hurley (London:
Penguin, 2000), 261.
48
Smith writes well on how a
certain decisional structure
produces the philosophical
subject (as separate from
an object—the real—that it
– 315 –
cannot know except through
itself) and how the nonphilosophical subject—as
“force-of-thought”—might
be understood, instead, as
always already a part of,
or a clone of, the real (see
Smith, François Laruelle’s
“Principles,” 45–61).
49
To continue the quote
from note 5, above: “nonphilosophy is also related
to Gnosticism and scienceiction; it answers their
fundamental question—which
is not at all philosophy’s
primary concern—“Should
humanity be saved? And
how?” And it is also close
to spiritual revolutionaries
such as Müntzer and certain
mystics who skirted heresy.
When all is said and done,
is non-philosophy anything
other than the chance for an
efective utopia?” Laruelle, “A
New Presentation.”
50
David Burrows and I attend
more fully to this in our
forthcoming book: David
Burrows and Simon O’Sullivan,
Mythopoesis–Myth-Science–
Mythotechnesis: Fictioning in
Contemporary Art (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press,
forthcoming).
51
One of the other key
thinkers in relation to this
area is the neuroscientist
and philosopher Thomas
Metzinger and his thesis of
the “ego tunnel” as productive
of what he calls the “myth”
of the self. See Thomas
Metzinger, The Ego Tunnel:
The Science of the Mind and
the Myth of the Self (New
York: Basic Books, 2009).
We might also turn again to
Brassier’s recent writings on a
certain kind of “nemocentric”
subject that is “produced”
through neuroscientiic
understandings of our place
in the world. In both of these
cases it is a question of
exploring a kind of nonsubject whose processes of
re-presenting the world (or
modeling) are opaque rather
than transparent (and thus
open to examination). Ray
Brassier, “The View from
Nowhere,” Identities: Journal
of Politics, Gender and Culture
8, no. 2 (Summer 2001): 7–23.
52
Mackay, “Introduction:
Laruelle Undivided.”
BEYOND
PLATO’S
CAVE:
ESCAPING
FROM THE
CITIES
OF THE
INTERIORITY
Justin Barton
– 316 –
1
This is an un-copy edited article to be published in Jon K. Shaw and Theo Reeves-Evisson
(eds.) Fiction as Method, Berlin: Sternberg, 2017.
Non-Philosophy and Art Practice (or, Fiction as Method)
Simon O’Sullivan, Goldsmiths College, London
In the following article I want to introduce François Laruelle’s non-philosophy – or
what is now also called non-standard philosophy – with a particular eye to its
relevance (if any) for art practice, when this latter term is very broadly construed.1
Although at times the following involves more questions than answers (and, indeed,
proceeds through its own circuits and over laps), at stake is the mapping out of a
speculative and synthetic practice of thought, which might also be described as the
deployment of fiction as method. In terms of the former coupling, my essay is
concerned, in part, with those modes of thinking – art included – that occur away
from the legislative and, indeed, more standard frameworks. A practice of thinking
that involves encounters and compatibilities and, ultimately, experimentation with a
terrain beyond typical ideas of self and world. In terms of fiction I am especially
interested in how the performance of the latter can operate to show us the edges of our
own reality – and also in the diagram as itself a form of speculative fictioning.
1. Definitions and Diagrams
In his work on non-philosophy (comprising of over 25 books to date and periodised
into 5 distinct phases of development) Laruelle claims to have identified and
demarcated a certain autocratic (and arrogant) functioning of philosophy; how it tends
both to position itself as the highest form of thought (enthroned above all other
disciplines), whilst at the same time necessarily attempting to explain everything
within its purview. Indeed, each subsequent philosophy must offer up its own
exhaustive account of the real, ‘trumping’ any previous philosophy in an endless
game of one-upmanship. John Ó Maoilearca puts this particular pretension more
strongly, suggesting that philosophy itself is a form of ‘thought control’ that attempts
to define the very act of thinking through its particular transcendent operations (more
on these below) (Ó Maoilearca 2015: 1).
1
The following account is heavily indebted to a number of other Introductions to Laruelle’s
thought, including those by Ray Brassier (2003 and 2007), Robin Mackay (2011), John Ó
Maoilearca and Anthony Paul-Smith (2012), John Ó Maoilearca (2015) and Anthony Paul
Smith (2016). These and other secondary texts are referenced throughout (often in footnotes),
but I also want to be clear at the outset that my understanding of Laruelle and, in particular,
the laying out of the tenets of non-philosophy in Section 1 of my essay, is based on these
rather than any exhaustive reading of Laruelle’s own books (and, as such, constitutes only an
initial foray in to what, for me, is new territory). Any errors in understanding are, of course,
my own.
2
Non-philosophy pitches itself against this particular apparatus of capture. Not as an
anti-philosophy (as, for example, in Alain Badiou’s description of Jacques Lacan’s
psychoanalysis), or as simply an ‘outside’ to philosophy (at least as this is posited by
philosophy). Indeed, non-philosophy does not turn away from philosophical materials
exactly, but, rather, reuses or, we might say, retools them. As Ray Brassier, amongst
many others, has pointed out (following Laruelle’s own suggestion) the ‘non’ here is
more like that used in the term ‘non-Euclidean geometry’ (Brassier 2003: 25). It
signals an expansion of an already existing paradigm; a re-contextualisation of
existing material (in this case conceptual) and the placing of these alongside newer
‘discoveries’
From these few sentences we can already extract two key characteristics (or distinct
articulations perhaps?) of non-philosophy: 1. It involves an attitude and orientation
towards philosophy that also implies a kind of practice (or, at any rate, a particular
‘use’ of philosophical materials). Laruelle also calls this a performance, as well as,
crucially, a science; non-philosophy is the ‘science of philosophy’ in this sense.
(Brassier’s writings on Laruelle attend specifically to this more ‘formal’ articulation
of non-philosophy). 2. It might be said to name other forms of thought – other
practices we might say – besides the philosophical (again, when these are not simply
positioned – and interpreted – by philosophy), whilst, in the same gesture, naming a
general democratisation of all thinking (Ó Maoilearca would be the key exponent of
this second articulation, hence the title of his recent book ‘on’ Laruelle: All Thoughts
are Equal (2015)).
I want to take each of these two articulations in turn, but before that a further brief
word about non-philosophy and the real. For Laruelle, as I have already intimated,
philosophy involves a particular take on the real; an account, explanation or
interpretation of the latter. Non-philosophy, on the other hand, is a thinking that
proceeds from the real, or, at a pinch, alongside it (rather than positing a real, it
assumes its always already ‘giveness’ as a presupposition or axiom). For nonphilosophy this real is itself radically foreclosed to thought, at least, as this is typically
understood (it cannot be ‘explained’ or interpreted in this sense); as such, we might
say that the third key articulation of non-philosophy is that it implies a form of gnosis.
In fact, alongside its formidable complexity there is a sense in which non-philosophy
can be immediately grasped in an almost banal – or at least naïve – sense. I will be
returning to this and adding some qualifications below.
i. The science of philosophy
For Laruelle then all philosophy involves a common function – or invariant – that he
names ‘decision’. Put simply, philosophy sets up a binary that dictates its subsequent
operations. It is always ‘about’ a world that, in fact, it has itself determined, posited as
its object. In Laruelle’s terms (in Brassier’s somewhat technical reading) this is ‘an
3
act of scission’ producing a dyad between a conditioned datum and a conditioning
faktum (Brassier 2003: 26). The decisional structure however involves a further
move: philosophy’s ‘auto-positioning’ as ultimate arbiter over these two terms.
Philosophy offers a certain perspective and higher synthesis – a ‘unity of experience’
– over both conditioned and conditioning (Brassier 2003: 26). Philosophy’s cut, we
might say, produces a particular subject and world and then offers a perspective (the
only one) from which to think both.
We might also call this philosophy’s ideological character: the real causes – or, at
least, in the last instance, determines – philosophy, but the latter is then abstracted out
and seen as itself cause of the real (hence, its production of the world). The
connections to two of Laruelle’s key pre-cursors, Marx and especially Althusser, are
explicit but we might also note that this perspective bears some resemblances to
Lacan’s theorisation of the retro-formation of the subject (that must come to reverse
the ‘illusion’ of the ego and assume its own causality), as well as Gilles Deleuze and
Félix Guattari’s own materialist account of the subject as residuum in Anti-Oedipus (a
subject that misrecognises itself as prior to the process – the syntheses of the
unconscious – that produced it). Indeed, in a relatively recent summary of nonphilosophy Laruelle himself suggests that non-philosophers are very close to both the
political militant and the analyst (Laruelle 2004).
This decisional mechanism is not restricted to philosophy as a discipline (or
discourse), but impacts on our thinking more generally (we are all philosophical
subjects in this sense). We might note here the resonances with Jacques Derrida’s
‘diagnosis’ of a logocentricism that is determinate in philosophy (at least in the
Western tradition), but also in other forms of apparently non philosophical thought
(the lack of hyphen here denotes the non Laruellian sense of these terms).
Commentators have suggested that non-philosophy (this time in Laruelle’s sense) is
both a less convincing deconstruction (as in Andrew McGettigan’s critical overview
of Laruelle) or, indeed, a more radical operation that itself re-positions deconstruction
as simply another form of philosophy (as in Brassier’s own overview) (McGettigan
2012; Brassier 2003). Whatever the understanding, it seems clear that Derrida is the
‘near enemy’ of Laruelle, but also (at least to this reader) that non-philosophy,
although clearly indebted to Derrida, involves something more affirmative (at least
potentially) than the melancholy science of deconstruction.
Non-philosophy is then an attempt to practice philosophy (at least of a kind) without
the aforementioned auto-positioning. Crucially, it does not involve a straightforward
disavowal of the philosophical gesture (again, it is not non philosophy in this more
straightforward sense); and, again, it does not involve recourse to a simple ‘outside’
that might then be simply folded back in by philosophy (as I suggested above, all
philosophy claims to supersede previous interpretations, to really get to the real
‘from’ a more radical outside perspective). Non-philosophy, for Laruelle, must then
attempt its task from within philosophy’s own interpretive circles (we might note,
4
again, the connections with deconstruction as a process always already occurring
‘within’ Western metaphysics).
To backtrack for a moment: as I mentioned above, for Laruelle, non-philosophy is not
another take on the real (or, indeed, a sufficient explanation of it), but proceeds from
the latter. For Laruelle it names a more radical immanence – arising from a
suspension of decision – that is specifically other to the world produced by
philosophy (whatever the claims of the latter about its own immanence might be).2
Again, non-philosophy is a thinking from a Real that is itself indifferent to that
thinking (there is no reverse causality (or ‘reciprocal determination’) in this sense).
On the one hand then – as I also mentioned above – this real is very simple: it is just
‘this’, immediately graspable, almost pre-cognitive (and, for Brassier, uninteresting –
and empty – in this respect). And yet, as Robin Mackay points out in his own
Introduction to Laruelle it is, in fact, not self evident at all (at least to the typical
‘subject’ that is in and of the ‘world’) (Mackay 2012: 2). Indeed, how could it be selfevident to a subject who has been produced by the very philosophical operation (the
decisional structure) in question?
Non-philosophy (at least in this particular articulation) will then use concepts, but
only after they have been untethered from their properly philosophical function – their
auto-positioning and what Laruelle also calls the ‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’
(simply put, their claim to truth – or, as Anthony Paul Smith puts it: ‘philosophy’s
faith in itself before the Real’ (Paul Smith 2016: 26).3 In fact, it is this that ‘explains’
2
As, for example, Laruelle will argue, in Deleuze’s philosophy (see, for example, 2012a)
Laruelle. Is this claim, however, entirely correct? In his last essay ‘Immanence: A Life’
Deleuze is very careful to distinguish his concept of immanence from one that is immanent
‘to’ (and, as such, involves a form of transcendence) (Deleuze 2001: 25-34). He also attends,
closely, to how a ‘point of view’ on this immanence cannot but involve a certain kind of
abstraction and ‘folding back’. A more detailed comparison on this point will need to wait for
another time, but we might note here Deleuze’s own sympathy (albeit with reservations) with
Laruelle’s non-philosophical project as evidenced by the footnote to the latter at the very end
of What is Philosophy? (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 234 n.16). For my own take on Deleuze
(and Guattari) as a form of non philosophy see ‘Memories of a Deleuzian: To Think is
Always to Follow the Witches Flight’ (O’Sullivan 2017a).
3
Indeed, Paul Smith is especially attuned to the arrogance of Philosophy – and, not least, its
connection to a ‘wider’ European colonial attitude (hence, the importance of non-philosophy
in the decolonisation of thinking). In his François Laruelle’s Principles of Non-Philosophy: A
Critical Introduction and Guide Paul Smith is also keen to maintain and defend the category
of the human (albeit this is not the human of a straightforward humanism, but of a more
generic ‘force-of-thought’) against those other readers of Laruelle – Paul Smith has Brassier
especially in mind – who are intent on dismantling the latter or hastening its demise (Paul
Smith 2013). Might we say then that Paul-Smith attends to the on-going importance of
phenomenology (especially Heidegger and Michel Henry) for Laruelle’s non-philosophy
(albeit in a ‘reduced’ form), whereas Brassier is interested (see footnote 4 below) in a reading
that effectively rids non-philosophy of any phenomenological residue (hence the focus on
5
some of the complexity of non-philosophy, both that it can read like philosophy (it
cannot but be very close to the philosophy it writes on), and also that it must use
neologisms and other unfamiliar terms – not only a new vocabulary but, at times, also
a new syntax – in order to articulate its non-philosophical operations away from
already existing philosophical language.
Could we perhaps diagram these relations between philosophy and non-philosophy
(in which the latter ‘ventriloquises’ the former), in relation to the Real, as in Fig. 1:
Fig. 1. The ventriloquism of non-philosophy (or fictioning)
[1. The Real; 2. Philosophy; 3. Non-Philosophy; 4. Fiction]
Here non-philosophy is less a representation of the real than a refraction of it. To
jump ahead slightly, might we also call this ventriloquism of philosophy by nonphilosophy a kind of fictioning, insofar as the ‘explanatory’ power of philosophy (its
various claims about the real) are transformed in to something else: models with no
necessary pretensions to truth. Certainly, in his more recent writings (as we shall see)
Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is concerned with just such a mutation of
philosophy that he calls ‘philo-fictions’.
We might also note, again, the connections to Marx and Althusser here: Philosophy as
a particular ideology (with its truth claims) and, thus, non-philosophy as a form of
ideology critique. The apparent ‘real’ world of philosophy – from the perspective of
non-philosophy – is itself revealed as a fiction, determined (in the last instance) by a
abstraction). These two positions revolve around different attitudes to alienation and reason.
For Brassier alienation enables freedom via the constructs of reason (hence the Promethean
character of his writing); for Paul-Smith non-philosophy promises a kind of overcoming of
alienation and a limiting of reason vis-à-vis a human that is always more than the latter.
6
more radical immanence that has not been determined by philosophy at all (indeed,
this real is, precisely, undetermined). Crucially however (and following Mackay once
more) one cannot draw a simple line of demarcation here between
ideology/philosophy and a science that ‘demystifies’ them. This would be to simply
produce a further binary that philosophy could then reach across, and, ultimately
subsume. It would be to produce yet another philosophical circuit, a further structure
of decision. Hence the importance of what Laruelle will call ‘superposition’, a placing
of the two alongside one another as it were (I will return, very briefly, to this in
Section 2 of my essay).
To see all this from a slightly different perspective – more topologically (or even nontopologically) as it were – we might suggest that non-philosophy involves a kind of
‘flattening’ of philosophy’s auto-positioning and a concomitant undoing of its
‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’ (again, its pretension of being able to account for
all of the real). We might then draw a second diagram as in Fig. 2:
Fig. 2 The flattening of non-philosophy (or ‘change in vision’)
[1. Philosophy (view from above); 2. Non-philosophy (as dropping down); 3. Philo-fictions
(and other modes of thought); 4. Non-philosophy (as clinamen)]
This diagram foregrounds the particular ‘change in vision’ (to use a Laruellian
phrase) that non-philosophy entails, a kind of ‘dropping down’ of philosophical
perspective and, with that, what we might call a rejigging of foreground and
background relations. Here, it is as if the conceptual material has been laid out flat –
as on a table top. The ‘view from above’ is replaced by something more immanent (in
7
fact, Laruelle suggests that non-philosophy is less an overview than like a line – a
clinamen – that touches on different ‘models’ of thought).
To jump ahead again slightly we might note an immediate and obvious connection
with art practice here insofar as non-philosophy becomes a practice that involves a
manipulation of material (and even the construction of a different kind of conceptual
‘device’ that allows for this ‘shift’ in view). We might however also note four brief
reservations before moving on to the second – and somewhat looser – articulation of
non-philosophy. First, is whether Laruelle’s diagnosis of all philosophy is correct?
Are there forms of philosophy that do not proceed by decision in the sense Laruelle
uses the term; this, ultimately, is where Brassier marks the limits of Laruelle’s method
(Brassier 2007).4 An attendant (and stronger) critique is that the operation of reducing
all philosophy to decision (albeit articulated in numerous ways) denies the specificity
of different philosophies and, indeed, can produces a kind of solipsism; this is
McGettigan’s take (McGettigan 2003). A third reservation is whether non-philosophy
involves anything other than a kind of ‘turf war’ amongst philosophers (afterall,
generally speaking, non-philosophy is read by philosophers). A final reservation (for
myself, a key one) is what, precisely, a concept does when untethered from the
‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’? This is something I will return to in section 2
below.
ii. Other modes of thought
In the second diagram above (Fig. 2) we might note the possibility that the ‘flattened’
philosophical materials – the philo-fictions – can be positioned alongside other forms
of non philosophical thought (note the lack of hyphen again here). Philosophy, when
untethered from its ‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’, becomes just one mode of
thinking alongside a whole host of others: artistic, but also the scientific, even,
perhaps, the animal (again, this is the democratisation of thought that is most
thoroughly tracked through in Ó Maoilearca’s work ‘on’ Laruelle).5 Non-philosophy
4
In Nihil Abound Brassier suggests that rather than a universal invariant decision – described
in this book as a ‘quasi-spontaneous philosophical compulsion’ (Brassier 2007: 119) – is,
rather, the hallmark of a particular kind of philosophy that finds its terminus in Heidegger
and, indeed, deconstruction. Indeed, for Brassier, it is only by understanding Laruelle in this
way – as offering something to philosophy (basically the suspension of the decisional
mechanism that in itself might allow for a ‘non-correlationist’ thinking) that the radical
implications of Laruelle’s thought can be staked out (for Brassier this must also involve the
extraction – from out of Laruelle’s own account of non-philosophy (and especially of the
human as locus of the real) – of a ‘de-phenomenlogized conception of the real as “beingnothing”’; hence the title of Brassier’s book Nihil Unbound (Brassier 2007: 118)).
5
As Ó Maoilearca remarks at the beginning of his book:
Non-philosophy is a conception of philosophy (and all forms of thought) that allows
us to see them as equivalent according to a broader explanatory paradigm. It enlarges
8
gives us an interesting way in which to (re)position philosophy and its materials (as
laid out above) – a radically different point of view as it were – but it also offers up
this corollary perspective on how different forms of thought invariably ‘co-exist’ and,
indeed, might interact. This is to posit a radical horizontality (or, in Félix Guattari’s
terms, a ‘transversality’) that operates between heterogeneous practices. In this
change of vision philosophy is brought down to earth, operating more as a fiction than
as a claim to truth (again, it is positioned as a model amongst others). In the same
gesture other forms of thought (for example art), in their turn, are given some
philosophical (or, at any rate, non-philosophical) worth insofar as they are no longer
unfavourably compared with a philosophy enthroned above them.
This second articulation of non-philosophy (as naming different kinds of thinking) is
less explored by Laruelle (although I will look below at two recent texts by him on
the kind of thinking that photography, for example, might perform), no doubt, as
Brassier suggests, because non-philosophy, in one respect anyway, has very little to
say about them (it does not involve yet another (philosophical) take on the different
terrains ‘outside’ philosophy that it can then appropriate via its own definitions of the
latter) (Brassier 2003: 27). But, of course, these other forms of thinking have been
theorised elsewhere (there is plenty of theoretical material out there on art, the animal,
and so on), and, more obviously, are already occurring without the help of philosophy
(as in the work of artists, scientists and so forth, but also, more radically, in the sense
that animals, for example, already think in some respects).6 The question is then
whether these theorisations, hitherto, have always been philosophical in character
(proceeding from decision) and, indeed, what a non-philosophical theorisation of, for
example, art might be (one that does not involve decision). Then there is also the
supplementary question as to whether these other non philosophical forms of thinking
need an account – from philosophy or non-philosophy – in the first place.
It seems to me that this is one of the most interesting areas in relation to nonphilosophy and art practice. That is, the diagnosis of how philosophy or theory
captures objects and practices (or, in fact, defines them as such in the first place) is
important, as is the ‘new’ perspective that non-philosophy offers in terms of the
democratisation of thought, but it is really how non-philosophy might reconfigure
what counts as a theory of art and how art itself works in practice, on the ground as it
were (especially when it is not explained, interpreted – or simply defined – by
philosophy). What kind of framework does non-philosophy offer for thinking about
the set of things that can count as thoughtful, a set that includes existing philosophy
but also a whole host of what is presently deemed (by standard philosophy) to be
non-philosophical (art, technology, natural science) (Ó Maoilearca 2015: 9).
6
Again, we might note the connections with deconstruction as a particular kind of practice
here; a diagnosis of Western metaphysics, but also – more elusively perhaps – a gesture to
forms of thinking that are irreducible to this.
9
art; but also what kind of thinking does art itself perform? Indeed, in terms of the
latter, is it a question of thinking – at least as this is typically understood – at all?
In fact, the above two aspects – of theory and practice we might say – are connected
insofar as the change in perspective announced by non-philosophy (the ‘dropping
down’) might at the same time produce a different model of what thought (understood
as a practice) might be (in passing we might note that this is the importance of theory
for practice – or even of theory as its own kind of (speculative) practice).7 I will be
returning to some of these questions in section 3 of my essay. To return more directly
to Laruelle, a more general question is what follows, for non-philosophy, from its
particular shift in perspective? What other kinds of thought does it make possible in
its very re-definition of thinking? To a certain extent this is precisely a work of
experimentation and, indeed, construction. The possibility of what Mackay calls ‘nonstandard worlds’ that arise from this shift and radical change in perspective cannot be
predicted – or, even, perhaps, articulated in typical – read philosophical – language
(Mackay 2011: 8).
In relation to this we might note Laruelle’s interest (alongside philosophy) in poetics,
or forms of writing – fictions – that are not for philosophers (afterall, it is pretty clear
from even a cursory look at Laruelle’s corpus that the readership of his major works
can only be philosophical in character – or, at least, must be familiar with
philosophy). 8 Forms of writing and thought that are untethered from decision. Indeed,
what forms of writing, we might ask, are really adequate to the properly nonphilosophical subject (especially when we consider that typically syntax – and
narrative form – is generally a kind of hand maiden to philosophy; I will return to this
below)?
To start to bring this brief reflection on what I have called the second articulation of
non-philosophy (the flattening) to an end we might suggest a couple more questions.
The first is how Laruelle’s account of different models and of an ‘algebra of thought’
differs from, for example, someone like Guattari and his own theory of
metamodelisation? In fact, it seems to me there might well be a highly productive
encounter to be forced between non-philosophy and schizoanalysis.9 To return to an
earlier criticism, we might also ask whether Laruelle’s thinking implies a certain
homogenisation, but also (and almost despite itself), a further ‘outside perspective’ or
7
On this point see Keith Tilford’s own unpublished essay on the implications of nonphilosophy for art: ‘Laruelle, Art, and the Scientific Model’ (Tilford n.d.). Tilford makes an
especially compelling distinction (though not one I use in my own essay) between ‘theories’
(based on decision) and ‘models’ (that are, precisely, revisable).
8
See, for example, the texts gathered together in ‘Appendix I’ at the end of From Decision to
Heresy (Laruelle 2012b: 353-408).
9
For Laruelle’s own non-philosophical response to Guattari and schizoanalysis (and, not
least, the collaboration with Deleuze) see ‘Fragments of an Anti-Guattari’ (Laruelle 1993).
10
overview (at least of a kind) ‘on’ other forms of thought (non-philosophy as just the
latest novel philosophy as it were)? Although non-philosophy does not involve the
same auto-positioning as philosophy it implicitly posits a kind of view from
elsewhere, or, perhaps, a view on a view (as exemplified in my own diagrams of its
operations). In fact, as I suggested in section i above, it seems to me that the latter –
the perspective of any view from above – has also to be dropped down in a further
flattening (it is in this sense that non-philosophy can only ever but be one form of
thinking – one perspective – amongst others).
To give this another inflection, we might also note that these different perspectives or
models are also ‘lived’ out in the world as it were. They are, we might say, performed
(hence the connection between non-philosophy and schizoanalysis). Which is to say
the realm of non-philosophical work is not only the table top – and the abstract (non)
philosophical plane – but also life and practice more generally (in this respect it is
especially the connection of Guattari’s abstract modelling to concrete practice (for
example, at La Borde) that marks out schizoanalysis as its own kind of non
philosophy). Could we then posit a more radical non philosophy? This would perhaps
name forms of thinking that do not ‘refer’ to philosophy and its materials, but neither
to any kind of overview (or, indeed, any clinamen that ‘touches’ other forms of
thought). A radical non that announces the necessity of always re-localising any
global view. This non does not name a terrain as such (‘outside’ philosophy) or,
indeed, any kind of steady state or consistent practice, but the continuing refusal of
any superior or global position (what we might also call a radical parochialism).
All this speculation aside (and, it has to be said thinking about non-philosophy breeds
this kind of speculation with its various loops and nestings), there is also clearly a key
issue here – a reason that, again, what I have called the second articulation of nonphilosophy is less explored by Laruelle. Indeed, following on from some of my
comments above we might note that it can never simply be a question of mapping out
a terrain outside of philosophy (for the practice of non-philosophy) as this will then
simply be co-opted by philosophy (as its material). Is this, ultimately, the limits of
non-philosophy as a particular practice? Like deconstruction before it (at least from
one perspective), non-philosophy – as a take on the structure and workings of
philosophy – is delimited by the very thinking it pitches itself ‘against’. Nonphilosophy can operate as a kind of trap for thought even as it diagnoses philosophy
as itself a trap.
2. Interlude: Philo to Photo-Fiction
I want now to briefly turn to Laruelle’s writings on what he calls ‘photo-fiction’ that
in many ways address – and bring together – the two articulations of non-philosophy
outlined above. Indeed, for Laruelle a way of thinking the relationship of philosophy
to non-philosophy is through photography and its relationship to what Laruelle calls
non-photography insofar as photography contains its own ‘Principle of Sufficient
11
Photography’ or, again, makes a particular claim to truth. Indeed, photography (at
least at first glance) is an accurate – and faithful – ‘picture of the world’; it is, we may
say, a graphic example of those standard modes of thought that Laruelle writes
against. Outlining a possible non-photographic practice is then also a way of outlining
a non-philosophical practice.
In his essay ‘What is Seen In the Photo?’ Laruelle pitches his own take on the
photograph against any ‘theory’ of photography that positions it, precisely, as a
double of the world. Indeed, the task is to think the photograph as nonrepresentational (however counter intuitive that might be) (Laruelle 2011). For
Laruelle this requires a certain stance or posture of the photographer – and with this
the instantiation of a very particular kind of relation to the real – which then, in turn,
entails the production of a different kind of knowledge (that does not arise from
representation). To ‘see’ the photograph (and photographer) as such means
suspending a certain privileging of perception and ‘being-in-the-world’ as paradigm.
In this refusal of phenomenology – and yet more philosophical ‘interpretive circles’ –
Laruelle suggests that science and scientific experiences of the world might operate as
a guide insofar as the latter proceed through a pragmatic and experimental
engagement with the real (or, at least, with a demarcated ‘section’ of it). So, just as
non-philosophy involves a particular take on philosophy, a use of it as material
(untethered from its interpretive function), so non-photography will involve a use of
the photograph as material (as very much part of the real) instead of (or besides) its
representational function. In each case the conceptual and photographic materials are
positioned as fictions – or what Laruelle, in this essay, calls photo-fictions and philofictions.
In a more recent essay that develops this idea of photo-fiction Laruelle tackles the
philosophical discourse of aesthetics more directly, tracking a move from the latter (a
philosophical account of art’s self sufficiency or truth) to what he calls, generally,
‘art-fictions’, and, with these, the practice of a ‘non-aesthetics’ (this being an
aesthetics not tied to a ‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’ but, instead, arising from
what he suggests, again, is a more a scientific paradigm involving the positing of
models) (Laruelle 2012c). On the face of it then this later essay is less about art
practice, photography or otherwise, but about philosophy (as instantiated in the
discourse of aesthetics) and how one might re-position the latter. Indeed, there is still
a minimal aesthetics at work here, at least of sorts (an account of what art ‘is’). That
said, Laruelle’s own claim is that these photo/philo-fictions operate between
photography and philosophy, with each discipline surrendering its own ‘auto-finalised
form’ or ‘auto-teleology’. The two disciplines are reduced down – themselves
flattened – and brought together in what Laruelle calls the matrix, or generic: ‘in
which photo and fictions (a philosophy or conceptuality) are under-determined, which
is to say, deprived of their classical finality and domination’ (Laruelle 2012: 16).
12
The generic – a kind of image or ‘space’ of thought that is non-hierarchical (or
radically horizontal to return to a term I used above) – is then this other strange
continent (of the real) that is yet to be determined. Laruelle will also call this levelling
out an algebra of philosophy/photography. This horizontality is important as
otherwise – as I mentioned above – non-philosophy becomes just one more superior
philosophical position (and thus is itself open to further ‘nesting’ by the positing of
further outside perspectives). Indeed, one might suggest that Laruelle’s own nonphilosophy is itself simply another form of thought amongst others in this sense;
although, as I also mentioned above, Laruelle (perhaps in a nod to Badiou, and
certainly to maintain a certain kind of philosophical perspective) also suggests that
non-philosophy has a specificity as a line – a clinamen – that ‘touches’ these other
fictions.
This second essay by Laruelle is then concerned with the building of a new
conceptual or theoretical apparatus that is capable of producing these strange photofictions or models of the Real. These are forms of thought (broadly construed) that are
less explanatory or interpretive of the world as it is, and more speculative in character.
Might we suggest that it is this experimental nature of photo-fictions that
characterises them as a form of art practice?
This strange kind of non-photographic apparatus is also necessarily a
phenomenologically reduced one. It ‘pictures’ what happens to experience when not
tied to a self/interpreter, or, again, when such experience is not ‘processed’ through
representation. We might also say the fictions that are then produced by it are
somehow weaker (again, they are ‘undetermined’), untethered as they are from a
certain pretension. A more modest form of thought perhaps, but also one that has the
potential to expand the very idea – and working out – of what thought is and might
become (it is in this sense that Laruelle’s ‘non’ announces a turn from hermeneutics
to something more heuristic).
The key for Laruelle in all this is, again, photo-fiction’s break with representation and
mimesis (indeed, he writes of the jouissance at the end of ‘photocentrism’). In itself
these photo-fictions imply and, it seems to me, help produce a new kind of subject (if
we can still call it this) or what Laruelle calls (in a nod to Kant’s own notion of a non
empirical transcendental subject) ‘Subject = X’. Again, they also imply a new
continent to be ‘discovered’ – or itself constructed – ‘beyond’ the ‘world’ of
philosophy/photography (Laruelle 2012: 15). Laruelle turns to quantum mechanics
here (and, indeed, in much of his recent writings) where he finds the tools adequate
and appropriate to this experimental re-organization or re-construction of the world
(outside of representation as it were). Such a ‘new’ scientific theory does not involve
yet more binaries, but, rather, a ‘superpositioning’ in which a third state is produced
by the addition (or ‘superposing’) of two previous states (superpositioning is a way of
dealing with the paradox I mentioned above of non-philosophy as both theory of
thought and just one mode of thinking itself). Indeed, it is precisely quantum
13
science’s break with representational ‘accounts’ of matter and the universe that makes
it so useful for non-philosophy. We might even say that non-philosophy, in this sense,
is quantum philosophy – and that the Subject = X is the quantum-subject.
3. Non-Art Practice
I want now to develop some of the above in 6 different but more specific
‘applications’ of non-philosophy to art practice. 10 In particular I want to test
Laruelle’s method when it comes to thinking through a non philosophical discipline,
with its own logics and history, but also, more particularly, in relation to an
understanding of performance as its own kind of ‘non-art’ (or what I also call
‘performance fictions’).11
i. Diagrammatics
This might be a name for the practice of recontextualisation, reorganisation and
general manipulation of philosophical materials that have been untethered from their
properly philosophical function or discourse. I have already laid out some of the
aspects of this kind of practice above, but, in relation to art more explicitly, we might
note the possibility that concepts be refigured diagrammatically. In a simple sense
they can be drawn, but, more generally, to diagram suggests a different ‘imaging’ or
even performance of concepts. In fact, art practice has always involved a take on
philosophy (and theory more broadly) that resonates with this – a ‘use’ of
philosophical materials as material.
A key question here is what these philosophical materials ‘do’ when untethered in this
way: what is their explanatory power (if that still has a meaning here)? Or, to put this
another way, can this be anything different than the use of philosophy as illustration,
or ‘caption’ (Laruelle himself uses the latter term when writing of philo-fictions).
What, we might ask, does the treatment of philosophy in this way allow us to think?
One answer is that it might, for example, suggest surprising and productive
connections and conjunctions between different conceptual resources (given that the
normal (philosophical) rules are suspended). 12 Philosophy (or non-philosophy)
becomes a more synthetic – and, again, speculative – practice in this sense (rather
than an analytic enquiry). More radically, this kind of practice opens up the different
space of and for thinking I mentioned above.
ii. Art as model
10
I am aware that this idea of ‘applying’ non-philosophy is highly problematic in relation to
non-philosophy; my comments below address this particular limitation.
11
For an example of some of the kinds of practice I have in mind see Burrows 2006.
12
My own book On the Production of Subjectivity (O’Sullivan 2012) included examples of
this kind of diagrammatic treatment of conceptual material.
14
Non-philosophy might also name the multiplicity of thinking – the other kinds of
thought – that subsist alongside the philosophical, and, perhaps also conceptual.
Indeed, there is the important question here of the role of affect in art practice – and
whether this more pathic register might also be understood as a kind of nonconceptual thinking; a different kind of non philosophy perhaps? Again, some of this
terrain has been laid out above, but, in relation to art practice, it seems to me that with
this second aspect, we are moving into more productive territory. Indeed, art practice
has long been involved in non-conceptual explorations (without the help of nonphilosophy), just as it has also involved its own particular take on conceptual material.
A similar question to that above might then also be posed here: what does nonphilosophy – in this democratising aspect – bring to art practice? Certainly, again, it
brings philosophy (and aesthetics) down from its throne, makes it more of a model
amongst others, and, in the same gesture, art’s own models are given a certain status
beyond being simple fiction (at least when this is opposed to truth). But what does
this modelling allow beyond this democratisation? As I mentioned above, very little is
said about this area – the other forms of ‘thought’ besides philosophy – ‘within’ nonphilosophy itself. Again, this, it seems to me, is partly because a certain
deconstructive logic is at play: any form of thinking, as thinking, is always already
determined by the cut that produces the world and subject that thinks.13
But perhaps we might rephrase this, and also put it in more positive terms: nonphilosophy cannot but use the stuff of the world and thus must use it differently,
untethering it from the world (in the sense of a world determined by philosophy). In
terms of art one thinks of William Burroughs and his cut-ups that, precisely, open up
a different space-time. Indeed, narrative – the logical sequencing of sentences (cause
and effect), familiar syntax, and so forth – are all key determining factors of the
world. Non-philosophy in this expanded sense might then also be a form of nonnarrative (or even a form of non-fiction, in which the ‘non’ names a widening of
context to include those formal experiments that go beyond simple narrative, as well
as a use of language beyond its representational function). Such art will need to be
‘read’, or, at least, maintain a minimum consistency of sense (or a patterning
perhaps?). Again, experiments in writing non-narrative fictions (or, at least, in playing
Nick Srnicek suggests something similar in his own take on a politics (and a certain aporia)
that leads from non-philosophy: any form of typical intervention in the world cannot but be
determined by that world (or, again, takes place within the horizon of decision) (Srnicek
2011). Non-philosophy can, in this sense, open a view from elsewhere (or, for Srnicek, it can
open up a kind of non-capitalist space), but it cannot offer any content (Brassier’s reading of
Laruelle’s method puts this necessary abstract character and formal inventiveness in more
positive terms as the very work of non-philosophy) (Brassier 2003).
13
15
with narrative schema) would be instructive here.14 We might also note, once again,
Laruelle’s own writing experiments.
iii. Non-art (and art history)
Another (and perhaps more appropriate) thinking through of non-philosophy in
relation to art is to examine whether art performs its own ‘auto-positioning’ and has
its own kind of ‘principle’ that doubles the ‘Principle of Sufficient Philosophy’: does
art also involve a certain kind of invariant ‘decision’ (however that might manifest
itself)? Insofar as art is representation (a ‘picturing of the world’) then the answer is
clearly yes (and the above comments on photography would have relevance here –
although work would need to be done to lay out how this particular structure operates
in art practice more generally). But, in this sense, we might also say that art has
already been through its own ‘non’ ‘revolution’ with the move from figuration to
abstraction (Malevich and Pollock representing the twin apotheosis of this tendency in
painting).15
In fact, with the further move beyond abstraction to objecthood we have practices
which, in their relationship to representation, ‘mirror’ the relation between nonphilosophy and philosophy. Certainly Minimalism, for example, was involved in
something else ‘beyond’ representation: the production of objects, assemblages and so
forth that were not ‘about’ the real, but part of it (and in writers such as Don Judd and
Robert Smithson we have clear articulations of this logic – the radical break their
practices announce – as well as an indication of the importance of fiction (as a mode
of writing) in articulating it). We need only add that this shift in perspective also
necessarily changes the perspective on previous art that is then seen as representation
but also as itself object (what else could it be?). We might also note the strange
practice of the ‘reciprocal readymade’ here, which involved using (representational)
art as material, as readymade.16 Contemporary practices that refer back – or re-use –
previous art, untethered from its representational functioning, would also be important
here (what is sometimes called ‘second order practice’). There is a similar structure to
non-philosophy’s use of philosophy in these kinds of practice, but, we might also
note, a similar limit insofar as such a practice cannot but involve a nesting of art
within art (within art). I will return to this.
We might also gesture here to the history of the avant-garde more generally that
involved a refusal of previous categories of art. Almost every Modern movement
involved this disavowal of a previous definition – the performance of a forceful ‘No’
14
In relation to this – and to an idea of ‘fictioning’ – see my essay ‘From Science Fiction to
Science Fictioning: SF’s Traction on the Real’ (O’Sullivan 2017b).
15
In Difference and Repetition, in the chapter on ‘The Image of Thought’, Deleuze suggests
that philosophy needs to go through a similar revolution to art (Deleuze 1994: 129-67).
16
Thanks to Nadja Millner-Larson for alerting me to this logic of the reciprocal readymade.
16
echoing throughout time (the manifestos embody this recurring motif, perhaps most
explicitly foregrounded in DADA which itself involved a refusal of ‘good sense’).
There was also, with the avant-garde, a concomitant drive to bring art in to life.
Indeed, in terms of non-art, a recurring feature of the avant-garde is the incorporation
of non-artistic material in order to disrupt, precisely, representation. From the
Readymade to Arte Povera to the Happening art has also been – at least in its initial
impulse – non-art. In terms of this it is surely Duchamp that best exemplifies this
refusal of representation, just as it is Kaprow that gestures to the very limits of the
frame (and that does most to collapse – or ‘blur’ – the art/life boundary).
There is a lot more to be said here about this relationship between art and non-art –
especially in relation to Laruelle’s own ideas about how an anti-philosophy (as
opposed to non-philosophy) invariably sets up an outside which then gets
incorporated in a renewed ‘definition’ (hence the interest of the reciprocal readymade
that does not look ‘outside’, but uses art as its material). There is also the issue of art
practice traversing this edge, often moving towards non-art status, only to hold back
(at the last moment as it were) in order to maintain an artistic status (again, it seems to
me that a certain deconstructive logic is at play with these practices that oscillate
between art and non-art). A question here might then be what an understanding of
non-art (in Laruelle’s sense) brings to the table given this particular history of Modern
Art?
One answer might be that it allows a radical re-thinking of the whole question of the
avant-garde and of the art/non-art dialectic. To recall: Laruelle’s non-philosophy,
does not posit an outside; indeed, it is not an avant-garde position in this sense.
Perhaps if we follow Laruelle then we are not so much exploring a territory beyond
accepted definitions, but re-configuring the very terrain of art and life (in terms of
superpositioning). Once again it would seem that non-philosophy and non-art has this
double face: on the one hand it allows a certain practice outside the laws and logics of
the discipline it seeks to undermine (it is heretical), but, on the other, it cannot but be
caught by these very forms (insofar as it must work within and with them).
iv. Ideology critique
In a return to some of my earlier comments about Althusser and ideology, another
take on the conjunction non-philosophy and art might be that non-philosophy can help
to diagnose and critique ‘Contemporary Art’ as a whole. It might help to identify a
particular logic at work – for example, indeterminacy – that is, as it were, a
structuring invariant, whatever a given practice might claim. Such is the strategy of
Suhail Malik who calls for an ‘exit’ from a Contemporary Art that is the handmaiden
of contemporary neoliberalism (see Malik 2017). Here the very ‘openness’ of the
work of art is seen as profoundly ideological. In relation to this recent critique (of
Contemporary Art) we might also note that there has long been a ‘tradition’ of radical
(or ‘social’) art history as a form of ideology critique that is intent on demystifying
17
the aesthetic and ideological functioning of art and, especially of ‘Art History’, by
giving a properly historical account of art objects. Might we even call this a kind of
non-Art History (the capitals denoting a certain disciplinary self sufficiency)?
But, to return to Malik, this is also a complex matter insofar as we might also say that
contemporary art (note: no capitals) is a practice that has itself been untethered from a
certain programmatic account (namely, modernism). Contemporary art is already
characterised by a radical democratisation; this, for example, would be Jean-Franois
Lyotard’s take (on postmodernism) or, indeed, Rosalind Krauss’ (on our ‘postmedium condition’). From this perspective it is Malik who is reinstating a certain
programme, or might we even say decision (about what art should do). Of course, it is
always possible to position the other’s point of view as the ideological one (witness
the Adorno/Lukács debates around autonomy versus realism), but it does seem to me
that positioning art as ideology critique – or as simply critical – and at the same time
dismissing practices that are not committed to this critique, cannot but limit our
understanding of art and, indeed, its terrain of operation (rather than, for example,
opening it up to further adventures).
Nevertheless a key question arising from this particular perspective is whether there is
indeed a non-art practice that utilises art as its material, but untethers it from its
dominant logics (whatever these might be). And, if so, whether this is something
different to what art already does. It seems clear here that it is the definition of art that
determines its non (and, as such, if the dominant logics are indeed indeterminacy, or,
perhaps, representation, then this will define non-art as non-representation and
determinate). A further question is whether art – or non-art – can itself escape these
interminable circuits of definition and re-definition? Can it offer a different kind of
‘knowledge’ ‘outside’ of art as it is typically understood?17
v. Performance fictions
Leading on from the above, and changing perspective a little, there is also the
compelling gnostic ‘account’ that non-philosophy gives of the Real that I mentioned
at the beginning of my essay. At the end of the conference on ‘Fiction as Method’ (the
progenitor of this book) Tim Etchells performed a ‘re-mix’ of the previous speaker –
M. John Harrison – and his compelling reading of one of his own short stories. Both
17
This is the question Amanda Beech asks in her own take on Laruelle and on what she sees
as problems with an art practice invested in freedom, immediacy, difference, contingency,
and so forth. For Beech, besides this critique of typical operating procedures and logics of
contemporary art, at stake is the outlining of a different practice – or science – of the image,
one which embraces its representational/mediatory character in its own kind of ‘criticalpolitical project’; or, in the terms of Laruelle’s own ‘non-differential space of the generic
matrix’: ‘What is the distinction between the paradigm of art as we know it, and another
category of art that we could imagine in this new configuration?’ (Beech 2014: 15).
18
presentations, one a piece of fiction the other a performance (though each partaking of
the other), were somewhat different to the previous papers. Indeed, if the latter had
generally been about fiction as method (albeit involving creative as well as critical
approaches) – here, in both of these last contributions to the conference, we were
presented with fiction as method itself. With both it was as if the whole conference
assemblage had somehow tipped – and phase shifted – from being ‘about’ the real, to
being ‘of’ (or alongside) it.
For myself this experience resonates with the radical immanence of non-philosophy.
Indeed, as I also mentioned above, there is something surprising and yet, at the same
time obvious, about Laruelle’s idea of a form of thought that is from the real rather
than yet another interpretation of it. As I hope I have made clear art practice is often
involved in this other kind of presentation. The conference, however, made the
difference between the two perspectives – or gestures – suddenly very apparent.
Indeed, performance in general has this quality of producing difference through a cut.
It is non-representation par excellence insofar as – in its very liveness – it offers an
‘experience’ of life ‘outside’ representation.18 However, there is also the question here
as to whether at least some kind of minimal framing is required to make it art, or else
it becomes ‘just life’ (this, again, is the edge that Kaprow traverses). In fact, it seems
to me that a life might well need some framing – a performance as it were – in order
that it be taken out of the frame it is usually experienced/perceived within (or, again,
what Laruelle calls the world). Counter-intuitively art practice, as performance, can
be more real than life because it is framed (at least minimally).
To return to the models and fictions referred to in my essay, we might say that the
latter are ways of side stepping more typical (often unseeable) frames of reference.
This is art practice as the production of fictions that allow – almost as side effect – for
a glimpse of the real (or, to refer back to the conference, it is the difference between
the two fictional worlds (our typical world and the world an art practice can present)
that allows for a bit of the real to leak through). Again, unless a fiction is produced the
danger is that a practice just presents a piece of the world as it is, a slice of already
existing reality that surrounds us on a day-to-day basis (as is the case with art
practices that simply archive the existing without transforming it). It is then through
the performance of a fiction that art can foreground the always already fictional status
of a world it is different from.
vi. The fiction of a self
18
Performance, as Tero Nauha has articulated, can be a practice that is alongside the real and
as such, might be thought of as an ‘advent’ (as oppose too an event that gets ‘recaptured’ by
philosophy). Nauha also makes a convincing case, following Laruelle, for performance as a
heretical practice (pitched against the ‘law’ of representation) (see Nauha 2016).
19
Performance art aside, it seems to me that non-philosophy is also at its most
interesting and compelling when it is thought in relation to a life that is lived
differently, or in terms of what Michel Foucault once called (though for different
reasons) ‘life as a work of art’. This is to ‘apply’ non-philosophy to expanded
practices beyond the gallery, but also to think about aesthetic practices in more
general terms, in relation to what Guattari once called the production of subjectivity
(and the expanded ethico-aesthetic paradigm that is implied by this).
Indeed, as I have gestured towards above, we might want to ask whether the very
structure of typical subjectivity – and of a ‘self’ – is not itself the product of a certain
philosophical decision (broadly construed), one that is lived on a day to day basis.19 A
non-philosophical take on subjectivity will involve a diagnosis of such a positioning
(again, typical subjectivity), but, for myself, more interesting is that it might point to
the possibility of being in the world without a fixed sense of a typical self (with all the
attendant issues this can bring). Laruelle seems to be suggesting something similar in
his ‘A New Presentation of Non-Philosophy’, not least when he suggests that nonphilosophy might be the only ‘chance for an effective utopia’.20
This is to live a life away from those forms that have caught and restrict it: it is to
refuse philosophy, especially in its key operation of producing the fiction of a
(separate) self – or, rather, its positing of the latter as not a fiction but as a truth (the
self as product of a certain decision and auto-positioning that is then occluded, hidden
from that subject). Non-philosophy might then be about untethering the self from its
auto-positioning, its own enthronement.
In fact, it seems to me, that what follows from this ‘insight’ is not the ‘dissolving’ of
the self, but, we might say, a holding of it in a lighter, more contingent manner – as,
precisely, a fiction (and, insofar as the self is the anchor point for numerous other
fictions, then these, too, are seen as fictions). Crucially, this might also mean the
possibility of producing other fictions of the self (or other fictions of non-self), and,
19
Paul Smith writes well on how a certain decisional structure produces the philosophical
subject (as separate from an object – the real – that it cannot know accept through itself) and
how the non-philosophical subject – as ‘force-of-thought’ – might be understood, instead, as
always already a part of, or a clone, of the real (see Paul-Smith 2016: 45-61).
20
The relevant quote:
…non-philosophy is also related to Gnosticism and science-fiction; it answers their
fundamental question – which is not at all philosophy's primary concern – ‘Should
humanity be saved? And how?’ And it is also close to spiritual revolutionaries such
as Müntzer and certain mystics who skirted heresy. When all is said and done, is nonphilosophy anything other than the chance for an effective utopia? (Laruelle 2004: n.
p.)
20
with that, the exploration of other ways of being in the world.21 Although there is not
the space here to go in to Laruelle’s own writings on this other kind of subject, we
might note his concept of the ‘generic human’, but also of the ‘stranger’, that names
this ‘radical ordinariness’ that is nevertheless at odds with the world (and which we
always already are up and above any ‘assumed’ subjectivity).
One of the other key thinkers in relation to this area is the neuroscientist and
philosopher Thomas Metzinger and his thesis of the ‘ego tunnel’ as productive of
what he calls the ‘myth’ of the self (Metzinger 2011). But we might also turn to
Brassier’s recent writings on a certain kind of ‘nemocentric’ subject that is ‘produced’
through neuroscientific understandings of our place in the world: in both cases it is a
question of exploring a kind of non-subject whose processes of re-presenting the
world (or modelling) are ‘transparent’ rather than opaque (Brassier 2011).22 A subject
who, in the words of Georges Bataille, is in the world like ‘water in water’.23
A compelling question – that I have gestured towards throughout my essay – is what
this terrain ‘outside’ the self might be like and if, indeed, it can be explored. Mackay
writes well on this discovery of the generic ‘beneath’ the subject produced by
philosophy and how we might begin to experience and experiment with it (for it is not
a given, but, to echo Deleuze and Guattari, needs to be constructed, piece by piece)
(Mackay 2012). Indeed, it seems to me that it is with this grand vision of the work of
non-philosophy that we begin to see the more profound connections with – and
radical implications for – what might be call a non-art practice. This then is the
experimental exploration, but also construction and performance, of new worlds and
new kinds of non-subjects adequate and appropriate to them. Or, more simply: fiction
as method.
Works cited:
Bataille, Georges (1989), Theory of Religion, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Zone
Books).
Beech, Amanda (2014), ‘Art and its “Science”’, Speculative Aesthetics, eds. Robin
Mackay, Luke Pendrell and James Trafford (Falmouth: Urbanomic).
21
I attend to this, in relation to psychedelic drugs, Buddhism and neuroscience, in my article
on ‘Myth-Science and the Fiction of the Self’ (O’Sullivan 2017c).
22
For a discussion of Brassier’s nemocentric subject and, indeed, the relation of a renewed
Prometheanism to a (renewed) definition of the human that is also at stake in Reza
Negarestani’s recent work, see my ‘Accelerationism, Prometheanism and Mythotechnesis’
(O’Sullivan 2016d).
23
Bataille is writing about the animal here, the full quote being: ‘every animal is in the world
like water in water’ (Bataille 1989: 19, 23, 25). Brassier’s account involves something
different; a working through, we might say, of future possibilities of the human (rather than
any regression to animality), albeit, interestingly, the two states resonate.
21
Brassier, Ray (2003), ‘Axiomatic Heresy’, Radical Philosophy, 121,
Brassier, Ray (2007), Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction (Bssingstoke:
Palgrave).
Brassier, Ray (2011), ‘The View from Nowhere’, Identities: Journal of Politics,
Gender and Culture, 8.2, 7-23.
Burrows, David (2010), ‘Performance Fictions’, Metamute, available at:
http://www.metamute.org/editorial/articles/performance-fictions (accessed 7 January
2017).
Deleuze, Gilles (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York:
Columbia University Press).
Deleuze, Gilles (2011), ‘Immanence: A Life’, Pure Immanence: Essays on A Life,
trans. Anne Boyman (New York: Zone Books).
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1994) What is Philosophy?, trans. H. Tomlinson and G.
Burchell (London: Verso).
Laruelle, François (1993), ‘Fragments of an Anti-Guattari’, available at:
https://linguisticcapital.files.wordpress.com/2013/03/laruelle_fragments-of-an-antiguattari.pdf (accessed 7 January 2017).
Laruelle, François (2004), ‘A New Presentation of Non-Philosophy’, available at:
http://www.onphi.net/texte-a-new-presentation-of-non-philosophy-32.html (accessed
7 January 2017).
Laruelle, François (2011), ‘What is Seen In a Photo?’, The Concept of NonPhotography (Falmouth/New York: Urbanomic/Sequence Press), pp. 1-28.
Laruelle, François (2012a), ‘I, the Philosopher, Am Lying’: a Reply to Deleuze’,
trans. Taylor Adkins, Ray Brassier and Sid Littlefield, The Non-Philosophy Project:
Essays by François Laruelle, ed. Gabriel Alkon and Boris Gunjevic (New York:
Telos), pp. 40-74.
Laruelle, François (2012b), From Decision to Heresy: Experiments in Non-Standard
Thought (Falmouth/New York: Urbanomic/Sequence Press).
Laruelle, François (2012c), ‘Photo-Fiction, A Theoretical Installation’, Photo-Fiction:
a Non-Standard Aesthetics, trans. Drew S. Burk (Minneapolis: Univocal), pp. 11-24.
22
Mackay, Robin (2012), ‘Introduction: Laruelle Undivided’, From Decision to Heresy:
Experiments in Non-Standard Thought (Falmouth: Urbanomic), pp. 1-32.
Malik, Suhail (2017), On the Necessity of Art's Exit from Contemporary Art
(Falmouth: Urbanomic).
McGettigan, Andrew (2012), ‘Fabrication Defect: François Laruelle’s Philosophical
Materials’, Radical Philosophy, 175, 33-42.
Metzinger, Thomas (2009), The Ego Tunnel: the Science of the Mind and the Myth of
the Self (new York: Basic Books).
Nauha, Tero (2016), Schizoproduction: Artistic Research and Performance in the
Context of Immanent Capitalism (Helsinki: University of the Arts).
Ó Maoilearca, John and Anthony Paul Smith (2012), ‘Introduction: The NonPhilosophical Inversion: Laruelle’s Knowledge Without Domination’, Laruelle and
Non-Philosophy, eds. John Mullarkey and Anthony Paul Smith (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press), pp. 1-18.
Ó Maoilearca, John (2015), All Thoughts are Equal: Laruelle and Nonhuman
Philosophy (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press).
O’Sullivan, Simon (2012), On the Production of Subjectivity: Five Diagrams of the
Finite-Infinite Relation (Basingstoke: Palgrave).
O’Sullivan, Simon (2017a), ‘Memories of a Deleuzian: To Think is Always to Follow
the Witches Flight’, A Thousand Plateaus and Philosophy, eds. Henry Somers-Hall,
Jeff Bell and James Williams (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).
O’Sullivan, Simon (2017b), ‘ From Science Fiction to Science Fictioning: SF’s
Traction on the Real’, Foundation: The International Review of Science Fiction.
O’Sullivan, Simon (2017c), ‘Myth-Science and the Fiction of the Self’, Subjectivity,
forthcoming.
O’Sullivan, Simon (2017c), ‘Accelerationism, Prometheanism and Mythotechnesis’,
Aesthetics after Finitude, eds. Amy Ireland, Baylee Brits and Prudence Gibson
(Melbourne: re:press).
Paul Smith, Anthony (2016), François Laruelle’s Principles of Non-Philosophy: A
Critical Introduction and Guide (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).
23
Srnicek, Nick (2011), ‘Capitalism and the Non-Philosophical Subject’, The
Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism, ed. Levi Bryant, Nick
Srnicek and Graham Harman (Melbourne, re.press, 2011), pp. 164-81.
Tilford, Keith (n.d.), ‘Laruelle, Art and the Scientific Model’, available at:
http://keithtilford.com/wp-content/uploads/2015/05/Tilford_Keith.pdf (accessed 7
January 2017).