Chapter 15
1
Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review
of the New Moralisms
Paul Macneill
2
3
L.15
CHANGE:
‘4,’ TO ‘4;’
4
Introduction The relation of the arts and ethics “has been a recurrent and central
concern” in Western culture from the early Greeks through to the present and
continues to be of concern to philosophers, artists, writers, politicians and the public
[9, p. 5]. Tolstoy’s polemical essay What is Art? (first published in 1897) argues that
art is essentially moral, if not spiritual. Great art could only be created by someone
who stands on a “level of the highest world outlook of his time.” It “should eliminate
violence” and make accessible “feelings of brotherhood and love of one’s neighbour”
[22, p. 90 & p. 166]. Although his is an extreme view, it was influential in his time.1
At the other extreme (and derided by Tolstoy) are those who claim that art and
ethics are autonomous—a view that can be traced back to philosopher Immanuel
Kant’s formalism in separating ethics and aesthetics [4, 6, p. 356]. Although there
are variants of autonomism (or formalism)—such as ‘Art for Art’s sake’—all of
them claim that morality is irrelevant to an assessment of the quality of the work of
art as art [14, p. 157]. Autonomism held sway in the arts, and within the philosophy
of art, for some time.
In the last 20 years interest in a relationship between ethics and the arts has been
revived by philosophers of art who argue that it is appropriate to judge some works
of art by moral standards. Jacobson describes this as the rise of a “Humean-style
moralism” in that many of its advocates develop their positions with reference to
Hume’s essay ‘Of the Standard of Taste’ (1757) [14]. Although Hume argues for
tolerance in judging the quality of a work of art from another era, he is relatively
1
For example: Tolstoy’s view influenced Stanislavsky. See Chap. 5.
P. Macneill (*)
Centre for Biomedical Ethics, Yong Loo Lin School of Medicine, National University
of Singapore, 21 Lower Kent Ridge Rd, Singapore, Singapore
Centre for Values, Ethics & the Law in Medicine, Sydney Medical School, The University
of Sydney, Sydney, Australia
e-mail:
[email protected] email:
[email protected]
P. Macneill (ed.), Ethics and the Arts, DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-8816-8_15,
© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014
167
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
168
P. Macneill
31
intolerant in upholding standards of “morality and decency.” For Hume, regardless
of the age, “where vicious manners are described, without being marked with the
proper characters of blame and disapprobation; this must be allowed to disfigure the
poem, and to be a real deformity” [12]. Many of the current commentators broadly
agree with Hume that expressions of morality may be a ‘deformity’ in some artworks,
although they distinguish their positions from Hume in various ways.
32
15.1
33
Noël Carroll, one of the leading advocates in this field, accepts as a minimum that
“there are intimate relations between at least some art and morality that call for
philosophical comment.” He argues this in opposition to those who claim that
morality and art are autonomous spheres of interest. Carroll identifies two forms of
autonomism: radical and moderate. ‘Radical autonomism’ is the position that “art
is a strictly autonomous realm of practice. It is distinct from other social realms
which pursue cognitive, political or moral value [and as such] it is inappropriate or
even incoherent to assess artworks in terms of their consequences for cognition,
morality and politics.” ‘Moderate autonomism’ is the view that whilst an artwork
may “traffic in aesthetic, moral, cognitive and political value… these various levels
are independent or autonomous… from other dimensions, such as the moral dimension.” It may be appropriate to comment on these attributes, but any evaluation of
the political effectiveness, or moral appropriateness of a work of art “is never relevant to its aesthetic evaluation” [1, p. 224 & p. 231; 20, p. 68].
Carroll develops a position he terms ‘moderate moralism.’ His claim is that
moral issues may be so central to the structure of some works of art, and particularly
those of a narrative kind, that the treatment of these issues is critical to assessing the
aesthetic quality of the work of art. Carroll adds that he “does not contend that artworks should always be evaluated morally, nor that every moral defect or merit in
an artwork should figure in its aesthetic evaluation.” He recognises that the moral
dimension of a work of art may not be recognised at the time and in the culture when
the work is first available. A highly regarded novel may go with no critique of its
racist assumptions when first published. Nevertheless “even where given audiences
do not detect the moral flaws in question, the artwork may still be aesthetically
flawed, since in those cases the moral flaws sit like time-bombs, ready to explode
aesthetically once morally sensitive viewers, listeners and readers encounter them”
[1, p. 236 & p. 234]. This point can be illustrated by Leni Riefenstahl’s Triumph of
the Will which is a documentary, set in Nuremberg in 1934, of a rally of the National
Socialist Workers’ Party. Many critics regard the film as a masterpiece,2 and it won
26
27
28
29
30
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
The New ‘Moralisms’
2
Devereaux regards Triumph of the Will as “masterful” [5, p. 231], Sontag as “superb” [21, p. 320],
and Kieran acknowledges the film’s “numbing beauty” [16, p. 347]. Carroll himself disagrees:
“Regardless of its moral standing, the film is aesthetically botched. It is uneven and ultimately
boring. It is not the best example for the current debate” [3, p. 83; 2, pp. 379–381].
15 Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review of the New Moralisms
169
awards in Germany, Venice and Paris in the late 1930s [5, p. 230]. Yet its staging of
Hitler and the Nazi party as heroic and powerful has, in hindsight, been seen as Nazi
propaganda and regarded (at least by Devereaux) as “morally repugnant.” Devereaux
concludes that “the highest aesthetic praise” should be withheld “from works of art
that present as beautiful, attractive, and good” when on reflection they “can be seen
to be evil” [5, p. 227 & p. 250]. These rallies were spectacular displays of flags,
uniforms and weapons, set within cathedrals of light. Hitler and Speer were deliberate in making an aesthetic link between triumph and terror. This larger context must
raise moral concern, and—from the perspective of moralism—is a factor in assessing
the aesthetic value of this film.
Berys Gaut, another of the advocates in this field, has a similar view to Carroll on
the relationship of art and morality and agrees that a moral assessment of some
artworks has a bearing on the aesthetic quality of those works. For Gaut “an artwork
has an aesthetic merit in so far as it possesses an ethical merit that is aesthetically
relevant” [9, p. 10; 8, p. 439]. He has developed his position, which he terms ‘ethicism,’ into a theory that aims to account for the conditions under which morality
relates to aesthetics. In more exact terms: “Ethicism holds that a work is aesthetically flawed in so far as it possesses an aesthetically relevant ethical flaw and aesthetically meritorious in so far as it possess an aesthetically relevant ethical merit.
The ethical flaws referred to are intrinsic ethical flaws… Intrinsic ethical flaws are
ethical flaws in the attitudes that works manifest towards their subjects. So ethicism
holds that works are aesthetically flawed in so far as they exhibit aesthetically relevant ethical flaws in their manifested attitudes” [9, p. 229]. The formulation is
worded in this careful way to defend ‘ethicism’ from any charge of simple moralism, and to specify that the relevant moral quality relates to the attitude displayed in
an artwork toward its subject, not simply because a work of art explores immoral
themes, events and attitudes. What is important for Gaut is whether or not the ‘manifest author’ (the author apparent in the artwork—not necessarily the narrator) celebrates, or appears to approve of immoral behaviour and attitudes in a way that is
apparently “aiming morally to corrupt its audience.” The prime examples of immoral
art of this kind (to which Gaut often returns) are Marquis de Sade’s novels which are
“ethically sick because of the attitudes they display of approving of, celebrating,
making positive judgements about and aiming to get their readers to enjoy the
sexual torture and multifarious degradation of the characters who suffer through
their pages” [9, p. 10].
Gaut advances three arguments for his ethicism: ‘moral beauty’; an argument
based on ‘cognitivist’ values of art; and a ‘merited response’ argument. His moral
beauty claim follows Plato, St Augustine and Hume (among many) who perceived
virtue as beauty. Gaut regards virtue as a “beautiful character trait” and, conversely,
moral vice as “an ugly character trait.” This links to the aesthetic value of an artwork
in that, “If a manifest author has a morally good character, it follows from the moral
beauty view that… the work has a beautiful aspect, in so far as the author has a beautiful character” [9, p. 120 & p. 127]. Gaut’s second argument, which draws on ‘cognitivist’ values of art, recognises that artworks may display insight and understanding
about the world, or insights into character, or moral understanding. They may well
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
170
P. Macneill
127
teach their audiences, and audiences may learn something from them. This is a
central value of art from a humanist perspective. Knowledge gained from art could
be propositional, or practical (as ‘know-how’), or phenomenal (in other words, experiential). It might also be ‘affective-cognitive’ in conveying knowledge about the
emotions in certain situations and it may lead to empathy, or manifest as appreciating “how to feel” in particular contexts. The argument is that an artwork is, “aesthetically good in so far as it manifests aesthetically relevant moral understanding (and
conversely for aesthetic badness and moral misunderstanding or failures to understand)” [9, pp. 136–138]. Carroll makes a similar point that artworks may contribute
(positively or negatively) to our moral understanding although not necessarily by
teaching something new, but by learning “how to apply those precepts to situations”
and by “deepening or enlarging our emotional understanding.” Where this occurs,
it is “natural and appropriate” for this to influence our evaluation of the work of art
[1, pp. 29–30]. Gaut’s third support for ethicism is the ‘merited response argument.’
He argues that “prescribed responses in a work of art are not always merited. One
way in which they can be unmerited is in being unethical. If the prescribed responses
are unmerited, that is a failure in the work” which may be an aesthetic defect when
the prescribed response is of aesthetic relevance [9, p. 233]. For example, if an
artwork endorses taking pleasure in the gratuitous suffering of others, that amounts
to both an ethical and an aesthetic defect, and establishes a further basis for relating
morality to any aesthetic evaluation of the quality of artworks.
128
15.2
129
One of the challenges to both Carroll and Gaut is the argument that ‘immoral’ works
of art may be worthy precisely because of the manner in which the immoral subject
is explored aesthetically. Jacobson’s paper ‘In praise of Immoral Art’ argues that
“What is properly deemed a moral defect in a work of art can contribute positively
and ineliminably to its aesthetic value” [14, p. 162]. He takes an opposing view of
Leni Riefenstahl’s Triumph of the Will (as it is discussed above) in stating that “the
moral defects of the flim are not aesthetic blemishes, because they are inseparable
from the work’s aesthetic value.” He claims that, “Like all the best immoral art, this
film is incorrigible: it can’t be sanitized… it can only be expurgated.” Jacobson is in
“broad sympathy with the idea that… narrative, art can significantly contribute to
something like moral understanding” but he questions the assumption that this can
occur by “acquaintance with morally felicitous perspectives only.” In a world in
which “many people are in the grips of some error… we need to know what they
think and why” [14, pp. 192–193; 15, p. 347]. Carroll, in responding to these arguments, allows that a “moral defect in an artwork might sometimes contribute to the
positive aesthetic value of an artwork,” but not in the case of Triumph of the Will.
At best one could argue that “its cinematic virtues vastly outweigh whatever aesthetic costs its moral defectiveness incurs” [2, pp. 380–381]. Hamilton (in line with
Jacobson) does not accept that a work is “aesthically flawed” if it is “morally
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
Challenges to ‘Moralism’: Immoral Works of Art
15 Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review of the New Moralisms
171
line: 155
objectionable” and he cites a number of “morally reprehensible”
artworks which are
AFTER:
“aesthetically all the better: for it makes them sparkle and ‘understanding’
crackle with life and
energy.” Nor would an argument that immoral art leads peopleADD:
to behave
‘of’ in morally
represensible ways (assuming that could be demonstrated) be relevant to the aesthetic value of the work [10, pp. 44–48].3 Kieran claims that there may be a benefit
from opening to ‘immoral’ art. However, rather than seeing this as a fundamental
challenge to Gaut’s ethicisim, he proposes ‘immoralism’ as a qualification to the
cognitivist conception of art. When an immoral work enhances our understanding
an immoral attribute, it inverts from a negative to a positive contribution to aesthetic
quality. As he puts it, “Where there is a cognitive pay off in virtue of the immoral
character of a work, and this is sufficient to outweigh our reluctance to indulge in
the responses sought from us, then the immoral character of the work turns out to be
an artistic virtue rather than a vice. A morally problematic work can thus, artistically speaking, redeem itself” [17, p. 138]. Jacobson “is amenable to this account of
aesthetic value” but he does not limit the assessment of art to “such purely instrumental effects of a work.” Rather it is “the significance of the aesthetic experience
itself—what the artists can get us to see, think, and feel—that matters” [15, p. 353].
Both Jacobson and Kieran draw a distinction between our responses to events in
life and toward similar events portrayed in movies and literature. Jacobson thinks it
is “patently absurd” to say we respond to fiction in same way as we do to real life
[14, p. 186]. Kieran concurs and illustrates the distinction between life and fiction
by our enjoyment of gangster movies, our capacity to sympathise with murderers
(for example in the novel The Postman Always Rings Twice), and the way we accept
the “cruelties or downright unfairness [of] comedies and satires.” Nor is this relaxation of our moral prohibitions limited to works of art. It is a feature of our imaginative activities that we sometimes “allow our moral scruples to go on holiday” for
example in indulging in sexual fantasies. Kieran’s point is that “the fictional or
make-believe context of a work allows us to engage with and enjoy putatively
immoral imaginative activity.” This leaves us “free to contemplate events portrayed
as we could or would not were the events themselves real.” Crucial however is
“knowing whether or not something is fictional” [17, pp. 134–136].
Hamilton has expressed concern about the tendency of theoretical approaches
(and Gaut’s theory in particular) to reduce the complexity of aesthetic and moral
qualities [10, pp. 47–48]. For similar reasons Jacobson takes a strong “antitheoretical view of the relation between moral and aesthetic value” arguing that
there is a false dichotomy between moralism and autonomism in that these positions
“fail to exhaust the philosophical possibilities on the relation between moral and
aesthetic value in works of art.” He contends that there is “no true theory of the relation between moral and aesthetic value” that adequately includes all possible artworks [15, pp. 342–343 & p. 346]. There may be a relationship in some cases, but
3
Gaut, for different reasons, does not rely on the “causal effects” of artworks in relating morality
to aesthetics [9, p. 10]. He does acknowledge however that “ethicism kicks away a prop” of anticensorship [9, p. 12]. He allows that his moralist position lends potential support to censors and
those who would curtail dissemination of artworks.
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
172
P. Macneill
193
the evaluations are complex and better discussed as part of any critique of a particular
work of art. Kieran disagrees with Jacobson’s “anti-theory approach” from a concern that it “seems to be a restatement of the problem rather than a solution to it.”
He (along with Gaut) claims that “we are owed some kind of account as to how and
why the relationship can go differently in distinct cases” [17, p. 138]. He takes this
further in justifying a need for theory and, in particular, Gaut’s ‘ethicism.’
194
15.3
195
Gaut has rejected both Jacobson’s anti-theory and Kieran’s qualification to ethicism,
maintaining his view that an aesthetically relevant moral flaw in a work is always an
aesthetic blemish. If an artwork asks the reader to “to take up an immoral attitude”
and “presents an immoral state of affairs as morally good” then the “attitude is
immoral” and the work fails to teach us anything about immorality since what it
presents is false [9, p. 185]. Whilst this stringent position appears “overly moralistic,” Gaut demonstrates that it can be applied sensitively [17, p. 135]. His review of
Nabakov’s Lolita is a perceptive and nuanced account that illustrates how some,
seemingly immoral works, are actually moral when the (manifest) author’s intentions are understood more comprehensively and subtly. The novel’s narrator,
Humbert Humbert, seeks to engage the reader’s sympathy for his child sex with
Lolita, and his justifications for killing Quilty, Lolita’s would-be lover. Gaut demonstrates Nabokov’s skill in developing the novel as an ethical journey over the 56 days
of Humbert’s ‘memoir.’ He also traces carefully Nabokov’s use of a double seduction
of the reader: first in persuading the reader to have sympathy for Humbert and (through
him) to vicariously enjoy sex with a child; and secondly in seducing the reader into
going along with Humbert (to some extent) in his justification for killing Quilty. His
conclusion is that “the novel’s deployment of these strategies does teach us, via a
particularly rich example, something about the complexity of moral and psychological judgement, of the need for fine discriminations of feeling and judgement, and of
the seductive powers of art.” He makes the broader claim that his ‘ethicism’ highlights aesthetic features of this and other works “that morally neutral critical methods
discern only dimly, if at all.” [9, pp. 194–202]. An advantage, it seems to me, of
Gaut’s insistence that this is not an immoral work, is in underscoring the identity of
the ‘moral view point’ with the “manifested author.” [9, p. 197 & p. 195]. This allows
Gaut to distinguish Lolita from other cases, such de Sade’s novels or Leni
Riefenstahl’s Triumph of the Will, where there is no redeeming feature in the
manifest author’s attitude. Nevertheless, this does appear as something of a quibble
in that Kieran can arrive at the same end by justifying ‘immoral’ aspects of this
book in terms of the cognitive value of what the author has to teach. Gaut’s critique
of Lolita, has also added complexity to his ‘merited response argument.’ To the
extent that Nabokov’s is successful in leading the reader into vicariously enjoying
sex with a child, and going along with Humbert in his justification for killing Quilty,
it could be said that he has induced ‘unmerited’ responses. In defending ‘ethicisim’
188
189
190
191
192
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
[AU1]
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
‘Ethicism’ and Its Critics
15 Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review of the New Moralisms
173
from this charge, Gaut points to “a characteristic pattern of enjoyment and recoil”
by which “we are shown that we can be seduced to take a kind of enjoyment in
something that we simultaneously abhor.” He distinguishes between these as ‘lowerorder’ and ‘higher-order’ prescriptions. The first response of enjoyment is “apparently prescribed” whereas the second is a “very different attitude” that is “really
manifested by the work.” Abhorrence triumphs as the overall attitude of the book
and as the ‘merited response’ [9, p. 197, pp. 230–231].
Jacobson points to an ambiguity in the word ‘merited’ when a prescribed
response is judged as ‘unmerited.’ It could mean that it ‘lacks propriety’ in the sense
that it might be inappropriate to laugh at a joke because it is racist or sexist; or it
could mean a response is not prudential or strategic, in terms of how others might
see one, or because one’s laughter would disturb others. Alternatively ‘unmerited’
could mean ‘unwarranted’ in the sense that laughter is not warranted because the
joke is not funny. His point is that Gaut conflates these terms and that the argument
that ‘prescribing an unmerited response is an aesthetic failure in the work’ relies on
this conflation. Only an ‘unwarranted’ response is relevant to the aesthetic quality
of an artwork. But to argue that an unwarranted response reflects on the aesthetic
merit of an artwork presupposes that the aesthetic quality of the work does not warrant that response: which begs the question of the work’s aesthetic value [14, pp.
170–179; 15, pp. 349–350].4 Gaut replies that a response may be warranted, but
nevertheless morally wrong. For example he does not deny that “people who took
pleasure in watching public decapitations during the French Revolution enjoyed
what was going on” (in other words their pleasure may have been warranted) but he
asserts that they were morally wrong to have done so [9, pp. 237–239]. This can
only mean that the ‘merited response argument’ is undermined as an argument necessarily linking morality to aesthetics and is exposed as a simple moral assertion:
that moral criteria are relevant in judging the appropriateness of a prescribed
response. Jacobson disagrees and insists that it is sufficient for the response to be
warranted. This is to ask: ‘Why should we relegate a work because it leads us into a
“wicked” or “morally offensive” perspective, when wickedness may be the work’s
aesthetic feature?’
Guat’s ‘moral beauty’ argument also appears anaemic following his critique of
Lolita. Is Nabokov (as ‘manifest author’) a morally virtuous and (therefore) a beautiful person? Or, to take a different novel, is Truman Capote, as ‘manifest author’ of
In Cold Blood, beautiful in this sense? These concerns seem irrelevant to the aesthetic worth of these works. Both authors manifest as gritty, resourceful, and masterful. These are not obviously moral qualities although they are aesthetic.
Admittedly ethicism does not require that all three of Gaut’s rationales function in
all morally commendable (or morally reprehensible) artworks. I also accept that an
observation that a “manifest author has a morally good character” may be relevant
in reviewing the quality of a particular artwork, but as a ground for linking morality
with ethics in a generic theory, it is insubstantial. There is a related concern that the
significance of the argument depends on a strict distinction between virtue and
4
The argument is petitio principii and, as such, a logical fallacy.
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
174
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
P. Macneill
beauty. This is to suggest that Gaut is overly categorical in defining qualities as
moral or aesthetic. There is an ambiguity, which Hamilton points to because “the
ethical and aesthetic often interpenetrate in a way which disables us from distinguishing them.” He believes that, “Gaut, like many other theorists, misses the point
because he often talks as if it is perfectly clear just what the moral import of a work
of art is. And if one wants to reason why this is so, the answer… is that he has a
strong tendency to operate with a simplified and narrow conception of morality,
according to which it is clear what is morally good and what morally bad [such as]
hurting others, refusing equal treatment” [10, pp. 45–46, p.48]. This is an aspect of
a more general concern that ethicism makes simplified and narrow assumptions
about both morality and art. Jacobson is similarly concerned about a tendency to be
“morally correct in some final way” which he associates with “Hume and the
Humean moralists.” His concern is that, in “championing the ethical criticism of
art,” they are unavoidably evaluating artworks in light of their “own moral commitments” [14, p. 160].
Hamilton resists Gaut’s ethicism as “surely far too strong” and simplistic. He is
sceptical of cognitivist claims that art gives us moral knowledge and, even in those
cases “where a work of art does effect a clarification in our moral thinking,” he sees
no good reason for assuming that this understanding will be “friendly to morality.”
It may lead one to hostility to morality or to despairing of other people. Alternatively
a reader may reserve all her sensitivity for fictional characters with little effect on
how she treats people in life. Nor is there any evidence that artists, or people who
regard the arts as important, are morally advanced although, “our knowledge of
art can easily flatter us into thinking it makes us morally better people.” When art
does appear to contribute to moral education, it is just as likely that this observation relates to people who were already sensitive to moral concerns [10, p. 39 &
pp. 43–44]. Jacobson identifies a core problem with moralism in Hume’s confident
statement that, when a work describes “vicious manners” without attributing
“blame and disapprobation,” then “I cannot, nor is it proper I should, enter into
such sentiments” [12]. This indicates a “muddle over the distinction between psychological and normative claims [that] has infected Humean moralism from its
beginnings.” Effectively, what one can feel or should feel becomes a barrier to
entry and may preclude any assessment of an artwork’s aesthetic value in the same
way as the “high price of opera tickets.”5 The difficulty is that one’s inability or
refusal may be a “false delicacy” resulting from “prejudice or a failure of imagination.” There has been a “litany of works condemned as immoral” (including
Ulysses, Huckleberry Finn, and Lolita) which “have always seemed indisputably
corrupt to their critics.” Nevertheless Jacobson steps back from concluding that
“built-in obstacles to the appreciation of a work never bear on its aesthetic value”
[14, pp. 187–191 & p. 168].
5
Carroll also discusses the point that if an artwork is “inaccessible to that person, he is in no
position to judge the work aesthetically” [2, p. 379].
15 Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review of the New Moralisms
175
Discussion This discussion of a relationship between the arts and ethics,
re-energised by ‘Humean-style’ moralism, has raised differing ideas about the
strength and nature of moral evaluations in estimating the aesthetic value of a work
of art. Although it is conceded by all the discussants, that not all moral attributes are
relevant to a work’s aesthetic value, and that many non-moral attributes are also
contributors, the debate has focussed on moral merits and demerits. In the broader
context of appreciating artworks, we respond to moral, cognitive and affective
aspects from our own perception (rather than in the object as Hume maintains). It is
not that a work is morally admirable, intelligent, perceptive, and emotionally
soothing, but that we may find those qualities in it. It is possible to distinguish
between a moral response and a critical appraisal, and to make “fine discriminations
of feeling and judgement” [9, p. 201]. This includes the possibility of having moral
revulsion alongside critical admiration. The observation that one is strongly affected
by a work of art may be the basis for attributing an affective power to the work and
recognising this as an aesthetic value—even though one is shocked or morally
affronted by it.6 This approach provides a flexible basis on which to understand
differences in our responses along each of these dimensions within ourselves and to
understand differences of judgment between people (some of whom may have come
to similar evaluations but have given different weights to them). It is also a more
constructive way of understanding the issues between autonomists (or formalists)
and moralists. Formalists, such as Fry and Greenberg, were keen to promote
creativity and protect art from limitations on its freedom [19, pp. 3–8]. This was, in
effect, to give weight to a cognitive dimension. Moralism may have been a necessary
corrective to dogmatic assertions of formalism—by pointing to the relevance (in
some artworks) of moral assessments to aesthetic evaluation—but it runs a risk of
overemphasising the moral dimension.
One may find French novelist Michel Houellebecq’s Atomised to be morally
repugnant and observe that its affect is a sense of despair and meaninglessness
(at least for some readers) [11]. In the reflective process I am advocating, these
responses can be distinguished. Even if one is morally repulsed, the novel’s capacity
to engender despair and meaninglessness is an aesthetic experience—albeit an
uncomfortable one. From an intellectual perspective, the novel can be related to
broader cultural issues. It may have captured a sense of “our atomised society”
(as suggested by its cover) and Houellebecq could be seen as, “A lyric poet in the
era of late capitalism” [13]. The fact that Atomised has won awards may also be
considered relevant.7 In this process, no one aspect (moral, affective, or cognitive)
can be assumed, in advance, to trump another, and the relative weight that is given
to each of these factors is itself a part of the reflection on a particular artwork.
Inherent in this proposition is that one’s aesthetic evaluation is separate from the
6
This is to side with Jacobson in valuing “the significance of the aesthetic experience itself”
[15, p. 353].
7
It was winner of the Prix Novembre prize and the International IMPAC Dublin Literary Award.
Houellebecq’s most recent novel The Map and the Territory was awarded the Prix Goncourt in
2010.
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
line:356
P. Macneill
NOTE REMOVAL
OF ‘a ’
question of whether one ‘likes’ the work or not. One may recognise Atomised as
having aesthetic merit, for any of the above reasons, yet not be open to reading any
more of Houellebecq’s novels. Resistance remains an option. There may be insufficient ‘pay-off’ (à la Kieran) for enduring the experience. Furthermore, I suggest
that something like this process occurs in the public arena. Contrary to Hume’s
essay ‘Of the Standard of Taste’ (which gives a determination of aesthetic quality to
“men of delicate taste”) aesthetic evaluation, as a public reflection, is open to all in
a process of continuing revision [12]. Montale’s notion of a work of art having a
“second life” in “memory and everyday circulation” is a relevant aspect of this
reflection [18, p. 21]. Houellebecq’s oeuvre may be forgotten in time, or alternatively it may be seen as the beginning of an emerging genre in literature that
embraces life as banal emptiness, just as Duchamp’s ‘Fountain’8 was (in hindsight)
a significant moment in the history of art and part of a challenge to the idea of art as
an original object of beauty [7, p. 43].
Whilst general propositions about a relationship between morality and aesthetics
may be of assistance, I don’t believe that one theory can adequately capture this process. Bernard Williams, in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, argues against allencompassing ethical theories and notes that not all moral reflections require theory
[23, pp. 111–119]. Any relation between ethics and aesthetics is established in critical
assessments of individual works of art, as Jacobson insists [15, p. 333 & p.346].
Devereaux makes the same point (in discussing “beauty and evil”) that the general
issue “becomes real only insofar as it arises in particular cases” [5, p. 252]. Appeal to
an overall theory of a relation between art and ethics and may divert attention from
the particular moral propositions on which it relies and gives any evaluation an illusory substantiality. Jacobson has “nothing to say against a moralist who takes himself
simply to be expressing, or even evangelizing for, his own evaluative convictions…
the only cost of moralism is bad taste.” What he objects to are the “grander ambitions” of Humean moralists who “suggest that a there are features of our emotional
engagement with art [that] lend credence to their view.” This is most evident in ethicism which displays a Humean “rectitude of that moral standard”9 as if there is one
objective standard, and for all time, on which all rational people could agree. It
amounts to taking prior moral standards and applying them as criteria in assessing the
quality of art. Jacobson proposes a more open approach on the ground that “objectivity in ethical matters is less a view from nowhere than an ability to view things imaginatively from a variety of ethical perspectives” [14, pp. 160–161 & p. 193].
Eaton contends that, “Seeing a connection with aesthetics requires that one have
a different way of thinking about ethics.” From her perspective, ethics is not a prior
standard by which
Fn: to
8 judge aesthetics. Rather, the relationship is synchronous, with
neither aesthetics
nor ethics “causally or conceptually prior.” Ethics is “more like
CHANGE
choosing one story
over
than “making an ethical decision.” Acting ethically
Chap.
9’another”
TO:
“requires acts of‘Chap.
imaginative
exploration,”
reference to symbols, personal myth, and
4’
fable, rather than rules or a “sheaf of principles.” In this picture, art and ethics are
176
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
8
9
See Chap. 9.
Hume’s Essay [12].
15 Ethics and the Arts: A Critical Review of the New Moralisms
177
understood as “essentially intertwined” and defined in terms of each other [6].
This view is preferable to Hume’s moral rectitude. It provides a rich, imaginative,
and more nourishing understanding of both morality and aesthetics. It is flexible and
able to accommodate changes in the arts, and is preferable as an attitude that allows
for an open exploration of the relation between ethics and the arts.
393
Acknowledgement I am grateful to Emeritus Professor Miles Little for his thorough and helpful
review of earlier versions of this chapter, for his many suggestions, and in particular for proposing
a reflective approach to aesthetic evaluation as containing “something of the moral, something of the
cognitive, something of the intuitive.” Any errors and distortions in this work are, of course, mine.
398
399
400
401
References
402
1. Carroll, Noël. 1996. Moderate moralism. The British Journal of Aesthetics 36(3): 223–238.
2. Carroll, Noël. 2000. Art and ethical criticism: An overview of recent directions of research.
Ethics 110(2): 350–387.
3. Carroll, Noël. 2006. Ethics and aesthetics: Replies to Dickie, Stecker, and Livingston. The
British Journal of Aesthetics 46(1): 82–95.
4. Carroll, Noël. 2010. At the crossroads of ethics and aesthetics. Philosophy and Literature
34(1): 248–259.
5. Devereaux, Mary. 1998. Beauty and evil: The case of Leni Riefenstahl’s Triumph of the will.
In Aesthetics and ethics: Essays at the intersection, ed. J. Levinson, 227–256. Cambridge/New
York: Cambridge University Press.
6. Eaton, Marcia Muelder. 1997. Aesthetics: The mother of ethics? The Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism 55(4): 355–364.
7. Eaton, Marcia Muelder. 2006. Beauty and ugliness in and out of context. In Contemporary
debates in aesthetics and the philosophy of art, ed. M. Kieran, 39–50. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishing.
8. Gaut, Berys Nigel, and Dominic Lopes (eds.). 2005. The Routledge companion to aesthetics,
2nd ed. New York: Routledge.
9. Gaut, Berys Nigel. 2007. Art, emotion, and ethics. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
10. Hamilton, Christopher. 2003. Art and moral education. In Art and morality, ed. J.L. Bermúdez
and S. Gardner, 37–55. London/New York: Routledge.
11. Houellebecq, Michel. 2000. Atomised. London: Heinemann.
12. Hume, David, Stephen Copley, and Andrew Edgar. 1993. Selected essays, World’s classics.
Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
13. Jack, David. 2010. Michel Houellebecq: A lyric poet in the era of late capitalism. Colloquy
Text Theory Critique 19: 15–27.
14. Jacobson, Daniel. 1997. In praise of immoral art. Philosophical Topics 25(1): 155–199.
15. Jacobson, Daniel. 2006. Ethical criticism and the vice of moderation. In Contemporary debates
in aesthetics and the philosophy of art, 342–357. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
16. Kieran, Matthew. 1996. Art, imagination, and the cultivation of morals. The Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54(4): 337–351.
17. Kieran, Matthew. 2006. Art, morality and ethics: On the (im)moral character of art works and
inter-relations to artistic value. Philosophy Compass 1(2): 129–143.
18. Montale, Eugenio, and Jonathan Galassi. 1982. The second life of art: Selected essays
of Eugenio Montale, 1st ed. New York: Ecco Press.
19. Reeve, Charles Edward. 2000. Brushes with freedom: Painting and the ethics of formalism.
Ph.D. dissertation, Faculty of the Graduate School, Cornell University.
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
394
395
396
397
178
439
440
441
442
443
444
P. Macneill
20. Schellekens, Elisabeth. 2007. Aesthetics and morality, Continuum aesthetics. London/New
York: Continuum.
21. Sontag, Susan. 1982. A Susan Sontag reader. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux.
22. Tolstoy, Leo. 1995. What is art? Penguin classics. London: Penguin.
23. Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy, Fontana master guides. London:
Fontana Press.
Author Query
Chapter No.: 15
0002110106
Query
Details Required
AU1
Please check and confirm the name “Humbert
Text Humbert”
Author’s Response
Confirm
L.5
Please change ‘Introduction’ to the same style as Level 1 numbered headings
(but leave un-numbered).
Introduction
The relation of the arts . . .
L.15
CHANGE: ‘4,’ TO ‘4;’
Line: 155
AFTER: ‘understanding’ ADD: ‘of’
Line: 356
NOTE REMOVAL OF ‘a ’
Fn: 8
CHANGE ‘Chap. 9’ TO: ‘Chap. 4’
L.312
Please change ‘Discussion’ to the same style as Level 1 numbered headings
(but leave un-numbered).
Discussion
This discussion of a . . .