Academia.eduAcademia.edu

On David K. Lewis' Principal Principle and It's Inconsistency

An opposition to the problem in the Principal Principle as espoused by SEP, apparently intended as the meaning of Lewis' original use of the Principle.

ON DAVID K. LEWIS’ PRINCIPAL PRINCIPLE AND IT’S INCONSISTENCY David K. Lewis’ principal principle is essentially two things: (A) We know what we know, and (B) If we know a probability of what is uncertain, the probability still applies. However, according to the SEP, what follows from traditional (Aristotelian) logic after this is the logical proof that no systems theory successfully handles probability, and thus, according to the empiricists who have much strength right now, that no philosophy would be possible systematically. I will endeavor to set out a counter-proof, which I think is successful and moderately intuitive. First, the key assumptions of the argument from syllogistic reasoning are as follows: (A) If we do not know what we do not know, there is proof of not-knowing. (B) If we do know what we do know, but by probability, then there is no assurance of not-knowing, and thus, no proof can follow. Thus, if we do know what we know, no proof follows (no deductions). But, if we do not know what we do not know, then there is no proof of not-knowing (probability means nothing). The problem with this from a scientific standpoint is that it assumes we cannot know a probability. From a philosophical standpoint, however, we must know that we cannot know a probability, because probability by definition does not provide absolute proof of anything, that is, so long as probability ranges between 0 and 1 without ever reaching the extremes. {Concomitant of this is the view, which I favor, is that if there is some viewpoint, however absurd, from which something can be viewed as false, then that thing is not absolutely true, which seems to be close to the original meaning of Aristotelianism. Hence we should favor absolutism if we can.} Of course, what we can see now is that the problem with the principal principle is that it does not have an absolute sense of truth. And an absolute sense of truth cannot be provided by probability, we assume. At least, if we assume the principal principle is the highest epistemological concept, we cannot reach absolutes through its use. Another way to phrase the problem is ‘the problem of relative absoluteness’. And, of course, so long as relativism is seen as the opposite of absoluteness, there is no solution to this problem without combining the two concepts (relativism and absoluteness). This is the problem according to my own theory of formalism, which favors objective coherence, but is also analytic with a slant towards language theories. Clearly the only solution to relative absoluteness, if it is unsolvable, is still more relative absoluteness. So, relative absoluteness must be the solution! So, how do we solve the problem of the principal principle with relative absoluteness? The answer to this is that relative absoluteness simply is ‘relative relativism equals absoluteness’. The next problem is absolute absoluteness, which is unnecessary for solving probability, as numbers do not have content. Nathan Coppedge / SCSU 2016/11/29, p.