Letters to the Editors
www.AJOG .org
Redefining ethics in home birth
TO THE EDITORS: In a recent opinion piece, “Planned
home birth: the professional responsibility response,”
Chervenak et al1 argue against the ethics of home birthing
stating that advocates of planned home birth have emphasized 4 points: patient safety, patient satisfaction, costeffectiveness, and respect for women’s rights. “We provide a
critical evaluation of each of these claims and identify professionally appropriate responses of obstetricians and other
concerned physicians to planned home birth.”
Regarding patient safety, the authors say, “Maternal and
fetal necessity for transport during labor is often impossible
to predict.” Home birth women by definition are selected
based on their health. They labor as nature intended without
interventions. In experienced hands, transport is rarely
“impossible” to predict. The authors state the most common
reasons for transport are pain relief and prolonged labor,
neither being unsafe. The argument against home birth in the
United States continues by presenting safety data from South
Australia, a system that has no resemblance here.
The authors state, “It is antithetical to professional responsibility to intentionally assign any damaged or dead
pregnant, fetal, or neonatal patient to this category, even if
the number is small.” Yet ample evidence exists that similar
cohorts of normal women delivered out of hospital vs a hospital
have cesarean section rates of 6% and 24%,2 respectively.
By that standard the increased morbidity of the hospital model
if held to the same standard would be professionally
irresponsible.
Regarding patient satisfaction, the authors assume the high
rates of transport undercut the raison d’être of planned home
birth. A Dutch study from 2008 showing persistent levels
of frustration for up to 3 years in 17% of transported women
is cited.3 That implies an 83% satisfaction rate. A fairer
comparison would be the satisfaction rate of US women
with successful home vs hospital births. I disagree with the
solution of supporting “homebirth-like” environments in the
hospital setting.
Minimal savings in cost comparison data from Britain are
cited, vs US cost comparisons. The cost of a typical home
birth in the United States is about 35% of that in hospitals.
Savings over a cesarean birth approach 80%.4 When cesarean
section rates approaching 35%5 are factored in, the savings is
even more significant.
Regarding women’s rights, the authors avoid using the
beneficence-based model of ethics which, as with vaginal
birth after cesarean, supports a woman’s reasonable choice.6
Instead it is stated, “From the perspective of the professional
responsibility model, insistence on implementing the unconstrained rights of pregnant women to control the birth
location is an ethical error and therefore has no place in professional perinatal medicine.” But home birth advocates do not
support unconstrained rights or rights-based reductionism.-
Stuart James Fischbein, MD
Sanctuary Birth and Family Wellness Center
11965 Venice Blvd., Suite 307
Los Angeles, CA 90066
angelfi
[email protected]
The author reports no conflict of interest.
REFERENCES
1. Chervenak FA, McCullough LB, Brent RL, Levene MI, Arabin B.
Planned home birth: the professional responsibility response. Am J
Obstet Gynecol 2013;208:31-8.
2. Stapleton SR, Osborne C, Illuzzi J. Outcomes of care in birth centers:
demonstration of a durable model. J Midwifery Women Health 2013;58:
3-14.
3. Rijnders M, Baston H, Schonbeck Y, et al. Perinatal factors related to
negative or positive recall of birth experience in women 3 years postpartum in the Netherlands. Birth 2008;35:107-16.
4. Childbirth Connection. Transforming maternity care. Average charges for
giving birth: state charts. Available at: http://transform.childbirthconnection.
org/resources/datacenter/chargeschart/statecharges/. Accessed April 22,
2013.
5. Martin JA, Hamilton BE, Ventura SJ, et al. Births: final data for 2010.
Natl Vital Stat Rep 2012;61:4-5.
6. Charles S. The ethics of vaginal birth after cesarean. Hastings Cent
Rep 2012;42:24-7.
ª 2013 Mosby, Inc. All rights reserved. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ajog.
2013.04.025
REPLY
Dr Fischbein claims that our criticism of planned home birth
from the perspective of the professional responsibility of
obstetricians does not succeed. Ethical analysis of planned
home birth, like ethical analysis of all topics in obstetric and
medical ethics, should be both evidence-based and argumentbased.1
On the topic of patient safety, Dr Fischbein states that the
need for transport can be predicted in “experienced hands”
but provides no documentation for this claim. The Birthplace in England study reported on transport rates as high as
45%.2 Dr Fischbein bears the burden of proof to identify
evidence-based criteria for the reliable prediction of the need
for transport and fails altogether to meet this professional
obligation. He then states that “pain relief and prolonged
labor” do not indicate unsafe clinical conditions, again without
supporting documentation. The claim that the experience in
another country does not apply in the United States requires
Dr Fischbein to demonstrate the disanalogy, which he does
not do.
Dr Fischbein states that a cesarean delivery rate in the hospital setting of 24% results in an unacceptable increased
morbidity when compared to the out-of-hospital cesarean
delivery rate of 6%. As applied to planned home birth, the claim
is absurd, inasmuch as cesarean deliveries are not performed
SEPTEMBER 2013 American Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology
279
Letters to the Editors
in the home setting. Even if the comparison were not absurd,
simply reporting the rates of a procedure in the absence of
outcomes data does not count as evidence-based reasoning.
Worse, the paper that Dr Fischbein cites provides outcomes
data on care in birth centers.3 Planned birth at home, the focus
of our paper, is not planned birth at a birth center. The outcomes in the latter cannot be represented as the outcomes of the
former. The disanalogy is obviouseand egregious.
Regarding patient satisfaction, our point in citing the Dutch
experience waseand remainsethat in one of the most highly
developed home birth systems in the world there are significant
rates of failure to achieve patient satisfaction. A dissatisfaction
rate of 17% is high per se and therefore intrinsically clinically
significant. Asserting the obvious corollary of 83% satisfaction
should be read for what it is: an attempt to distract the reader
from a substantial, documented problem with planned home
birth. Dr Fischbein then states that he disagrees with national
efforts to improve the homelike setting of hospital delivery
without any supporting reasons. Asserting conclusions in the
absence of supporting reasons is what Platoelong agoehad
Socrates in the Dialogues characterize as “mere opinion,” which
never counts as argument-based reasoning.
As to cost-effectiveness, we emphasized that analyzing the
cost of home birth by comparing charges for home birth to
charges for hospital birth is incomplete and therefore
potentially misleading. Dr Fischbein’s invocation of relative
costs of vaginal vs cesarean delivery does not address relative
overall cost. His claims about comparative cost are therefore
incomplete and misleading.
As to women’s rights, Dr Fischbein invokes the ethical
analysis of vaginal birth after cesarean delivery by Charles,4
who argues that the autonomy of pregnant women is justifiably constrained by the professional judgment of obstetricians about what is medically reasonable.4 Dr Fischbein
neglects to inform his reader that Charles4 bases her argument explicitly on our approach to obstetric ethics. Having
rejected our approach (albeit without any supporting argument), Dr Fischbein invokes a paper based on it. Dr Fischbein
succeeds in both deceiving his reader and violating the
principle of noncontradiction. This principle forbids simultaneously holding a proposition and its denial to be true and
is therefore a disabling mistake in both evidence-based and
argument-based reasoning.
www.AJOG.org
Planned home birth is a serious topic in obstetric ethics.
Judgments about its ethical acceptability must therefore be
deliberativeeexplicitly appealing to the results of evidencebased and argument-based reasoning.5 Dr Fischbein’s letter
does neither and therefore makes no serious contribution to
how obstetricians should understand their professional responsibility concerning planned home birth.
Frank A. Chervenak, MD
Weill Medical College of Cornell University
525 East 68th St.
New York, NY 10065
[email protected]
Laurence B. McCullough, PhD
Baylor College of Medicine
Robert L. Brent, MD, PhD
Thomas Jefferson University
Malcolm I. Levene, MD
Leeds University
Amos Grünebaum, MD
Weill Medical College of Cornell University
Birgit Arabin, MD
Philipps University
The authors report no conflict of interest.
REFERENCES
1. McCullough LB, Coverdale JH, Chervenak FA. Argument-based
ethics: a formal tool for critically appraising the normative medical ethics
literature. Am J Obstet Gynecol 2004;191:1097-102.
2. Birthplace in England Collaborative Group. Perinatal and maternal
outcomes by planned place of birth for healthy women with low risk
pregnancies: the Birthplace in England national prospective cohort study.
BMJ 2011;343:d7400.
3. Stapleton SR, Osborne C, Illuzi J. Outcomes of care in birth centers:
demonstration of a durable model. J Midwifery Womens Health 2013;58:
3-14.
4. Charles S. The ethics of vaginal birth after cesarean. Hastings Cent
Rep 2012;42:24-7.
5. Chervenak FA, McCullough LB, Brent RL, Levene MI, Arabin B.
Planned home birth: the professional responsibility response. Am J
Obstet Gynecol 2013;208:31-8.
ª 2013 Mosby, Inc. All rights reserved. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ajog.
2013.04.026
Planned home birth: the professional responsibility
responseea midwifery response
TO THE EDITORS: The clinical opinion related to planned
home birth by Chervenak et al1 requires a midwifery response.
Home birth is a complex choice that includes the rights of
women over their bodies; these rights do not go away because
280 American Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology SEPTEMBER 2013
health professionals or governments ban them. The authors
suggest that women’s rights should be superseded by the
clinician’s obligation to protect the pregnant woman and the
“fetal, neonatal patient.” This paternalistic discourse privileges