London Review of Education
Volume 13, Number 2, September 2015
BOOK REVIEWS
Authority and the Teacher, by William H. Kitchen
London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2014, 202 pp., £16.99 (pbk), ISBN 978-1-4725-2984-8
Authority and the Teacher is a book based on the doctoral thesis of William H. Kitchen, a former
teacher of mathematics. The author sets out to re-examine and pursue the debate around
authoritative education, which centres on teacher authority. The author builds on the work of
philosophers such as Polanyi, Oakeshott, and Wittgenstein to build a conceptual understanding
of knowledge, teaching, and learning so as to highlight the need for a foundational authority in
education, at the same time addressing counterarguments from the progressive tradition. The
arguments for bringing back trust and faith in the judgement of teachers are persuasive; however
the case for establishing unquestioned acceptance among young pupils of the judgements of this
authority is problematic. Nonetheless, the project has managed to forge useful connections and
ask some tough questions: Why is teachers’ authority being undermined? Why do we need this
authority in education? What is the relationship of teachers’ authority to teaching and knowledge
development? What are the consequences for education and learning of an absence of teachers’
authority? Such questions are worthwhile and important to engage with in the quest to better
understand and deine teachers’ authority and, more broadly, the role of other authorities within
education.
In ‘A deinition of authority’ (chapter 3: 53) the author mentions that one needs to
separate authority from power. He explains that the component of legitimacy within authority
accompanied by discipline, i.e. habit formation, differentiates it from power, whereas power
involves punishment to instil fear in the pupil and is rather damaging. However, one is left
wondering whether teachers could ever have authority without any real power, an aspect left
unexplored by the author. This is because of his focus on a singular kind of authority, rather
than on the multiple kinds that are operational within the education system. On the other hand,
the author believes that legitimacy can be achieved only from the process of training within the
community, without any mention of gaining classroom legitimacy. He argues that this is because
children have neither knowledge, nor the capacity to reason, nor doubt to begin with. The
teacher, then, is the sole individual who can teach them and make them learned individuals like
herself. Although the author acknowledges the importance of discussion in the classroom, he
maintains that the teacher should be the one to stir children towards an idea of correctness
(chapter 4: 70). This notion of correctness espoused by the author may hold for mathematics
teaching, but becomes problematic in other disciplines like social sciences, which in many ways
rely on students relating their classroom knowledge to their knowledge and understanding of
the world outside and on adding to the collective knowledge of their peers and teacher.
A good part of the irst chapter is spent in an attempt to persuade the reader of the
worthwhileness of engaging with arguments for authority in education, in the climate of childcentred and progressive ideals that have come to evoke suspicion about any discussion of authority.
This chapter draws heavily on the sociological perspective of Frank Furedi (2009), a proponent of
adult authority in education, who claims that the loss of interest in the topic is a consequence of
misconceptions and confusions around the idea of authority and what it represents. Education,
Furedi says, is being perceived as a battleground whereon societal problems are fought over and
London Review of Education
187
educational goals are directed towards the future, with little concern for the present, leading
to instability within the education establishment. Furedi argues that this has caused the demise
of traditional authority, alongside frequent rather than occasional ‘educational intervention with
an anti-knowledge and anti-authority campaign’ (City and Guilds Group, 2014: 12), i.e. a move
towards lifelong learning models that accord diminishing importance to formal schooling, subject
disciplines, and the authority of the teacher. Building on the sociological arguments of Furedi,
the author explores the role of the teacher in relation to knowledge. The author states that
knowledge should be seen as a collective inheritance of experiences and judgement, contrary to
the current rhetoric in education of change, skills-based education, and lifelong learning, which
he considers an effort to disown our past practices and intellectual heritage without any critical
engagement, as when he notes that ‘one wonders if Euclid’s geometry ever becomes redundant?’
(p.18). He argues that there is no better candidate to initiate the young into this knowledge than
the teacher, with the legitimacy she gains from the adult community as a trained expert; trust in
teachers, hence, is not ill founded.
Previous arguments made in favour of authoritative education are taken up in chapter 2.
According to the author, G.H. Bantock and R.S. Peters both defend authoritative education against
the popular progressive ideology. However, to identify progressivism with an ideology is not just
a misrepresentation of the progressive movement but points to a misunderstanding of the term.
Bantock is recognized for bringing the ideas of freedom and authority together, while R.S. Peters
is noted for elucidating the role of the teacher in initiating the child into a shared value system.
Lawrence Stenhouse’s contribution is acknowledged in bringing forth knowledge as a force for
the emancipation of teachers and students, but the author distances himself from Stenhouse’s
suggestion of extending more control to students over their learning. The author thinks that the
child-centred movement has provided important criticism of traditional education but failed to
provide any solutions. In the author’s view, this movement promotes an anti-authority campaign
through its support for the idea that the child should be able to create her own meaning of the
world, thus reducing the teacher’s status to that of a facilitator.This position is thus characterized
by the author as irresponsible and restrictive of the idea of knowledge. In addressing the topic
of creativity, which under authoritative education is assumed to be conining, the author argues
that this claim is baseless, as even creative processes require initiation by an expert teacher to
hone students’ skills for creative endeavours later. Choice is often associated with freedom, yet,
drawing from Bantock (1970), the author believes this needs to be seen alongside responsibility,
which is learnt only after a process of discipline and initiation by educators, before choice is
made available to children.
Knowledge is explored through Polanyi, Oakeshott, and Wittgenstein (chapters 5, 6, and 7)
as involving not just facts but also judgement, which can be developed under submission to the
teacher’s authority. While information can be gained from sources other than the teacher, this
information is useless until combined with judgement and can only be taught by the teacher and
imbibed by the pupil in imitation of the teacher and her practice. At the same time the question
of foundationalism in knowledge, i.e. of what knowledge is based on, ultimately culminates in
chapter 8 (156) with Wittgenstein’s categorical distinction between Certainty and Knowledge,
the idea being that knowledge results after a proposition has been subjected to doubt and the
doubt circumvented. Certainties on the other hand are indubitable. It is these habitual bedrock
certainties, previously debated by the community, on which knowledge is founded. Teaching is,
then, based on trust rather than reason. But these are the very ideas on which one inds it dificult
to side with the author. Even if one agrees that one begins with no foundation in knowledge, one
is left with crucial questions: for instance, at what point in time is that foundation of knowledge
achieved? Even if this judgement is left to the discretion of the teacher, to claim that certain
188
Book Reviews
knowledge has been subjected to doubt by people in the past and hence should be taken at face
value is unacceptable if one does not want to undermine the intellectual capacity of children
and wants to promote critical thinking skills. Questions and doubts are not just for challenging
the legitimacy of the teacher or her knowledge but can work as a mechanism in the process of
learning (Legare et al., 2013). They help further the process of thinking and channel our search
for further clariication or information on the topic. They can also provide feedback to teachers
about student understanding, an aspect the author fails to consider.
William H. Kitchen’s work brings to the surface important questions in relation to knowledge,
teaching, and learning. There remain several issues, as I have highlighted, that the author has not
considered in his project and that need further work. However, the book has paved a useful path
to re-examine arguments for and against an authoritative education.
Ekta Singla
UCL Institute of Education
[email protected]
Acknowledgements: Professor Judith Suissa and Nicholas Wollaston.
References
Bantock, G. (1970) Freedom and Authority in Education. London: Faber & Faber.
City and Guilds Group (2014) ‘Sense and instability:Three decades of skills and employment policy’. Online.
www.cityandguilds.com/~/media/Documents/news-insight/oct-14/CGSkillsReport2014%20pdf.ashx
(accessed 6 July 2015).
Furedi, F. (2009) Wasted:Why education isn’t educating. London: Continuum.
Legare, C.H., Mills, C.M., Souza, A.L., Plummer, L.E., and Yasskin, R. (2013) ‘The use of questions as problemsolving strategies during early childhood’. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 114 (1), 63–76.
doi:10.1016/j.jecp.2012.07.002