JUSTICE, FEASIBILITY, AND IDEAL THEORY:
*
A PLURALIST APPROACH
BY ANDREW MASON
KEYWORDS: ideal theory, justice, pluralism, realism, G. A. Cohen, John Rawls
Abstract: A qualified pluralism is defended that recognizes value in a variety of forms of political
theory and resists arguments that purport to show that one particular approach should occupy a
privileged position. Against realists, it is argued that abstract analyses of political values that bracket
a wide range of facts about people and their circumstances can be both coherent and important,
whereas against those who think “ideal theory” or the identification of ultimate principles should come
first, it is argued that the case for always giving it priority is weak.
When political theorists reflect upon what they do, they are often drawn to
making specific methodological prescriptions. John Dunn contends that “[t]he
purpose of political theory is to diagnose practical predicaments and to show us how
best to confront them,”1 while at the other end of the spectrum G. A. Cohen declares
that “the question for political philosophy is not what we should do but what we
should think, even when what we should think makes no practical difference.”2 Even
allowing for a distinction to be made between political philosophy and political theory,
these prescriptions seem to me to be unduly constraining. Political theory is a diverse
field, accommodating highly abstract inquiries that aim to identify fundamental
normative principles by putting to one side facts about our natures and the
circumstances in which we live, as well as more grounded forms of reflection that
begin by paying close attention to the political problems we face and then seek
guidance from the normative principles that are immanent in our practices. In
response to attempts to draw limits to what kinds of political theory should be done,
or to elevate some forms above others, I shall defend a qualified pluralism that
recognizes value in a variety of approaches and resists arguments that purport to show
that one particular approach should occupy a privileged position. Against realists, I
2
argue that abstract analyses of political values that bracket a wide range of facts about
people and their circumstances can be both coherent and important, whereas I argue
against those who think “ideal theory” or the identification of ultimate principles
should come first, that the case for always giving it priority is weak.3
I focus on the notion of justice in particular.4 I examine three claims that pull
in different directions, but any one of which, if it were correct, would alone threaten
to place a serious limit on legitimate theorizing about justice. The first is that a socalled “ideal theory of justice” is both useless and misconceived because it is founded
on the assumption that citizens agree on principles of justice, thereby depriving it of
practical relevance and displaying a misunderstanding of the nature of the political.
The second claim is that we cannot justify a principle of justice without taking into
account what the effects would be of adopting it in the particular context that it is to
govern. And the third one is that we cannot justify conclusions about what justice
requires in the circumstances we face, with the constraints they impose on us, unless
we know what justice would require in the absence of these constraints. This third
claim comes in radical and moderate versions, both of which I shall examine. Neither
denies the legitimacy or importance of theorizing about justice that takes into account
local facts about what is feasible. But one version maintains that if we are to justify
our practical conclusions fully, we have to abstract from all facts about what is
feasible in order to identify and then defend the ultimate principles of justice that (it is
claimed) must underlie the arguments for these conclusions; the other version
maintains that in order to justify these conclusions fully, we need to develop an
account of justice that involves putting to one side at least some “soft” constraints that
may change over time, while keeping in place “hard” constraints that derive from
3
physical laws, unchangeable facts about the natural environment, or aspects of human
nature that are fixed.
I. IDEAL THEORY AND THE CIRCUMSTANCES OF POLITICS
Inspired by Rawls’s work, many political philosophers aim to develop an ideal
theory of justice, or at least, part of one. Ideal theorizing has been criticized on a
number of grounds, however. In this section I focus on what I think is one of the most
serious challenges to it, which has emerged from a realist perspective, namely, that
ideal theory is founded on the assumption that there is convergence on principles of
justice, and that this assumption not only deprives ideal theory of any practical
relevance but also betrays a misunderstanding of the nature of the political:
disagreement over conceptions of justice is part of the enduring circumstances of
politics;5 insofar as ideal theory assumes convergence on a particular conception, it
denies a constitutive feature of the political.6
I want to avoid getting drawn into an unprofitable discussion of the nature of
ideal theory, so I will simply stipulate that the aim of an ideal theory of justice is to
give an account of a society that is fully just, subject to the constraint that this account
be capable of playing some role in guiding political action, with the precise nature of
that role standing in need of further elucidation.7 I will assume that a fully just society
is one in which the basic institutions realize whatever the correct or best principles of
justice are that apply to them, and in which its members comply with whatever the
correct or best principles of justice are that apply to their behavior. I will also assume
that because ideal theory has the ultimate aim of playing a role in guiding political
action, it must employ a feasibility condition of some kind. Although there is room for
reasonable variation in terms of the formulation of that condition,8 an account of a
4
fully just society must at least be compatible with hard constraints — that is,
constraints on our capacity to realize principles that are part of the human condition
because they are rooted in physical laws or other unchangeable features of the natural
environment (such as scarcity of resources), or in aspects of human nature that are
fixed.9
The realist challenge that I am interested in does not deny that there may be
correct or best-defended principles of justice. Instead it argues that disagreement over
principles of justice will persist even under favorable conditions by appealing to
empirical claims about the sources of disagreement over these principles, in particular,
to the way in which disagreement is rooted in what Rawls calls “the burdens of
judgement”10 and in a variety of nonrational causes. A realist who presents the
challenge I am envisaging holds that there are no grounds for thinking that citizens
will come to endorse the same principles solely on the basis of reasoned argument,
nor that the nonrational causes that influence their judgments about what principles to
accept will lead them to converge on the same set.11 From the claim that disagreement
over political principles will persist, and is a source of conflict between citizens, he or
she concludes that one of the main purposes of political theory is to guide us in the
face of it, or at least to enable us to reflect upon its normative significance.12 A vision
of a fully just society where principles of justice are universally shared might provide
reasons for action for philosopher-rulers who inspire devotion and whose authority is
unquestioned, but it does not provide reasons for action for real states or ordinary
citizens living in a democratic society mired in deep and often fractious disagreement.
In response to this challenge it might be argued that ideal theorizing is not
intended to generate practical recommendations by itself. Rather, its main purpose is
to enable us to develop a nonideal theory that can lead to such recommendations. That
5
may be true, but it doesn't answer the challenge I am considering, at least when it is
presented in its most powerful form. Defenders of ideal theorizing about justice think
that it can play a role in guiding political action because the vision of a fully just
society that it is in the business of working out can serve as a target at which to aim,
or at least as a standard against which to judge the extent of injustice,13 which, when
combined with knowledge of what is feasible and the probabilities that different
courses of action will achieve their aims, together with an assessment of the likely
costs of each, can provide reasons for political action, such as a reason for favoring
one particular reform over another. The realist position I am considering maintains
that a vision of a fully just society in which everyone converges on the same
principles of justice cannot coherently serve as a target, or even as a standard that
guides action, because disagreement is part of the enduring circumstances of politics.
One reply here might be to challenge the realist’s factual prediction: for
example, one could try to show that disagreement to a large extent has its roots in
nonrational causes, the power of which are likely to diminish over time as our
understanding of the issues improves. I have doubts about the prospects of success of
a response of this kind. Alternatively, one might defend a milder version of the claim
that convergence is achievable that is more plausible empirically. For example, in
Political Liberalism Rawls suggests that under favorable conditions citizens will tend
to converge on a set of reasonable liberal conceptions of justice.14 Although citizens
may continue to disagree over which reasonable liberal conception to endorse, it
might be thought that they will each come to hold one such conception. But that claim
could also be regarded as empirically implausible, unless the notion of a reasonable
liberal conception is understood in a way that makes it very inclusive. 15 And even if it
is understood inclusively, it nevertheless seems likely that even under favorable
6
conditions a significant minority of citizens will endorse unreasonable illiberal (or
nonliberal) conceptions of justice.
Do ideal theorists need to assume convergence on a vision of a fully just
society and, if so, does this assumption create a problem for them in the way that
some realists think it does? It might seem that ideal theorists cannot avoid making an
assumption of this kind given that they aim to identify the principles that would
govern a fully just society, and a fully just society is one in which there is full
compliance with principles of justice. Strictly speaking, however, full compliance
with principles of justice does not require there to be convergence on those principles.
The citizens of a state may comply with a principle, or a law that embodies it, despite
disagreement with it: they may regard this principle or law as binding on them,
perhaps because they regard the procedures that led to its adoption as authoritative; or
they may recognize self-interested reasons for complying with the law, for example,
they may be deterred from breaking it by the prospect of being punished.16 Viewed in
this light, the Rawlsian conception of a well-ordered society in which citizens actually
endorse the principles that govern it goes beyond full compliance and incorporates an
element that is unnecessary for an ideal theory of justice.
In response it might be said that a society in which citizens not only comply
with the correct principles of justice but also endorse them would be more just, so an
ideal theory of justice must assume convergence. In such a society everyone would
act justly, that is, they would act from the true motive of justice; no one would comply
with principles of justice merely because of the threat of sanctions. Indeed it might be
thought that Rawls assumes convergence in a well-ordered society precisely because
he wants to give an account of a fully just society that could be stable for the right
reasons. But even if we suppose that a society in which citizens act from the motive
7
of justice would be more just because it would be stable for the right reasons, this
does not seem to imply that a fully just society requires convergence on the very same
principles. A society might be fully just even though some comply with just laws and
policies merely because they recognize the just authority of the decision-making
procedures that govern them and despite believing that the majority of their fellow
citizens are mistaken in their view that these laws and policies are just.
Insofar as an ideal theory does assume convergence, it would be best to regard
this as an idealization — that is, as an assumption that may not hold true in any
actually existing society, or indeed any feasible society, but which is made in the
process of building a theory in order to simplify its construction.17 For example,
Rawls assumes that all members of a society are “rational and able to manage their
own affairs” and that the subject matter of a theory of justice is the basic structure of
society “conceived as a closed system isolated from other societies.”18 The potential
problem with these assumptions is not that they describe a state of affairs that is hard
or impossible to bring about (or that would require a massive violation of individual
rights in order to do so), but rather that they may have the effect of creating too large
a gap between the theory and the societies to which it is meant to apply for it to be
capable of playing a role in guiding political action.19 So does the assumption of
convergence create too large a gap between the theory and the circumstances to which
it is meant to apply for it to be capable of doing so?
This idea of action guidance is vague: let us say that an ideal theory cannot
play any role in guiding us if it cannot provide us with any reasons for action
whatever available empirical knowledge is combined with it. There are several ways
in which a principle that is part of an ideal theory might provide us with a reason for
action when combined with empirical knowledge: for example, it may provide a
8
reason here and now for performing an action it prescribes, or it may provide a reason
for bringing about a state of affairs in which we could perform that action. And there
are different ways in which a principle might provide a reason for action without that
reason being conclusive: there may be several principles in play in a given context
that give us conflicting reasons for action; and these principles may reflect or express
different values, or they may reflect or express different aspects of an internally
complex value. But so long as an ideal theory when combined with empirical
knowledge can provide some reason for action in the circumstances we now confront,
then that would seem a sufficient response to the charge that it cannot play a role in
guiding us, even if this reason is outweighed by others.20 So how might an ideal
theory that assumes convergence on principles of justice play such a role?
Even if disagreement and conflict that is rooted in it are a constitutive feature
of politics, political activity need not always be limited to maintaining order in the
face of it. There is generally room in modern democracies for the pursuit of other
ideals and ordinary citizens as well as politicians need to form a view concerning
what policies they should advocate and support. This is where an ideal theory of
justice seems to have a potential role to play in guiding action, while at the same time
deepening our understanding of the issues and making possible a fuller justification of
our practical decisions. For example, an ideal theorist can work out in more depth the
visions of a just society that citizens may already have within their sights and assess
their strengths and weaknesses. The conclusions she reaches, when combined with
empirical judgments concerning what is politically feasible, what arrangements are
likely to be stable over time, and what costs would be incurred in instituting those
arrangements — together with reflection upon the normative implications of
noncompliance — may then provide her with a reason to support or reject particular
9
policies, a reason to defend those policies in public debate, and a reason to vote for
particular representatives in elections. Ideal theory, when it is founded on an
assumption of convergence on principles of justice, is limited in the guidance it can
provide for dealing with persistent and widespread disagreement over what justice
requires when that disagreement leads to noncompliance with laws and policies. But
ideal theorists would regard the inquiry into the proper principles for governing a
society where that occurs as part of nonideal rather than ideal theory.
Realists are likely to argue that my response to the challenge posed by
intractable disagreement over principles of justice fails to engage at a sufficiently
deep level with it. Indeed this appears to be what lies behind Matt Sleat’s insistence
that realism is not simply a version of nonideal theory.21 For him, the idea that there
needs to be a division of labor between ideal and nonideal theory misses the point that
we don’t need ideal theory to reflect upon the political problems that confront us, and
that in assuming away disagreement ideal theory fails to appreciate that such
disagreement is a constitutive feature of the political. I shall return to the issue of
whether we need ideal theory to justify our practical conclusions and, if we don’t,
what its point might be, later in this essay. With regard to the nature of the political,
ideal theorists can accept that disagreement is the stuff of politics without subverting
what they do: they can insist that ideal theory can provide practical guidance when
combined with knowledge about what is feasible, while conceding that it is
nonpolitical in an important way.22 In order to be plausible, the envisaged division of
labor between ideal and nonideal theory would involve giving the latter a considerable
degree of autonomy in relation to the former, and not merely because nonideal theory
will need to pay attention to empirical research in order to identify what courses of
action are feasible.23 Deep disagreement is not merely a constraint on the realization
10
of principles of justice, but raises very different kinds of normative questions. When
nonideal theory takes it into account, the question for it would not simply be: “What
way of proceeding in the face of the fact that people will inevitably disagree with the
principles delivered by an ideal theory will enable us to make the most progress
toward a fully just society, in the light of what is feasible and the costs of
implementation?” It would also need to focus on questions such as the following, and
the way in which they arise in particular contexts: How should we respond to those
fellow citizens who hold (what we believe to be) unreasonable conceptions of justice
and what procedures should be constructed to deal with such disagreements? What
reasons, if any, can be given to those who do not regard political procedures as
authoritative to comply with the outcomes of those procedures when they make
“demands for legitimation”?24 How should we respond to those who, we believe,
unreasonably reject those procedures?
II. PRINCIPLES AND THEIR CONSEQUENCES
Even if some forms of theorizing about justice had no practical relevance, they
might nevertheless be thought to provide intellectual or philosophical illumination, in
much the same way that within metaphysics or epistemology a theory of truth or a
theory of knowledge might do so.25 Ideal theory, when it is defined in the way that I
have done, must have practical relevance if it is to fulfill its purpose, but we might
follow Alan Hamlin and Zofia Stemplowska in drawing a distinction between ideal
theory and the theory of ideals, with the latter encompassing abstract normative or
evaluative theorizing that is not constrained in any way by a need to play some
practical role.26 Accordingly, my aim in this section is to defend, against a different
realist challenge, the coherence and value of theorizing about ideals when that simply
11
aims to help us to understand an ideal better. This form of theorizing might enable us
to identify principles for ranking logically possible states of affairs in terms of how
just they would be, but it would do so without any regard to the practical implications
of these principles for the society we inhabit, what institutions would be required to
realize them, or the feasibility of implementing them.
Some realists, such as Edward Hall, would reject this mode of theorizing
because they maintain that we cannot properly assess normative principles without
considering what they entail, and in order to assess them “we must consider how
principles map on, or apply to, the factual contexts which they aim to govern.”27
Elizabeth Anderson, although not a realist in any conventional sense, goes further in
one respect, maintaining that ideals need to be put into practice before they can be
properly assessed. In her view, ideals offer solutions to problems that we experience
and they need to be tested by “seeing whether they solve the problems for which they
were devised, settle people’s reasonable complaints, and offer a way of life that
people find superior to what they had before.”28
Hall is surely correct that some principles, particularly those designed for the
immediate purpose of governing institutions and policy, cannot be properly assessed
without considering the effects of putting them into practice. His contentious claim is
that this is true more generally of all normative principles.29 Indeed, Hall’s thesis
when it is understood as a universal claim about normative principles has an air of
paradox to it, for how are we to assess the effects of putting a principle into practice
without appealing to more fundamental normative principles that are not assessed in
this way? Surely an assessment of the effects of putting a principle into practice will
at the very least involving determining whether it treats people as equals, whether, for
example, it is consistent with the more fundamental principle that each person’s life
12
matters equally; yet we cannot insist without circularity that this more fundamental
principle be assessed in terms of the consequences of putting it into practice.
Even if I am right that there are fundamental principles that cannot be assessed
by considering the effects of implementing them, we might think that these principles
can always be interpreted differently, and that selecting the best interpretation of them
will involve considering those effects. If someone proposes that the best interpretation
of the principle that we should treat people with equal concern and respect is a luck
egalitarian principle according to which no one should be worse off than another
through no fault of one’s own, then we cannot assess whether he or she is right except
by considering the consequences of implementing that principle. Indeed it might be
thought that even principles such as this one will be indeterminate until they are
embodied in institutions and policy, lending support to Anderson’s more radical
contention that we need to test ideals by actually putting them into practice. For this
reason it might even be regarded as a mistake to think of institutions simply as the
means through which principles are realized since institutions are always partly
responsible for giving content to principles. William Galston expresses this idea in the
following terms: “institutions provide arenas within which abstract concepts of
principles and aims (rights, the general welfare) are worked up into concrete
conceptions. As such, they help define the community’s purposes, rather than simply
putting prior understandings into effect.”30 This line of thought perhaps receives some
support from Wittgenstein’s considerations concerning rule-following.31 Although his
remarks on rule-following are complex, and their import is a matter of scholarly
debate, his observation that any rule can be interpreted differently, and his apparent
view that what determines the correct interpretation of it are the practices in which it
is embedded, have clear resonances here.
13
But even if fundamental principles, such as the principle that we should treat
people with equal concern and respect, admit of different reasonable interpretations,
there are some interpretations that are ruled out as unreasonable because they cannot
be reconciled with our intuitions about what abiding by this fundamental principle
involves. We can often probe these intuitions by considering imaginary cases, and in
this way give more content to the principle. Indeed, specific interpretations of the
fundamental principle that we should treat people with equal concern and respect,
such as the luck egalitarian principle, might also be refined and assessed in this way.
Elizabeth Anderson is skeptical about thought experiments when assessing ideals and
principles, on the grounds that evaluative judgement involves expressing feeling, and
we are not particularly good at predicting our feelings about states we have not yet
experienced.32 While accepting that our intuitions sometimes differ from what we
expect when we are confronted by real rather than imaginary cases, it seems to me
that we should not exaggerate this truth. No doubt it gives us some reason to worry
about the assessment and refinement of principles solely by considering imaginary
outcomes, but it does not give us reason to think that this way of proceeding has no
legitimate role to play.
Indeed, consideration of imaginary outcomes may be the best way, or even the
only way, of determining whether it is the case that a principle has some force but is
outweighed by another principle, or whether instead it is an incorrect principle and
should be rejected.33 That a principle would have bad consequences if implemented is
rarely a conclusive reason for rejecting it. Consider the principle “from each
according to his ability, to each according to his need.” Hall argues that if the
implementation of this socialist principle of justice would require an ethos that could
only be sustained by repressive state intervention because it goes against the grain of
14
human nature, then this would give us sufficient reason to reject the principle.34 But
there are other conclusions that might be drawn here. For example, we might suppose
that this principle needs to be balanced against another principle of justice that
requires us to respect basic liberties (or to maximize equal basic liberties) and which
is outweighed by the latter. If that were the correct diagnosis, the socialist principle
would still possess independent force. Whether this is the correct diagnosis could be
“tested” by asking what the principle would imply in relation to a range of cases,
some of which are unlikely to obtain, where it could be implemented without
repressive state intervention perhaps because human beings were differently
motivated, and seeing whether its implications for those cases match our considered
judgments. It is hard to see why these reflections would be incoherent, even though
such circumstances might be far removed from “the factual contexts” that the
principle is to govern.
The idea that some legitimate forms of normative theorizing, including
theorizing about justice, might involve identifying principles and then testing them
against our intuitions about imaginary examples in a way that is independent of any
consideration of how those principles could be realized through institutions, has the
implication that when we turned to that question we might find that it is impossible in
practice ever to realize these principles, and that they could never provide reasons for
individual or collective action. This might make us start to wonder whether theorists
engaged in this activity are investigating a rather different concept from those whose
work is motivated by practical concerns.35 Indeed, could it be argued that those
engaged in this purely intellectual activity are no longer in the business of theorizing
justice at all, even if they use that term? It might be claimed that the point of the
concept of justice is to guide political action, in the sense distinguished earlier, which
15
would seem to imply that a judgment cannot be a judgment of justice unless it can
guide political action. This might even be taken to support the view that adequate
principles of justice in particular must meet some sort of feasibility condition, even if
normative or evaluative theorizing in general is not subject to such a condition.36
This is a difficult argument to finesse since we need some way of justifying
the claim that the concept of justice has an inherently practical purpose. It is most
plausible when it is understood as a claim about our ordinary practice of using the
term, for example, when we say “these welfare reforms are unjust,” or “the protesters
were dealt with unjustly” and so on, where the point of making these claims is to
persuade us of the importance of some action in response.37 But even if we can show
that the concept of justice has a practical purpose in our ordinary use of it, and that
theorizing about the requirements of justice is inherently an exercise in practical
reason, it is hard to know what follows from it.38 If the identity of a concept is fixed
by its point, it might seem to follow that those who defend normative or evaluative
principles that can give no practical guidance, whether now or in the foreseeable
future, must be employing a different concept. But that would be misleading if it was
then taken to imply that there is no connection at all between “justice” in its practical
sense and “justice” in its purely theoretical sense. Although it seems unobjectionable
to suppose that theorists may be engaged in very different activities — some are
seeking to understand “justice as such” in a way that is independent of any concern
for what is feasible and the costs of implementation, whereas others are seeking to
provide principles of justice to govern a possible society — we cannot avoid the issue
of what the relationship is between these two forms of activity. Regarding these forms
of activity as focused on different concepts that happen to be denoted by the same
term would encourage the view that they are entirely unrelated, yet this seems
16
mistaken.39 It will be denied by many of those who see themselves as trying to
understand justice as such, for they will argue that this form of reflection is logically
prior, because without it we won’t fully understand the principles that are being
proposed for governing an actual or possible society, or be able to justify these
principles fully. If they can establish this claim, it would in effect turn the tables on
the realist.
III. FEASIBILITY AND THE JUSTIFICATION OF ACTION-GUIDING PRINCIPLES
Why might it be thought that the full justification of action-guiding principles
relies on first identifying fundamental principles of justice that provide us with an
understanding of justice as such, without any concern for what is feasible or what
costs would be incurred in implementing them? G. A. Cohen has argued that ultimate
normative principles, including ultimate principles of justice, are not constrained by
facts about human incapacity. When a fact about human incapacity “is said to exclude
a principle because it can’t be obeyed, we may then ask what we should say about the
putatively excluded principle on the counterfactual hypothesis that it could be obeyed.
And it is only when we thus clear the decks of facts about capacity and get the answer
to that counterfactual question that . . . we reach the normative ultimate.”40 In other
words, we reach ultimate normative principles in these cases by abstracting from what
is feasible, employing a chain of counterfactual reasoning that involves asking
questions such as, “If it were possible to implement this principle, would justice tell
us to do so?” or “If it were possible to implement the principle, would an injustice be
involved in not implementing it?” The relevant ultimate principles do not express or
entail categorical ought statements; rather they express or entail statements such as “if
it is possible to do A, then you ought to do A.”41 Presumably Cohen would say much
17
the same about the costs of implementing a principle: if someone objects to a
principle on the grounds that implementing it would be costly, then in order to
identify the correct ultimate principle we should ask questions such as, “If
implementing this principle could be done in a way that was costless, would justice
favor doing so?”
What follows from this? It might seem to be a short step to the conclusion that
the identification of the ultimate principles that are required in order to justify the
principles — or as Cohen would have it, rules of regulation — that apply in particular
circumstances would always require us to “clear the decks” of all facts about what is
feasible and what costs would be incurred in implementing them. 42 That does not
follow, however. In some cases the ultimate principle that is needed to justify an
appropriate rule of regulation in a given set of circumstances may have to be
identified in the light of what is feasible, for there are some ultimate principles that
apply precisely because of facts about what is feasible. Consider, for example, the
principle that everyone should be allowed to have the amount and quality of material
resources that they want. If someone objects to this principle on the grounds that it is
impossible in practice to satisfy because there are not enough material resources to go
around, Cohen’s method of interrogation would have us ask, “if it were possible to
allow everyone to have the amount and quality of material resources that they want,
would this be what was morally required?” The answer then might well be “yes”: if
material resources were simply unlimited, now and in the future, then what objection
could there be to this principle? So the principle that everyone should be allowed to
have the material resources they want is an ultimate principle that applies on
condition that resources are bountiful. But if we want to identify the ultimate
18
principles of distributive justice that apply to our world and help us to devise rules of
regulation for it, then we have to do so on the assumption that resources are scarce.
More generally, it seems to me that “clearing the decks” of facts about what is
feasible is not the way to identify a number of the ultimate principles that ground the
rules of regulation relevant to us and the societies in which we live. Consider another
example. Suppose that in circumstances where it is possible to meet everyone’s needs,
justice requires us to do so. But imagine that it is impossible to meet everyone’s needs.
The principle that we ought to do so does not provide us with any guidance. Even if it
should not be rejected as an ultimate principle on those grounds alone, we
nevertheless need some further ultimate principle to guide us in determining and
justifying the rule of regulation that applies under these circumstances where the
possibilities are limited, and which explains and justifies how we are meant to balance
conflicts between, for example, helping the neediest by meeting some of their needs
as opposed to bringing more people up to the level at which all their needs are met.
The lesson to be learnt here is that there are some ultimate principles the applicability
of which depends on facts in the sense that these facts are a condition of the
application of the principle. In such cases, we arrive at the ultimate principle by
keeping in view these facts rather than clearing them away. This may help to deflect
some of the criticism of Cohen’s work that has come from realists: even if ultimate
principles of justice are not constrained by facts about what is feasible, some of these
facts may be relevant because they are conditions for the application of ultimate
principles.43
Even when the full justification of the rules of regulation that apply in a given
set of circumstances does require us to abstract from what is feasible and identify the
principles that would apply if those circumstances did not limit our options, it is often
19
possible to achieve an adequate justification of what rules of regulation apply without
doing so. First, as Amartya Sen points out, we can make judgments about what is
better without making judgments about what is the best, 44 and these judgments may
often be adequately justified without reference to ultimate principles. Furthermore, as
John Dunn argues, even when we cannot identify the best outcome, we may be able to
identify the worst possible outcome (for example, nuclear obliteration), and the need
to avoid it may provide us with an adequate justification for a particular policy.45
Second, we may be able to show that in the circumstances we confront, a
particular rule of regulation follows from any of a number of principles, in which case
there may be no need to probe further. For example, strict egalitarian, prioritarian, and
sufficientarian distributive principles may entail the same rule of regulation to govern
the redistribution of resources in some circumstances where options are limited.
Third, we can reason analogically on a case by case basis to conclusions that,
even though they are not backed by a deductively valid argument containing an
ultimate principle as a premise, may nevertheless be adequately justified. Consider,
for example, the analogy that Judith Jarvis Thomson used in her well-known article
on the permissibility of abortion in which you are asked to imagine waking to find
yourself hooked up to a famous violinist who has a fatal kidney ailment, and given
your blood group you are the only person who can keep him alive.46 If he is
unplugged from you now, he will die, but in nine months he will have made a full
recovery. Thompson argues that even if the violinist has a right to life, it is morally
permissible for you to disconnect him. She concludes by analogy that even if a fetus
has a right to life, it is morally permissible for a pregnant woman to abort it. The
crucial thing to note here is that Thompson’s argument is not deductively valid, and
nor does it have as one of its premises a general moral principle: it simply appeals to
20
the idea that the two cases are relevantly similar. To the extent that its conclusion is
justified, its justification relies on the considered judgment that we make in relation to
the case of the violinist, and on the two cases being relevantly similar, rather than on
an appeal to principles — and of course many of the objections to it have involved
drawing out relevant differences between the cases. Insisting that the analogy
provides a justification for the conclusion only if we can identify the principles that
underlie it would seem to me to be mistaken.47
The search for “ultimate principles” through abstracting from all
considerations concerning what is feasible may also take us a very long way from
where we are now. Sometimes we may want to say that it leads us to principles for
beings unlike us, or for a society unlike ours, rather than to ultimate principles for us
or the society in which we live. Galston makes much the same point when he says that
reflection on political values that is motivated only by intellectual concerns, and is a
purely truth-seeking activity, may be the political theory equivalent of science
fiction.48 He is perhaps more skeptical than I am about the value of this kind of
activity. In my view it is nevertheless an important and worthwhile approach, for it
may deepen our understanding of the concept of justice by telling us what justice
would be like if we were very different beings from what we are, or if we had kinds of
information or technology that will always be unavailable to us. The way in which it
deepens our understanding of the concept of justice is no different in the relevant
respects from the way in which some of the bizarre thought experiments that
philosophers of mind engage in may deepen our understanding of the concept of
personal identity, for example, imagining that a person wakes up with all of Guy
Fawkes’s memories, or that we split a person’s brain in two and transplant each half
into a new body, or that we “download” all of a person’s memories and “upload
21
them” into a new brain. Reflection on these cases may not provide us with any
additional help when it comes to judging whether the person in front of us is the same
person we met up with ten days ago, but they do nevertheless have the potential to
further our understanding of the nature of personal identity.
In this respect I am also disagreeing with David Miller when he challenges
what he calls the “Starship Enterprise view of political philosophy.”49 Unlike Galston,
Miller in the end thinks that this view of political philosophy is incoherent. He thinks
that in order to be coherent, political theory must operate under at least some
feasibility constraints and make some assumptions about what human beings are like
and the circumstances under which they are living. On this issue, I am at least partly
on Cohen’s side. I think he is right that we can always coherently and meaningfully
ask: What principle would apply if human nature was differently constituted — if we
had different capacities or inclinations, for example — or what principle would apply
if the world was very different — if there were unlimited resources in it, for example
— and I believe that in doing so we learn something about the concept of justice, even
if we don’t identify (more) ultimate principles for us, constituted as we are and
subject to various hard constraints.50 Indeed by considering what would be just in a
very different society from ours where we were differently constituted, we may learn
how various aspects of our society or our natures are important conditions for the
application of those principles that do apply to us.
IV. ON THE ALLEGED PRIORITY OF IDEAL THEORY
Cohen’s argument is designed to show that the identification of ultimate
normative principles sometimes at least requires us to abstract from facts about what
is feasible, including facts about human incapacity that may have the status of hard
22
constraints. But there is a less radical argument available that is intended to show that
ideal theorizing which abstracts from most or all “soft” constraints — that is,
constraints that are malleable to some degree — must be prior to nonideal theorizing
that addresses the issue of what we should do now in the face of those constraints.
According to this view, we can be justified in thinking that we are making genuine
progress toward a fully just society only if we are in possession of an ideal theory that
tells us what justice would require in the absence of most or all soft constraints. It
constitutes a response to those such as Sen who think that practical conclusions about
what we should do now can be justified without any clear understanding of full justice
because we can be justified in thinking that a state of affairs is more just or less unjust
without knowing what a fully just state of affairs would be. (If it were successful, it
would also cast doubt on my argument above, that we can adequately justify what
principles apply in the circumstances that confront us even if we have not successfully
identified the ultimate principles that underpin them.)
The key argument here is developed by John Simmons, building on Rawls's
conception of the relationship between ideal and nonideal theory.51 He argues that any
defensible nonideal theory of justice must have a transitional rather than merely
comparative character. Its transitional character means that it requires for its
application some reasonably well worked-out theory of perfect or full justice.52 Even
if we can say of two states of affairs C and D that D is more just than C, this does not
suffice to show that we ought to move to D since a move to D might block the path to
a fully just society or make that transition much more difficult. Under these
circumstances, it may be the case that we ought to take one step back in order to take
several steps forward. Simmons concludes that we need an ideal theory that provides
us with a conception of full or perfect justice that sets an ultimate target in order to be
23
able to determine whether or not there is a problem of path dependence of this kind.
He argues that for similar reasons we need an integrated conception of a fully just
society, rather than simply a conception of what it would mean for a society to be
fully just along one dimension, for example, in terms of gender justice. Without an
integrated conception of a fully just society, we will not be able to tell whether a
reform along one dimension that leaves other dimensions unaffected, and which
makes a society more just when judged in purely comparative terms, nevertheless
takes us further away from perfect justice understood as an integrated ideal.
Simmons is surely correct that path dependence matters. Indeed, it matters
even for those who think ideal theory is unnecessary or deeply flawed for some reason,
for there may be circumstances in which we can feasibly create a state of affairs that
would be more just but we should nevertheless not do so because we would then risk
much greater injustice in the future.53 But there are a number of possible lines of
response to Simmons’s claim that a proper appreciation of the problems created by
path dependence establishes the priority of ideal theory. I will focus on three. He
partially anticipates the first of these, but it nevertheless shows that there is
considerable scope for nonideal theorizing without the possession of anything
resembling a worked out ideal theory. It relies on pointing out that our social
scientific knowledge is highly limited and we do not have the ability reliably to
predict what impact efforts to make a society more just will have in the longer term.54
Indeed, our knowledge of the future tends to become more uncertain the more distant
it is from the present. We are rarely in a position to know that we could get closer to
full justice by taking a path that involved making society less just in the short- to
medium term. Evidence one way or the other will be very hard to come by, yet it is
24
bound to affect any justification for choosing a path that makes society less just in the
short- to medium term on the grounds that it brings us closer to full justice.
Simmons acknowledges some of these points but concludes from them that
when our knowledge of the future is insufficient, all we can do is muddle through and
then “it may seem acceptable to cross our fingers and just accept whatever
comparative gains in justice we can get or single-mindedly attack some particular,
salient injustice.”55 But it seems to me that this is the situation we face in the majority
of cases when we are contemplating the justice of reforms. I would draw the more
radical conclusion that in the absence of strong evidence — evidence that is likely to
be unavailable to us —– that a reform that produces a significant comparative gain in
the short term is highly likely to make things much worse in the long run, then we are
justified in supporting it or pursuing it, and indeed are often morally required to do so.
Second, suppose that full justice will not be achieved even though it could be
achieved because, say, there are powerful people with a vested interest in preventing
it from being achieved.56 Under these circumstances, why think that it is full justice
that should serve as the target, rather than some other standard that there is some
probability we could achieve? Why would it be justified, say, to move further away
from what is the best we will achieve on the grounds that doing so would nevertheless
leave open the bare possibility of moving closer to full justice? Or suppose that full
justice will not be achieved in the foreseeable future. Why should we choose a course
of action that keeps open the possibility of achieving it in the distant and
unforeseeable future, even though it takes us further away from the best we can
achieve in the foreseeable future?
Perhaps these reflections give us grounds for thinking that ideal theory should
be conducted in the light of a different feasibility condition, namely, that principles
25
should be compatible with what could be achieved in the best of foreseeable
circumstances, rather than with what could be achieved when constrained only by
human nature and physical laws. But this brings me to the third problem, namely,
how are ideal theorists to justify the particular feasibility condition that they are to
employ when constructing the account of full justice that is to serve as the moral
target or the standard against which reforms are to be judged? Indeed different ideal
theorists place different feasibility conditions on the adequacy of normative principles.
For example, Rawls supposes that principles of justice are adequate, that is, are
candidates to be adopted within ideal theory, only if they could be realized in a
manner that is stable for the right reasons under favorable circumstances, that is,
under the best of foreseeable conditions.57 This seems to be more restrictive: it would
seem to rule out a principle that is compatible with hard constraints but where we
have good reason to think that it could not be realized under the best of foreseeable
conditions, given the nature of the soft constraints that exist here and now.58 Allen
Buchanan, in contrast, argues that ideal theory should meet the condition of “moral
accessibility,” which involves satisfying three conditions: first, it must be feasible to
implement it, so it must be “compatible with human psychology, human capacities
generally, the laws of nature, and the natural resources available to human beings”;
second, there must be a “practical route from where we are now to at least a
reasonable approximation of the state of affairs that satisfies its principles”; third, the
state of affairs that it specifies as ideal must be attainable without unacceptable moral
costs.59
Simmons defends Rawls’s conception of ideal theory against Buchanan’s on
the grounds that Buchanan’s is in tension with regarding the principles of ideal theory
as ultimate standards, for Buchanan’s version entails that those principles will change
26
as facts about moral accessibility change and it does not allow us to condemn
arrangements that there is no practicable way of reforming.60 But this response cuts no
ice against those who hold that ideal theory should set a moral target that is accessible
from where we are now, rather than identify standards to be used in assessing courses
of action, and judging the injustice involved in states of affairs, even when there may
be no practicable means of reform from our current position. It is hard to see why we
should think that there is a uniquely correct account of the feasibility condition that
the principles of justice defended within ideal theory should meet. There may be
limits on what can count as a defensible feasibility condition that are imposed by ideal
theory’s action-guiding role, but these will permit different reasonable interpretations
of that condition, perhaps as a result of different views concerning how accessible the
target it sets needs to be, or perhaps as a result of contrasting conceptions of how ideal
theory should guide action, that is, whether it should set a target at all or merely
provide a standard compatible with hard constraints that is to be used in assessing
different courses of action and states of affairs, irrespective of whether that standard is
unattainable now or even in the foreseeable future. Because ideal theories may
reasonably interpret the feasibility condition differently, they may incorporate
different soft constraints and — if they see themselves as setting a target — employ
different timeframes for its application.
V. CONCLUDING REMARKS
I have claimed that different kinds of political theory are valuable and no
particular type should always come first. But I am not arguing for a Paul Feyerabendstyle methodological anarchism according to which anything goes.61 Different kinds
of political theory can be done well or badly: an ideal theory can make idealizations
27
that create too large a gap between it and the society to which it is intended to apply,
with the result that it is incoherent because it cannot fulfill its aim of playing a role in
guiding political action; reflection upon political problems may be vitiated by the
neglect of important empirical evidence, and as result lead to flawed practical
recommendations. Even when a type of political theory is done well, it may be
misapplied, or unjustifiable conclusions may be drawn from it: we cannot
straightforwardly draw conclusions about what justice requires us to do in our world
from a theory about what justice would require us to do in a world that was very
different from our own or in which we were very different.
The value to us of a particular kind of political theory depends in part on what
question we want to address, and what we are seeking to gain from addressing it. Are
we merely seeking intellectual or philosophical illumination by trying to understand
“justice as such” or are we trying to find solutions to practical problems — or both?
Political theory that serves a practical purpose by providing guidance on what we as
individuals, or as collectives, ought to do, whether here and now or in the foreseeable
future, is clearly important. But so too is political theory that is unnecessary for
reaching adequately justified conclusions concerning what we should do, or that
would provide guidance only in some remote possible world, or that merely serves an
intellectual purpose. Political theory of this kind is valuable because it can provide us
with a fuller or more complete justification for our conclusions about what we should
do, or a deeper understanding of ideals such as justice. Employing David Miller’s
somewhat loaded terms, we might say that there is value in doing political philosophy
from the perspective of the crew of the Starship Enterprise — that is, theory that
brackets all considerations of feasibility, including those that arise from human nature
28
— instead of, or in addition to, political philosophy for earthlings, constrained by
what is possible for societies of them, given where they are and what they can achieve.
Nor need there be anything wrong with political theorizing that accepts the
constraints imposed by deeply entrenched political beliefs, choosing in effect to be
limited by considerations of political feasibility, and asking how we should act in the
face of the fact that our fellow citizens have emphatically placed some reforms off the
political agenda.62 Indeed, doing so may be important for addressing questions such as
“What should we do here and now?” which is a legitimate question for a political
theorist. For example, political theorists might ask questions about what regulatory
frameworks should be applied to publicly funded faith schools in Britain, given the
widespread commitment to these schools among members of different religious
groups and the distinctive tradition of state funding for religious schools that exists
there, even if we believe that it would be better or more just if these schools did not
exist. Indeed I would like to see more political theory of this kind, even though it will
have a more parochial character and may not travel very well across political
boundaries.
Since different types of political theory address different questions, there is a
division of labor between them, and they may often complement each other. But that
does not settle the issue of whether these questions ought to be addressed in a
particular order of priority. As part of my defense of pluralism, I have resisted the
idea that the questions raised in ideal theory concerning what principles would govern
a fully just society should always be addressed first. But what of the view that
nonideal theory should always come first because our theorizing should start from
reflection on particular injustices, with the aim of reaching practical conclusions about
what should be done to overcome them?
29
Sometimes the view that nonideal theory should come first is based upon a
conviction about the proper role of political theory in a democratic society — in
particular, the view that it ought to make a contribution to public debates about what
laws and policies should be enacted. For the reasons I have given, however, it is not
clear why we should think that the value of political theory consists solely in a
contribution of this kind. But it might be thought that the priority of nonideal theory
can be grounded in the deeper idea that we are able to understand what is just only by
reference to what is unjust. David Schmidtz seems to endorse this deeper idea when
he suggests that “[j]ustice is less a property than an absence of properties that make
for injustice.”63 If justice is simply the absence of injustice, then we have to identify
injustice before we can know what justice is. But that it is not enough to show that
nonideal theory must come first, if by “nonideal theory” we mean “theory that aims to
reach justified conclusions about how we should respond to injustice in the light of
what is feasible under the circumstances.” For even if justice is simply the absence of
injustice, it does not follow that it would be misconceived to try to describe a society
that had no injustices (that is, was fully just) without first addressing the issue of how
those injustices should be tackled in practice in order to make it more just. In the face
of particular injustices, we might think it valuable to deepen our understanding of the
nature and character of these injustices and the relationships between them by
addressing the issue of what a society might look like in which they had all been
eradicated and no new ones had been introduced, irrespective of whether it was
feasible to bring about such a society. And we might think that this approach is
worthwhile partly because we believe that the kind of understanding we would then
acquire is valuable in itself and partly because we believe that if we were to acquire it,
30
we would have more confidence in the proposals we make for reform in the light of
what we judge to be feasible, and be better equipped to defend these proposals.64
Politics and International Studies, University of Warwick
31
*
I would like to thank Matthew Clayton, Stephanie Rinaldi, David Schmidtz
and Adam Swift for their written comments on an earlier draft, and the other
contributors to this volume for their discussion of it. The final version was written
while I was a visiting fellow at the Justitia Amplificata Centre for Advanced Studies
at the Goethe University Frankfurt am Main. I would like to thank Rainer Forst for
inviting me, and the fellows and staff at the Forschungskolleg Humanwissenschaften
for making my period of residence there so enjoyable and productive.
1
John Dunn, Interpreting Political Responsibility (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990), 193.
2
Gerald A. Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2008), 268.
3
It is easy to forget that it is not just critics of ideal theory who have sought to
limit the pluralism of political theory; it is also those ideal theorists who have argued
that ideal theory needs to be done first.
4
There is a difficult issue concerning whether we should think of justice as a
master value — in effect whether we should regard “justice” as an umbrella term that
shelters any weighty consideration relevant to our evaluation of social arrangements
— or whether we should think of it as simply one important value among many. Some
realists have objected to the primacy that Rawlsians give to justice in evaluating
social institutions, but that criticism makes sense only if we regard justice as one
value among several. I will sidestep this underlying issue and simply assume that a
theory of justice has an important place in our normative thought, even if there are
other independent values the theorization of which raises the same methodological
issues, and even if justice does not have the kind of primacy that Rawls attributes to it.
32
5
See Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1999), especially 1-4, 149-63. See also William Galston, “Realism in Political
Theory,” European Journal of Political Theory 9 (2010): 385-411, at 391; Andrew
Mason, “Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of Politics,” Political Theory 38
(2010): 658-83, especially 658-64; Matt Sleat, Liberal Realism: A Realist Theory of
Liberal Politics (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2013), esp. chap. 2.
6
Mason, “Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of Politics,” 664; Matt
Sleat, “Realism, Liberalism and Non-ideal Theory Or, Are there Two Ways to Do
Realistic Political Theory?” Political Studies, DOI: 10.1111/1467-9248.12152, p. 10.
7
Some define ideal theory more broadly so that it includes theorizing that
involves no concern with action guidance, but for reasons that will become clearer I
prefer to distinguish ideal theory “proper” from theorizing about ideals that has no
inherent concern for guiding action. For discussion of the nature of ideal theory, see
especially A. John Simmons, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” Philosophy and Public
Affairs 38 (2010): 5-36. See also Zofia Stemplowska, “What’s Ideal About Ideal
Theory?” Social Theory and Practice 34 (2008): 319-40; Ingrid Robeyns, “Ideal
Theory in Theory and Practice,” Social Theory and Practice 34 (2008): 341-62; Alan
Hamlin and Zofia Stemplowska, “Theory, Ideal Theory, and the Theory of Ideals,”
Political Studies Review 10 (2012): 48-62.
8
How it is formulated will depend in part upon precisely what role an ideal
theory is thought to play in guiding political action: see Section IV for further
discussion.
9
For discussion of the distinction between hard and soft constraints, see Pablo
Gilabert and Holly Lawford-Smith, “Political Feasibility: A Conceptual Exploration,”
33
Political Studies 60 (2012): 808-825, at 813; Holly Lawford-Smith, “Understanding
Political Feasibility,” Journal of Political Philosophy 21 (2013): 243-59, at 252.
10
See John Rawls, Political Liberalism, paperback edition (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1996), 54-58 — though, of course, Rawls seems to think
that the burdens of judgment affect the justification of comprehensive moral doctrines
in a more fundamental way than the justification of principles of justice. See also
Sleat, Liberal Realism, pp. 133-36; David Schmidtz, “Nonideal Theory: What It Is
and What It Needs to Be,” Ethics 121 (2011): 772-96, at 781-83.
11
In one sense of this slippery term, realists are claiming that the notion of
justice is essentially contestable. Even though the reasons that people give in favor of
their own particular interpretations have force, they are not logically compelling. See
Andrew Mason, Explaining Political Disagreement (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1993), especially chap. 2.
12
Sleat, Liberal Realism, chap. 2.
13
For the importance of distinguishing between the different roles that ideal
theory might play, for example, in providing a gauge or standard, a model or template,
or a target, see Jennan Ismael, “A Philosopher of Science Looks at Idealization in
Political Theory,” this volume.
14
Rawls, Political Liberalism, xlvii-xlix.
15
Rawls’s category of reasonable conceptions of justice is narrower than one
might initially think, for it seems to exclude libertarian conceptions and some
communitarian ones: see Mason, “Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of
Politics,” 661.
16
This shows that an ideal theory can acknowledge the need for legal
institutions even in a fully just society, for they may be necessary for securing full
34
compliance. Indeed Rawls himself maintains that legal institutions would be needed
to motivate full compliance in such a society because without them people will lack
the assurance that others are doing their part. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev.
ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 211.
17
Onora O’Neill contrasts idealizations such as these with abstractions:
“[a]bstraction . . . is a matter of bracketing, but not of denying, predicates that are true
of the matter under discussion”; in contrast, an assumption “idealises when it ascribes
predicates . . . that are false in the case in hand, and so denies predicates that are true
of that case.” (Onora O’Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue. A Constructive Account of
Practical Reasoning [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996], 40-41.) The
assumption of convergence is rather different from that of full compliance. The latter
is also sometimes regarded as an idealization, but that is misleading: it is not an
assumption introduced for the purpose of simplifying the construction of the theory,
but rather it is part of what makes a theory ideal in the relevant sense: a society could
not be fully just unless its institutions realize the relevant principles of justice and its
members comply with the principles of justice that apply to them.
18
Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 218, 6. It can be misleading to regard
idealizations as falsehoods in the way that O’Neill does. In ideal theories, they are
best understood as a kind of counterfactual reasoning. Rawls is not asserting that all
members of society are able to manage their own affairs or that societies are closed
systems; instead he is asking what principles would apply to a society in which all its
members had capacities above a particular threshold, joined it at birth, and exited it at
death.
35
19
For relevant discussion, see especially Laura Valentini, “On the Apparent
Paradox of Ideal Theory,” Journal of Political Philosophy 17 ( 2009), 332-55; Colin
Farrelly, “Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation,” Political Studies 55 (2007), 844-64.
20
We might also distinguish between action guidance and practical relevance.
Even if an ideal theory could not provide us with reasons for action here and now but
is likely to provide us with reasons for action in the foreseeable future, then that
would show that it has practical relevance. Indeed, if we cannot justifiably rule out the
possibility that the theory will provide reasons for action in the foreseeable future,
then that would seem to be enough to show that it has practical relevance.
21
See Sleat, “Realism, Liberalism and Non-ideal Theory.”
22
See Matt Sleat, “What is a Political Value?” this volume.
23
See Mason, “Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of Politics.”
24
Cf. Bernard Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2005), 8-10.
25
See David Estlund, “What Good Is It? Unrealistic Political Theory and the
Value of Intellectual Work,” Analyse and Kritik 33 (2011): 395-416
26
See Hamlin and Stemplowska, “Theory, Ideal Theory and the Theory of
Ideals,” 52-58; Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, 268. See also Adam Swift,
“The Value of Philosophy in Nonideal Circumstances,” Social Theory and Practice
34 (2008): 363-87, especially 366-68; Estlund, “What Good Is It?”
27
Edward Hall, “Political Realism and Fact-Sensitivity,” Res Publica 19
(2013): 173-81, at 174; see also 175-76.
28
Elizabeth Anderson, The Imperative of Integration (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2010), 6.
36
29
Hall’s thesis seems to rule out the possibility of deontological principles that
give us pro tanto reasons for prohibiting certain kinds of actions independently of
what costs would be incurred in doing so. But it is primarily directed against the factinsensitive ultimate principles that are not tailored to fit any practical purposes that G.
A. Cohen thinks underpin rules of regulations that guide our decision making.
30
Galston, “Realism in Political Theory,” 393.
31
For Wittgenstein’s remarks on rule-following, see Ludwig Wittgenstein,
Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, 3d ed. (Oxford: Blackwell,
1967), paragraphs 138-242.
32
See Elizabeth Anderson, “Reply to Critics of The Imperative of
Integration,” Political Studies Review 12 (2014), 376-82, at 379.
33
In this context it is worth noting that G. A. Cohen responds to Anderson’s
own critique of luck egalitarianism, which argues against luck egalitarianism partly by
considering what the effects would be of implementing it, by maintaining that her
argument does not undermine the luck egalitarian principle itself but merely shows
that we need to consider the costs in terms of other values of trying to implement it
and then balance the value of implementing it against those costs. See Elizabeth
Anderson, “What Is the Point of Equality?” Ethics 109 (1999): 287-337; Cohen,
Rescuing Justice and Equality, 271.
34
Hall, “Political Realism and Fact-Sensitivity,” 178.
35
For relevant discussion, see Anca Gheaus, “The Feasibility Constraint on
the Concept of Justice,” The Philosophical Quarterly 63 (2013): 445-64; Andrew
Williams, “Justice, Incentives and Constructivism,” Ratio 21 (2008): 476-93, at 49092; Adam Swift and Zofia Stemplowska, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” in David
37
Estlund, ed., Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2012), 384-85.
36
See Andrew Mason, “What is the Point of Justice?” Utilitas 24 (2012):
525-47, at 527-28.
37
See David Miller, “A Tale of Two Cities; or, Political Philosophy as
Lamentation,” in his Justice for Earthlings: Essays in Political Philosophy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 237-39.
38
Simon Hope emphasizes the idea that reflecting upon what justice requires
of us individually or collectively is a form of practical reason rather than theoretical
reason. See Simon Hope, “Idealization, Justice, and Practical Reason,” this volume.
39
It seems to have highly counterintuitive consequences. See Gheaus, “The
Feasibility Constraint on the Concept of Justice,” 452.
40
Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, 251.
41
Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, 252.
42
For the distinction between ultimate principles and rules of regulation, see
Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, chaps. 6-7, esp. 263ff.
43
This would not undermine Cohen’s thesis that ultimate principles are not
grounded in facts of any kind. As he emphasizes, when a fact is a condition of the
application of a principle, it is not part of the justification of it. See Cohen, Rescuing
Justice and Equality, 331-36.
44
See Amartya Sen, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?” The
Journal of Philosophy 103 (2006): 215-38; The Idea of Justice (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2009). See also Anderson, The Imperative of Integration, 3.
38
45
See Dunn, Interpreting Political Responsibility, 197. See also Judith N.
Shklar, “The Liberalism of Fear,” in J. N. Shklar, Political Thought and Political
Thinkers, ed. S. Hoffman (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 10-11.
46
Judith J. Thomson, “A Defence of Abortion,” Philosophy and Public Affairs
1 (1971): 47-66.
47
For more on the nature of analogical reasoning, and defenses of it, see
Mason, Explaining Political Disagreement, 30-35; Cass Sunstein, “On Analogical
Reasoning,” Harvard Law Review 106 (1993): 741-91, especially 773-81.
48
Galston, “Realism in Political Theory,” 402-3. The title of David Miller’s
paper, “Political Philosophy for Earthlings,” in his Justice for Earthlings: Essays in
Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), alludes to
much the same point.
49
Miller, “Political Philosophy for Earthlings,” 31.
50
See Mason, “What is the Point of Justice?” 539, 546.
51
Simmons, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” 21ff; 34-36. Rawls maintains that
ideal theory provides “the only basis for the systematic grasp” of the problems raised
by noncompliance that are treated within nonideal theory, and that ideal theory “is the
fundamental part of the theory of justice and essential for the nonideal part as well”
(Rawls, A Theory of Justice,8, 343).
52
Simmons, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” 22.
53
Suppose for example that a society has reasons of justice for putting in place
a package of austerity measures, but adopting that package would make it highly
likely that a fascist government will end up in power. We don’t need an ideal theory
of justice to believe with justification that it would be better not to implement the
austerity measures. I owe this example to Jerry Gaus.
39
54
Nor do we even have the kind of knowledge that would enable us reliably to
distinguish hard from soft constraints in our determination of what constitutes perfect
justice. See also Hamlin and Stemplowska, “Theory, Ideal Theory and the Theory of
Ideals,” 59; Swift and Stemplowska, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” 379-80.
55
Simmons, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” 24.
56
For discussion of the distinction between what people can’t do and what
they won’t do and its significance for normative theory, see David Estlund,
Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2008), 264-70; “Utopophobia,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 42
(2014): 113-34.
57
See Rawls, Political Liberalism, xix; Justice as Fairness: A Restatement
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 13.
58
Miller thinks that Rawls’s feasibility condition also excludes principles with
implications that we would find intolerable: "for Rawls the limits of political
possibility are set not just by political laws, but by the range of outcomes that we —
people in modern liberal societies — would regard as fundamentally unacceptable”
(Miller, “Political Philosophy for Earthlings,” 33).
59
Allen Buchanan, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination. Moral
Foundations of International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 60-62.
60
Simmons, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” 29-30.
61
See Paul Feyerabend, Against Method 3d ed. (London: Verso, 1993),
especially chap. 1.
62
Miller seems to deny that this is a legitimate form of political theorizing: see
“Political Philosophy for Earthlings,” 46-47.
63
See Schmidtz, “Nonideal Theory,” 774.
40
64
Indeed, it seems to me that these are the reasons why G. A. Cohen thought
we should strive to identify the correct fundamental principles of justice; it’s not that
he thought that the project of devising the best “rules of regulation” for a society was
unimportant.