Docimini 'Ramis
.
)3jurlof,
AUTHOR
TITLE
PUB DATE
NOTE
-
A
010 057
Thomas; Jamieson, Dale
Semantics -and the Number of English .Sentences.
78
17p.
.
MRS PRICE
DESCRIPTORS
,6
:
'
'HF-80.83.HC-S1.6i4Ius Postage.
Coaprehension; Deep Structitre; *English; Grammar;*
Language Patterns; *Linguistic Theory: Logic;
Nominkls; *Seafinticv *Sentences;.*Sentence.
Structure;_Surface Stracture;.Synta:x
*Chomsky (Boas)
.
-
,
IDENTIFIERS
..
.
-
ABSTRACT
41,
as to no been said that there ate.an infinIte'
It
t*.is
number of English sentenceo. "This is the cat- 'that caught the
an English'sestenCe. So is "This is thftiCa*.that caught the rat. i that
stole the cheesp...."_?.This is the cat with white paws.thaVcaugh the
rat that stole the timed'', is unobjectionable as well. Since a.aear
W
t
cutoff point cannot be'ecified, it is`temptipg to resort or
"the
three dots.r_This studyrproposes that the argugent from-t4e'lack of a
clear cutoff,point
infinity is a bad argument; the set of English.
sentences may be
fizzy set rather than a standard set. Furthermore,
it is .argued tha !the initial question 'suppresses several quite,
1
distinct 4W4stio s: A theory constructed to acCount,for4formal,
relations between 'sentences' - sight warrant the poRiting of infinite
semantic-structures. 1. theory cdmisttudted to account- fOr humAn
understanding probabLy would not. 'The Common claim that infinity is
necessary if there are to be' novel and Areative uses'ofzlanguage is
found to to be entirely without gihstante. (AnthOr/AN)
.
;, ..
:
.
-
,
"x
4
44,
i
**************7!***************4,*4*********41,*************4***O*:,
*
Reproductions .supplied by EDES "aief the ,best that can Ppe 'made
,
from the.:30riginel.,.'docupent.. '-'1
c ''.! .
*
*
.
*******************4!******************* ******4,*`*************-***********
,
.,
.
,,
1.."
.
.--I
-
.
40
SEMANTICS AND THE_NUM3ER OF ENGLISH SENTENCES
4.
f
I)
CY
u.AYbaPAINTAMINIT OF HEALTH.
-PERMISSION TO REPRODOCE; THIS
MATERIAL HAS BEEN. GRANTED BY
EDUCATION a WELFARE
NATIONAL INSTITUTE OP
EDUCATION
.
P
THLS DOCUMENT HAS SEEN REPRO
-t
DUCED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED FROM
Ting PERSON OR ORGANQAT ION
ta,t1wo IT POINTS Or VIEW OR OPINIONS
STATED DO NOT NECESsARtLY REPerE;SENT OFFICIAL NATIONAL leesTITutg OF
EDUCATION POSITION OR POLICY
TO THE EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES
INFORMATION SENTER (ERIC) AND
I.
.46 USERS OF THE ERIC SYSTEM: ".
e
ti
-
4
`
-6
by
0
O
O
.17)
Thomas pjurlOf
Departmept of Philosophy
Dale' Jamieson
Unixi.pi"sity'of North Carolina
ChapeltHill, NC 27514
.
_Department ofePhilosophyState Univei;sity of New York
pollege at Fredonia,
-'Fredcnia,.!0/
.
e
S
14,653
.
401.
" tql
s
4
SemanticsAnd The Number of ..EvgliSh Sentences
1.
How mapy
English sentences can be understood?
4
Veryt, very
0
many.
Noam Ch6msky has said and perhaps woufa'stilIIsay
indefiAtely many or infinitely many (not noticing the
difference, of which more later).1.. How many English .sen-'
fences are there? 'Zellig Harris has said and perhaps,
would still say denumerably infinitely many.2
Many or
.
.7
very many is not.enaugh according to Chom sky and Harris.'
The dsiffetence between very large members and in-inity is
.supposed to reflect interesting'" features of human languages.
2.
These Views have recently, been`challenged-by,Paul Ziff.3
1
...:there - .;;moo, important sense in which
it is trlike that there are infinitely Ak
many English sentences.4,
Ziff would agree that there is an unimportant sense in which
lgott
.
therE`A're'infinitely many English sentences." One van do
9.'4,00r5.
arithmetic in English:
But Ziff. thinks that this, possibility
"Is not Elldminating with respect to English structure or
'.%English grammar or anything like-it."5
Ziff has* no quarrqa.
with syntactit components that generate infinitely many
syntactic'
structures.
His qualms en
with semantics.
Although it is child's play to characterize powerful syntactic devices-capable of
%enerating.an infinity of sentences there's
no reason to believe that the semantics
- of English (or of any natural language) is
ota consonant or even coMparable character.°
And he gores on.
Inevitably one will produce nons nical
sentences or sentences that are tterly
incompreheil§ible to speakers of t 4
"language.)
3.
Jonathan Bennett-has responded ioZiff's challenge.
In
his Linguistic Behaviour Bennett replies to Ziff with the
following.
Butthe question 'How many English sentences are there?' does not mean 'How
many sentences are there which would be
understood by speakers of English?' and
no one would give the answer 'infinitely
many' to the latter question...The notion
of what has meaning iS admittedly founded
upon .the notion of what is
a
the two are not ce-extensive.
but
Bennett supposas that the notion "what has moOkning" and-the
notion "what is understood" have extensions.. Thus he sup-
poses tHht there 3.s some-cIassose members are "what bias
mpaning".and another class whose members are "what is Understood."
.Bennett aIso.talks about "the class of 'English
7
sentences ".`9
But these predicates are not well-defined.
Hence there is no sib .thing as : "the class of 'English
sentence: ", npr tho -;cXenSipns .of the notions "what has mean.
.
10'"But if we suppose that
j_neo:and nwh.a7t, is lirder,ktood.
goes-make sense" to talk abOli.extensions in this context,
.
.
Bennett.is certainly corre'ct: :There are English sentences
:
.
th.. -1. ;411 never be u nderstood- by En lish-speakers.
.
Some since
.
they will ne4T.be uttered,.some- since _they are too complex,
$
some fdr ci,ther..reasoris.
Bennett assumes a stronger thesis
wl
.7
P
a
3
however.
He assume
-that there are English sentences that
could not be uRdeAtood by English-speakers.
.
4. .If Ziff's position were'that being ai,sentence (or having
meaning) is co- extensive with being understood, then, Bennett
uld have an easy victory and Ziff's paper could largely
e ignored.
Things are not thatiimpli, however.
Let'us look'at an example.'
dinar2y we have no diffi-
culty in understanding the following sentences:
(a)
My uncle is a linguist.
(b)
My father's brother is aclinguist.
(a) and (b) have (roughly) the same meaning. 11
(Notice' that-one might very well know the meaning of a
entenceor that two sentences are synonymous without having
understOoif the sentences.
Someone might know that the sen-
tence written on a piece of rper.in,his left pocket has
(roughly) the sarte meaning .as the sentence written on.a
piece Ad' paper in hiA right pockethim so.
sentence.
SozeoAle...might have told
Nevertheless he might not have Understood either
He might never have looked at.them.)
Suppose that
from tomorrow on English speakers cannot make heads or tails
of subordinate groups of two Nouns if the noun?, can be re=
versed.
Examples Of such pairs would be 'mother's daughter',
'father's brother' and 'a circle under a triangle'.
T
Would
-
Ziff say that since (b) cannot be understood by English
speakers, although
:
/) presents no problems, "Cb) is not an
4
an English sentence?
We hope not.
Failure to understand
(b) need not be ettributed to the se
ntics o
(b), but
should most likely be attributed to n urological factors.
/
After all, (al and (b) have (roughly)
(Roan
he same meaning.
Jakobson discusses a type of aphasia that would ex.
plain our case.12)
What Ziff. would say is that failure to
understand a candidate .for an English sentence may disqualify
it as an English sentence if the failure can be attributed
tg semantic factors.13
He does not say that a candidate
for an English sentence must be disqualified if the failure
can be attributed to neurological factors.'''
S.
One has to be careful in attributing the failure to understand a sentence to semantic factors.
Some cases are fairly
114
straight forward:. The failure b3=lsomeone under some' condition
to understand
(c)
7.is green.
could be attributed to the fact that .a number is. not +he= kind
of thing that is colored; and this might be thought of as a
semantic factOr.
Notice that we don't claim that anyone would
fail to understand an utterance of (c) under any conditions
whatever, just that there are conditions under which someone/,
would fail to underrstand (c) due to semantic factors.
Why do we attribute this faillire of understanding to
semantic factors?
Because we take (c) to haver the syntactic
structure MP + VP, and
ence to be syntactically well-formed.
1
Thus, this failure of understanding must be due to sementic factors.
Contrast (c) with 'Ball dolphin mop cathedrhl.'
a string that has the Syntactic structure NP + NP + NP
and thus is not syntactically well-formed.
(Of course schemes
have been devised that count all deviance as syntactic.
Similarly schemes have been devised that count all deviance
as semantic. Neieher seem particularly well-motivated.14)
A
FUrther complications are presented by other cases.
For example
_..
(d)
This sentence is in English.
If someone cannot understand an utterance of (d)
because he
cannot figure out that 'this' in '(d) refers to,(d), the fail.
ure to understand (d) cannot be attributed to semantic faCtors
namely, the refepence of 'this' in
d) on this occasion.
kather'it-can be attributed to the failure to appreciate-the
,relevant semantic factors. ."'But don't confuse the last ease
with the following;
-ft)
This
ntence- is ,falie.
f
One Could argue that, if conceived self-referentially, (e)
could not be'understo
y any English speaker.
(e) is, of.'
course, a version of
he well-known "liar paradox."
assume it to be tr e
t.follows that it is-false and vice
versa.
No vle kno
.4
7,41
at it would be like for (e)-to be true,
or what it would 14 ike4for it to be false.
pursue this line
If we,
argunient.15'
We will not
6.
any linguists c14 that that there are infinitely many
English sentences.
is an answer to.
It is often unclear what question this
How many English-sentences are there, of
course; but as we shall see, what is asked by this question
is far from clear.
Here i
an example:
It is astonishing to find that even this
truism [the implicit ability to understand
indefinitely many sentences] has recently
been challenged. See Dixon (1963). However, it seems that when Dixon denies that
a language has infinitely maiy sentences,
he is using the term "infinite" in some
special and rather obscure sense. Thus on
the same page (p.. 83) on which he objects
to the assertion "that there are an infinite number of sentences in a language" he
states that "we are clearly unable to say
that there is any definite number, N, such
that no sentence contains more than N
clauses" (that is, he states that the'
language is infinite). Either this is a
blatant self-contradiction, or else he has
some new sense of word "infinite" in mind.16
A
-
ti
.
But surely the mistake is Chomsky's, and Dixon is-not con*
tredicting himself.
.
On Chomsky's view, that there is no
'
4(
definite nutter of English semiencAs
is equivalent to the
.
claim tbdc there-are infinitely many ;nglish
sentences.- Why
rot, not infinitely many but no definite number?
In standard
set theOry 17 if a set has no definite finite number of
elements:
4
it. has infinitely many elements. And all finite sets
have a
deeinite number of eleznants.
But these are standard
where_ membership is we.17defined.
or it is not.
.
Somethingw.7Ither e :Amber
If we take another approach and think of the
set of English sentences as a fuzzy set indefinite, does
not,
IR.
imply infinite.
In fuzzy set theory membership is graded.
.
An element is assigned a numbet in the inclusive interval
(0,1).
The number assigned to an element with respect
set is the-degree to which that element beiongs
It does not make sense to ask how many membe
o a
the set.
a fuzzy set
1111.
has since membership in a fuzzy set is not an either/or
'question.
There is, for example, no answer to the question:
.
-.
How many tall men are there?
Some people are taller than
....,f
others.
S
are clearly members of the (fuzzy) set of tall
men. :.Some not so clearly.
tall'men gre there?
Some clearly not.
No answer.
04t how many
°
And it does not follow that
there are infinitely many tall men.18
Mgybe Chomsky tholighf of this: Whis is the cat that
caught the rat.' is an English sentence.
So is "This it the I
1*
cat that caught the rat that stole the cheese.'.
'This is the
cat with white paws that caught the rat that stole the cheese.'
is also an English sentence'.
And it seems that one can,go
on like this.
There is no definite cutoff
For how long?
point Chomsky claims, and he is right.
one can go on forever?
That is, have we shown that there is
unbounded redursionk English?
we nee
Of course not,
To show this
a proof of unbounded recursion and not just a proof
\
that the
Does it follow that
is no definite cutoff point.
,
Chomsky does.not
.
provide such a proof.
That there is no definite cloff point
,
.
,does not create any problems.
Maybe we are dealing with fuzzy
setS,,and. then we do not need definite `,cutoff points.
I
8
7.
How
many'Elph
sentences are there?
Is the question how
many English sentences car be understood?
Or how many syn-
tactically well-forr4e4 English sentences are there?
Or hout-
many syntactic structures, a. syntactic tlileory of English. shOuld
generate?
,
.
Or how many semantically non-deviant English
sentences are there?
Or how many English sentences a semat'
tic theory of English should account for?
Or how many'accept.
,
able English sentences are there?
We will not quarrel with an ininite syntactic
ent;
Maybe infinity allows us to simplify-syntaotic theory.
Maybe it makes it less complicated.
'\
ii
infinity
Ziff's rejection of
is based on semantics, and we will at-tend
end to
The question is:
8.
man-
,
.
tic structures in the following.
si
.
,
How many English_sentenc0 shoula a
semantic theory of English account for?
What should a semantic theory.do?
But a priar question:
Asvig meaning to Syntactic'.
structures; - account for saneness of meani
between sen'tences;
.
phrases,. words and Mbrphemes;'account for paraphrase'; chirac;5
terize logica
and sem4ntic entailmen
These are
.
commonly cited requirements..
If we, start with an infinite
syatactic component and adopt these requirements (o'r at least
some of them, and no others), then"a semantic theory should.
%.
account for an infinite numb:r of English sentences:
-
This is-
.4.
the picture exhibited by philosophers and log.cians such as
'_ Richard Montague and Donald Davidson.
A langtage is thougIt
of.as an abstradt structure, notts a means of cpmmUniktiCin
.
10
9
among humans
But there is a piroblem.
In most formal
theories the syntax is constructed so that it.fits the
se
inc
ntics, and syntactic and semantic well-formedness coLinguists have often made a distinction bqtween
e.
sentences which are' syntactically lcviant and those which
Are semantically deviant, and thes,notions do not coincide.
Sentence (c) on ,page 4 is perhaps syntactically well - formed.
That is, there might be a reasonable syntactic theory of
English such that (c) does not violate any rule in this
theory.
But it is semantically deviant.
There are diffi1
culties in drawing a~ line between syntactic and semantic
deviance. 20
The distInction is clear enough, however, to
allow one ti6 point to sentences .Shat do not 'violate
syntactic rule .but do violate semian'tic rules. -In other
words:
Not every syntactically well-formed sentence is
semantically well-formed.
This is enough to show that an
_infinite syntactic component does not imply an infinite
semantic- component.
conclusion.
We need non.syntactkedarv'm
for this
One such argument could be that infinity in
semantics allows forsimpler semantic theories. Bdnnett argues
op
in-this way in Linguistic Behavior.21
.
Given the primitive:
state of semantic thebry this argument is AiffiCult toeeval%late, so we will remain agnostic on this .point.
9.
.Something is'missing from the picture exhibited.by
411.
Montague and Davidson.
Sometimes more is. wanted fr/M a
semantic theory than that
relations.
account for formal semantic
Some have wanted semantic theory to lid in the
`
10
understanding of what it in to understand a sontenee
(phrase, word, morpheme):
This concern with understanding
is a characteristic of Ziff's work in linguistics and
semantics.??
It serves to distinguish Ziff's work from that
of Montague .and Davidson.
s
Is there anything infiniti about understanding?
trivial sense the answer is no:
In a
People's lives are finite,
attention-spans are short, memories are limited.
Linguists in the Chomsky-Katz mold also claim to be concerncd with understanding:
We may thus regard'the development of a model
of the semantic .component as taking .up the
explanation of,a speaker's ability to produce
and understand indefinitely many new sentences."
3ut they are unimpressed with short attention-spans and limited
memories:
Linguistic theory is concerned primarily with
an ideal spea)er-listener,in a completely homogvnebuS speech-community, who knows its lang. uage perfectly and is unaffected by such.
grammatically irrelevant conditions as memory
iimitarions 1 dis-tracTions , shifTn "of`" artention
and inteest( and errors (rardom or character-istic) in applying his knowledge of the language
in actual performance.24
These linguists explicitly hold .that there is an infinite num.ber of English senteces.
How can the concern with understand-
ing be reconciled with this claim?
In the following way:
Ling.:istics is not about "cheap empirical facts"; it is about
the behavior of ideal speaker hearers.
Two lines of assault can be mountea against this position.'
.
One could disagree with -6-14 goals- of linguistic the°
.. conceived by Chomsky and Katz. This we shall not do;
.444aasssbeen well don4 elsew'here..2 5 Instead we will take
another
,
tine of 'assault. 'Let us require of a: semantic
theory that it
__:
-eee6count for the
mploYed by speaker-hearers in
employed
..,
1c
understanding
.
.
sentences.
What are strategies? A strategy . would not be so-called
it did not aid in achieving what it is a strategy for.
Strategies are like algorithms.;, both are procedures for solving
problems. Howekft fall.gbrithis are like strategies ;
4.1
-
strategies- are
icient -proced-urs for...solving prcsblems.
There are ,problems for which algorithms exist but require so
7,1\
.mUch
timie.'fof
their implementation.'that in practice. they can...
not be
, employed. (The only 'known algorithms that. are solutions
to the problem of the' traveling sales
tour is ;an example.26)
The strategies ,employed by human speake hewers cannot be of,'
this. kind. If they-Were;; 'the. rapiditylof human understands
would be left. unexplained. But this argument for the efficiency.
,
of the strategies
argument for the
employed by qiuman
.speaker-thearers is not an
.
such strategies. It oculd be
the case that there are strategies like the following:
finiteness of
a means
as means what a means
means what a means
%.
JS-
\
.
That 1
12
*11.
every seciuence of a's, raea,n
what.:Clid initial a means:
This. stiAtegy-i.rould be efficient'and would account for an ink*
.
Here the problem is not with under,.
number of sentences.
finite
--
4"
standing but With-prOduction. -ftmarrspeakelphearers do notand"
17'.
could
produce such ,sentences Cat least past some unspecified
number Of iterations).
Since humanspeaker-hearers do nOt acid
sudh,entences, there is no reason to believe
Leould note
sproducb
that such "strategies are employed in'understanding.
*
/What 2igf'says is right: It is not pere.chance that only a
finite number of sentences are uttered and understood; it could
not be gtherw ise.
The strategies empldyed by human speaker:-c
hearers in understanding are finite, however-ideal.you want these
humaris to be; and 'what-.humans opera''te on is finite as' well.
lit
o.
An 'nfinitk'ofsentences is .a lot.
One'can.go 'on and on and
on and on and on and-64:*0 not,r4.Ch:infinity., HoW-many English
a '
sentences are there? :Probably not as many as there,are electrons
...
in the universe.
.
Probably not 10
79
.
,
But you may not be. swayed. .What about novelty?
.
creativity?
.
,
What about
C
.
What about the do-called "rationalistu'tradition in
i
linguistics?
One bad argUMent that is "repeated in the,lingUistic.
literature is that infinity is required if we are to say hew and
.
1114,
,
.
: interesting things.. But aselmostL.eveyone knows; only a finite
°
number of En5;ish sentences"nae been and will be uttered.
:Finnegan's Wake, 77 Dream Songs and all of'ShakesPeare and
Striridberg were written from finite resources.
.
.;
14
-
But again one
,11 7!
"t
might say4that none of these ;works could have been written. we
.
there not an infinite number of unuttered s-entences.
have thought
One w
.N.-
th.a.-t. Linguistics is an empirical science.
'Nos; we.
l'
.
discover that it
--Wj. ''
h4unts the realin,of "unactualized:possib-leatc-'!-:-,',71"
_
,
:,
..*r%
Linguists who make such claims 4.evour themselves.:2/-..,
( ,, . k -2-4,-,-'
\ '''
f
I'j
):
//
/
\
6 .r.
..6.2:.
1
1
l
;
.1
a.
1
3
116
J
'
NOTES,
,
.
r
of the Theory of Syntax, MIT Press, 1965, lip.
1S.
3-62..
Z.
(
ris, kathematical Structures of Language, Interseience Pub -
ers3
1968- pp.14--.1.1.
.
3P;75.ff "The ,Number of English Sentences," Foundations of Language
1974,'pp..519-532.
)Ibid. , p. 19.
-N
p. 521.
6Ibid., pp. 529-530.
7
p p -530
8
J. 1,"
Bennett; Linguistic Behaviour, Cambridge University:Press, 1976
pp. 279-280.
9
Ibid., p. 279.
10On this point
see Dana Scott's excellent es ;ay, "Background to
Formalization, "" in
Truth., Syntax and Modality, H. LeBlanc (ed.) ,'
North Holland, 1973, p. 244 -273_,
`11 There is, a ,comiilication that
we shall ignore: An uncle can be a
-;*.zinoti-fer's%br ther or an aunts husband rather than a. fathero's
brother;:
7
ti
Jakobsori::-, Studies on Child Language and Aphasia, Mouton
'197f- -pp 75-1'4..
fact he has said this in conversation. It is difficult to,. find
this., view stated, explingitly in "The Number of English Sentences,"
however.
14See
See forf,example: J. McCawl,ey, '''Concerning the Bas.e Component in
a, Trams farmational Grammar "', Foundation of Language 1968 pp . 243 - 269;-'.
and K. An.tley, "McCawley's Theory of Sel-ectional Restriction,
Foundations of Language 21'97.4, pp., -257-272.
15
For this, vieur, see P. Ziff,. Semantic Analysis, Cornell' University
Press, 1960, 'plb 136-138:
0
16T
N.Chansky,oD.cit., footnote 9, p. 198.
The inserted clause is from
p. 15. The reference tg,Dixon is to his Linguistic Science and
Logic, Mouton & Co., 196'3.
16
17
An elementary'introduction to set theory can be found in R. Stoll,
Set Theory and Logic, W. H. Freeman and Company; 1963.
4
18 10
1
fuzzy set theory has been developed in great detail. The locus
classicus is Zadeh, "Fuzzy Sets," Information and Control MS;
pp.' 338-353.
&See, for example, the papers by Montague sand Davidson in Semantics
cof Natural Language, D. Davidson and G. Harman Cedb.:), Reidel, 1972.0
For dascussions of some of these difficulties, see: U.
"ExPlorations in Semantid' Theory," in etIrrentiti,ends in Linguistics
Volum* III, T. Sebeok,(ed.), Mouton,,
Turnings, Cornell University Press, 19b6, pp. 119-133; G. Lakbff,
"On Generative Semantics," in Semantics, D. Steirgoerg and L.
Jakobovits(eds.), Cambridge University Press, 1971, pp. 232-296.
21
22
0. cit.., gip. 277-278.
See, for example, Understanding Understanding, Cornell-Ufilversity
Press, 1972.
2S
24
25
J. Xatz, Philosophy of Language,, aarper-&-Row, 1966, p. 151.
.
.-
N. Chomsky, op.cit.,
:
.
.
.
3.
,
.
.
See, for example, D. Hymes, "Toward .Linguistic Competence, Working
Papers in Sociolinguistics 16, University of Texas at Austin,'
Department of Anthropology; G. Harman, "PdYchological.Aspectsiof the
Theory of .Syntax," Journal of Philosophy 1967, pp.. 75-q7; B. berwing,
Transformational Grammar as a Theory. of Language Acquisition,
Cambridge University Press, 1973, -pp. 259-296.
'
.
26
27
.
..,
.
..-
See H. Lewis and C; Papadimitrii.ou, " Thg Efficiency of' Algorithms ,"
Scientific American 1978, pp. 96-109:,
earlier
1
An earlier :version of this paper was presented at a, conference on"Productivity, NoVelty, and Creativity in Language" at the University
of Louisville. Ike wish to thank'JonatIlan Bennett and Paul Ziff for
aluable correspondence and conversatiO t concerning these topics.
r
Thanks also to R. J. Haack and Richard Sharvy.
'