REVIEWS
Ahmed Alwishah & Josh Hayes (eds.). Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2015. 278 pages. ISBN: 9781107101739.
Peter Adamson*
Some sense of Aristotle’s standing in Islamic culture is conveyed by a hadīth in
which the Prophet proclaimed, “I am the Aristotle of this community.” As in Latin,
one could simply say in Arabic “the Philosopher” and expect readers to know who was
meant. And when al-Fārābī was honored with the title of “the second master,” it was
superluous to identify the irst. Admittedly Avicenna, the Islamic world’s greatest
early thinker, displaced Aristotle as the central philosophical igure in the eyes of
subsequent generations. But in what I would call the “formative period” of philosophy
in the Islamic world – that is, up to the time of Avicenna – the study of philosophy
was, much as in Latin Christendom, nearly synonymous with the study of Aristotle.
Even thereafter, attempts were made to ight the tide of Avicennism by reinstating
Aristotle’s authority, as both Averroes and ‘Abd al-Latīf al-Baghdādī sought to do. here
was also a resurgence of interest in Aristotle’s works, along with other Hellenic sources,
during the Safavid period.
All of this means that there is plenty of material to be tackled in a book entitled
Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition. Indeed, the volume’s editors have had to deine their
remit more narrowly than the title could suggest, for a full examination of this topic
would be tantamount to a undertaking a general survey of philosophy in the formative
period and of Aristotle’s continued relevance even today. Eschewing this unfeasibly
broad conception, the editors have gathered papers looking at the transmission of
Aristotle’s works and at some of the leading Muslim thinkers’ direct engagements with
his thought during the formative period.
he volume is organized in keeping with curriculum of Aristotelian studies in Late
Antiquity. After a general discussion of the Arabs’ reception of Aristotle by Cristina
(not “Christina,” as this book persistently calls her) D’Ancona, it begins with the
contributions of two papers by Paul hom and Riccardo Strobino, respectively, on
Avicenna’s use of Aristotle as regards logic. hese are followed by papers on Poetics and
*
Prof. Dr., Fakultät für Philosophie, Wissenschaftstheorie und Religionswissenschaft, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München
DOI dx.doi.org/10.15808/Nazariyat.2.3.D0020
NAZARİYAT Journal for the History of Islamic Philosophy and Sciences
Rhetoric – which belong here, given the “extended Organon” of the Arabic tradition
– by Uwe Vagelpohl and Frédérique Woerther. Paul Lettinck and Andreas Lammer
contribute papers on natural philosophy, and the psychology or philosophy of the
mind (for Avicenna and many others, an aspect of natural philosophy) is dealt with
by Ahmed Alwishah and Yehuda Halper. After Calvin Normore’s general look at
the nature of metaphysics in the Islamic world, the volume ends with Josh Hayes’
summation of what is known about the Arabs’ reception of Aristotle’s Ethics and
Claudia Baracchi’s rather bewildering piece on political philosophy.
Before picking out some of the more interesting themes, I would like to dwell
upon what is not, or only barely, included here. his is not necessarily meant as a
criticism, for, as already noted, the editors had to limit their project’s scope. But
given that their chosen focus is rather traditional, it may be worth pointing out
other directions that could have been explored. First, it is worth emphasizing the
philological importance of the medieval Arabic-language translations of Aristotle.
Given that these translations are based on very early and now lost manuscripts, they
represent witnesses that should be taken seriously in textual criticism regarding
Aristotle himself. Second, the reception of Aristotle in Arabic does continue beyond
the formative period; however, the papers presented here do not (to his credit,
Normore highlights this limitation of his piece: pp. 178, 199).
hird, “the Arabic tradition” would include Jewish and Christian thinkers,
who, however, receive little coverage here. For example, the Christian Yahyā Ibn
‘Adī, recognized by his contemporaries as the leading Aristotelian of his time, is
mentioned only once (by Lammer, p. 128). Fourth, and along the same lines, the
Muslim thinkers focused upon are mostly the usual suspects; al-Kindī, al-Fārābī,
Avicenna, and Averroes feature prominently. A fortiori almost nothing is said about
the impact of Aristotle beyond the narrow bounds of falsafa, even though such
things as the hadīth mentioned above and his frequent appearance as a wise sage in
“wisdom literature” show that his cultural resonance reached well past such specialist
philosophers as Averroes or the members of the Baghdad School. Here, it might
also be interesting to relect upon areas of his thought that had surprisingly little
echo outside the specialist circles, as Vagelpohl does when he notes the surprising
fact that Arabic culture largely ignored Aristotle’s Poetics and Rhetoric, despite the
centrality of poetry and eloquence in that culture (p. 83).
Fifth and inally, even though D’Ancona notes the importance of the PseudoAristotelian texts on which she is such an expert, the remainder of the volume
focuses squarely on the transmission and use of the authentic Aristotelian corpus.
Again, this is fair enough and probably would even be expected by most readers.
But one should bear in mind that to some extent it may distort the picture of what
“Aristotle” meant in this culture.
184
Reviews
Of course listing the things that a volume has not done is one of the easiest (and
for the editors, most annoying) ways for a reviewer to respond to a book. So let’s
shift our focus to the wealth of interesting contributions that it does make. I will
not survey the content of each article, as such an overview is well presented by the
two editors in their introduction. Rather, I want to dwell on how this volume shows
the distance between the original Aristotle and the Aristotelianism we ind in the
Arabic tradition. Even leaving aside the Pseudo-Aristotelian material, readers were
almost always using Arabic translations and had no recourse to the original Greek
texts. As Vagelpohl puts it, commentators undertook their task within a “closed
circle” (p. 91) and could not know, for instance, that their version of Meteorology was
very diferent from the one transmitted in the Greek tradition (on this example, see
Lettinck, p. 107). Even translations that adhered closely to the Greek necessarily
introduced a whole new layer of technical terminology that became determinative
of Arabic Aristotelianism.
Another kind of distance was introduced by the inluence of Late Antiquity’s
philosophical literature. As Lammer shows, even so fundamental a notion as
“nature” was understood by Arabic philosophers not simply in light of Aristotle’s
deinition in Physics, but through such ancient commentators as Philoponus. he
latter’s Neoplatonic understanding of nature as a “power that has descended into
bodies” (p. 124) became a standard part of the “Aristotelian” deinition of nature
in Arabic, only to be rejected by Avicenna. his illustrates yet another factor that
distanced Arabic Aristotelianism from the teachings of the authentic corpus: the
originality with which that corpus was read, interpreted, and criticized. Reading
Strobino’s detailed discussion of scientiic inquiry in Avicenna, for example, one
sees that he is working within an Aristotelian paradigm and yet bringing to that
paradigm his own concerns and conceptual apparatus (for instance, by aligning
conception and assent with deinition and syllogism, p. 73). His ambitious and
sophisticated theory of self-knowledge and self-awareness, fully studied here by
Alwishah and in a recent book by Jari Kaukua1, is another good example.
Of course Avicenna was unusual in being determinedly original with respect
to his sources, as shown in Dimitri Gutas’ classic and similarly titled Avicenna and
the Aristotelian Tradition.2 But the same goes for more self-consciously Aristotelian
thinkers. his is clear from Halper’s look at “intentionality” in Averroes that,
1
2
Jari Kaukua, Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2015).
Dimitri Gutas, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction to Reading Avicenna’s Philosophical
Works (Second, Revised and Enlarged Edition, Including an Inventory of Avicenna’s Authentic Works)
(Leiden & Boston: Brill, 2014).
185
NAZARİYAT Journal for the History of Islamic Philosophy and Sciences
incidentally, exempliies the point just made about Arabic terminology, with the
notorious case of the untranslatable word ma‘nā, as well as from al-Fārābī’s prologue
to a commentary on Rhetoric. As Woerther shows, this prologue makes numerous
subtle changes to Aristotle, not least by making space for the Qur'ān and the hadīth
within a legal framework (pp. 103-4). Here we see the importance of another
distancing factor, namely, religious context. All three Abrahamic faiths provided a
context for philosophy in the Islamic world, which helps explain why God is more
central in Arabic metaphysics (a discipline that was even called ilāhiyyāt) than in
Aristotle’s Metaphysics.
As these examples will hopefully show, the volume as a whole provides a rich
portrait of Aristotle’s reception in the formative period. It ofers both original
research and more general pieces that bring together the state of the art on a given
topic in chapters that could have been at home in a “companion” or “handbook”
to the Arabic-language Aristotle. I take it that this mixture is intentional, in light
of the editors’ own contributions: Alwishah’s piece on self-awareness criticizes
and goes beyond previous secondary literature, whereas Hayes’ chapter on Ethics
is largely a summary of what has already been established by previous scholarship.
hus any reader with an interest in the Arabic reception of Aristotle will want to
read this book, even if specialists may ind some of the material familiar and those
who are new to the subject may ind that some of the contributions require a degree
of background knowledge that they do not possess.
186