Herbert Read Gallery
University for the Creative Arts
Canterbury, UK
Inspired by the actions and interactions between
the purposeful individual, the ‘smart’ object, and
the social body.
Intentionality is bound up with individualism
— Mieke Bal.
One can have a goal but be in no condition to achieve it. Yet, can one gain agency
yet avoid intentionality? Through four diferent projects this exhibition explores the apparent
contingent relation between actions and purposes in four arenas: the technological, the
aesthetic, the political, and the social.
Abdulbari Kutbi’s Pirouette Robots roam around the Herbert Read Gallery, changing
their direction of progress when inding obstacles. Although able to take simple decisions
thanks to a system of interconnected nodes, as with more complex examples of Artiicial
Intelligence, the question of the machine’s own will remain for now an attractive possibility.
Amongst the robots, Abigail Hunt and Kieren Reed’s artwork Liminal occupies the
gallery space. Made up of several dozens of simple geometric sculptures, it is a piece to be
experienced through action. Visitors are invited to activate the work with the hope that their
participation will provoke moments of unsolicited disorientation, exchange, and discussion.
/5
Recent political eforts such as the international Occupy movements, or the Spanish
‘Los Indignados’, have been criticised for their lack of concrete objectives. Now that the
outcomes of those movements are becoming viable political options with clear intentions,
it is worth considering how to gain agency while avoiding the instrumentalization of one’s
actions. Rosana Antolí’s video and performance Disobedient Silences recognises the risks
of aligning actions and purposes by transforming the gallery into a space of protest for
bodies and objects.
Agency is always relational; it depends on our position within a group or in a situation.
On 15th September 2015, members of the community who are researching and developing
Turner Contemporary’s 2018 exhibition about T.S Eliot’s poem The Waste Land, met at
the gallery in Margate to discuss their thoughts on the terms ‘agency’ and ‘intention’. They
followed a philosophical enquiry methodology starting with the question ‘Is not having an
intention a type of intention?’
/7
Intentions in Art History and Beyond
by Emma Brasó
/9
Fallacies
Art historians vary in their approach to artistic intention: some try to discover the
purpose of an artwork in external evidences related to the life of the artist (like private letters,
diary entries or even death certiicates); for others, the verdict of whether the artist has
succeeded in their creative intent depends entirely on internal evidences available in the
artwork itself. While the former are accused of carrying out “the intentional fallacy,” the latter are
described as perpetrating “the expressive fallacy”. Taken that both viewpoints present internal
problems, some interpreters have tried to come up with hybrid conceptions of intention,
while less conciliatory ones, like cultural theorist Mieke Bal, have rejected intentionality for
being a concept inevitably compromised by its ties to individualism. In the exhibition Agency
without Intention, the exploration of the term “intention” went beyond its strict application
to the interpretation of art. And yet, the inluence of its particular understanding in new art
history—and more speciically, its radical questioning by Bal—is largely responsible for my
own take on the concept.
Writing at the time of the success of neo-expressionistic styles in the art market of
the 1980s, Hal Foster seemed dismayed: “Why, then, if the expressionist iction seems so
suspect, is it renewed today?”1 For the art historians like Foster who were working under the
inluence of post-structural ideas (what is loosely known as “new art history”), such assumptions
about the expressive value of art, concealed long-sustained ideological goals that seemed
unafected by the theoretical recognition of the constructed nature of all forms of expression.
The “expressionist iction” or “expressive fallacy” (as Foster titles his essays for reasons that
will soon become clear) was not only practiced by artists and supported by art dealers; it also
characterized a much disputed type of art historical interpretation that relied on the supposed
“immanent expressive meaning” of the artwork, as the members of Art & Language ironically
1 Hal Foster, “The Expressive Fallacy,” in Recordings. Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics (Seattle, WA: Bay Press,
1985), 75.
described it.2 For art historian Rosalind Krauss the unproblematic use of terms like “originality”
and “authenticity” tried to preserve the positivist interpretation of art—as well as the institutions
defending such view—from the scrutiny of theory. Art & Language, on the other hand,
censured the expressive critics for ignoring or hiding any relection on the material conditions
of production that made the artwork possible (for instance, the economic needs of the artist).3
Hal Foster’s essay The Expressive Fallacy is a direct a reference—a critical one—to
a seminal text in literature theory, Monroe Beardsley and William Wimsatt’s The Intentional
Fallacy, originally published in 1946. Focusing on poetry criticism, the essay is considered
an early call to move away from the disproportionate attention paid to authors and their
intentions when analyzing the success and meaning of poems. For Beardsley and Wimsatt,
a poem does not belong to the critic nor to the author, but to the public: “It is embodied in
language, the peculiar possession of the public, and it is about the human being, an object
of public knowledge.”4 This public dimension of the poem implies that also the evaluation of
the work has to occur in the public sphere without resorting to the author’s private intention
as a judging standard. What they endorse as a correct method for literary criticism is one
centered on what is internal (or public) to the poem—semantics, syntax, plus cultural
references—, rather than what is external (or personal)—the author’s diary entries, letters, etc.
What constitutes the interiority and what the exteriority of the artwork—and their
respective role in the interpretation of art—is a guiding principle to understand how art
historians and critics position themselves in the intentionalist debate. In a case study on
Edouard Manet’s painting Un Bar aux Folies-Bergère (1882), art theorist Thierry De Duve’s
accepts the methodological premises of Beardsley and Wimsatt with telling efects. The
stated purpose of de Duve’s essay is to demonstrate that this artwork in particular is the
painter’s “pictorial testament,” or, in other words, a inal explanation by Manet of his own
artistic innovations.5 In order to do so, de Duve goes through a detailed comparison of
two contradictory models of perspective projection that could equally match the spatial
construction at work in Manet’s bar. This exercise is supposed to follow a correct method in
Beardsley and Wimsatt’s sense, for de Duve is careful to emphasize that he is supporting
his analysis only on internal evidences available in the artwork itself instead of using external
ones like the critical reception of the work at the time or the artist’s biography (although de
Duve has external information like the fact that Manet died in 1883, soon after inishing Un
Michael Baldwin, Charles Harrison, and Mel Ramsden, “Art History, Art Criticism, and Explanation” (1981), in
Art History and Its Methods. A Critical Anthology, ed. Eric Fernie (London: Phaidon Press, 1995), 266.
2
Rosalind Krauss, “Sincerely Yours,” in The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths
(Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press, 1985), 193.
3
Monroe Beardsley and William Wimsatt, “The Intentional Fallacy” (1946), in Philosophy Looks at the Arts.
Contemporary Readings in Aesthetics, ed. Joseph Margolis (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1962), 93.
4
Thierry De Duve, “Intentionality and Art Historical Methodology: A Case Study,” nonsite.org 6 (July 2012),
accessed 3 April, 2015, http://nonsite.org/article/intentionality-and-art-historical-methodology-a-case-study.
5
Bar). The main problem that de Duve encounters is that in order to pick one of the two
internally valid geometric reconstruction (and their respective conclusion about the painting’s
meaning), he must link the picture back to the artist’s intention, and in the absence of external
proofs, he must rely on his personal judgement. De Duve—who is aware of how by escaping
the “intentional fallacy,” one can end up producing an “expressionist iction”—concludes,
In the absence of “external evidence” (a piece of writing by the artist, the reviews of
the critics, the testimony of contemporaries, etc.), what access do we have to the artist’s
intentionality? None other, I would argue, than what I called aesthetic intuition. Is it
methodologically trustworthy? The question will not be settled here, but it is raised.6
Towards the agency of images
Despite art history’s problematic dependence on the correct identiication of
artistic intentions, for the art critic Thomas McEvilley, “it is clearly impossible to exclude
the artist’s intentions from the critical process” as information as apparently objective as
the date of an artwork has an undeniable impact on our critical awareness of what we
then believe the artist knew or intended.7 Such inevitability has fostered last-minute
attempts to re-conceptualize the term, while the gradual transformation of art history into
visual culture has facilitated other interpretations that welcome the possibility of applying
the idea of agency to artworks themselves independently of the intentions of its makers.
David Summers’ 1986 essay Intentions in the History of Art is a critical analysis of
intentionalism that tries to come up with a hybrid conception of the term. The art historian
starts by acknowledging that the abdication of what is exterior to the artwork implies both
theoretical and historical challenges: on the one hand, it implies throwing “the whole burden
of a work’s signiicance upon its presumed formal expressive univocity,” while, on the other,
it ignores how socio-historical contexts play an important role in explaining why artworks are
designed the way they are.8 In light of this, what Summer proposes is “a certain deinition
of intention” that will maintain the centrality of the work’s internal evidences but will also be
able to give a contextual or structural explanation for change. Such deinition proposes that
intention is never only a subjective act or individual will, but that intentions are inevitably tied
to trans-personal circumstances such as the appearance of a new technique or the decline
of a typology. For instance, if Leonardo da Vinci intended to paint a unique composition
6
Ibid.
7
Thomas McEvilley, Art and Discontent: Theory at the Millennium (Kingston, NY: McPherson, 1991), 46.
8
David Summers, “Intentions in the History of Art,” New Literary History 17, no. 2 (1986): 307.
/ 11
of The Virgin and Child with Saint Anne, he necessarily depended upon and transformed
“existing technical and iconographic traditions” available to him at the time.9 Thus, if intentions
are contextual and historical rather than only subjective and individual, Summers argues that
it could be possible to recover them by analyzing how motifs, techniques, and formats (all
trans-personal) are embodied in the artworks themselves. Summers’ explanation of how
internal evidences are capable of accounting for exteriority is, however, compromised by the
introduction of another concept, the “arbitrary”, which is how he justiies those “aspect of a work
assignable to the artist himself as an agent,”10 in an attempt to avoid historical reductionism.
A diferent take on the part of history in the interpretation of the artworks—or, more
exactly, on “the agency of images over time”—is pursued by the cultural theorist Mieke
Bal.11 In her view, the term intention has an implied positivism and individualism that makes
it ill-itted to account for “art’s efective and afective results” throughout history, including in
the present.12 To thwart intention, she introduces “narrativity” as a way to complicate the
opposition between interior and exterior. Narrativity, in Bal’s view, includes in the explanation
of artworks the way they afects us now, despite such efects being unintended, unknown
or incompatible with the intentions of the maker. If, as she argues, we acknowledge “the
temporal efect of delay as an integral part of the image”13 (or, in other words, if we accept that
the internal analysis of the artwork has to contain the story of the processes through which
in diferent circumstances art is able to signify diferently), we could theoretically account
for an image’s agency without either having to rely on the biographically veriied intentions
of the artists nor having to eliminate the socio-historical dimension of all interpretations.
Bal’s narrativity is an invitation for the art historian and others to engage with the historical
circumstances, personal interests and particular goals of all interpretations by critically
acknowledging the active role of the interpreter, rather than focusing on trying to recreate the
context, concerns, and intentions of the artist.
Conceiving agency without intention
Agency without Intention included four projects: two robots, a multi-part social
sculpture, a recorded conversation, and a performance for four dancers. Each work
approached the exhibition’s premise from a diferent angle, although the most interesting
9
Ibid., 311.
10
Ibid.,319.
11
Mieke Bal, “Intention,” in Mieke Bal Reader (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006), 236.
12
Ibid., 263.
13
Ibid., 256.
moments occurred when the diferent projects overlapped. For instance, Abdulbari Kutbi’s
Pirouette Robots roamed around the gallery changing their direction of progress when
bumping into any of the numerous plywood blocks making up the social sculpture Liminal,
designed by Abigail Hunt and Kieren Reed. The robots were also the starting point for a
conversation about agency and intention with the members of The Waste Land research
group (this discussion was recorded before the exhibition and screened in the gallery).14
The Waste Land research group is a variable group of people who are jointly developing
the content for an exhibition inspired by T.S. Eliot’s eponymous poem. The outcome
of this horizontally-curated experiment will be presented in the spring of 2018 at Turner
Contemporary, Margate. I approached the organizer of this group, Trish Scott, to discuss with
its members their understanding of agency and intention because I felt that their decision to
work together and with an institution implied questions around these same concepts: What
was the intention of Turner Contemporary to start such a socially-engaged, participatory
project? What level of agency were the participants given? Was the intention of each one of
them the same as the group’s intention or the institution’s one? Which one would prevail?
As said, we selected the robots to initiate this conversation, which then followed
the format of a philosophical enquiry in which the participants were asked to agree
or disagree with what had been said before.15 What the robots allowed was to present
a very practical example of an agent without apparent intention: the robots were able to
make simple decisions when confronted with physical obstacles thanks to a system of
interconnected modes, yet their actions could hardly be interpreted as following a complex
purpose of their own. During the subsequent discussion, references to the intention of
the robots’ designer were inevitably introduced, and the parallel relation between robot/
artwork, designer/artist was easily established. It was encouraging, from my perspective,
that several of the participants agreed with the possibility of artworks producing in the
recipient efects unintended by their creators. There was also some confusion about
the deinition of the terms agency and intention themselves. Some people thought they
were not easily diferentiable, or that one was just the way through which you achieve the
other. Despite these terminological diiculties, throughout the hour-and-a-half dialogue we
were able to establish an important diference between the two concepts: while intention
operates at a personal level (even in the case of collective intentions), agency is relational,
always dependant on our position within a group or in a situation. Or, to put it diferently,
while the articulation of one’s intentions—although inevitably inluenced by contextual
circumstances—remains in an ideal sphere, agency is intrinsically connected to action,
An edited version of the ilm recorded during the conversation is available online. Agency without Intention,
Youtube, accessed 24 December, 2015, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Gm9fODpVNrA.
14
15 For more information on this pedagogical approach see “What is Philosophical Enquiry,” Thinking Space,
accessed 24 December, 2015, http://thinkingspace.org.uk/about-philosophical-enquiry/.
/ 13
and therefore contingent to the distribution of power within existing social structures.
The conversation with The Waste Land research group introduced the split between
agency and intention in the technological sphere where machines and robots that are apparently
able to make their own decisions cannot be said to have intentions of their own.16 Another
perspective on the both aesthetic and social implications of separating agency from intention
was presented in the exhibition by the multi-part social sculpture Liminal. Liminal, composed
by more than 70 wooden geometric pieces, was scattered throughout the loor of the Herbert
Read Gallery with the intention that visitors would feel free to interact with the modules by
moving, piling or sitting on them. The wall text in the gallery speciically referred to this call to
action in the following terms: “Visitors are invited to activate the work with the hope that their
participation will provoke moments of unsolicited disorientation, exchange, and discussion.”
In the case of Liminal, the work staged a situation through which to discuss the
type of agency ofered to audiences in supposedly interactive pieces. In recent times,
numerous artists have produced projects which are conigured as situations in which the
public is supposed to participate in one or another way. This “relational aesthetic” as Nicolas
Bourriaud described it,17 has run parallel to a discourse of social engagement, in which
audiences are supposed to be empowered through their interaction with the art presented.
Yet, many of such projects usually imply an under-discussed relation between the quite
limited agency given to audiences and the very strong intentions of artists and curators.18 In
the context of Agency without Intention, what Liminal allowed was to construct a fascinating
socio-aesthetic situation in which the agency of audiences was being openly negotiated
in relation to the intentions of the artists and curator, and the limitations of the institution.
Finally, the performance that Rosana Antolí conceived for the opening of the
exhibition consisted of four dancers moving disobediently. Subtly at irst and very noticeably
as the event developed, the performers executed routines alien to the normative movement
dynamics in a conventional art opening. The departing point for this commission was a
political concern with the diferent roles played by agency and intention in recent protest
movements worldwide. In preparatory conversations with Antolí, we were particularly
interested in discussing how collective political eforts such as the international Occupy
movements, or the Spanish “Los Indignados” had been criticised for their lack of concrete
objectives. What their critics saw as a weakness, we saw as their main advantage: by
protesting and defending political agency for “normal” citizens but not stipulating a list of
Of course, numerous science iction plots revolve around the possibility of machines having their own
motivations that contrast with those of the humans designing them. For now, though, that kind of artiicial
intelligence remains a ictional one.
16
Nicolas Bourriaud, Relational Aesthetics, trans. Simon Pleasance and Fronza Woods with Mathieu Copeland
(Dijon: les presses du réel, 2002).
17
For a critical assessment on the role of intentions in socially engaged art, see Erik Hagoort, Good Intentions.
Judging the Art of Encounter (Amsterdam: Foundation for Visual Arts, Design and Architecture, 2005).
18
concrete goals, these movements were gaining political signiicance while avoiding the
instrumentalization of their actions by any particular party. Although in a far less concrete
context, the dancers at the opening were also clearly presenting alternative ways of moving
and behaving, yet their intentions (as well as those of the artist) remained unknown. In so
doing, their agency as disobedient bodies was evident, while also less easily jeopardized.
In her reconsideration of the role of artistic intention, Mieke Bal requests interpreters
to acknowledge the theoretical and ideological positions of their own readings and
presentations—a request that philosopher Rosi Braidotti so accurately reinstates as “Don’t
do the God trick, don’t speak from nowhere.”19 Following their advice, Agency without
Intention was conceived to investigate through art works and art-related situations a
particular hypothesis about our present social order: that, in light of advances in technology
and the limits of artiicial intelligence, art’s institutionalized interest in the social sphere, and
the appearance of political sensibilities that avoid becoming political parties, it is possible—
and useful—to conceive agency independently of intention. However, that was only a
position, for the projects presented in the exhibition exist beyond the particular interests,
ideas, assumptions or economic needs of the curator, artists, and participants that were
involved with them momentarily.
Emma Brasó is Cultural Programme Curator at
University for the Creative Arts, Kent, and PhD
candidate at Royal College of Arts, London.
Rosi Braidotti, “Thinking as a Nomadic Subject” (video of lecture, ICI Berlin, 7 October, 2014), accessed 28
January 2016, https://www.ici-berlin.org/event/620/.
19
/ 15
/ 17
/ 19
/ 21
/ 23
INDIVIDUALS ARE SEXY
/ 25
/ 27
/ 29
/ 31
The Space Between:
A Personal Reflection on the Artwork Liminal
by Kieren Reed and Abigail Hunt
/ 35
This text has developed through an ongoing dialogue between ourselves as artists
and collaborators, audience members, curators and others who have come into contact
with our artwork Liminal over the last ive years. As our most signiicant collaborative artwork
to date, we wish to ofer a narrative to explore Liminal, where it came from, how we were
inluenced to make it, its methodologies, references and its impact as an artwork as well as
its efect on our wider practice. We are keen to explain how it has changed our perceptions
and inluenced our ideas and thinking as well as how we now wish to move it forward as
a continuing strand of our artistic practice. As an addition to this text we have included a
lexicon of terms that we ind continually relevant to us. We have chosen to deine them within
our own thinking and understanding, perhaps not always completely in line with an oicial
deinition, but giving an insight into our methodologies and ideas.
Liminal is a one hundred and twenty piece wooden sculpture of varying geometric
forms. The artwork is activated by a relationship with its audience, who interact with it
physically through touch, movement and composition.1 Liminal has a familiarity to it,
and we have always felt that this is one of the keys to its potential. Ideas of mimicking
or repeating universally acknowledged shapes and forms sit comfortably with us as a
homage to that which has gone before. Liminal sits somewhere between the possibilities
of curated untouchable sculpture and the allowing of interaction and exploration of an
audience role, in part reaching towards the educational. We have always been interested
1 Since 2011, Liminal has been experienced by over 40,000 people. It became the subject of the ilm The Art
Handlers by artist Anna Lucas and was part of a research programme for Tate. It was also presented, exhibited
and discussed at the Inside/Outside: Materialising the Social symposium as part of the series The Tanks: Art in
Action, at Tate Modern and it has been shown in various spaces at both Tate Britain and Tate Modern. Notably
it was shown in the McAullay Gallery, Tate Modern for a focused exhibition in December 2013. This followed a
summer of events programmed around Liminal that public workshops led by us, the development of performance
artworks and animations using Liminal and ilm screenings in collaboration with the Tate Archive. To date it
continues to be shown at Tate Modern and as an artwork, it has been highly inluential in informing education
policy and practice at Tate.
Most recently a second part of Liminal, with some re-thinking and the introduction of some revised and newly
created shapes and forms was shown as part of the Agency without Intention exhibition at The Hebert Read
Gallery in Canterbury where it was interacted with by two Pirouetting Robots by artist Abdulbari Kutbi, and human
performers as part of new work by Rosana Antolí. It was also altered and used by the public throughout the
duration of the exhibition.
in this positioning and the awkwardness and indeinable nature of Liminal as an artwork.
This has created opportunity for the piece and yet has also created its own frustrations
for us in terms of how the piece is considered, discussed and contextualised by others.
The name ‘Liminal’ references the space between; a luid place where the possibilities of
change have the potential to take place. We titled it as such, both because this not quite
deinable moment was key to the meaning and aims of the artwork, but also because we
wanted a simple single word which we hoped would become descriptive of its very self.
The decisions on the forms and shapes of Liminal were explored initially through
drawing shapes, creating paper constructions, having discussions with each other, and
considering what would it together physically and visually. We didn’t want to over complicate
the forms the sculpture took. They were created and explored openly, within part of a normal
studio practice—not pre-designed, but created through a making process. Some shapes
didn’t make the inal set. Others were altered or introduced later. Form, balance and negative
space were all important. As were the relationships between diferent pieces and the idea
of multiples and sets. Observations of our (then) two year old son and his capabilities of
building afected our thinking. What help did he need to work with these shapes? Physical
help in moving and lifting—yes, often. Mental support in the consideration of his actions
with them—much less often. These actions of building are central to play. Left with a set of
pieces or objects of any kind, even a very young child will explore their physicality through
touch. Groups of, or individual, adults are also inclined to pick up, touch and explore objects
with their hands and ingers, as long as the situation in which they are ofered objects isn’t
restricted by social constructs of expected behaviours. Creating and imitating (consciously
and subconsciously) architectural and sculptural spaces is a natural activity for the human
involved in the act of play. The familiarity, yet ambiguous and not directly representational
nature of the modular type blocks and shapes that make up Liminal, makes suggestions
for creating and building. There lies a potential for testing ideas and placing basic elements
together to explore the relationships between them. The nature of the Liminal pieces enables
a spontaneity in their use. They hold potential for simple and fast interactions or allow a more
considered approach to the forming of relationships between the shapes.
The production of these elements evolves in the studio.We imagine forms,
make references, construct and edit. We imagine how they may be used, how they
might be placed together; what its where, how a block might sit. We consider the
relationships shared between the pieces. Collaboratively we explore and develop
ideal formations but these explorations stay within the studio and as a key reference
point. Photographic documentation of the work only happens after it has been used.
We found that as a commissioned artwork within an educational/participatory
context we had more freedom in making, in that the work had an openness and possibility
for continued editing. We also had access to diferent funding through the possibility of
working on related programming on and around Liminal. This positioning created diiculties
in how seriously the artwork was considered by some. An educational context immediately
encouraged considerations of the work around play and creativity. We equally wanted to
explore functionality and the use value of these pieces and what their wider impact could be.
They hold other possibilities for practical use, as seating, shelving, display and screening.
We have explored performative elements—creating things to set rules, carefully considering
the passing of elements from one to another, documentation through moving image, using
the blocks as a starting point for perspective drawing, and for highlighting relationships
between Liminal and other artwork in the gallery context.
When we irst created Liminal we were interested in capturing and allowing the
processes of the studio to become more exposed. The touch of the artists’ hand on
surfaces; the movement and shifting of ideas through placement of pieces; the endless
possibilities of arranging and rearranging elements, building and rebuilding, constructing
and deconstructing; the capturing of a haptic and the experience of weight, surface and
texture. We wanted to explore the knowledge and understanding of a material that takes
place on a deeper level when the sense of touch is added to that of sight. Looking to
present the possibilities of usefulness—function and practicality to work alongside the
visual and aesthetic of decision making—we were interested in taking that exploration of
object and material which usually happens privately in the artists’ studio and unusually
make it a part of the gallery space and the gallery experience. For us, art, and in particular
sculpture, is a physical thing—a relationship between the hand and the object. Much art
history and theory talks of such, but on exhibiting in a traditional scopic centric gallery
context, that understanding of touch is usually removed from the visitor experience,
even often placing a second element of glass or a barrier to add to this removal.
A few years ago when visiting a Jef Koons exhibition, we witnessed a family having
a conversation that illustrates this point. A father was looking around with his two teenage
sons and he was telling them that they must not touch any of the artworks. The sculptures
on display were inlatable beach toys cast in highly polished stainless steel. Visually they
were so close to the original objects it was questionable that they could be anything diferent.
The younger son, choosing his moment carefully, reached out and touched one of them and
his father (but not the gallery invigilator) seeing him, quickly reprimanded his behaviour. “But
I wanted to know if it really was made of metal” the boy said, justifying his act. “Otherwise
it could just be a beach toy”. “Well it’s not allowed” replied his father as they continued
to look around. A short time later, the dad was overheard to ask, “So, what did it feel
like?” A lovely descriptive discussion followed as the boy, after only one rapid stolen touch
was able to describe the coldness and the weight of the object to his rule bound father.
When the gallery removes the possibility of touch, a real awareness of an artwork
can also be lost. What the boy said is true; without conirmation through touch how can we
know that these artworks are what they claim to be? And without that touch, does it matter if
they are or not what they say they are? The boys’ father wanted to know too—even though
/ 37
he knew through learned and widely acknowledged gallery behaviour that it wasn’t allowed.
We have deeply considered and remained aware of our relationship with damage
and failure. The simple fact was that we were preparing Liminal for daily handling in the
gallery space and for things that we could not predict, would largely not witness and would
not be in control of. The elements of Liminal were made under normal studio conditions and
the individual pieces were tested for strength and durability. This, for us, makes for a slightly
perverse way of creating an artwork. As part of the process of making, each type of block was
held above head height and dropped. Dropped until it cracked. Dropped until it smashed.
Then assessed for the points of weakness, remade, strengthened; altering adhesives, ixings
and joints. The feeling of destroying in the studio is nothing compared to the moment, on the
irst day it was open to the public, of watching someone else holding a piece aloft and hearing
the sharp thwack as it hits the loor. That irst time staying intact. Over a short time eight
pieces of the same shape were identically crushed at a weak point we hadn’t irst noticed,
leading us to revise and alter continually. This raised questions and discussions for us about
expected behaviours, unspoken gallery rules, public pushing boundaries, and of how much
information we needed to supply the public with in order to protect them and the work?
These are interesting discussions and perhaps are still not completely resolved. We gave
over the control of the artwork, we watched it evolve and initiate discussions, some of which
we were part of and some not. Authorship is part of our considerations. We are interested
in the handover and the experience of letting the work go and of giving over our control.
We believe that there is a tacit knowledge that surrounds and supports Liminal.
This may be due to its familiar nature and its visual relationship with play or play apparatus,
or it could be in the forms which are similar to furniture or functional objects that we are
surrounded by. It also holds within it a familiarity of material and the softness of wood.
It feels under our hand as we would expect it to. We are not drawn to touch it because
we don’t know what it would feel like, more because we do know and we are expecting
something which is then conirmed through our ingertips. The substance of Liminal wears
down gradually, taking on some of the residue of the space it has shared. It gathers the
sheen of the polish from the loor, dust collected within its corners, markings and scratches
from clothing, jewellery and other furniture, brio markings from low level graiti. These traces
become part of its history. The nature of unintended changes to the piece sits alongside the
considered modiications which take place through its use.
An important intention of Liminal is that it is used. It’s active. We perhaps didn’t
quite realise just how vital this was when we irst made it and we always envisaged it to
have a more relective static context in its future. Our original thinking on this was challenged
when we were invited to be part of a small group of participants who would interact with
Rasheed Araeen’s artwork Zero to Ininity. At the time, we were really considering how Liminal
was being contextualised by others and we had a really strong desire to move it away
from its participatory use into a diferent phase of itself which would change it into a more
traditional and formal artwork. We felt this shift and reconiguration would help the artwork
to be considered in a diferent context. Taking part in the performance for Rasheed was
invigorating and insightful. He talked to us later at length, identifying that once an artwork
has been removed from you, you no longer have the agency over your work (idea) and
that this can be diicult to come to terms with. He talked about ownership and value. Zero
to Ininity was always intended to be handled—by many people—really until its point of
destruction. But that destruction was really insigniicant, because it was this use that was the
value in the work. Rasheed’s critique was that the preservation and continued conservation
of the artwork (because of its value relating to his success and recognition of him as an
artist) was afecting this original purpose. Not by much but signiicantly. It was diicult for
this to be anything but a static work, only activated very infrequently (the performance we
were involved in, was the irst time it had been handled in ten years and we were also
given gloves to wear and strict instructions as to what was and was not allowed in order
to preserve the work), because otherwise it could have been damaged and its scarcity
as an object would be questioned. The interactions and Rasheed’s intended hopes for
the work can only exist now in the main through photographic documentation and some
video (of our recent performance), but this is a problem we could see he was still having
to deal with. This conversation with Rasheed and the resulting discussions we had after
meeting him, really afected how we thought of Liminal and altered our desires for it to
become ixed. Our concern with its recognition by a knowing art audience is integral to it as
a piece of work and is central to what we are trying to explore with Liminal. This shift in our
thinking has been highly inluential in how we now see the work and in how our ideas are
moving forward both in terms of the piece itself and other artworks in our wider practice.
The conversations we had together after meeting Rasheed fed into continued
thoughts about agency and ownership, authorship and the roles of audience. Liminal is
often discussed in terms of ‘agency’. Indeed, at the Herbert Read Gallery it appeared as part
of an exhibition with an exploration of the intentions of agency as its title. We are interested
in this consideration, but we have struggled with ‘agency’ as a term and its implications on
and around socially engaged practice. Liminal in its very being is about passing over the
possibilities of what it can become to others and this is not something we ind particularly
easy, but is something we are fascinated by. As Liminal continues it could perhaps be seen
to be authored by us, but as something we certainly don’t retain agency over. This has
created artistic and aesthetic questions for us and our practice. This very point is perhaps
where the strength and interest in the artwork lies. We are also interested in the idea of
the ego, in exploring where we place ourselves as artists and as the directors of visual
decision making. Liminal leaves us with that tension. It enforces an artistic confrontation
in witnessing an aesthetic that doesn’t always match our regime or our intention. And
then there is the issue of others seeing the piece in a coniguration or setting that is not
part of our own visual thinking but that visual, whatever it is, is always associated with us.
This play on control and ownership of the visual has come up for us in other artworks
/ 39
(KADN kiosk, 2007). In the past, we have taken back the aesthetic when it ventured too far
from our own, incorporating methods within our work to ensure we retain some visibility,
some presence of our intentions for the piece. Liminal also has this. It does not invite the
incorporation of other elements in the gallery space, but yet it can be used with those things
that happen to be around it— gallery architecture, furniture or people. Liminal does not have
a set parameter and as much as we have deined its edges within the gallery space, there are
many possibilities for how it may look. The gallery space perhaps works to create the social
structure that aligns the norms to allow for agency to be given away at moments as part of an
un-verbalised agreement between us as artists and the audience. Physical engagement is
invited, but it is also so loaded that it is not possible to negate it. As artists we are interested
in the potential of forgoing agency, allowing interaction and participation in the creative act.
Liminal is very open and has many potentials, yet this potential is still controlled and set within
rules which it within ideas around social norms and expected behaviours, play and risk.
Liminal allows an engagement with an artwork in a diferent way. Unlike placing
a painting on a wall or a sculpture on a plinth, it can be something else to each person
who comes into interaction with it. It can be shifted by an individual, a group of people or
even a robot. We as artists can use it to programme additional content—perhaps within a
performance, built up into a screen to show a ilm, as a table or surface for placing a drink, for
leaning on, as a place to rest, to contemplate, to wait, to watch. It can become a play thing, a
static coniguration, a moving element in a ilm. Its use might include the people around it, or
it may be moved around, placed and left. Its use may be considered or incidental, conscious
or less so. We have always felt that in its simplicity, people know what it does, they know
how to use it and the knowledge around it as an object is tacit. This gives agency. We have
long questioned and suggested that it is in this movement, this use, this interaction that the
artwork ‘happens’ and without this interaction, this explored intention, the artwork is nothing
more than a set of wooden blocks. But thinking this, it became an artwork from the irst
moment it was moved by someone other than us, and now, even when it rests in storage, it
is an artwork for the happenings it has undertaken and the history of its interactions. Though
we still retain agency over Liminal as a whole, perhaps on a diferent level agency is shared
between those others who have used it in many diferent ways.
We continue to move our ideas forward, to see how the sculpture evolves and to
consider what its potential might still be. We work to consider and explore its alterations, its
shift in pushing forward, to move outside, to become more incidental, to work more casually
within a space, making further references to functionality and working beyond individual
pieces. How can Liminal inluence games and play to a continued degree and alter, impact
and afect programming even more? Our relationship with Liminal is that the work is in
lux, never inished. It is for us a critique on commodiication, a critique of conservation, of
happening and of when to stop. Liminal is an idea that is still growing up. It is active and
alive through its movement. In time it may grow into this, into that, into something more. The
pieces are picked up, moved, relected upon and moved again. We like how it looks in this
coniguration, but who knows what the next grouping will bring to our thinking.
/ 41
Abigail Hunt is an artist and educator, BA
Loughbrough University, MA Institute of
Education, UCL. Kieren Reed is Head of
Undergraduate Sculpture at The Slade
School of Fine Art. BA Kington University, MA
Chelsea College of Arts. Kieren Reed and
Abigail Hunt have been collaborating since
2001.
A Lexicon of Terms we find ourselves using in reference to our
artistic practice or that we are particularly interested in with
regard to our artwork Liminal
by Kieren Reed and Abigail Hunt
Some of these words we ofer our own deinition of, others we just wanted to include
as we think they are valid in this set of thinking. This list is presented in no particular order—
except being the order of a thought process.
liminal: the space between, a space that holds the possibility for something to
happen / agency: action or intervention producing a particular efect / tacit knowledge:
knowledge that is diicult to share through the use of words or descriptions but that can be
shared through alternative means if given enough time / formal: when the aesthetics are
obvious / naming: deinition / audience / participant(ion) / user / perform(er/ance) /
activate(ing) / viewer: audience not physically involved / worker: Fordist / technician:
title given to those in the gallery who supported the publics use of Liminal / block / element
/ form / piece / cube / object / work / original / play / interaction / intention /
haptic: interaction with something using touch / materiality: applying the use of materials
in building and making things / rules / risk / value / worth / scarcity / method: how
its done / gallery / furniture / edges: in terms of both the edge of the object and the
boundary of the gallery / struggle / question / point / confrontation / creative act:
Duchamp 1957 / social norm: known or expected behaviour / active / static / future
/ remove(d) / edit / collaboration / ideal formation: our imagined coniguration
of elements or blocks / aesthetic regime / education(al) / continued editing /
programming: scheduled actions / functionality: practical use, possibilities for such /
creativity / use value: functionality / impact: the afect / seating / shelving / display /
/ 45
screen / practical use: functionality / studio: private space, making space / weight: in
relation to the body / material knowledge / usefulness / scopic centric: concentrated
or orientated around visual experience / self relective / inluence / methodologies:
our thinking and how we do it / lexicon: the vocabulary of a branch of knowledge / ideas /
geometric / untouchable sculpture: see social norm combined with scopic centric and
gallery / audience role / design(ed): similar to an artwork / negative space: the places
in between the pieces and the gaps and voids inside the blocks themselves / architecture
/ architectural space: relation to volume and the body and surroundings greater than the
body / sculptural space: relating to the object and thing not necessarily relating to the
body/ modular / static coniguration: when Liminal has been left by a participant in a
particular position / considered / incidental: happy accident / game
/ 47
Agency without Intention. October — November, 2015
Abigail Hunt, Kieren Reed, Abdulbari Kutbi, Rosana Antolí,
and the collaborationof The Waste Land research group at Turner Contemporary.
Exhibition curated by Emma Brasó.
Publication designed by Rafa Prada.
Photography:
Kieren Reed, Katie Jolin, Rob Roach and Antonia Adjei-Mensah.
Images on pages 8 and 40 from the video
Disobedient Silences by Rosana Antolí.
With thanks to:
Trish Scott, Sam McElhinney, Ayisha De Lanerolle, Sarah Kent,
Melissa Sirol, Valeria Tello, and Simon Merriield.
Herbert Read Gallery
University for the Creative Arts
Canterbury, UK
© All rights reserved
ISBN 978-0-9930502-5-1