406
The Use and Abuse of the History of Educational Philosophy
The Use and Abuse of the History of Educational Philosophy
Avi I. Mintz
University of Tulsa
IntroductIon
As philosophers of education we endure gloomy pronouncements about our work
and the prospects for our field. We are told that our scholarship is “boring,”1 and hear
reports that the number of philosophy of education faculty positions is declining.2
Students are advised that, if they hope to pursue a career in the field, they shouldn’t
focus exclusively on educational philosophy, but rather develop expertise in some
other area of education such as curriculum, policy studies, etc. in order to improve
their chances of being employed in a school of education.3 Long-time members of
the philosophy of education community warn that the lack of relevance of our field
for educators might cause the field to “slide into extinction.”4 In many ways, we are
part of a field in flux; we frequently reconsider the proper domain of educational
philosophy and its methods.5
Taking stock of our work, and our field more generally, requires an encounter
with our past, an encounter that might suggest directions for our future. This year’s
PES conference theme – between past and future – invites us to do precisely this
kind of work, and this article takes up that challenge. I am interested, particularly,
in how we treat our history: what kind of encounters with the history of educational
philosophy occur, and what kinds of encounters do we encourage? I argue that we
fail to reckon sufficiently with the history of educational philosophy; particularly,
our work on the history of educational philosophy (a) too often neglects educational
theorists whom we ought to study and (b) adheres to a “history + implications” model
that encourages presentism and undermines the value of such scholarship.
What do phIlosophers of educatIon do?
Before I offer such an argument, however, it is worth asking whether it is actually true that educational philosophers neglect the history of educational philosophy.
In fact, as I discuss below, there are scholars in our field who believe there is too
much published on the history of educational philosophy. In 2012, Mathew Hayden
performed a service to the field of educational philosophy by examining the topics
covered in Studies in Philosophy of Education, Journal of Philosophy of Education,
Educational Theory, and Educational Philosophy and Theory. He included 1,572
articles from 2000 to 2010 to give us an unprecedented glimpse at, as the title of his
study suggests, what philosophers of education do. Regarding the history of educational philosophy, Hayden’s analysis shows that 422 articles, or 26.8% of the total,
explicitly mention in the title, abstract, or keyword one or more “great thinkers.” But
with further probing, it turns out that 76.3% of those are twentieth century “great
thinkers.” That leaves only about 7% of articles that mention a pre-twentieth century
educational philosopher in the title, keywords, or abstract, and many of those articles
do not substantially address the work of a “key thinker” but merely mention one
in passing in the abstract or subtitle.6 There’s nothing problematic about studying
PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION 2016 | Natasha Levinson, editor
H I Philosophy
L O S O P HofYEducation
O F E DSociety
U C A T| Urbana,
I O N 2 Illinois
016
© P2018
Avi I. Mintz
twentieth century philosophers of education – one could reasonably argue that the
single philosopher no one can afford to neglect is John Dewey. Yet Dewey’s and
others’ educational ideas did not emerge ex nihilo; they are part of a long tradition
of thinking about education. And, therefore, the fact that a mere 7% of educational
philosophy articles mention pre-twentieth century great thinkers in the title, keywords,
or abstract – and to reiterate, these are journals in educational philosophy, not in
education more generally – indicates that educational philosophers do not regularly
deal substantially with their history.
Is there really too lIttle Work In the hIstory of educatIonal phIlosophy?
I anticipate an objection to my claim that there is too little work done on the
history of educational philosophy. Some would see the 26.8% of articles that mention
“great thinkers” and conclude that, as a community of scholars, we spend far too
much time on “great thinkers.” Gert Biesta argues that rather than focusing on “so
called-original philosophical sources,” we should instead spend time discussing the
work of other philosophers of education, and ensure that our work is relevant to the
wider concerns of the educational community.7
I am largely sympathetic to Biesta’s concerns; indeed, as I argue below, I side
with him on the issue of focusing on “educational” rather than narrowly defined
“philosophical” problems of education. But I disagree (a) that “relevance” should
guide our work and (b) about how best to encourage educational philosophers to
read and cite each other’s work. With respect to the latter, I think that Biesta is
right in that, since so few of the scholars in our community are writing historical
scholarship, we don’t end up productively engaging the scholarship of others in our
community when we publish such work. Furthermore, I agree with Biesta that we
do indeed need to worry that every paper on Plato or Rousseau seeks to reinvent
the wheel, rather than contribute to an evolving scholarly interpretation of Plato’s
or Rousseau’s educational philosophy. However, such an evolution only occurs in
disciplines in which a critical mass of scholars are in conversation with one another.
Thus, scholarship on the history of educational philosophy is not inconsistent with
scholars of educational philosophy engaging one another.
relevance and educatIonal phIlosophy
Biesta is by no means alone in encouraging us to be concerned about the relevance of our work. Eric Bredo, also weighing in on historical work, writes: “it is
often easier to retreat into an analysis of some esoteric philosopher’s thought …
than to propose solutions to the educational difficulties of our time.”8 John White
calls on us to turn away from “inward looking” work in educational philosophy,
instead placing broad questions of social policy at the centre of our work.9 René
Arcilla worries that if our work fails to be relevant, then we, qua faculty members,
will fail to be relevant.10 Robert Floden, in his 2005 Presidential Address at the PES
Annual Conference, proposed that our work ought to seek occasions to contribute
to conversations about educational aims and policies.11 Bredo, White, Arcilla, and
Floden are but four of the many educational philosophers who have called on us to
make our work more relevant. Perhaps it seems odd that anyone might argue against
relevance; if the field is in trouble, how could irrelevance make anything better? Yet
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
407
408
The Use and Abuse of the History of Educational Philosophy
there is one unambiguous advocate of the view that, while we should not embrace
irrelevance, we should question the priority of relevance in our field. In the early
1980s, Harvey Siegel responded to the “go practical” ethos with an argument that
we should just concentrate on doing good scholarship, regardless of its practicality.12
Twenty years later, Siegel remained a lone voice in a special issue of Educational
Theory about the relationship between philosophy and education, arguing against
granting priority to conducting relevant scholarship. Siegel wrote:
If philosophy of education fails to engage educators in conversation, and contributes not a
whit to the solution of social problems or the flourishing of democratic society, but nevertheless advances its own intellectual agenda – gaining further insight into issues concerning the
aims of education, the nature of good teaching, the inevitability of indoctrination, the rights
of children, the obligations of schools, or the inability of rational argumentation to provide
objective, “power-independent” reasons for particular positions on these and other issues – its
future is assured. It is its scholarly agenda, not any Dewey-imposed social one, that determines
the content and integrity, and so the longevity, of philosophy of education.13
I think that Siegel is right that the philosophy of education community should worry
less about relevance and more about setting its own intellectual agenda. I do not
know if Siegel would endorse the following, but I argue that we ought to add to
Siegel’s list the history of educational philosophy – a subject that warrants study not
because it contributes to contemporary concerns (though it may do so), but because
it advances the understanding of the philosophical problems of education.
Before I continue, it is worthwhile to note that the neglect of the history of
educational philosophy is also, in many ways, a reflection of positive developments
in and contributions to our field. Many are attracted to the field precisely because
of its relevance to contemporary educational problems. Anecdotally, I have heard
numerous people say that they were attracted to “applied philosophy” because they
wanted to do philosophy that might make a difference in the lives of others. This is
an estimable motivation, and it presents scholars with exciting opportunities – the
sort of opportunities that will contribute to the longevity and flourishing of the field.
Second, educational philosophers typically hold positions in schools of education where there exist institutional pressures to produce work that is relevant to a
professional school that predominantly focuses on K-12 schooling. Many scholars
depend on external funding, which is often awarded for research that prioritizes a
direct impact on students and schools. Though this institutional pressure distorts
educational philosophers’ intellectual agenda, it is not entirely negative – it often
reflects a laudable effort to improve the education of K-12 students.
Third, educational philosophers themselves have challenged the relevance of
the history of educational philosophy in two other ways. Analytic philosophers have
loomed large in Anglo-American educational philosophy and have relatively less
interest in engaging with the history of philosophy, focusing instead on using philosophical analysis to better understand and clarify educational concepts and claims.
Others in the field believe that the history of western philosophy is permeated by tacit
and explicit biases that have served sexist, racist, imperialist, and other exclusionary
ends, and to study it would be, in effect, to endorse it.14
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
Avi I. Mintz
of What value Is hIstory of educatIonal phIlosophy?
I do not deny that it benefits our community of educational philosophers, and
the broader educational community, that some, or even many, of us pursue studies
on contemporary, “relevant” problems. I also would not want to understate the challenge that historical work might present to those seeking employment as educational
philosophers in colleges of education. Yet there are many reasons why engaging with
the history of educational philosophy would improve, as Siegel puts it, the “content
and integrity, and so the longevity, of philosophy of education,” and I identify six
here. The first three describe ways that the history of educational philosophy can be
“relevant.” But I then turn to arguments that point to the potential corrosiveness of
“relevance” in historical scholarship.
The first reason that the history of educational philosophy is valuable also
provides an argument in favor of embracing a canon that many find objectionable.
If we neglect to examine the ideas that have come to shape and limit contemporary
practices, we cannot take the proper steps to improve them. Claudia Ruitenberg
writes: “it is only through a critical examination of our intellectual traditions that
we can come to understand our own thinking today.”15 Wilfred Carr argues that “the
future development of the discipline depends on transcending and correcting the
limitations of the present by transcending and correcting misunderstandings inherited
from the past.”16 If we do not come to recognize these limitations, they will inhibit
our contemporary thinking about education, and they will limit our contribution to
educational practice as well.
Second, theorists who ignore the history of their field risk reinventing the wheel.
Many fundamental questions of education have received considerable attention from
thinkers in the past. Awareness of historical arguments may allow us to build upon
sophisticated theories rather than to explore the same ground anew.
Third, engagement with the history of educational philosophy lends us vocabulary
and concepts that can serve to advance contemporary arguments about education.17
This is the primary way that educational philosophers currently make use of the
history of educational philosophy. The model for such scholarship entails, first,
deriving some vocabulary or a concept from a historical philosopher and, second,
working out the practical implications of that vocabulary or concept for educational
policy or practice. Henceforth, I will refer to this model as “history + implications.”
“History + implications” may sometimes enable a critical and sophisticated
grasp of contemporary problems. However, I think that this use of the history of
educational theory potentially creates two serious problems. One, if a paper aims
to argue for a particular approach to a contemporary practical problem and, hence,
is aimed at a broad audience of educational scholars and practitioners, much of
the philosophical work in the first half of the paper will do little to invite a general
audience into the work.18
Two, the “history + implications” model has detrimental consequences for the
quality of the historical scholarship. Consider the treatment of Nietzsche in our journals. Because “history + implications” seems to be the standard model for engaging
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
409
410
The Use and Abuse of the History of Educational Philosophy
the history of philosophy in our field, scholars working on Nietzsche do not merely
study Nietzsche’s ideas on education to see what they uncover. Rather, they seem
constantly to bear in mind how they can articulate the contemporary relevance of
studying Nietzsche. Concerning ourselves with the implications of Nietzsche’s theory, rather than with Nietzsche’s theory alone, will sometimes result in a distortion
of Nietzsche’s ideas into something useful for contemporary educational practice.
Hence, in our journals, as Eliyahu Rosenow has revealed, Nietzsche has emerged as
“a democratic and liberal educator par excellence.”19 This is not to say that Nietzsche
fails to give us cause to think about his uses for democratic and liberal education.
Indeed, there will always be intelligent and creative scholars who will identify arguments that challenge the scholarly consensus. However, the disproportionate amount
of work that identifies Nietzsche’s practical benefits for contemporary education
should make us question whether “history + implications” is the ideal model for
our historical scholarship in educational philosophy. To repeat, the model has value,
and we should continue to use it when we are indeed interested in using historical
ideas to reflect on the present. But when we want to explore educational ideas, we
should be free to focus on better understanding those ideas, regardless of whether
their immediate use in education is evident or desirable.
The fourth benefit of more work on the history of educational philosophy concerns determining our own intellectual agenda. Part of the anxiety over the relevance
of our scholarship arises from the fact that we see educational practitioners and the
broad educational community as the audience for our work. By holding others to
be the audience of our work, we also empower them to be the arbiters of our work.
Concern with the reception of our work by others can be a good thing, for it might
help us to see more clearly the parts of our work that are needed and appreciated by
others and, consequently, encourage us to do more of it. However, we cannot expect
such a concern to sustain our discipline. Scholarship on the history of educational
philosophy positions us as arbiters of the quality, integrity, and value of a greater
proportion of our intellectual agenda.
Fifth, it would be pedagogically useful for students (but not only for them) to
work on the complex and sophisticated arguments about educational philosophy that
are found throughout its history. To elucidate, for example, problematic assumptions
in the No Child Left Behind policy is valuable. But for students of education to work
on more intellectually-taxing historical arguments about the purpose of education in
society cannot but help their scholarly development.
Sixth, if we believe that the philosophy of education is important – that is,
problems of education, broadly conceived, are of vital human concern – then some
members of our community ought to work on the history of the conversations that
contribute to our understanding of these problems. One might object, “but shouldn’t
we leave these historical questions to historians?” Historians of education today, I
would reply, are most often historians of schooling. As such, they neglect the history
of educational philosophy even more than we do. Occasionally, classicists and others
work on the periods and educational ideas with which we are concerned. As a scholarly
community, however, it is up to us to articulate the relationships between different
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
Avi I. Mintz
periods and ideas, which historians, classicists and others may or may not study.
Most importantly, it is our community that can ask, to borrow the words of Richard
Watson (who was writing about the history of philosophy generally), “what did the
philosopher say? … what did the philosopher mean to say? … Did he support his
position adequately or inadequately? … How did the philosopher’s contemporaries
respond? Who had the better arguments? What developed philosophically out of all
this?”20 With respect to educational philosophy, these are questions we are disposed
to ask and that we are best-suited to answer. If members of our community do not
address these questions, then we run the risk that no one will.
educatIonal phIlosophy versus educatIonal theory/thought
Biesta is correct that educational philosophers are overly concerned with the
history of philosophy as academic philosophers construe it. Anxiety over our relationship to the parent discipline has occasionally led to a slavish focus on philosophers
from the “philosophical canon” and the exclusion of important figures who shaped
educational theory in fundamental ways. James Muir has forcefully criticized our
scholarly community for failing to deal adequately with its own history. Muir has
sought to elevate Isocrates, Plato’s rival, to a more prominent place in the history
of educational theory, particularly because of his profound influence on liberal arts
education.21 Muir is undoubtedly correct about the importance of Isocrates, not only
historically, but also for his crucial and substantial contributions that shaped, and
continue to shape, the conversation in educational philosophy. Our general failure
to understand this competing conception of civic education, contested by Plato,
limits our ability to understand Plato’s educational ideas (and Plato is one of the
few historical philosophers to which we occasionally refer). Furthermore, despite
the fact that we generally acknowledge the influence of Locke’s work on education,
we publish so little on him that he did not make Hayden’s list. And, despite frequent
reference to him, we published only 12 articles on Rousseau in these journals.22 But
Isocrates, Locke, and Rousseau are just a starting point. Our field should be studying
“non-philosophers” who articulated important educational theories such as Xenophon, Catherine MacCaulay, Helvetius, Johann Friedrich Herbart, Friedrich Froebel,
Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi, and Maria Montessori. And despite our great affection
for Dewey, we should not neglect his less celebrated colleagues like George Counts,
Isaac Kandel, and William Bagley. We will continue to neglect a valuable resource
for our scholarly community, educational researchers, and educational practitioners
if we do not begin to do a better job of identifying and studying key conceptions of
education. If such work requires us to label our canon as the history of educational
theory or educational thought, rather than the history of educational philosophy,
because it engages figures who are not typically identified as philosophers, I say
that we would sacrifice little.
conclusIon
I do not suggest that everyone in our community should produce scholarship
on the history of educational philosophy, nor that we should cease doing “relevant”
work. Rather, I offer three suggestions for ways to address the lack of attention to
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
411
412
The Use and Abuse of the History of Educational Philosophy
our history. First, I hope that we might define our intellectual agenda more broadly
and recognize that the history of educational philosophy is within its domain.
Second, I think that we should recognize that there is a tacit “history + implications” model to which much of our historical work conforms, and that we must
encourage and allow for work on educational philosophy that is not based on this
model. I suspect that this is no small matter, as “relevance” is deeply entrenched in
the evaluative criteria of our scholarship. Our journals and conferences routinely
require that submissions relate to contemporary educational policy or practice.
Such a criterion must be called into question. If tomorrow the gatekeepers in our
community opened the door to historical work that does not conform to the “history
+ implications” model, that would be a critical initial step to improving the quality
and diversity of historical scholarship in educational philosophy.
Third, we need to spend some time cultivating our canon, which currently fails
to encompass important educational theorists who may not be readily identified as
“philosophers.” I recognize that our identity among educational researchers and other
academics, and our very self-identity, is based largely upon being “philosophers”
who do educational philosophy. And I know that I will convince few to surrender
the title. But, personally, I would call myself an educational theorist rather than an
educational philosopher if it freed me to focus more on philosophical problems of
education, regardless of whether we find them in the work of so-called philosophers
or others. The history of educational thought presents an open invitation for current
scholars – there are contrasts to be made, conceptions to be explored, and assumptions
to be exposed. We ought to encourage people to accept that invitation.
1. D. W. Hamlyn, “Need Philosophy of Education Be So Dreary?,” Journal of Philosophy of Education
19, no. 2 (1985): 159-165, 159.
2. For example, see Nicholas C. Burbules, “The Dilemma of Philosophy of Education: ‘Relevance’
or Critique? Part Two,” Educational Theory 52, no. 3 (2002): 349-357, 349-50; Daniel Vokey, “What
Are We Doing When We Are Doing Philosophy of Education?,” Paideusis 15, no. 1 (2006): 45-55, 47.
3. Burbules, “The Dilemma of Philosophy of Education,” 350.
4. René Arcilla, “Why Aren’t Philosophers and Educators Speaking to Each Other?,” Educational Theory
52, no. 1 (2002): 1-11, 10. See also the notes of despair in Dennis C. Phillips, “Philosophy of Education:
In Extremis?,” Educational Studies 14, no. 1 (1983): 1-30, 1; and Eric Bredo, “How Can Philosophy of
Education be both Viable and Good?,” Educational Theory 52, no. 3 (2002): 263-271.
5. On the nature of educational philosophy, see, e.g., George Pollack, “Philosophy of Education as Philosophy: A Metaphysical Inquiry,” Educational Theory 57, no. 3 (2007): 239-260. On the methods of
educational philosophy, see Claudia W. Ruitenberg, What do philosophers of education do?: and how
do they do it? (Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010).
6. Matthew Hayden, “What Do Philosophers of Education Do? An Empirical Study of Philosophy of
Education Journals,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 31, no. 1 (2012): 1-27.
7. Gert Biesta, “Editorial: Publishing in Studies in Philosophy and Education,” Studies in Philosophy
and Education 29, no. 1 (2010): 2-3; see also Gert Biesta, “Is Philosophy of Education a Historical
Mistake? Connecting Philosophy and Education Differently,” Theory and Research in Education 12,
no. 1 (2014): 65-76.
8. Bredo, “How Can Philosophy of Education be both Viable and Good?,” 270.
9. John White, “Philosophy, philosophy of education, and economic realities,” Theory and Research in
Education 11, no. 3 (2013): 294-303, 303.
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
Avi I. Mintz
10. Arcilla, “Why aren’t Philosophers and Educators Speaking to Each Other?,” 10.
11. Robert E. Floden, “When is Philosophy of Education?,” in Philosophy of Education 2005, ed. Kenneth
R. Howe (Urbana-Champaign: Philosophy of Education Society, 2006).
12. Harvey Siegel, “How ‘Practical’ Should Philosophy of Education Be?,” Educational Studies 12, no.
2 (1981): 125-134; Harvey Siegel, “The Future and Purpose of Philosophy of Education,” Educational
Theory 31, no. 1 (1981): 11-15; Harvey Siegel, “On the Obligations of the Professional Philosopher of
Education,” Journal of Thought 18, no. 2 (1983): 31-37; and Harvey Siegel, “John White on Philosophy
of Education and Philosophy,” Theory and Research in Education 12, no. 1 (2014): 120-127. See also,
Israel Scheffler, “Relections on Educational Relevance,” Journal of Philosophy LXVI (1969): 764-773.
13. Harvey Siegel, “Philosophy of Education and the Deweyan Legacy,” Educational Theory 52, no. 3
(2002): 273-280, 279.
14. A position challenged in David P. Burns, Ann Chinnery, Claudia W. Ruitenberg, and David I. Waddington,
“Taking on the Traditions in Philosophy of Education: A Symposium,” Paideusis 18, no. 2 (2009): 3-18.
15. Ibid.
16. Wilfred Carr, “Philosophy and Education,” Journal of Philosophy of Education 38, no. 1 (2004): 5573, 59. See also, drawing on MacIntyre: Vokey, “What Are We Doing When We Are Doing Philosophy
of Education?,” 51.
17. See the recent discussion (drawing on R.S. Peters) about the value of this sort of historical scholarship
in Stefaan E. Cuypers, “The Power and Limits of Philosophy of Education,” Theory and Research in
Education 12, no. 1 (2014): 54-64, 57-8.
18. See also John White, “The Medical Condition of Philosophy of Education,” Journal of Philosophy
of Education 21, no. 2 (1987): 155-162, 160.
19. For a comparison of Anglo-American and German educational philosophers’ articles on Nietzsche,
see: Eliyahu Rosenow, “Nietzsche’s Educational Legacy: Reflections on Interpretations of a Controversial
Philosopher,” Journal of Philosophy of Education 34, no. 4 (2000): 673-685, 675.
20. Richard A. Watson, “What is the History of Philosophy and Why is it Important?,” Journal of the
History of Philosophy 40, no. 4 (2002): 525-528, 525. See also, M.A.B. Degenhardt, “Philosophy of
Education and the Historical,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 18, no. 1 (1986): 25-35, 26. Marc
Depaepe offers a helpful disciplinary distinction: “When studying classic texts on education, for instance,
historians lay far more stress on the context than on the text itself, in contrast to philosophers, whose
priorities are the exact opposite.” Marc Depaepe, “Philosophy and History of Education: Time to bridge
the gap?,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 39, no. 1 (2007): 28-43, 30.
21. James Muir, “Political doctrine, philosophy, and the value of education: The legacy of Isocrates and
the Socratic alternative,” Journal of Educational Thought/Revue de la Pensée Éducative 33, no. 3 (1999):
255-278; James Muir, “Is our history of educational philosophy mostly wrong?: The case of Isocrates,”
Theory and Research in Education 3, no. 2 (2005): 165-195.
22. The inattention to Rousseau has been partly corrected recently as two special issues – Educational
Theory (Vol. 62, no.3) and Studies in Philosophy and Education (Vol. 31, no. 5) – were published on
him in 2012 (after the period of Hayden’s analysis) on the 250th anniversary of Émile’s publication.
PH I LO S O PHY O F E D U CAT I O N 2 0 1 6
413