Introduction
Subverting the Meaning of ‘Theory’
Marcelo Lopes de Souza, Richard J. White,
and Simon Springer
Anarchists have often been accused of ‘voluntarism’ and hostility towards
‘theory.’ If we consider some apparently concrete aspects (such as a comparison between Marxism’s much more impressive record of achievements in
the domain of theory and anarchism’s comparatively modest achievements in
the same domain), it seems that there is real evidence to support this kind of
thesis. However, upon closer examination things seem much more complex.
The original meaning of theory is related to observation and to an outsider
perspective. More precisely, theoria [θεωρία] is the Greek word for contemplation, the theoros being a spectator, or someone who contemplates something. These characteristics define a speculative activity, at first glance precisely the opposite of Marxism. Again: at first glance. Ironically, this supposed ‘philosophy of praxis,’ once synthesized by Marx in the famous XI
thesis on Feuerbach (‘Philosophers have hitherto only interpreted the world,
in various ways; the point is to change it’), has been strongly committed to
‘objectivity’ in a sense that is prone not only to a hierarchical and authoritarian approach to history and knowledge but also to rationalism and theoreticism. It is not necessary to be a ‘post-modern’ relativist to see the limits of
this kind of approach, typical of both ‘orthodox’ Marxism and Marxism in
general.
At this juncture, it is very useful to present more or less at length some
key aspects of Cornelius Castoriadis’s reflection on ‘theory’ in the context of
his radical critique of Marxism. His is probably the most original and profound critique of this sort ever made, and it offers the philosophical soil on
1
2
Introduction
which we have tried to ground some of our own contributions to the literature. For Castoriadis, Marx’s dialectic is a ‘closed dialectic,’ like the Hegelian one that was its source of inspiration. Therefore, it ‘is necessarily rationalist. It at once presupposes and “demonstrates” that the whole of experience
is exhaustively reducible to rational determinations’ (Castoriadis 1998, 36).
For him, however, dialectical thought can be different from this—namely, it
can be ‘open’ in the sense of a non-rationalistic, non-rigid and non-teleological way of thinking. But ‘such a transformation of the dialectic is possible . . .
only if the traditional and secular idea of theory as a closed system and as
contemplation is superseded’ (Castoriadis 1998, 37). ‘And this was indeed,’
as Castoriadis, one of the most radical and inclement critics of Marxism
during the second half of the twentieth century, conceded himself, ‘one of the
essential intuitions of the young Marx’ (Castoriadis 1998, 37). Apart from
several other problems identified by Castoriadis, this ‘essential intuition’
unfortunately largely vanished within the framework of Marx’s later work
(precisely the phase praised by almost all Marxists). This disappearance was
for ‘good’ reasons: It corresponds to the approach that predominates in
Marx’s oeuvre, especially in those works regarded by Marx himself as his
most important ones. The political implications of such a view are summarized by Castoriadis as follows:
[I]f there is a true theory of history, if there is a rationality at work in things, it
is clear that the direction this development takes should be left to the specialists of this theory, to the technicians of this rationality. The Party’s absolute
power—and within the Party, the ‘coryphaei of Marxist-Leninist science,’ in
the remarkable expression coined by Stalin for his own use—has a philosophical status. It is based in actual fact more genuinely on the ‘materialist conception of history’ than on Kautsky’s ideas, taken up again by Lenin, concerning
‘the introduction of socialist consciousness in the proletariat by middle-class
intellectuals.’ If this conception is true, this power must be absolute; democracy is then only a concession to the human fallibility of the leaders or a pedagogical method of which they alone can administer the correct dosage. The
choice indeed is absolute. Either this conception is true, hence defines what is
to be done, and what the workers do is valid only inasmuch as they conform to
it. The theory itself cannot be confirmed or infirmed by their action, for the
criterion lies within it and it is the workers who show whether or not they have
been lifted to ‘the consciousness of their historical interests’ by acting in
accordance with the watchwords which concretize the theory in given circumstances. Or the activity of the masses is an autonomous and creative historical
factor, in which case any theoretical conception can be no more than a link in
the long process of realizing the revolutionary project. It can, and it even must
be overturned by this process. The theory, then, no longer takes for itself
history as given in advance and no longer posits itself as the standard of reality
but accepts entering truly into history and being jostled and judged by it. All
historical privilege, all ‘primogeniture’ is then denied to the organization
based on the theory. (Castoriadis 1998, 39)
Introduction
3
The ultimate consequences are lucidly stressed a few lines later:
Thus history was found, once again, to have produced something quite different than what it seemed to be preparing: under the cover of revolutionary
theory, the ideology of a force and a social form that was yet to be born—the
ideology of bureaucracy—was constituted and began to develop. (Castoriadis
1998, 40)
Fortunately for us, however, the point is not a matter of choice between
this kind of theory and no theory at all. The task of binding together reflection and action in a way that those who practice reflection are not separated
from all the others—this ‘union,’ as Castoriadis, underlined, is still our task,
and it remains to be accomplished: ‘The intention of this union was present at
the origin of Marxism. It has remained a mere intention—but, in a new
context, it continues, a century later, to define our task’ (Castoriadis 1998,
41). While apologizing for quoting at length, we nevertheless think it is
surely worthwhile to reproduce all three of the following paragraphs:
Since the beginning of the recorded history of human thought, innumerable
philosophical doctrines have succeeded one another. For as long as we can
trace the evolution of societies, political ideas and movements have been
present. And all historical societies can be said to have been dominated by the
open or latent conflict between social strata or groups, by class struggle. However, in each case, the world-view, the ideas on the organization of society and
of power and the actual antagonisms between the classes have been tied together only in an underground, implicit and unconscious manner. And in each
case a new philosophy has appeared, one that was going to reply to the problems that the preceding ones had left unresolved, a new political movement
established its claims, in a society torn by a new social conflict—and yet
always the same one.
In its beginnings, Marxism presented an entirely new demand. The union
of philosophy, politics and the real movement of the exploited class in society
was not going to be a mere addition but a genuine synthesis, a superior union
in which each of the elements would be transformed. Philosophy could be
something different and something more than philosophy, more than a refuge
from impotence and a solution to human problems in the realm of ideas, to the
extent that it would translate its demands into a new politics. Politics could be
something other and more than politics, technique, manipulation, the use of
power for particular ends, to the extent that it would become the conscious
expression of the aspirations and interests of the great majority of people. The
struggle of the exploited class could be something other than a defence of
particular interests, to the extent that this class would aim at the suppression of
all exploitation through the suppression of its own exploitation, at the liberation of all through its own liberation and the establishment of a human community—the highest of abstract ideas to which traditional philosophy had been
capable of aspiring.
4
Introduction
In this way, Marxism posed the project of a union of reflection and action,
of the highest sort of reflection and the most every day action. It set out the
project of uniting those who practice this reflection and this action and the
others, eliminating the separation between an elite or an avant-garde and the
mass of society. In the divided and contradictory world of the present it wanted
to see something other than a new version of the eternal incoherence of human
societies; it especially wanted to make something else of it. It asked that, in the
challenges put to society by the people who live in it, we see more than a raw
fact or the workings of fate, the first babblings of the language of a society to
come. It aimed at the conscious transformation of society by the autonomous
activity of men, whose real situation leads them to struggle against it. And it
saw this transformation neither as a blind explosion, nor as an empirical practice, but as a revolutionary praxis, as a conscious activity that remains lucid
about itself and is not alienated from itself in a new ‘ideology.’ (Castoriadis
1998, 41)
Undoubtedly, as some ‘heterodox’ Marxists would surely protest, there
have always been Marxists (or at least self-professed ones) who were and
have been sensitive and wise enough to largely avoid most of these problems.
It suffices perhaps to remember cases such as that of a Marxist as lucid and
honest as historian Edward P. Thompson (who incidentally knew and very
much respected Castoriadis’s objections) to avoid the temptation of absolute
demonizing of all those who regard(ed) themselves as Marxists in some way.
However, if Thompson and some others only correspond to that type of
exception that ‘proves the rule’ (as we think they do), the essence of Castoriadis’s point is totally valid.
Now, let us pose the question: What is to be done? How could we understand ‘theory’ from a radically different perspective? Again, Castoriadis can
help us—and again in his characteristically provocative manner:
Theory in itself is a doing, the always uncertain attempt to realize the project
of clarifying the world. And this is also true for that supreme or extreme form
of theory—philosophy—the attempt to conceive of the world without knowing, either before or after the fact, whether the world is actually conceivable, or
even just what conceiving of something exactly means. It is for this reason,
moreover, that there is no question of ‘going beyond philosophy by realizing
it.’ We ‘go beyond’ philosophy—that is to say, we do not forget it, even less
despise it, but set it in place—when we understand that it is simply a project,
one which is necessary yet uncertain as to its origin, its import and its fate; not
exactly an adventure, perhaps, but also not a chess game, and certainly not the
realization of the total transparence of the world for a subject and of the
subject for itself. And if philosophy were to set down for a politics that aspired
to be both lucid and radical the prior condition of total rigorousness, demanding that this politics be wholly founded on reason, politics would be within its
rights to answer: have you then no mirrors at home? Or does your activity
consist in setting up standards for others which you are incapable of applying
to yourself? (Castoriadis 1998, 49)
Introduction
5
A further (and for us crucial) question is, then, the following one: How well
have anarchists and other left-libertarians performed when measured by these
standards?
As far as anarchists are concerned, we are convinced that they have been
by and large—at least intuitively—aware of the flaws, shortcomings, bottlenecks and risks typically embodied in Marxists’ use of ‘theory.’ We are also
convinced that this has been one of the reasons why they have been very
often partly misunderstood by Marxists (and others), as they seem to be ‘antitheoretically’ minded. There are other reasons, however, and these belong to
the reasons why we are equally convinced that left-libertarians should be
self-critical in some respects in the face of the legacy of classical anarchism—as well as convinced that in order to grasp the radical alternative to
Marxism we urgently need, we must go beyond (classical) anarchism. Indeed, this is precisely what Castoriadis did, and many more have done since
the second half of the twentieth century, by being radically critical of both
Marxism and capitalism at the same time but not endorsing the classical
anarchist legacy uncritically. 1
As mentioned, anarchists and other left-libertarians have been at least
intuitively aware of the problematics typically embodied in Marxists’ use of
‘theory.’ However, even if it is true, this is no excuse for a problem whose
existence we should admit, and which Castoriadis criticized as early as the
end of the 1940s: ‘Theory’ has often been regarded with suspicion or as
something pejorative by many anarchists (‘theory’ as something opposed and
inferior to ‘practice’). This refusal of ‘theory’ is based on a prejudice, and a
particularly (self-)damaging one, as it narrows our vision and diminishes our
ability to put things into context, to make comparisons and to think forward.
Voluntarism (in political terms) and empiricism (in philosophical and scientific terms) cannot be but miserable alternatives to Marxist rationalism. It is
fair to concede that anarchists and other left-libertarians have had their motives for thinking this way, as ‘theory’ has often served as intellectualized
justification for heteronomous power, very often expressed in a hermetic
language (and being as such an exclusionary power tool); be that as it may, it
is high time to depart from this ‘theory-is-nothing-but-blah-blah-blah’ bias.
This condemnation of theory has very often presented itself as an antiacademic bias, as if science/philosophy could be reduced to products produced by universities and the academic industry (not to mention the fact that
not all academic works are bad or useless, right?). An important aspect lies in
the fact that Marxists, unlike anarchists, massively entered the academic
world during the second half of the twentieth century—and, self-identified
(even if not always in a totally conscious way) with the class of bureaucracy,
they have been easily co-opted by the state apparatus under ‘real socialism’
(in a rather sophisticated, insidious manner) both in the West and, more
recently, in Latin America. But have left-libertarians been ‘pure’ or ‘immac-
6
Introduction
ulate,’ as somehow implicitly suggested by many? Admittedly, this lack of
interest in systematic, deep engagement in conceptual, theoretical and philosophical discussion does not necessarily have anything to do with ‘pureness’
in the sense of ‘intellectual honesty’ and ‘political integrity.’ In many cases
ignorance is just that—ignorance (and maybe an excuse for sectarianism,
arrogance and dogmatism, problems that have been by no means a monopoly
of Marxists).
Yet Marxists have used the empiricism of many anarchists as an alibi to
denigrate them as a whole—and that is simply unfair. The problem here is
not only that Marxism’s ‘theory’ is, as we have seen, objectionable; the
problem is also that left-libertarians have always produced knowledge, and
often a sophisticated one—sometimes even in form of high-level theoretical
contributions. Failing to acknowledge it (due to intellectual blindness or
simply for political reasons, as Marxists have done for almost two centuries,
beginning with Marx himself) is ridiculous. Let us consider first the work of
Proudhon. Despite all its problems and shortcomings, his several contributions, from the discussion of the ‘federative principle’ to the theories of
surplus-value (acknowledged even by a Marxist such as Georges Gurvitch;
see Gurvitch 1980), cannot be denied (Souza 2012b; Springer 2014b). Let us
now consider those two figures who count among the most consistent authors
of the classical period of anarchism: geographers Élisée Reclus and Piotr
Kropotkin. As far as Reclus is concerned, it suffices to give as an example
his posthumous major work, L’Homme et la Terre (Reclus 1905–1908),
where we can find several important theoretical insights, to see the extent of
his intellectual achievements. Reclus was, among other things, a forerunner
of what could be termed ‘critical and dialectical conservationism’ (Souza
2015, 428)—that is, neither an environmental ‘conservationist’ prone to
make concessions to capitalism nor a ‘preservationist’ in ‘deep ecology’
style—a pioneer of critical urban studies (his analyses of residential segregation, the role of urbanization and urban networks are remarkable, and to
some extent they anticipated several ideas later developed by others, such as
Walter Christaller’s ‘central place theory’), a sophisticated thinker about the
relationships between ‘evolution’ and ‘revolution.’ The case of Kropotkin is
no less important, as he offered, for example, a deep refinement of the ‘federative principle’ by means of his seminal discussion about territorial decentralization and economic-spatial deconcentration (see Kropotkin 2002)—not
to mention his other theoretical achievements, such as the theory of ‘mutual
aid,’ whose merits were still acknowledged one hundred years later by nothing less than one of the most famous paleontologists of the twentieth century,
Stephen Jay Gould. More recently, the works of Murray Bookchin demonstrate the possibility of prolonging the tradition without becoming intellectually fossilized. From his discussions of ‘social ecology’ (Bookchin 2005 and
2007; for the ‘pre-history’ of his approach, see the important essays con-
Introduction
7
tained in Bookchin 2004) to his analyses of ‘urbanization without cities’
(Bookchin 1992 and 1995; for an earlier discussion, see Bookchin 1974) to
his proposal about a ‘libertarian municipalism’ (see, for instance, Bookchin
1992, 1995 and 2007), Bookchin made many politically important theoretical
contributions. Interestingly, in spite of a remarkable record of intellectual
achievements, knowledge developed by anarchists and other left-libertarians
has commonly been neglected and not seldom attacked and dismissed as
irrelevant (for instance, Marx’s and Engels’s derogatory remarks about Reclus, who was reduced by them to the status of a mere ‘ordinary compiler’). Is
it not possible to see in this kind of devaluation a kind of elitarianism?
‘Theory’ is something politically crucial, provided it is intimately connected
with practice in the context of praxis.
Certainly, left-libertarians have presented some important weaknesses,
and they can and should be addressed not only by political agitation and
organizing but also by reflection and study. For instance, the domain of
political economy is a veritable Achilles heel of left-libertarian thought, as it
has not been developed with the same richness as Marxian versions, even if
such latent potential exists. However, their weaknesses and strengths are
curiously connected with each other: Though there is an evident lack of deep
knowledge in terms of economic processes and factors on the part of many
left-libertarian authors (a situation that has generated some inconvenient dependencies, such as Bakunin’s less critical acceptance of Marx’s economic
theories, while divergence between these thinkers was largely confined to the
realm of explicit power relations and also derived from a clash between
egos), left-libertarians’ usual refusal of economism has often been narrowly
interpreted as a weakness when it is actually a strength. Considered from this
point of view, left-libertarians are not behind Marxists; at least to a large
extent, they are actually ahead. Such an impression, obviously, should not
lead to any arrogance: Self-criticism is absolutely necessary if left-libertarians want to play an increasingly relevant role in the future. But they have
demonstrated a path that is an alternative to econocentrism, and existing
society more generally, since the nineteenth century in terms of both theoretical and philosophical reflection, even if very often only in an ‘embryonic’ or
rudimentary way—and this advantage cannot be underestimated.
Beyond making libertarian theorizing deeper, wider and infused with
greater density (in order to cover a whole set of subjects to some extent
neglected by left-libertarians), it is also necessary to achieve it without entering theoreticism, elitarianism and scientism. It is possible, though not easy.
Reclus and Kropotkin represent fascinating examples, and their works are
filled with plenty of ideas and insights that are still useful for us. But we do
not share their time, and so their approaches to subjects such as the idea of
‘progress,’ the role of science and technology, and the importance of Comtean positivism are similarly not shared by us. Castoriadis and Bookchin
8
Introduction
correspond to more contemporary examples and sources of inspiration. In
fact, the left-libertarian ‘family’ includes anarchism (from the classics to
more contemporary attempts to slightly update the classical heritage without
making any major revision, such as Latin American ‘especifismo’), as well as
streams that are significantly different from classical anarchism, such as
Bookchin’s neo-anarchism (later termed ‘communalism’) and Castoriadis’s
radically anti-Marxist ‘project of autonomy.’
The reasons for distinguishing between anarchists in a strict sense and
some heterodox representatives of the left-libertarian ‘family’ are above all
conceptual and theoretical in nature, despite some practical implications.
Nevertheless—and this is a crucial point on which Marcelo Lopes de Souza
has insisted for many years (see, for instance, Souza 2014)—the (left-)libertarian alternative (both to the capitalist and to the Marxist approaches to
society, history and the production of space) includes a wide range of perspectives, all of them belonging to the same ethical and political universe. It
is for this exact reason that Simon Springer (2014a, 306) writes:
You can call this ‘anarchism,’ ‘critical anti-hegemonic iconoclasm,’ ‘paradigm
destabilizing recalcitrant analysis,’ ‘non-conformist insurgent praxis,’ or
‘don’t tell me what to do theory’ for all I care. The point is, we are talking
about a mind-set of breaking archetypes, tearing up blueprints, and scribbling
over leitmotifs.
In terms of commitment to self-management, horizontality and decentralism, and above all in terms of an anti-authoritarian/anti-statist ethos, it could
be said that classical anarchists, neo-anarchists and ‘libertarian autonomists’
all speak the same ‘language’ regardless of their specific divergences or
‘dialects.’ 2
Even if there are and there must be (in the name of coherence) strong
connections between our concepts/theories, on the one hand, and our practices, on the other, there are not necessarily fundamental disagreements between, say, anarchists and neo-anarchists (or even ‘libertarian autonomists’)
in terms of practice, and by no means automatic ones (in the sense of being
automatically or mechanically derived from conceptual and theoretical differences). Convergences have been much more important than divergences
between all kinds of left-libertarians. This is already clear when we consider
the old anarchists of the nineteenth century and the early twentieth century,
and it is still evident within the broader framework of the left-libertarian
thought of the second half of the twentieth century and the beginning of the
twenty-first century. After all, what differentiates left-libertarians from each
other is not a matter of aim/end, but rather a matter of emphasis (more on
certain aspects than on others) or, in some cases, even just of aesthetic and
Introduction
9
stylistic preferences and idiosyncrasies, sometimes maybe also of tactics
(more than of strategy, though these also exist).
Nonetheless, from a non-dogmatic perspective, a few controversies are
unavoidable; and they should be regarded as highly positive, as they show
the vitality of the left-libertarian thought. The idea of a ‘society without
power,’ for instance, as central as it can be for many in terms of identity, was
consistently criticized by Castoriadis, who objected that it represented too
narrow an understanding of the concept of ‘power’ (usually reduced by classical anarchists to state power, or at least to heteronomous power in general). 3 On this basis, considering that a society entirely ‘without power’ would
be no more than an ‘incoherent fiction’ (Castoriadis 1983, 16), he proposed
instead of ‘anarchy’ the concept of ‘autonomy.’ Nowadays, autonomy is a
key concept even among anarchists, whether aware of Castoriadis’s work or
not. Incidentally, the narrowness of the typical classical anarchist understanding of concepts such as ‘power’ (not reducible to a possession of the
state), ‘law’ (not reducible to formal, state-sponsored laws), ‘government’
(not reducible to the state apparatus and heteronomy) and ‘authority’ (not
reducible to heteronomous forms of authority and to authoritarianism) were
criticized not only by Castoriadis but also by neo-anarchist Murray Bookchin. 4
A further flaw (but hardly a true controversy nowadays) is related to the
epistemological and methodological value of positivism (and the example of
natural sciences) for understanding society: While praised by Piotr Kropotkin
as detrimental to dialectical thought, positivism (and scientism) has been
refuted by many authors (among them some brilliant Marxists like Theodor
W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, main figures of the Frankfurt School).
Additionally, the belief according to which science and modern technology
are essentially good (as keys to ‘progress’), shared by classical anarchists
such as Kropotkin and (in a more sophisticated way) Élisée Reclus, has been
largely discredited. In short, anarchism, as we have received it from the
classics, cannot be treated un-historically (as Marxists have very often done
with Marx’s legacy). Nevertheless, beyond all possible and necessary updating and rectifications, a core of principles, values and traditions of ethical
and practical-political (‘praxical’) importance remains as a powerful bond
between all those who share the left-libertarian field. And one thing is certain: Anarchism was the first representative of the left-libertarian ‘family,’
and it still is its most well known representative.
All these discussions show that the torch that has been carried since the
mid-nineteenth century by thinkers like Proudhon and Bakunin continues to
illuminate our discourses and actions. The flame that has been kept alive for
many generations and in many countries is very strong today not only politically but also intellectually. At this right moment, history is being written by
social movements, protests and resistances that are largely or basically in-
10
Introduction
spired by a left-libertarian ethos—a praxis that is directly or indirectly, deeply or superficially animated by theoretical ideas debated by many people at
many times and many places.
The scholars(-activists) whose contributions are contained in this volume
work in and/or come from different countries, where they are conducting
research and contribute to conceptual and theoretical advances about the
spatial dimension of resistance against heteronomy (and of building autonomous, non-authoritarian alternatives). Owing to this geography of our authors, they bring to the subject different sets of experiences and approaches.
That is what we envisaged from the very beginning when we first conceived
of this project. We wanted it to be geographical in the double sense of being
about geography, but also written from a broad dispersion of authors.
Though Anglophone authors are overrepresented here—a problem difficult
to solve especially for practical reasons, although all three editors of Transgressing Frontiers have been committed at least to mitigating it, dealing with
problems such as the unexpected withdrawal of the contributions of three
non-Anglophone colleagues—it would be unfair to say that an Anglophone
(or Eurocentric more generally) approach clearly dominates this volume. In a
very consequent way, our authors are usually far away from Eurocentrism
(something that even continues to plague the left more often than not), and
they sometimes even try to question the very pillars of Eurocentrism in an
explicit and systematic way, as the chapters by Adam Lewis and Vanessa
Sloan Morgan so eloquently demonstrate.
The first chapter is by Marcelo Lopes de Souza. It is a contribution to
more conceptual clarity regarding the term ‘libertarian,’ in order to avoid a
too narrow interpretation of the ‘(left-)libertarian family’ as well as to help in
overcoming a specific (but increasingly influent) U.S.-American bias regarding that term. Who are the ‘libertarians’? Is their message (still) reducible to
anarchism? How have different political cultures perceived the contents and
meanings of this contested word? Who has contested it, and what is actually
at stake? The author has tried to offer a discussion around these issues that
helps in expanding our horizons beyond the usual clichés.
The next chapter on non-domination, governmentality and the care of the
self is by Nathan Eisenstadt, whose analysis is based on a four-year autoethnographic engagement with two anarchist social centres and associated
projects in Bristol (England). As the terms ‘governmentality’ and ‘care of the
self’ already suggest, Michel Foucault’s thought is one of the pillars of his
arguments; however, he develops a rich and complex dialogue with several
other authors (late twentieth-century Black Feminist critique plays an important role here) and looks for inspiration in contemporary anarchist anti-
Introduction
11
oppressive practices such as social centres. Refreshing in comparison to the
narrow understanding of ‘government’ that has been held by most anarchists
in the past (and even some anarchists in the present), Nathan acknowledges
that counter-governmentalities are still governmentalities. As he concisely
puts it:
Anarchists are concerned with the taking and re-making of space and territory:
from squats, social centres and community gardens to factories and farms.
They are concerned with the cultivation of self-governing subjects: from consensus decision-making at occupied encampments and self-organization in the
workplace, to the ethics of everyday-life including dietary choices, conduct in
relation to others and in the cultivation of a liberating relationship to oneself.
These practices require a certain ‘bridling of the passions,’ ‘work on’ or ‘care
for the self’ in order to attain a particular state of being to which anarchists
aspire: non-dominating and non-dominated. Freedom requires self-discipline.
Moreover, as an assemblage of discourses and practices that aspires to universality, anarchism urges others to discipline themselves: to participate, to take
control, to resist, to drop-out, to rage, to organize, to get empowered.
Thus, according to Nathan, ‘[a]narchism is a mode of governing through
freedom.’
The chapter by Gerónimo Barrera de la Torre and Anthony Ince is a
dense, yet beautifully inspired, contribution that deals both with theory/epistemology and with pedagogy, as it explores ‘the possibilities of a “poststatist” epistemology in geography and its possible contributions to a radical
pedagogical and methodological agenda within the discipline and social sciences more generally.’ As a continuation of the themes explored in Volume 1
of this series (The Radicalization of Pedagogy), it is clearly a relevant contribution both to a (political-)pedagogical debate and to the advancement of
theoretical and epistemological reflections about the links between geography and (left-)libertarian political thought. This framework draws mainly
from anarchist thinkers, but also from other writers such as Boaventura de
Sousa Santos and Bolívar Echeverría. Agreeing with Maia Ramnath,
Gerónimo and Anthony contend that in spite of being contrary to colonialism, as a project that appeared within European modernity, anarchism has
specific historical and geographical roots, hence being necessary to ‘decolonize our concept of anarchism.’ Again quoting Maia Ramnath, and in line
with Souza’s (2014) insistence of libertarian plurality, the authors then suggest that ‘anarchism should be conceived as just one manifestation of a large
family of egalitarian and emancipatory principles and projects. In a decolonial approach to anarchism’s Occidental roots, [Ramnath] considers that “we
could locate the Western anarchist tradition as one contextually specific manifestation among a larger—indeed global—tradition of antiauthoritarian,
egalitarian thought/praxis, of a universal human urge toward emancipation,
12
Introduction
which also occurs in many other forms in many other contexts. Something
else is then the reference point for us, instead of us being the reference point
of everything else. This is a deeply decolonizing move.”’ Erin Araujo’s main
source of inspiration, the Mexican Zapatistas—who can by no means be
reduced to the label ‘anarchists,’ while nonetheless clearly being libertarian
and anti-authoritarian at the same time—demonstrates this point very nicely.
In her chapter Erin asks the question ‘What Do We Resist When We
Resist the State?’ Basing her approach on a distinction between ‘strong theory’ and ‘weak theory,’ she says that ‘strong theory is recognized as the use of
powerful discourse based in evidence sought through simplified, clear, nonmessy descriptions of events that fall easily into clean categories and explanations, while weak theory embraces nuance, thick description and emergent
spaces that may not necessarily be clear, clean discourses, but rather a mixture of openness and exploration in the research process.’ She also claims
that ‘weak theory’ is particularly useful and promising regarding the task of
‘embracing horizontal forms of research.’ In a fashion similar to that of
Gerónimo Barrera de la Torre and Anthony Ince, she also engages in a
dialogue with post-colonial thinkers from the Global South such as Walter
Mignolo and Boaventura de Sousa Santos (the latter of which is actually an
‘in-between scholar,’ a Portuguese intellectual who has developed strong ties
with Brazil) in order to better understand the possibilities of surpassing a
colonial and strict Western/Eurocentric way of thinking. The spatial practices
of Mexican Zapatistas finally serve here as vivid illustrations and sources of
inspiration.
For their chapter, Nick Clare and Victoria Habermehl deal with a peculiar
and particularly difficult task: To bring ‘communization theory’ (a heterogeneous set of approaches and ideas rather than a single theory) and anarchist
geography (from several points of view an even more plural reality) together
within the framework of an attempt at nurturing a dialogue between anarchism (or [left-]libertarian thought and praxis) and so-called ‘autonomous
Marxism.’ What potentially makes this task difficult, and perhaps even a
little risky, especially from a left-libertarian point of view, is indirectly answered by the following chapter. Be that as it may, to the extent that they
recognize that ‘communization theory fails to properly engage with any form
of space, let alone an anarchist/anti-capitalist approach,’ their engagement
with the commons and their ‘wish to develop a theory that engages with
these spatialities in producing communization: commonization’ surely deserve attention on the part of left-libertarians.
Although the kind of dialogue envisaged by Clare and Habermehl can be
at least partly fruitful, the difficulties that are historically implicated (and
recently updated) in a largely hypothetical dialogue between Marxists and
libertarians (a dialogue that has been actually neglected or avoided by both
sides) are precisely the subject of the chapter titled ‘“Feuding Brothers”?’
Introduction
13
written by Marcelo Lopes de Souza. The author examines the various aspects
of the challenge Marxism represents for left-libertarians today, focusing especially on the difficult relationship between libertarian and Marxist sociospatial researchers and activists. In terms of the respective intellectual heritages, ‘ideally,’ the author states, ‘Marxists would give libertarians due credit
for idea(l)s such as horizontality, self-management and radical decentralization (as well as for criticisms against “socialist” statecraft, “dictatorship of
the proletariat,” and so on); in turn, libertarians should show more interest in
political economy (but without falling into the trap of Marxist economism, as
Castoriadis brilliantly warned). Furthermore, libertarians of all sorts would
do well to recognize classical anarchism’s shortcomings (“naturalism,” narrowness of its understanding of concepts such as “power,” “law,” “authority”
and “government”).’ Unfortunately, as the author stresses, we do not (and
never will) live in a perfect world. ‘Therefore, this kind of expectation is
unrealistic, and such a delusion can do libertarians a big harm in this moment
of history, when they are potentially strong as never before since the 1930s.’
This is not to deny the importance of dialogue, but just a plea for non-naivety
on the part of libertarians.
The next chapter also deals with a difficult dialogue, but this time within
the boundaries of left-libertarian thought itself. In ‘The Citizen and the Nomad,’ Ben Pauli focuses on and discusses the differences but also complementarity of the ideas developed by two (neo-)anarchists, Murray Bookchin
(who towards the end of his life preferred to call himself a ‘communalist’)
and Hakim Bey. From our own viewpoint, the conflict between Bookchin
and Bey should be understood in the context of a conflict between generations, although Ben’s contribution is less explicit in this regard. Bookchin,
who was born in 1921, grew up in the 1920s and 1930s, a time when classical
anarchism was still very much alive. Bey (alias Peter Lamborn Wilson), in
contrast, was born in 1945 and was politically socialized in a very different
world, being a teenager and a young man during the decisive years of the
raising of the ‘rebels-without-a-cause’ generation (1950s) and Western
counterculture (1960s and early 1970s). Every piece of knowledge is deeply
rooted in culture, geography and history, and so it is also ‘situated.’ Bookchin’s concerns and attacks (against not only Bey but also what he called
‘lifestyle anarchism’ in general) can be seen as a manifestation of discomfort
on the part of an activist forged within the framework of a working-class
milieu in the face of more fragmentary (and individualistic) manifestations of
anarchism that are themselves the expression of an age characterized by
disillusion and, especially in comparison with the nineteenth century and the
early twentieth century, also by pessimism and conformism. Bookchin
misses ‘revolution,’ though not in a Leninist sense, and is very suspicious
about the glorification of fragmentary insurrections. Bey, on the other side,
instinctively understands some aspects of our age better than Bookchin and
14
Introduction
adapts himself with fewer difficulties. That is not to suggest that Bookchin
was a sort of anachronistic classical anarchist lost in the second half of the
twentieth century; on the contrary, Bookchin’s contributions to the critical
reflection on ecology and technology, his very positive valuation of social
movements other than the workers’ movement, and his sensitivity towards
the potentials and limits of our big cities in terms of re-invigorating/recreating direct democracy practices show very well the essentially contemporaneous character of his major contributions. However, Bookchin could not
easily accept what he understood, perhaps even correctly, as a rather defensive or (even worse) individualistic and ‘aestheticizing’ posture.
If Murray Bookchin can be criticized for a certain lack of sensitivity in
terms of some limits (and perhaps also potentialities) of our time, Hakim Bey
can be criticized for being largely an adaptive expression of this same time,
in spite of all the radical elements and intentions present in his thought. But
beyond these criticisms, the question about prospects and possibilities for
resistance remains open, and surely both Bookchin and Bey can (on the basis
of a re-contextualization of the virtues and limits of their ideas) contribute to
our efforts in this direction. Perhaps some concrete examples of contemporary emancipatory praxis, such as the ‘Zapatist territory’ in Chiapas (regarded as inspiring by Bey, as Ben Pauli shows), can help in building some
bridges between Bookchin’s and Bey’s approaches to socio-spatial transformation. At the end of the day, we can confirm again and again that good
radical theory is illuminated all the time by radical praxis. We must bear in
mind this intellectual and political principle particularly when dealing with
the two next contributions: Vanessa Sloan Morgan’s and Adam Lewis’s
accounts of indigenous resistance and the need for anarchism not only to be
radically anti-colonialist but also to purge itself from colonial residues.
In fact, the two following chapters deal with the same subject—colonialism and its long-lasting effects—and show a remarkable mutual complementarity. Both are a mixture of theoretical discussion and empirical evidence
from North America. Vanessa Sloan Morgan goes first, where she discusses
the importance of making it clear from an anarchist perspective that ‘colonialism, and therefore capitalism, remains at the centre of socio-spatial state
institutions.’ More specifically, she wants to investigate the entrapment involved in a certain logic of violence and silence, and with this purpose she
explores the ‘culturally hegemonic, relationally ontological form of settler
colonialism that is at the core of Indigenous-settler relations.’ She wants to
highlight the strong relationship that must exist between anarchist and anticolonial thought and praxis, insisting that only on the basis of a clear anticolonial commitment can anarchism be truly coherent. For his part, Adam
Lewis develops a dilaceratingly (self-)critical reflection that is even more
viscerally opposed to granting any privileges to ‘settlers.’ In a chapter of
broad significance, he offers readers what can be understood as a deeply
Introduction
15
critical reflection on settler colonialism, having the United States and Canada
as ‘sources of inspiration.’ Interacting with the Indigenous resurgence movements across Canada and the United States and the attempts to formulate
Indigenous futures outside the state and capitalism, Adam shows that there is
no possible emancipatory project (at least not a coherent one) that can be
committed to decolonization while sparing capitalism and statecraft—in a
nutshell, the very pillars or our heteronomous world. Adam Lewis wisely and
acutely warns that ‘without attention to the histories of settler colonialism,
and enduring Indigenous resistance, anarchism is overlooking a foundational
structure of oppression and domination (and privilege for anarchist settlers)
while also pushing aside engagement with some of the people who know
most about living outside and confronting the state and capital.’ In light of
this, he then goes on to conclude that ‘[a]narchism needs to develop a critique of settler colonialism (and, more specifically, relationships to land,
place and context), so we can more effectively fight where we are, but also so
our methods of resistance and hopes for the future don’t come at the expense
of others who were resisting long before us.’
The final chapter—this time dealing with the presence of ‘invasive’ beings—is by Nick Garside. As he says, ‘In nearly all cases referring to feral or
invasive animals that I examined, there was a common theme that meant
feral animals, aliens and non-natives were judged as unnatural (and thus
unwelcome) outsiders and, as such, a disturbance to be dealt with by whatever means necessary. However, the discourse ‘autochthonous’ (‘native,’ ‘indigenous’) versus ‘exotic’ is a power discourse full of consequences. The
reason most often given for eradication of the individual species is preservation of the ‘integrity’ of the collective environment, while much of the language (‘authenticity,’ ‘purity,’ ‘natural,’ ‘native’) associated with conservation projects has rightly been challenged and shown to have xenophobic or
even racist connotations. However, as Nick asks, ‘How could anyone not
want to save the integrity of the ecological/social/cultural community?’ As
we see, this question embodies an ideological trap. Nick’s viewpoint is
against this logic, where he looks to a ‘disruptive promise’ that can emerge
from claiming the language of the ‘invasive’ as a kind of political metaphor
for envisioning one’s political agency: ‘[T]he disruptive promise of being
feral can become a radically democratic way of participating in modern
democracy. . . . I consider feral a border or boundary term that describes a
creature that is neither wild nor domestic, and at times both wild and domestic—never conforming to either simplistic classification. As such, one who is
feral is invasive.’ In a world full of tensions in the wake of (partly exogenously ignited or nurtured) civil wars and their many refugees, not to mention immigrants driven by famine or ‘natural’ disasters, Nick argues that
‘[f]eral citizens know they do not have the answer to democracy’s many
paradoxes and tensions, so, along with being interested in expanding the
16
Introduction
public sphere and revitalizing democratic culture, they are perpetual learners
who perform as observers and active listeners as well as storytellers and
actors.’ This is a perspective that promotes a highly stimulating intellectual
and political enterprise.
Undoubtedly, many challenges lie ahead—and numerous gaps remain
within the landscapes of left-libertarian geography that wait to be filled. But
it is hoped that this volume will be of assistance for all left-libertarian scholars and scholars-activists who want to meet those challenges with the purpose of helping advance radical theory and praxis in the spirit of revolt.
NOTES
1. Alongside Castoriadis (1922–1997), several other relevant names could be remembered
here, such as neo-anarchist (and later self-identified as a ‘communalist’) Murray Bookchin
(1921–2006). By the way, one of us (Marcelo Lopes de Souza) has not regarded himself as an
anarchist in a proper or strict sense, but rather as a ‘(left-)libertarian autonomist’ particularly
inspired by Castoriadis’s ‘project of autonomy.’ (A brilliant introduction to this ‘project’ can be
found in Castoriadis [1990]. Anglophone readers can also benefit, for instance, from the text
‘The Logic of Magmas and the Question of Autonomy,’ included in The Castoriadis Reader
edited by David Ames Curtis [Castoriadis 1997], and, of course, from The Imaginary Institution of Society, Castoriadis’s magnum opus, also available in English [see Castoriadis 1998].)
2. We should not forget that disagreements are nothing new among left-libertarians. The
sometimes explicit disagreements between Proudhonian mutualistes, Bakuninian collectivists,
Kropotkinian anarcho-communits, and so on testify to the differences among classical anarchists themselves (we can call ‘classical anarchism’ the thinkers, political forms of organizing and practical experiments carried out particularly between the middle of the nineteenth
century and the 1930s; after the Second World War, classical anarchism has been only residually present as a political force, and its intellectual legacy has been more or less strongly reframed—apart from a few very dogmatic people who insist in living in the past). Those who
one of us (Souza 2012a, 2012b, 2012c, 2014) has called ‘neo-anarchists’ (such as Murray
Bookchin) depart from the classics on several important points (in Bookchin’s case, both the
interpretation of concepts like ‘government’ and ‘power’ and the approach to some organizational or strategic aspects such as the value of consensus, strongly relativized by him) while at
the same time maintaining an explicit commitment to the anarchist tradition. In so doing, neoanarchists stand in contrast to a thinker such as Castoriadis, who did not see himself as representing the continuance of this tradition—in spite of the fact that there are, in essence, many
more convergences than divergences between Castoriadis’s ‘projet d’autonomie’ and the anarchist tradition. From the viewpoint of Marcelo Lopes de Souza (not shared by Castoriadis
himself, who was unfair towards anarchists sometimes), the ‘project of autonomy’ basically
corresponds to an updated and particularly sophisticated version of the century-old political
project of a radically free society. Last but not least, it must be stressed that, as the leftlibertarian lineage cannot be mistaken with the ‘right-libertarian’ approach to society (a grotesque, typically U.S.-American species. For continental Europeans and Latin-Americans, ‘libertarian’ does not even need the word ‘left-,’ as it is implied that libertaire [Fr.], libertario
[Span. and Ital.], libertário [Port.] and libertär [Germ.] traditionally do not have anything to do
with right-wing, hyper-liberal tendencies—see Souza’s chapter ‘“Libertarian,” libertaire, libertario’ in this volume), similarly Castoriadis’s approach to autonomy cannot be mistaken with
Marxist ‘autonomism’ (an interesting oxymoron!) as represented by authors such as John
Holloway, who wrote a book about ‘changing the world without taking (state) power’ without
giving any credit at all to those who first developed this view: the anarchists.
3. ‘Anarchy’ comes from the Greek word anarchia (ἀναρχία), which can be understood as
a society ‘without rulers’ (= an [not, without] + arkhos [ruler, leader, authority]). In practice, it
Introduction
17
has been also understood as ‘powerlessness’ and ‘lawlessness.’ On Castoriadis’s critique of the
idea of a society entirely ‘without power,’ see, for instance, Castoriadis (1983, 16); on his
widening of the concept of ‘power,’ see Castoriadis (1990).
4. The following passage is highly illustrative of Bookchin’s broad perspective:
‘[A]narchists have long regarded every government as a state and condemned it accordingly—
a view that is a recipe for the elimination of any organized social life whatever. While the state
is the instrument by which an oppressive and exploitative class regulates and coercively controls the behavior of an exploited class by a ruling class, a government—or better still, a
polity—is an ensemble of institutions designed to deal with the problems of consociational life
in an orderly and hopefully fair manner. Every institutionalized association that constitutes a
system for handling public affairs—with or without the presence of a state—is necessarily a
government. By contrast, every state, although necessarily a form of government, is a force for
class repression and control. Annoying as it must seem to Marxists and anarchists alike, the cry
for a constitution, for a responsible and a responsive government, and even for law or nomos
has been clearly articulated—and committed to print!—by the oppressed for centuries against
the capricious rule exercised by monarchs, nobles, and bureaucrats. The libertarian opposition
to law, not to speak of government as such, has been as silly as the image of a snake swallowing its tail. What remains in the end is nothing but a retinal afterimage that has no existential
reality’ (Bookchin 2007, 95).
REFERENCES
Bookchin, M. 1974. The Limits of the City. New York: Harper Colophon Books.
Bookchin, M. 1992. Urbanization without Cities: The Rise and Decline of Citizenship. Montreal and Cheektowaga: Black Rose Books.
Bookchin, M. 1995. From Urbanization to Cities: Toward a New Politics of Citizenship.
Londres: Cassel. [Revised version of Urbanization without Cities.]
Bookchin, M. 2004 (several years). Post-Scarcity Anarchism. Edinburgh and Oakland: AK
Press, 3rd edition.
Bookchin, M. 2005 (1982). The Ecology of Freedom. The Emergence and Dissolution of
Hierarchy. Oakland and Edinburgh: AK Press.
Bookchin, M. 2007 (several years). Social Ecology and Communalism. Oakland and Edinburgh: AK Press.
Castoriadis, C. 1983 (1979). ‘Introdução: socialismo e sociedade autônoma.’ In Socialismo ou
barbárie. O conteúdo do socialismo. São Paulo: Brasiliense.
Castoriadis, C. 1990 (1988). ‘Pouvoir, Politique, Autonomie.’ In Le monde morcelé—Les
carrefours du labyrinthe III. Paris: Seuil, 113–39.
Castoriadis, C. 1997. The Castoriadis Reader. Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Castoriadis, C. 1998 (1975). The Imaginary Institution of Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gurvitch, G. 1980 (1964). Proudhon e Marx. Lisbon: Editorial Presença and Martins Fontes.
Kropotkin, P. 2002 (1899). Fields, Factories and Workshops. Online: http://dwardmac.pitzer.
edu/Anarchist_Archives/kropotkin/fields.html (accessed 1 December 2002).
Reclus, É. 1905–1908. L’Homme et la Terre. 6 vols. Paris: Librairie Universelle. Online (facsimile reproduction): Librairie Nationale Française (http://gallica.bnf.fr; specific address
varies according to the volume).
Souza, M. L. de. 2012a. ‘The City in Libertarian Thought: From Élisée Reclus to Murray
Bookchin—and Beyond.’ City 16(1–2): 5–34.
Souza, M. L. de. 2012b. ‘Marxists, Libertarians and the City.’ City 16(3): 315–31.
Souza, M. L. de. 2012c. ‘Libertarians and Marxists in the 21st Century: Thoughts on Our
Contemporary Specificities and Their Relevance to Urban Studies, as a Tribute to Neil
Smith.’ City 16(6): 692–98.
Souza, M. L. de. 2014. ‘Towards a Libertarian Turn? Notes on the Past and Future of Radical
Urban Research and Praxis.’ City 18(2): 104–18.
Souza, M. L. de. 2015. ‘From the “Right to the City” to the Right to the Planet: Reinterpreting
our Contemporary Challenges for Socio-Spatial Development.’ City 19(4): 401–36.
18
Introduction
Springer, S. 2014a. ‘For Anarcho-Geography! Or, Bare-Knuckle Boxing as the World Burns.’
Dialogues in Human Geography 4(30): 297–310.
Springer, S. 2014b. ‘Why a Radical Geography Must Be Anarchist.’ Dialogues in Human
Geography 4(30): 249–70.