Philos Stud (2011) 154:251–277
DOI 10.1007/s11098-010-9536-x
Truth and meaning redux
Ernie Lepore • Kirk Ludwig
Published online: 20 March 2010
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010
Abstract In this paper, we defend Davidson’s program in truth-theoretical
semantics against recent criticisms by Scott Soames. We argue that Soames has
misunderstood Davidson’s project, that in consequence his criticisms miss the mark,
that appeal to meanings as entities in the alternative approach that Soames favors
does no work, and that the approach is no advance over truth-theoretic semantics.
Keywords Donald Davidson Truth-theoretic semantics Meaning
Scott Soames
1 Introduction
Forty-three years ago, Donald Davidson, in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ (1967), suggested
that insight into meaning might be gained by reflection on how to construct and to
confirm a Tarski-style truth theory for a natural language. The suggestion has been
influential, but it has not been well understood.
In a recent paper, Scott Soames argues that this project has now run its course
(2008). He argues that Davidson’s two rationales for his project were unsuccessful
and that what he sees as the most promising recent attempt along the same lines, by
Affiliation of K. Ludwig after July 1, 2010: Department of Philosophy, Indiana University, Bloomington,
IN 47405-7005, USA.
E. Lepore (&)
Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University-New Brunswick, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020,
USA
e-mail:
[email protected]
K. Ludwig
Philosophy Department, University of Florida, Gainesville, FL 32611-8545, USA
e-mail:
[email protected]
123
252
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
Jim Higginbotham, is likewise unsuccessful. It should be replaced, he argues, with
an older style theory that assigns entities to expressions, and which aims to explain
the meaning of complex expressions by showing how to recursively construct
appropriate entities to assign to them on the basis of assignments to their significant
parts. Davidson’s own animadversions against such theories, he argues, while not
without force, can be avoided by appeal to some ideas from Wittgenstein’s
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1961).
This paper argues (a) that Soames has misunderstood Davidson’s project, (b) that
once we clarify the project, we can see it escapes his objections unscathed, and (c)
that the appeal to meanings as entities does no work in Soames’s alternative
approach to semantics and is no advance over truth-theoretic semantics.
The program of the paper is as follows: we begin with Soames’s characterization
of Davidson’s project, and a brief indication of how he mischaracterizes it. We then
turn to Soames’s evidence for his interpretation. This involves both an account of the
historical context, and a reading of a key passage in ‘‘Truth and Meaning.’’ We show
that his reading of the historical context does not fit Davidson’s project and that
placing the key passage in its proper context in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ as well as the
rest of Davidson’s corpus shows Soames’s interpretation to be incorrect. To this end,
we look closely at how Davidson sets the stage for his suggestion that constructing
and confirming a truth theory for a natural language is a way to pursue the project of
devising a compositional meaning theory. We consider several stages in his rejection
of the appeal to assigning meanings, construed as entities, to words or sentences as a
way of providing a compositional meaning theory for a language. We pay particular
attention to an illustration that Davidson gives using a simple reference theory to
show why assigning entities to expressions is not in itself useful and how they can be
dispensed with, and we also show how this illustration presages Davidson’s own
suggestion for how to use a truth theory in pursuit of a compositional meaning theory.
We look at why he rejects assigning meanings as entities to sentences, and note a key
observation he makes about what the effective goal is of a compositional meaning
theory. In the light of this, we review the passage Soames cites and his criticisms of
Davidson’s project. Lastly, we consider Soames’s own positive proposal; we argue
that it is no advance over Davidson’s and is instead a step backwards.
2 Davidson’s project and Soames’s characterization of it
There are two issues to separate at the outset, one interpretive, one not. First, is
Soames right about what Davidson’s project is and that as characterized it cannot be
carried out? Second, is Soames right that if the project he characterizes cannot be
carried out, no broadly Davidsonian program of truth-theoretic semantics is tenable?
We will defend an interpretation of Davidson’s project significantly different from
Soames’s. But even were our interpretation mistaken, we still maintain it represents
a Davidsonian project that escapes Soames’s criticisms.
Soames begins with a mischaracterization of Davidson’s project which informs the
rest of his paper, i.e., that it was an attempt ‘‘to explain knowledge of meaning in terms
of knowledge of truth conditions’’ (p. 1). He continues, ‘‘[f]or Davidsonians, these
123
Truth and meaning redux
253
attempts take the form of rationales for treating theories of truth, constructed along
Tarskian lines, as empirical theories of meaning’’ (p. 1). Both claims are mistaken.
The first characterization is not one Davidson ever gave nor is it one he would
have endorsed. Davidson’s project was to devise a satisfactory theory of meaning,
ultimately, as he states it in the preface to Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation
(2001), to answer the question: ‘‘What is it for words to mean what they do?’’ This
project decomposes into two parts. One part concerns how the meanings of complex
expressions, and ultimately sentences, depend on the meanings of words. The other
part concerns understanding what it is for primitive expressions to mean what they
do. Davidson suggested progress could be made on the first project by indirection,
by reflection on what we learn from constructing a truth theory for a language
subject to constraints designed to ensure it meets Tarski’s Convention T, or its
analog for natural languages with context sensitive elements (henceforth,
‘Convention T’ abbreviates this disjunction). Progress on the second project was
to be attained in turn by reflection on how one could empirically confirm a truth
theory that, meeting appropriate constraints, would have identifiable theorems from
which one could read off what each sentence of the object language means, or, more
precisely, for any utterance of a sentence in the language, what it means.
Clearly, neither part of this project is about explaining knowledge of meaning, and
so neither is about explaining knowledge of meaning in terms of knowledge of truth
conditions. In addition, it is clear even from this brief and general characterization
that it is not just knowledge of what a truth theory states that is to provide insight, but
also the knowledge that arises from reflection on how to construct and confirm a
theory that meets Convention T. We will return to this point at greater length.
With respect to the second part of his project, it is, first, not easy to see how
giving such an account would amount to explaining knowledge of meaning in terms
of knowledge of truth conditions. Second, it turns out that it is not the truth theory
per se that is an empirical theory of meaning. This is clear by Davidson’s middle
period, and if we can take his retrospective remarks at face value, it was how he was
thinking about it even in ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’ for which there is also evidence in
how he develops the project there.
3 The historical context
Why does Soames think Davidson intended to explain knowledge of meaning in
terms of knowledge of truth conditions? He provides a just-so story about the
origins of Davidson’s project in the theory of meaning. Soames suggests Davidson’s
idea fell out of a combination of Quinean skepticism about meaning and reflection
on Tarski’s work on the semantic conception of truth:
[i].
For those laboring under the Quinean legacy of skepticism about analyticity,
synonymy, and meaning, the idea afoot was that extensional notions from the
theory of truth and reference were respectable, whereas intensional ones from
the theory of meaning were not.
…
123
254
[ii].
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
Since Tarski’s seminal work in the 1930s, it has been common place to view
an interpreted formal language as the result of adding a model, plus a
definition of truth-in-a-model, to an uninterpreted formal system, thereby
arriving at an assignment of truth conditions to every sentence. But if truth
theories can be used in this way to endow sentences with meaning, then
surely, it seemed, they can also be used to describe the meanings of already
meaningful sentences—provided, in the case of natural language, that we are
clever enough to find the requisite logical forms to which to apply them. (p. 2)
His suggestion is that Davidson, like Quine, was a nihilist about meaning—not
just a skeptic about the utility of introducing entities called meanings, but also about
the intelligibility of the concept of meaning. Yet at the same time, he was to have
thought that Tarski’s work provided a way of endowing sentences with meaning by
adding a model to a formal system and defining truth-in-a model. But if one thought
the first, why on earth think the second? The second can be true only if the first is
false.
Davidson was not in fact a nihilist about meaning, even if he held that meanings,
construed as entities, have no useful role to play in the theory of meaning. Perhaps it
is a conflation of Davidson’s rejection of meanings with a rejection of meaning that
has led some commentators—e.g. (Chihara 1975; Stich 1976; Katz 1982, pp. 183–
185; Soames 1992; Cummins 2002; Glock 2003, pp. 142ff.) and now (Soames
2008)—to think Davidson was rejecting the very project he announces at the
beginning of ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ (p. 17; page citations for Davidson are to
Davidson (2001), when essays are reprinted there) rather than its pursuit by
indirection.1
[a]
It is conceded by most philosophers of language, and recently by some linguists,
that a satisfactory theory of meaning must give an account of how the meanings
of sentences depend upon the meanings of words.2 Unless such an account could
be supplied for a particular language, it is argued, there would be no explaining
the fact that we can learn the language: no explaining the fact that, on mastering a
finite vocabulary and a finitely stated set of rules, we are prepared to produce and
understand any of a potential infinitude of sentences. I do not dispute these vague
claims, in which I sense more than a kernel of truth. Instead I want to ask what it is
for a theory to give an account of the kind adumbrated.3
Later in ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’ Davidson says, ‘‘the task of a theory of meaning
as I conceive it is not to change, improve, or reform a language, but to describe and
1
A different misunderstanding is expressed in Horwich (2005, p. 4 & Ch. 8) who suggests Davidson
aimed to analyze sentence meaning in terms of truth conditions. Why this is a mistake will become clear
in the course of our discussion. This misunderstanding is also widespread. Burge gives it as if it were the
standard account of Davidson in Burge (1992, pp. 20–1).
2
In his initial characterization of the project, Davidson talks of meanings in the plural. What emerges
from his discussion is that the kernel of truth in the following claim does not require the assignments of
meanings to sentences or words.
3
The same project is his theme in ‘‘Theories of Meaning and Learnable Languages’’ (1966), published
the year before ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’ and in ‘‘Semantics for Natural Languages’’ (1970) read first in
1968, the year after publication of ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ (1967).
123
Truth and meaning redux
255
understand it’’ (p. 29).4 Quine’s project in Word and Object (Quine 1960), in
contrast, was to provide a scientifically respectable replacement for the ordinary
notion of meaning, one constructed out of the concept of stimulus synonymy.
Davidson is not engaged in this sort of project, though he was importantly
influenced by Quine, particularly in regarding the empirical content of theories of
meaning as exhausted by the evidence available to an interpreter, and, specifically,
to a radical interpreter. But what he took from Quine he transformed for his uses in
pursuit of an understanding of what it is for words to mean what they do, where
‘mean’ is used in its ordinary sense.
We also note that Davidson was not thinking of truth-in-a-model in invoking
Tarski, but instead Tarski’s work on absolute theories of truth (1983). There is no
suggestion in Tarski that we endow sentences with meaning by defining a truth
predicate for the language of which they are a part. The idea went the other way: if
we know the definition matches object language sentences with meta-language
sentences that translate them, we know it is materially adequate, if it is formally
correct. Davidson would have had to be seriously confused about Tarski to have
reasoned in the way outlined in passage [ii].
4 A key passage in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’
It is no accident that Davidson is often interpreted as pursuing what might be called
a Replacement Strategy. There are passages in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ which strongly
suggest this, and Soames quotes one of the most striking (p. 24).
[b]
There is no need to suppress, of course, the obvious connection between a
definition of truth of the kind Tarski has shown how to construct, and the
concept of meaning. It is this: the definition works by giving necessary and
sufficient conditions for the truth of every sentence, and to give truth
conditions is a way of giving the meaning of a sentence. To know the semantic
concept of truth for a language is to know what it is for a sentence—any
sentence—to be true, and this amounts, in one good sense we can give to the
phrase, to understanding the language. This at any rate is my excuse for a
feature of the present discussion that is apt to shock old hands; my
freewheeling use of the word ‘‘meaning,’’ for what I call a theory of meaning
has after all turned out to make no use of meanings, whether of sentences or of
words. Indeed, since a Tarski-type truth definition supplies all we have asked
so far of a theory of meaning, it is clear that such a theory falls comfortably
within what Quine terms the ‘‘theory of reference’’ as distinguished from what
4
In ‘‘Semantics for Natural Languages’’ (1970, p. 62), Davidson says, ‘‘Making a systematic account of
truth central in empirical semantics is in a way merely a matter of stating old goals more sharply.’’ He
goes onto say, ‘‘Some problems that have dominated recent work on semantics would fade in importance:
the attempt to give ‘the meaning’ of sentences…’’; but here the inclusion of ‘the meaning’ in quotation
marks serves to indicate he has in mind producing entities that will serve as meanings and a standard for
translation; it is also Davidson’s view that the standard for translation emerges only in the context of
radical interpretation.
123
256
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
he terms the ‘‘theory of meaning.’’ So much to the good for what I call a theory
of meaning, and so much, perhaps, against my so calling it.
Is this not evidence that what Davidson calls a theory of meaning is one in name
only; isn’t he proposing to replace the old pursuit of a theory of meaning with the
new, more tractable and intellectually respectable project of constructing a truth
theory for a language? Does this not establish, as Soames puts it, that ‘‘Davidson
thought that systematic knowledge of truth and reference could do all legitimate
work for which we need a notion of meaning’’ (p. 3)? Does it not show Davidson’s
‘‘strategy was to embrace Quine’s rejection of analyticity, synonymy, and our
ordinary notion of meaning, substituting knowledge of truth and reference for
knowledge of meaning—whenever there was something genuine to be captured’’
(p. 3)?
To answer these questions, we must first place the passage in its context.
Here’s ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ in a nutshell: Davidson begins with the project of
how to provide a compositional meaning theory for a natural language. He rejects
the utility of an appeal to meanings as entities. He offers an initial argument against
any such appeal that rests on the observation that assigning meanings to expressions
and even concatenation leaves the difference between a list and a sentence
unexplained. He develops the point by drawing some lessons from reflection on a
simple reference theory, viz., that it is not necessary to assign an object to every
significant part of a complex referring term to provide an assignment of referents to
any of an infinite class of recursively generated referring terms. He extends this idea
to the rejection of assignments of meanings as the referents of sentences (so that,
although not all words are assigned meanings, every sentence is) primarily through
an appeal to an argument widely known as ‘The Slingshot’. Then he despairs of an
appeal to a theory that generates theorems utilizing ‘means that’, if neither the
sentences following it nor terms of the form ‘that p’ are referring terms. He observes
that the desired work would be achieved if we can match each object language
sentence with a meta-language sentence that ‘gives its meaning’, for that is in effect
what generated theorems of the form ‘s means that p’ do. He then proposes that a
truth theory can be used effectively towards this end. We examine these stages in
some detail before returning to [b].
5 A lesson from a simple reference theory
In passage [a] above, Davidson states his ostensible goal in ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’
namely, to inquire into what it is to give an account of how the meanings of
sentences depend on the meanings of words. In the first few pages he considers and
rejects the appeal to assigning meanings, construed as entities, to words as a way of
explaining sentential meaning in terms of word meaning.
Suppose the meaning of ‘Theatetus’ is Theatetus and the meaning of ‘flies’ is the
property of flying. So far as this goes, ‘Theatetus flies’ might as well be interpreted
as a list: Theatetus, the property of flying. Since concatenating ‘Theatetus’ with
‘flies’ is semantically significant, to be consistent, we must assign to concatenation
123
Truth and meaning redux
257
itself an entity, say, a relation of instantiating. But this only increases the list:
Theatetus, the relation of instantiation, the property of flying.5
Davidson’s critical point emerges clearly in the context of a theory of complex
singular terms. The expression ‘The father of David’ concatenates ‘The father of’
(treated as primitive here) with ‘David’. If ‘The father of’ refers to a function, how
can this help determine what the complex refers to? We might say: ‘the father of’
refers to that function such that its value for argument x is the father of x. Clearly,
reference to the function plays no role in the explanation. The same information is
captured by: ‘the father of’ concatenated with a singular term t refers to the father of
what t refers to. Here we have a rule that determines, relative to assignments of
referents to primitive expressions, what any expression formed from concatenating
‘the father of’ with a singular term refers to.6 No assignment of anything to ‘the
father of’ is required. This rule uses ‘the father of’, of course, but it turns out that
this is unavoidable. As Davidson says,
[c]
…the task was to give the meaning of all expressions in a certain infinite set on
the basis of the meaning of the parts; it was not in the bargain also to give the
meanings of the atomic parts. On the other hand, it is now evident that a
satisfactory theory of the meanings of complex expressions may not require
entities as meanings of all the parts. It behooves us then to rephrase our
demand on a satisfactory theory of meaning so as not to suggest that individual
words must have meanings at all, in any sense that transcends the fact that they
have a systematic effect on the meanings of the sentences in which they occur.
(p. 18)
In the case of our theory of reference, we can state a simple criterion of success: a
theory should entail every sentence of the form ‘t refers to x,’ where ‘t’ is replaced
by a structural description of a singular term and ‘x’ by that term itself. This
condition should look familiar; it is an analog of Tarski’s Convention T, but for a
theory of reference, restricted to cases where the object language is embedded in the
meta-language. Generalizing, we seek a theory that satisfies Convention R:
An adequate theory entails every sentence of the form ‘t refers to x’, where ‘t’
is replaced by a structural description of a singular term and ‘x’ is replaced by
a term in the meta-language that translates it.
5
Alternatively, assign an individual concept to ‘Theatetus’ and read ‘Theatetus flies’ as the list: the
individual concept of Theatetus, the property of flying, and instantiation. This only renders the problem
more evident.
6
It has been suggested to us that the problem raised here applies to the approach we sketch below. The
line of thought seems to be this: ‘‘You say that the theory that assigns the function and the argument to
expressions does not say how to put them together to get the meaning of ‘Theatetus flies’. But the sorts of
theories you recommend consist of axioms and rules and the theory doesn’t say how to put them together
to get theorems. So it’s the same thing!’’ The tu quoque charge misunderstands the point of the argument,
which is that (i) the information we need to understand is not given by the assignment of entities to
expressions; and (ii) knowledge of those assignments, excepting in the case of ordinary referring terms, is
not included in the information that is needed. Furthermore, it is not, as we will explain, part of our view
that an axiomatic reference or truth theory contains all the information that is needed, though it is part of
our view that information about assignments of meanings to all expressions in a language is not needed.
123
258
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
Having gotten this far, we are only a tiny step away from stating explicitly what
each singular term in our fragment means. This is not a step Davidson took, but it is
instructive to follow out its implications. Restricting attention for the moment to a
theory the language of which embeds the object language, a syntactic criterion
suffices for identifying theorems that satisfy (R). Given an adequate theory, it will
entail, inter alia,
‘The father of’a ‘David’ refers to the father of David.
Since the expression used on the right of ‘refers to’ translates the one mentioned
on the left, we can replace ‘refers to’ with ‘means’ to derive:
‘The father of’a ‘David’ means the father of David.
Thus, omitting for now an account of ‘x means y’, we have a way of generating,
for an infinite class of expressions built up systematically from a finite vocabulary,
an explicit statement of what each means.
Looking at languages we do not already know will allow us to register further
points that pave the way for understanding Davidson’s proposal to use a truth theory
in pursuit of the project of understanding how the meanings of complex expressions
depend on the meanings of their significant parts.
Consider as an object language a fragment of French consisting of singular terms
‘Marie’, ‘Jean’, and any concatenation of ‘La mère de’ with a singular term. Call
this infinite fragment ‘L’. Theory S for L in an English meta-language consists of
axioms (1)–(3):
1.
2.
3.
‘Marie’ refers in L to Mary.
‘Jean’ refers in L to John.
For any singular term t in L, ‘La mère de’a t refers in L to the mother of what t
refers to in L.
Its (informally stated) rules of inference are: (I) From (3), any instance may be
inferred; (II) from any sentences of the form ‘t refers in L to y’ and any sentence of
the form S(what t refers to in L), S(y) may be inferred. A canonical reference
theorem of S is any theorem derived from (1) to (3) using (I) and (II) which is an
instance of ‘t refers to y,’ in which ‘y’ is replaced by a meta-language referring term
that does not include ‘refers to’. Since in each base axiom the term used on the right
of ‘refers to’ translates the one mentioned on the left, and since in (3) ‘the mother
of’ in the meta-language translates ‘La mère de’ in L, in each canonical reference
theorem the meta-language expression used on the right of ‘refers to’ translates the
expression mentioned on the left.
Any theory of reference which satisfies this requirement on its axioms we shall
say satisfies Convention A. That S satisfies Convention A, given rules (I)–(II),
suffices for it to satisfy Convention R. At this point, we add another valid rule of
inference: (III) From a canonical reference theorem of the form ‘t refers in L to y’
infer ‘t means in L y’—call any theorem so derived a canonical meaning theorem.
If we know [KS]
(i)
the axioms of S, as stated in (1)–(3),
123
Truth and meaning redux
259
(ii) what each axiom of S states and that each states what it does,7
(iii) in base axioms the term used on the right of ‘refers in L to’ translates the one
mentioned on the left, and in (3) ‘the mother of’ in the meta-language
translates ‘La mère de’ in L,
(iv) rules of inference (I) and (II),
(v) what a canonical reference theorem is, and
(vi) rule of inference (III).
we are in a position to know for any expression of L what it means in this sense: we
are thereby in a position to know for an arbitrary singular term t of L its
corresponding canonical meaning theorem. Moreover, we can come to know this on
the basis of being able to derive this canonical meaning theorem from axioms that
we know give the referents of object language terms using expressions in the metalanguage that translate them. Thus, we see how the meanings and referents of the
contained terms contribute to determining the meanings and referents of the
complex expressions, given how they are combined in them.
For primitive names, the theory states their referents and shows their meanings
(relative to the knowledge that it satisfies Convention A). For the primitive recursive
term ‘la mère de’, the theory gives a rule that says what the reference of the
expression is in terms of the referent of another, and this rule shows what the
expression means by using an expression that translates it, in the same grammatical
role to the right of ‘refers to’.
In S we find in microcosm Davidson’s suggestion for how to pursue the project of
giving a compositional meaning theory using materials drawn from the theory of
reference. We need to unfold a bit more of the story before extending the idea to the
whole of a language, and not just a fragment involving complex referring terms.
6 Rejecting the direct extension to sentences
Reflection on S shows us that we do not need to assign a meaning to every word in
order to fix the referents for complex referring terms. This suggests we do not need
to assign meanings to every word to assign meanings to sentences, though we might
retain the idea that each sentence has a meaning, construed as an entity, associated
with it. A simple way of implementing this idea is to treat sentences as referring
terms that refer to their meanings, and then extend a reference theory to cover
sentences so understood. This is to take predicate terms generally to be functional
terms and sentences to be complex referring terms, derived from supplying an
7
We need both (i) and (ii) because (ii) does not ensure that we know the syntactic forms of each axiom,
which is required if we are to use them to derive canonical reference theorems, as opposed to knowing
what they are by way of names or descriptions. We need to know what the forms of the axioms are to use
the canonical proof procedure to isolate the right set of theorems. We are assuming that knowledge of a
grammar for the language of the truth theory that sorts expressions into grammatical categories such as
noun phrase, verb phrase, determiner, noun, verb, adverb, adjective, etc., relative to which we understand
the rules of inference. This plays a role in putting the knowledge specified in (i) and (ii) together in a way
that enables us to understand the language of the reference theory, which is essential if we are to use it to
understand object language expressions.
123
260
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
argument term for the functional term, which refer to their meanings. In line with
the observations above, however, we need not take seriously the idea that the
functional terms refer to anything (anymore than we did with ‘the father of’). All we
need is a rule that takes us from an expression mentioned to a term used that refers
to what the first expression refers to. For ‘rouge’ we give the axiom:
For any referring term t, t a ‘est rouge’ refers to red(what t refers to).8
Davidson sought to scotch this proposal as well with an argument later dubbed
‘The Slingshot’ (by Barwise and Perry 1981). This argument (we have argued
elsewhere; Lepore and Ludwig 2005, pp. 49–55) is guilty of equivocation, or
ultimately relies on an assumption that is supposed to be its conclusion. But the
proposal should be scotched anyway. What does the work in the proposal is that the
meta-language referring terms are sentences alike in meaning to their corresponding
object language sentences. The only role reference plays in the theory is to facilitate
the matching object language sentences mentioned with used meta-language
language sentences that translate them. Since this effect can be achieved without
positing meanings, as we will show, they are entirely gratuitous.
7 The proposal to use a truth theory in pursuit of a meaning theory
All of this is still background for the proposal Davidson eventually makes, and
keeping it in mind renders transparent that he is not abandoning pursuit of the
project of explaining how the meanings of sentences depend on those of their
significant parts—though he abandons this particular way of expressing it. The
trouble, as he sees it, is that assigning entities to words and sentences simply does
not advance the project.
[d]
What analogy [with our simple theory of reference] demands is a theory that
has as consequences all sentences of the form ‘s means m’ where ‘s’ is
replaced by a structural description of a sentence and ‘m’ is replaced by a
singular term that refers to the meaning of that sentence; a theory, moreover,
that provides an effective method for arriving at the meaning of an arbitrary
sentence structurally described…My objection to meanings in the theory of
meaning is not that they are abstract or that their identity conditions are
obscure, but that they have no demonstrated use. (pp. 20–21)
The transition to Davidson’s novel proposal occurs in the following passage,
which we quote in full as it is crucial to understanding how he thinks a truth theory
is relevant to the project of ‘‘Truth and Meaning.’’
[e]
…having found no more help in meanings of sentences than in meanings of
words, let us ask whether we can get rid of the troublesome singular terms
supposed to replace ‘m’ and to refer to meanings. In a way, nothing could be
easier: just write ‘s means that p’, and imagine ‘p’ replaced by a sentence.
8
A clear potential problem with this is that it assumes the meaning of t is fixed by its referent. The
Slingshot in fact exploits this in one of its assumptions.
123
Truth and meaning redux
261
Sentences, as we have seen, cannot name meanings, and sentences with ‘that’
prefixed are not names at all, unless we decide so. It looks as though we are in
trouble on another count, however, for it is reasonable to expect that in
wrestling with the logic of the apparently non-extensional ‘means that’ we will
encounter problems as hard as, or perhaps identical with, the problems our
theory is out to solve.
[f] The only way I know to deal with this difficulty is simple, and radical. Anxiety
that we are enmeshed in the intensional springs from using the words ‘means
that’ as filling between description of sentence and sentence, but it may be that
the success of our venture depends not on the filling but on what it fills. The
theory will have done its work if it provides, for every sentence s in the language
under study, a matching sentence (to replace ‘p’) that, in some way yet to be
made clear, ‘gives the meaning’ of s. One obvious candidate for matching
sentence is just s itself, if the object language is contained in the metalanguage.
As a final bold step, let us try treating the position occupied by ‘p’ extensionally:
to implement this, sweep away the obscure ‘means that’, provide the sentence
that replaces ‘p’ with a proper sentential connective and supply the description
that replaces ‘s’ with its own predicate. The plausible result is
(T) s is T if and only if p
What we require of a theory of meaning for a language L is that without appeal
to any (further) semantical notions it place enough restrictions on the predicate
‘is T’ to entail all sentences got from schema T when ‘s’ is replaced by a
structural description of a sentence of L and ‘p’ by that sentence.
[g] …it is clear that the sentence to which the predicate ‘is T’ applies will be just
the true sentences of L, for the condition we have placed on satisfactory
theories of meaning is in essence Tarski’s Convention T that tests the adequacy
of a formal semantical definition of truth. (pp. 22–23)
In [e], when Davidson writes, ‘‘it is clear we have found no more help in
meanings of sentences than in meanings of words,’’ he is thinking about the project
of assigning entities, called ‘meanings’, to words and sentences, and his complaint,
as passage [d] makes explicit, is that introducing these entities does nothing to
explain how the meanings of sentences depend on those of words. It surely does not
help us to arrive ‘‘at the meaning of an arbitrary sentence structurally described.’’
This hardly rejects the project of providing a compositional meaning theory, as
Soames claims, for Davidson’s complaint is that an appeal to meanings (as entities)
fails to do the work required for that project!
Davidson goes onto ask whether we might simply refuse to treat the position after
‘means’ as referential, casting the target theorems in the form ‘s means that p.’ The
difficulty with this proposal, he says, becomes how to formulate a theory that starts
with axioms attaching to words and recursively generates theorems of this form, for
it would seem we cannot invoke the apparatus of quantificational logic (objectual
quantification, at any rate) to reach into the position occupied by ‘p’, as it would
seem we must in order to utilize the axioms attaching to significant parts of ‘p’.
It is clear, however, that if such a theory were available, it would allow us to
match each object language sentence s with a meta-language sentence the same in
123
262
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
meaning, but in something like a use position, for ‘s means that p’ is true iff the
sentence that replaces ‘p’ translates s. Once we relinquish the goal of assigning
entities to words and sentences that are their meanings, we can see that the work
essentially comes to this.
This is Davidson’s point in the third sentence of passage [f], when he writes, ‘‘The
theory will have done its work if it provides, for every sentence s in the language under
study, a matching sentence (to replace ‘p’) that, in some way yet to be made clear,
‘gives the meaning’ of s.’’ He hedges, first, because it is obvious he is not giving the
meaning of s by introducing an entity as its meaning, and the description literally
would require that, and, second, because there is more to giving the meaning of a
sentence than matching it with one in the meta-language the same in meaning (or use
profile): it is also a goal to show how the meaning of the sentence is determined by, or
depends on, the meanings of its significant parts and their mode of arrangement.
The design problem, then, is this (paraphrasing a sentence in [d]): formulate a
theory that has as consequences all sentences of the form ‘s—p’, where ‘s’ is replaced
by a structural description of sentence and ‘p’ by a metalanguage sentence that gives
the meaning of that sentence; a theory, moreover, that provides an effective method
for arriving at the meaning of an arbitrary sentence structurally described.
Davidson’s great insight was to see that there was a form of theory ready to hand
that fits the bill, namely, a Tarski-style truth theory that satisfies Convention T. He
arrived at this suggestion indirectly: what we want is a replacement for ‘—’ in ‘s—p’
that permits us to exploit the familiar tools of logic on the position occupied by ‘p’ so
as to formulate a theory that has as consequences, for each sentence s of the object
language, a theorem of the relevant form in which the sentence that replaces ‘p’ gives
the meaning of s. We can achieve this straightforwardly if the meta-language embeds
the object language, and the sentence that replaces ‘p’ is s itself. Given that we want
the mentioned sentence matched with a used one alike in meaning, and given that we
demand an extensional filler, we must supply a predicate for s so as to have a
sentence on the left hand side and a truth-functional connective between left and
right. The simplest connective that does the job is ‘if and only if’, as exhibited in (T)
above. But if the goal is to be able to derive for each sentence of the object language a
theorem of this form in which ‘p’ is replaced by s, what we will have (assuming
consistency) is a theory meeting Tarski’s Convention T for the language.
This is Davidson’s point in [g], an observation we hope it is becoming clear was
his aim all along. Note that he speaks of Tarski’s Convention T as being the
condition ‘‘we have placed on satisfactory theories of meaning.’’ With this wording,
he clearly is not limiting himself to vocabulary from the theory of reference, for
generalizing Convention T to an arbitrary meta-language requires the theory to
entail each instance of (T) in which the metalanguage sentence that replaces ‘p’
translates the object language sentence s.9
In passage [f], a line that has drawn extensive exegetical and critical attention is
Davidson’s statement of what we require of a theory of meaning, namely, that
9
It is obvious that for a context sensitive language the syntactic criterion won’t work; we cannot give
context relative truth conditions for ‘I am hungry’, e.g., using a sentence with context sensitive features.
This requires a generalization of Tarski’s Convention T. We want theorems to provide context relative
truth conditions which interpret utterances of object languages sentences relative to those contexts.
123
Truth and meaning redux
263
‘‘without appeal to any (further) semantical notions it place enough restrictions on
the predicate ‘is T’ to entail all sentences got from schema T, when ‘s’ is replaced by
a structural description of a sentence of L and ‘p’ by that sentence.’’ Why does he
say, ‘‘without appeal to any (further) semantical notions’’?
This expresses a natural ambition, once one sees how the trick is to be turned, to
see whether we may gain insight not only into how what complex sentences mean
depends on their contained semantical primitives and mode of combination, but also
into connections between concepts in the family of meaning and others, and, in
particular, since we see we have in effect a truth theory, between the concept of
meaning and the concept of truth. But this doesn’t preclude that the goal is to match
an object language sentence with a meta-language one that gives its meaning, in the
straightforward sense that is guaranteed when the used sentence is the same as, and
used in the same sense as, the object language sentence.
Davidson is clear that this is not a shift in the nature of the project, nor is it a
rejection of the goal of solving the original problem:
[h]
The problem, upon refinement, led to the view that an adequate theory of
meaning must characterize a predicate meeting certain conditions. It was in the
nature of a discovery that such a predicate would apply exactly to the true
sentences. (p. 24)
In summary: (i) Meanings, construed as entities of words or sentences are no help
in advancing the project of understanding how the meanings of sentences depend on
the meanings of words—that is, how we manage to be in a position to understand a
potential infinity of non-synonymous sentences on the basis of grasp of a finite
vocabulary of semantical primitives. (ii) The project of formulating an intensional
logic for handling ‘s means that p’, once we stop treating ‘that p’ as a referring term,
looks to encounter ‘‘problems as hard as, or perhaps identical with, the problems our
theory is out to solve’’ (p. 22). (iii) But the end result looks to be to match a sentence
s in our target language with a sentence ‘p’ in the meta-language the same in
meaning; and this goal, upon reflection, may be pursued without getting ‘‘enmeshed
in the intensional,’’ for the matching may be achieved if we are able to provide a
formally correct definition of a predicate ‘‘is T’’ that entails every sentence of the
form (T), where ‘p’ is replaced (to put it generally) by a sentence that translates s.
(iv) But this requires the definition meet Tarski’s Convention T (if the language is
non-context sensitive), and thus we discover a connection between our primary goal
and the definition of a Tarski-style truth predicate for a language. (v) This is not to
replace the original goal with another, or to eschew giving a compositional meaning
theory in favor of giving a truth theory, but to discover a way of getting at what we
wanted with a bit of indirection which turns out to be helpful.
8 Re-evaluating the key passage
It is in this context that we should understand Davidson when he says ‘‘the definition
works by giving necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of every sentence,
and to give truth conditions is a way of giving the meaning of a sentence. To give
123
264
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
the semantic concept of truth for a language is to know what it is for a sentence—
any sentence—to be true, and this amounts, in one good sense we can give to the
phrase, to understanding the language’’ (see the full passage [b] in §4). His idea is
not that truth conditions are meanings, nor is he reifying truth conditions, for this
expression appears only in the phrase ‘give the truth conditions’.10 For Davidson,
the locution ‘truth conditions’ is syncategorematic. His hope was that a theory, for a
context sensitive language, that matches object language sentences with metalanguage ones—the utterances of which are true or false together—would ipso facto
meet a suitable analog for Convention T, and it would do so in a way that reflected
the rules attaching to words governing their contributions to what sentences mean,
since what sentences mean determines under what conditions they are true.
When he says,
This at any rate is my excuse for a feature of the present discussion that is apt
to shock old hands; my freewheeling use of the word ‘meaning’, for what I call
a theory of meaning has after all turned out to make no use of meanings,
whether of sentences or of words.
his point is that pursuing the project of saying how what sentences mean depends on
what their words mean need not in the end invoke meanings as entities. Soames is
quite mistaken to conclude Davidson has thereby rejected the project of giving a
theory of meaning in favor of some distinct project. Rather, Davidson has merely
discovered a novel way to pursue it which dispenses with meanings as entities and
which does not use even ‘means’ in the theory itself (though we’ll explain presently
how to reintroduce it and how to clarify the manner in which the truth theory
functions in a meaning theory).11 Davidson means no more than this when he says,
Indeed, since a Tarski-type truth definition supplies all we have asked so far of
a theory of meaning, it is clear that such a theory falls comfortably within what
Quine terms the ‘theory of reference’ as distinguished from what he terms the
‘theory of meaning’.12
He is not in this passage embracing a theory of reference to the exclusion of a
compositional meaning theory; he is not replacing one project with another. Even if
he eschews meanings as entities in the theory of meaning, he does not discard the
concept of meaning as too obscure or confused for scientific work.13 Quine’s agenda
was never Davidson’s despite whatever inspiration he drew from Quine.
10
See Cummins (2002) for an example of an author who takes Davidson to be reifying truth conditions
and assigning them as meanings to sentences.
11
Church (1951, p. 102) seems to have had essentially this insight, as noted by Wallace (1978, p. 54).
12
Quine describes the contrast he has in mind as follows: ‘‘The main concepts in the theory of meaning,
apart from meaning itself, are synonymy (or sameness of meaning), significance (or possession of
meaning), and analyticity (or truth by virtue of meaning). Another is entailment, or analyticity of the
conditional. The main concepts in the theory of reference are naming, truth, denotation (or truth-of), and
extension. Another is the notion of values of variables’’ (Quine 1953, p. 130).
13
In this context we can also treat a passage in a later paper which seems to echo the theme here. In ‘‘In
Defense of Convention T,’’ Davidson says, ‘‘In the previous paragraph, the notion of meaning to which
appeal is made in the slogan ‘The meaning of a the sentence depends on the meanings of its parts’ is not,
of course, the notion that opposes meaning to reference, or a notion that assumes that meanings are
123
Truth and meaning redux
265
In this light, we can see clearly that Soames’s replacement interpretation is
mistaken. Davidson was doing something much more interesting than jettisoning the
project that his article starts out describing. He was offering a novel approach, one
reached by reflections which led him to conclude assigning entities to expressions
does not illuminate how we understand complexes on the basis of their parts, and by
noticing that in effect the goal was to arrive at a matching of mentioned object
language sentences with used (and so understood) meta-language sentences. It is
therefore a significant error to say the ‘‘grand Davidsonian-cum-Quinean theme
presupposed that truth and reference can be retained while meaning is rejected’’ and
then to go onto criticize Davidson on the grounds that ‘‘it is not clear that our
ordinary notions of truth and reference can be separated from our ordinary notion of
meaning’’ (p. 4).
Davidson exploits a truth theory for two purposes: first, to illuminate how the
meanings of complexes depend on the meanings of significant parts, reframed as the
project of illuminating how complexes are to be understood on the basis of
understanding their significant parts; second, to illuminate meaning by showing how
constraints on a truth theory stated using, ideally, non-semantic vocabulary suffice
for the theory to meet Contention T. We will return in §10 to the relation of these
projects to explaining knowledge of meaning in terms of truth conditions, after we
have looked in more detail at how the first of these two tasks can be achieved.
9 The role of a truth theory in a meaning theory
We divided Davidson’s project into two in the previous section. The first, providing
a compositional meaning theory, we shall call the initial project; the second,
providing a deeper understanding of meaning in general, we call the extended
project. We gain greater clarity into his project if we first describe how a truth
theory can be used to pursue the initial project. For this purpose, recall the example
of a reference theory S for fragment L. We observed that if we had certain
knowledge of S, i.e., that described in [KS], we would be in a position to interpret
every expression in L, and not merely to say what its referent is. One condition we
must know is that its axioms use meta-language expressions to give the referents of
primitive terms that are the same in meaning as object language expressions and that
those of its axioms which give recursively the referents of recursive devices of the
language do so using a meta-language expression in a sentence of the same form
Footnote 13 continued
entities’’ (1973a, pp. 70–71). He goes onto say, ‘‘The slogan reflects an important truth, one on which, I
suggest, a theory of truth confers a clear content. That it does so without introducing meanings as entities
is one of its rewarding qualities’’ (p. 71). There are two points here. First, the truth theory itself employs
only semantic concepts drawn from the theory of reference; second, it makes no use of assignments of
meanings as entities. This is not to disclaim the aim of giving the meaning of each sentence of the
language by way of identifying for it a theorem in which the truth conditions for it are given using a
sentence alike in meaning (that is required by Convention T!), or by doing so on the basis of axioms that
use expressions alike in meaning to those that give their truth, reference and satisfaction conditions (for
that is, after all, the idea about how it is to be done). It is only to take not of the fact that what the theory
shows it does not say.
123
266
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
which translates the recursive device in the object language. If we knew this, we
would be in a position to understand complex expressions in the fragment on the
basis of understanding their significant parts, and we would also be in a position to
state explicitly the meaning of each expression of the object language. What puts us
in this position is not knowledge of what S states, but rather knowledge about it.
If we identify the meaning theory with what we know that enables us to
understand any expression of the object language, then the reference theory is not a
meaning theory. The meaning theory is, rather, what we have to know about the
reference theory to position ourselves to understand complex expressions on the
basis of their parts. Note that the theory does not explain what primitive expressions
mean, though that information can be gleaned from its axioms, given that we know
they satisfy Convention A. But, as Davidson remarks, ‘‘the task was to give the
meaning of all expressions in a certain infinite set on the basis of the meaning of the
parts; it was not in the bargain also to give the meanings of the atomic parts’’ (p. 18).
This model for a compositional meaning theory carries over more or less directly
to sentential meaning, replacing reference with truth. We will use a language
without context sensitive features and quantifiers, though the lessons generalize to
more complex languages in a relatively straightforward way. We give a theory T
(‘refers to’ and ‘is true’ are to be understood as restricted to the object language),
and assume rules of formation given in the natural way.
[T]
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
‘Claudine’ refers to Claudine.
‘Robert’ refers to Robert.
For any name N, Na ‘dort’ is true iff what N refers to is sleeping.
a
For any names N1, N2, Na
1 ‘aime’ N2 is true iff what N1 refers to loves what N2
refers to.
For any sentence S, ‘Ce n’est pas le cas que’a S is true iff it is not the case that S
is true.
a
For any sentences S1, S2, Sa
1 ‘et’ S2 is true iff S1 is true and S2 is true.
‘N’ ranges over names and ‘S’, ‘S1’ and ‘S2’ over sentences of the object
language. To see how the meanings of the complexes depend on those of the parts
and to interpret any sentence of the language, we need to know about T only the
following:
(i)
(ii)
What the axioms are, as stated in (1)–(6).
What each axiom states and of each that it states what it does.14
14
We assume a grammar for the truth theory as a background for understanding the rules of inferences
that sorts terms into categories such as noun phrase, verb phrase, determiner, verb, noun, adverb,
adjective, connective, etc. As noted in connection with theory S, this is needed if we are to put the
information in (i) and (ii) together so as to come to understand the language of the truth theory, which is
essential to using it to interpret object language sentences. It should be noted in connection with this that
the object is to gain insight into the rules that attach to expressions in the object language which govern
how they contributed to fixing the truth conditions of object language sentences by way of their meaning.
It no part of this that we represent what the theorist knows as a model of how the speaker’s competence
with respect to the rules is realized, and it could not be, given that we presuppose the speaker has a
language as a condition on stating what he could know. We thank Miguel Hoeltje for helpful discussion in
connection with these issues.
123
Truth and meaning redux
(iii)
(iv)
(v)
267
That in each reference axiom the name used on the right of ‘refers to’
translates the name mentioned on the left.
That in each predicate axiom the predicate used in the meta-language in
giving truth conditions for the object language sentence translates the object
language predicate.
That in each recursive axiom the logical connective used in the metalanguage to give the truth conditions for the object language sentence
translates the logical connective in the object language.
Given (iii)–(v), it is clear that, provided an adequate logic, T has as theorems all
sentences of the form,
(T) s is true iff p,
where s is replaced by a structural description of an object language sentence and
‘p’ is replaced by a meta-language sentence that translates s. We also need a way of
identifying just those theorems which draw only on the content of the axioms. We
call any proof procedure which draws only the content of the axioms and whose last
line is of form (T) and in which no semantic vocabulary of the meta-language
remains (i.e., ‘is true’) a canonical proof procedure. As rules of inference, we allow:
Universal Instantiation (UI): from a universally quantified sentence any instance
may be inferred.
Substitution (S): from any sentences of the form ‘t refers to y’ and any sentence of
the form S(what t refers to in L), S(y) may be inferred.
Replacement (R): for any sentences x, y, S(x), S(y) may be inferred from
x a ‘iff’a y and S(x).
Replacement is limited; the aim is to so restrict the rules that any proof of a
sentence of form (T) without semantic vocabulary on its right hand side is a
canonical proof. Its last sentence we call a canonical theorem. Since in a canonical
theorem the sentence on the right of ‘iff’ translates the one mentioned on the left, we
can validly infer the sentence we get from replacing ‘is true iff’ with ‘means that’
(Davidson 1970, p. 60). We will call this inference rule Transference.
Transference (T): from any canonical theorem, ‘s is true iff p’, ‘s means that p’
may be inferred.
In addition to (i)–(v), we need to know:
(vi)
(vii)
The rules of inference UI, S, R, and T
That any proof of a sentence of form ‘s is true iff p’ without semantic
vocabulary on the right hand side from the axioms on the basis of the rules UI,
S, and R is a canonical proof, and, hence, the sentence is a canonical theorem.
This puts us in a position to infer for each sentence of the object language a metalanguage sentence that explicitly states what the object language sentence means, on
the basis of a proof that traces out, at each step, the contribution of each object
language expression to fixing the truth conditions of the sentence to which it
contributes, on the basis of reference or truth conditions given using a term the same
123
268
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
in meaning with it. We can thus see what the contribution is of each semantical
primitive to the interpretive truth conditions of the sentences in which it occurs on
the basis of what it means.
Any theory for a language like this that satisfies conditions (iii)–(v) satisfies
Convention A, which requires that the axioms for primitive expressions meet an
analog of Convention T, namely, that they provide reference and truth conditions
(and satisfaction conditions when we move to a language with quantifiers) using
terms in the meta-language that translate the object language terms for which they
are used to give reference and truth (and satisfaction) conditions. Convention A is a
condition on a truth theory that, relative to an adequate logic, ensures it satisfies
Convention T. Call any truth theory that meets Convention A interpretive.
Let us take stock. We have shown how a truth theory may be exploited in pursuit
of the goals of a compositional meaning theory. However, we have not claimed the
truth theory is a compositional meaning theory. That would be a mistake. Rather, we
have claimed that having certain information about a truth theory for a language
positions us to interpret each object language sentence and to see, through a
canonical proof of a canonical theorem, how its parts contribute in virtue of their
meaning to fixing the truth conditions of the object language sentence in a way that
provides its interpretation.15
10 The role of empirical constraints
Davidson never cleanly separated the initial from the extended project. He aimed to
illuminate how understanding complexes depends on understanding their parts at
the same time that he illuminated meaning generally. To this end, he treated the
truth theory as empirical. His goal was to show what it would take to confirm a truth
theory for a language which met a suitable analog of Convention T. In this way, the
theory and its concepts are related to evidence that does not presuppose their
application. This illuminates theoretical concepts by showing how they organize
data on the basis of which they are applied.
Initially, Davidson thought that the mere extensional adequacy of a truth theory
would suffice, if the targets were natural languages with context sensitive elements
(indexicals, demonstratives, tense, and the like). His hope was that bi-conditionals
such as (S),
(S) ‘Snow is white’ is true iff grass is green,
15
Interestingly, if we identify a meaning theory with what we must know, then we need not know the
truth theory: we need to know what it is and what its axioms mean, but knowledge that its axioms are true
is not part of what we must know to do the work that needs to be done. This is important because it might
enable us to apply this technique to a language with vague terms and semantically defective terms without
worrying about the truth theory not being true. At the same time, though, relative to the knowledge that
the terms in the object language are not semantically defective, we can infer that the truth theory is true,
and so, relative to this additional bit of knowledge, come to know what the truth theory states. See Lepore
and Ludwig (2005, Ch. 10).
123
Truth and meaning redux
269
would be eliminated, given the need to secure the right truth conditions for utterances
of ‘This is snow’, ‘This is grass’, ‘This is green’, ‘This is white’, etc.16 Davidson’s
hope was that, for natural languages, satisfying extensional adequacy alone would
suffice for the theory to meet Convention T (more properly, Convention A). But, while
context sensitivity helps, extensional adequacy is not enough; we can always add to the
satisfaction conditions for a predicate axiom a condition that does not affect truth, but
does affect meaning. Extensional adequacy would not distinguish between (i) and (ii):
(i).
(ii).
Any function f satisfies ‘x is red’ iff f(‘x’) is red.
Any function f satisfies ‘x is red’ iff f(‘x’) is red and 2 ? 2 = 4.
The latter generates non-interpretive canonical theorems.
Davidson acknowledged the problem and tried to avoid it by insisting on
confirmability by the Radical Interpreter. His hope was that any truth theory
confirmable from the standpoint of a Radical Interpreter would satisfy Convention T.
It is noteworthy that Davidson’s shift shows rather convincingly that his goal was
not, contra Soames, to replace a meaning theory with a truth theory. For the
objection Davidson is responding to is that truth is insufficient to secure that the
theory meets (a suitable analog of) Convention T. If he were pursuing a replacement
strategy, this objection would have provided no reason to change course.
For present purposes, it doesn’t matter whether Davidson’s new suggestion is
adequate.17 Our current concern is to defend a semantic program that sees a truth
theory as providing a vehicle for a compositional meaning theory. It is this more
limited project Soames is attacking. To meet his attack, it suffices to show how a
truth theory can be used in pursuit of a compositional meaning theory.
11 Soames’s criticisms
Soames says (p. 1) that what Davidson aims to do is
…to explain knowledge of meaning in terms of knowledge of truth conditions
[and that f]or Davidsonians, these attempts take the form of rationales for
treating theories of truth, constructed along Tarskian lines, as empirical
theories of meaning.
What would it be to explain ‘‘knowledge of meaning’’? Whose knowledge? What
kind? It is most natural to interpret the project so described as explaining the
knowledge of speakers of a language. But, then, Soames’s suggestion would seem to
be that Davidson was proposing speakers know their languages by way of knowing
a truth theory—how else to interpret ‘‘in terms of knowledge of truth conditions,’’
16
Soames declares (p. 6) that Davidson thought ‘‘truth theories that are both true and compositional will
end up deriving only those statements [‘S’ is true iff P]’’ in which what replaces ‘P’ translates ‘S’. Again,
he is mistaken. Davidson’s idea was that context sensitive elements in natural languages would play a
crucial role. As he himself notes (Footnote 10 on p. 26 of Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation;
Davidson 2001), ‘‘[c]ritics have often failed to notice the essential proviso mentioned in this paragraph.
The point is that (S) could not belong to any reasonably simple theory that also gave the right truth
conditions for ‘That is snow’ and ‘This is white’. (See the discussion of indexical expressions below).’’
17
We are convinced it is not. See Lepore and Ludwig (2005, Ch. 11).
123
270
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
which would seem to be propositional knowledge. Davidson, however, explicitly
denies this.18 He is not offering a psychological theory about the mechanism by
which speakers understand. He has no commitment about whether ‘‘knowledge of
meaning’’ is explicable in terms of propositional knowledge.
His goal is, rather, to describe a general framework for providing a compositional
meaning theory which would enables us to show how what complexes mean
depends on what their significant parts mean and their mode of combination, and,
thereby, to show how to illuminate the structure of a complex practical ability.
We start with semantical primitives; these are expressions the understanding of
which is not derived from an understanding of their components. A speaker’s
understanding of each will involve a disposition to use it in accordance with a
semantical category into which it falls and the specific meaning it has within that
category that sets it apart from other items in the same category. Grasp of its category
amounts to knowing how it is to be combined with other terms given their categories
and how being so combined helps determine what the complexes it helps to form
mean. This does not entail propositional knowledge of rules. Rather, we know how to
put terms together to mean various things and how to interpret the results of putting
them together in appropriate ways. The upshot involves propositional knowledge,
but of what utterances mean and the conditions under which they are true.
The compositional meaning theory concerns knowledge of meaning only in the
sense that it aims to capture the structure of the language of which speakers have
knowledge—in the sense of being competent speakers of it. It shows us something
about what it is that speakers have knowledge of, and so something about what the
structure of their dispositions with respect to words in it have to be.19 No further
account is on offer of what semantic competence consists in or how it is realized.20
18
In ‘‘Radical Interpretation’’ (Davidson 1973b, p. 25), Davidson says, in motivation for asking the question
‘‘What could we know that would enable us to understand any potential utterance of a speaker?’’, that ‘‘… it is
not altogether obvious that there is anything we actually know which plays an essential role in interpretation.’’ In
‘‘A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs’’ (Davidson 1986, p. 438), he says, ‘‘To say that an explicit theory for
interpreting a speaker is a model of the interpreter’s linguistic competence is not to suggest that the interpreter
knows any such theory…They are rather claims about what must be said to give a satisfactory description of the
competence of the interpreter.’’ In ‘‘The Structure and Content of Truth’’ he says that the aim of the theory is,
inter alia, to describe a certain complex ability: ‘‘it at once describes the linguistic abilities and practices of the
speaker and gives the substance of what a knowledgeable interpreter knows which enables him to grasp the
meaning of the speaker’s utterances. This is not to say that either speaker or interpreter is aware of or has
propositional knowledge of the contents of such a theory’’ (Davidson 1990, pp. 311–312). In ‘‘The Social
Aspect of Language’’ he says, ‘‘let me say (not for the first time): I do not think we normally understand what
others say by consciously reflecting on the question what they mean, by appealing to some theory of
interpretation, or by summoning up what we take to be the relevant evidence’’ (Davidson 1994, p. 3).
19
By ‘the structure of their dispositions’ we mean no more than ‘what the rules are with respect to the
use of the words which the dispositions express’.
20
This serves as a response to another objection we have heard: that the account of how to provide a
compositional meaning theory would mean that a child learning its first language would have to have the
concept of truth, which is implausible. This would be so only if we were making the claim that the way the
competence that the theory represents is realized in speakers is by way of their having propositional knowledge
of the theory itself. But we have no such commitment, and it cannot be taken to be a general commitment of
giving a compositional meaning theory because every compositional meaning theory that aims at an explicit
statement of the meaning of every sentence will deploy concepts which a child learning a first language will not
plausibly have, such as the concept of meaning itself.
123
Truth and meaning redux
271
No explanation is being offered of how speakers learn the languages they speak, or
of why they speak the languages they do. An analogy: if you describe the rules of
chess, you say what it is that someone who knows how to play chess has to know, in
the sense of knowing what to do in playing. You don’t explain how he knows it, or
what his knowledge consists in, or how or why he learned chess.
Explaining knowledge of meaning, in any sense other than the rather attenuated
sense of describing the structure of what is known, is no part of Davidson’s project.
So it could not have been his aim to explain knowledge of meaning in terms of
knowledge of truth conditions. But suppose it were. Then how would treating
theories of truth as empirical theories of meaning have helped to explain knowledge
of meaning in terms of knowledge of truth conditions? It is not obvious. For to treat
a theory of truth as an empirical theory of meaning does not entail that knowledge of
meaning is to be explained in terms of knowledge of truth conditions. And showing
that a theory of truth can be empirically confirmed and used as a theory of meaning
would not show that speakers of the language possess knowledge of a truth theory.
There is some reason to believe Soames does not intend ‘explaining knowledge
of meaning’ to be about explaining speaker competence in terms of knowledge of a
truth theory, for he treats the psychologizing of Davidson’s program as a last gasp
defense of the justificatory project. An alternative, less natural reading of
‘explaining knowledge of meaning’ is as the project of explaining what knowledge
of truth conditions would suffice for knowledge of meanings. This is closer to what
Davidson had in mind, but, as we hope has now become clear, it was not his
(considered) view that knowledge of what a truth theory states ipso facto suffices for
knowledge of meaning, even for a theorist.21 It is rather knowledge of, and about, a
truth theory that puts us (theorists who know it) in a position to interpret its subject.
21
Soames says, ‘‘Davidson originally held that a truth theory for L qualifies as a theory of meaning, if
knowledge of what it states is sufficient for understanding L’’ (2008, p. 5). It is fair to call a body of knowledge
sufficient to interpret any sentence of a language on the basis of rules governing its semantical primitives a
meaning theory for the language, and it is fair to say this is what Davidson sought in an account of how the
meanings of sentences depend on the meanings of their contained words. It would then follow that if knowledge
of what a truth theory states sufficed to understand the language for which it was a theory, then it would be a
meaning theory. This conditional thesis is trivial and nonsubstantive, and there is no reason to think Davidson
would not have been happy to endorse it. But since it is trivial and nonsubstantive, it is also not a thesis that he
would have had to give up. The substantive question is what knowledge one could have (propositional
knowledge) that would suffice to interpret a speaker’s language. And the exegetical question about ‘‘Truth and
Meaning’’ is what Davidson’s position on that was. In ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’ he does speak as if the meaning
theory is the truth theory. But even there it seems clear he was thinking that the required knowledge went well
beyond what was stated by the truth theory, for he offers an argument to show that a true truth theory would meet
an appropriate analog of Convention T for a context sensitive language because it would track correctly the use
(actual and potential) of predicative terms in combination with demonstratives. Isn’t it transparent that that is
something one would have to know in order to use the truth theory for interpretation? In a retrospective remark
in ‘‘Reply to Foster’’ Davidson says, ‘‘That empirical restrictions must be added to the formal restrictions if
acceptable theories of truth are to include only those that would serve for interpretation was clear to me even
when I wrote ‘Truth and Meaning’. My mistake was not, as Foster seems to suggest, to suppose that any theory
that correctly gave truth conditions would serve for interpretation; my mistake was to overlook the fact that
someone might know a sufficiently unique theory without knowing that it was sufficiently unique. The
distinction was easy for me to neglect because I imagined the theory to be known by someone who had
constructed it from the evidence, and such a person could not fail to realize that his theory satisfied the
constraints’’ (Davidson 1976, p. 173). If we take Davidson at his word (why wouldn’t we?), he misexpresses his
underlying thought in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ when he speaks as if the truth theory were a meaning theory itself.
123
272
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
Soames’s final criticism is lodged after he reviews various things we have to
know about a truth theory to use it to interpret another. It follows his observation
that a theory with a reasonably robust logic will have T-theorems which are not
interpretive.
The natural response is to add a definition of canonical theorem to truth
theories, picking out, for each S, a unique T-theorem as translational.
However, it is doubtful that this would provide the needed justification. Once
information about canonicality is added, the only role played by knowledge of
the canonical truth theorem (CTT) is that of allowing one to identify a claim in
which S is paired with a certain content, which is then stipulated to be the
content expressed by a translation. Neither the truth of CTT, nor the fact that it
states the truth conditions of S, plays any role in interpreting S. All it does is to
supply a translational pairing, which could be supplied just as well in other
ways. One could get the same interpretive results by replacing the truth
predicate in a translational truth theory with any arbitrary predicate F
whatsoever. Whether or not the resulting theory is true makes no difference.
To interpret S, all one needs to know, of the canonical F-theorem, is that it
links S with the content expressed by a translation of S. No one would
conclude from this that translational F-theories count as theories of meaning.
Why, then, suppose that translational truth theories do? So far, we have been
given no answer.
The collapse of this justificatory attempt should not be lamented. Prompted by
Foster’s objection into invoking a notion of paraphrase beyond anything in the
truth theories themselves, we face the dilemma of appealing to a notion strong
enough to overcome the objection, at the cost of robbing truth and reference of
their cherished roles in explicating meanings, or of not overcoming the
objection at all. (p. 7)
Soames’s objection rests on the assumptions that Davidson, as well as
Davidsonians, are committed to saying the truth theory itself is a meaning theory
and that truth and reference are supposed to explicate meaning. We hope it is
transparent to you by now that neither assumption is correct.
The goal is to exploit a truth theory to do the work of a meaning theory. We start
with axioms for primitive expressions and arrive at theorems which match object
language sentences with meta-language sentences that in some sense give the their
meanings. This is exactly what Soames describes the theory as doing.
Although in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ it may have looked as if Davidson hoped
extensional adequacy would suffice for a truth theory for a natural language to
satisfy an appropriate analog of Convention T, so that we would show important
connections between truth and meaning, his later work clearly did not seek to do so
but rather to illuminate meaning by showing how to confirm an interpretive truth
theory for a speaker from evidence that presupposes neither knowledge of meanings
nor knowledge of contents of the speaker’s propositional attitudes. So the
‘‘cherished goal’’ was not central to the project as a whole and was a feature
perhaps only of its initial phase. It is not something Davidson was committed to for
123
Truth and meaning redux
273
more than a brief period, and it certainly is not something contemporary
Davidsonians need be committed to in pursuing truth-theoretic semantics.
In response to Soames’s claim that all the theory does is match object language
sentences with meta-language sentences that translate them, we agree that it does
that, but that is not all it does. Soames says the theory need not be true to issue in
theorems which match object language sentences with meta-language sentences that
translate them. This too is correct, as we noted above. Any predicate could play the
role. However, as Davidson observed, if the theory is true, the predicate has the
extension of the truth predicate. And if the predicate is the truth predicate and the
axioms meet Convention A and the primitive expressions are not semantically
defective, then theory is true, and we can retrieve more information from the theory
than what is expressed in its theorems of form:
s means that p.
Proofs of the canonical theorems exhibit how parts of sentences, in virtue of their
meanings, contribute to fixing the truth conditions of these sentences, by way of
using terms the same in meaning. We see exhibited in the proof the semantic
structure of the sentence and how it fixes truth conditions. This is not what the proof
says, but it can be culled from the proof. Someone in possession of such a theory
and appropriate knowledge of it is in a position to understand the compositional
structure of the language. That is more than being able to pair object language
sentences with meta-language ones that translate them. So, this objection misses its
target, and it misses where some of the real utility of a truth theory lies in showing
us how languages work.22
12 Soames’s alternative approach
Soames offers an alternative approach to semantics; we end with a few critical
remarks about it. His proposal has two parts. First, we should reintroduce meanings
as entities. He has in mind a Russellian picture on which we have particulars and
universals assigned to words as appropriate. Obama is assigned to ‘Obama’, being
red to ‘is red’; and so on. He then imagines a theory that generates appropriate
assignments of complexes of these to complex expressions. This is the picture
Davidson faulted in the first pages of ‘‘Truth and Meaning.’’ Soames admits there
are problems. Take (i)–(ii).
(i)
(ii)
a is larger than b
ha, b, is larger thani
(ii) is an object and seems not to be intrinsically representational. How can it be the
meaning of (i)? (i) has truth conditions, (ii) does not. Soames rejects the proposal
22
Davidson makes this point in explaining why a theory of truth consisting just of the infinite class of (T)
biconditionals in which the right hand side translates the sentence mentioned on the left is inadequate:
‘‘Such a theory would yield no insight into the structure of language and would thus provide no hint of an
answer to the question how the meaning of a sentence depends on its composition’’ (Davidson 1970,
p. 56).
123
274
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
that it is a sui generis fact about the proposition.23 His idea is that we interpret the
relation R in which a, b, and is larger than stand in (ii) as representing that a is
larger than b (or more properly: the fact that a, b and is larger than stand in the
relation R represents that a is larger than b). It is not that their standing in the
relations they stand in intrinsically represents that a is larger than b; it is rather that
we treat it as representing that. Soames says: ‘‘The answer rests not on anything
intrinsic to R but on the interpretation placed on R by the way that we use it’’
(Soames 2008, p. 18). What this comes down to is that we treat that fact that a, b,
and is larger than stand in the relations they do in (ii) as meaning that a is larger
than b.
Suppose a theorem of our theory assigned to (i) the meaning (ii).
The meaning of ‘a is larger than b’ in L is ha, b, is larger thani
To enable us to understand the object language sentence, we need to assume that
what we treat the proposition as representing is what the sentence represents.
Suppose we have so constructed our theory and notation for propositions that we
know that among its theorems are all sentences of the form ‘The meaning of s in L is
p’ where ‘s’ is replaced by a structural description of an object language sentence
and ‘p’ is replaced by a structure description of a proposition that (relative to our
conventions) represents what s does. Suppose further we have a formal way of
identifying theorems in the relevant class, and that we have identified the theorem
above as one of the relevant class. Then we have a rule for reading off from the
propositional notation in the metalanguage what the proposition represents—by way
of being able to generate from the notation for the proposition a sentence in the
metalanguage that represents what it does. In the present case, we know that the fact
that a, b, and is larger than stand in the relations they do in ha, b, is larger thani
means that a is larger than b (i.e. represents what ‘a is larger than b’ represents). We
can therefore infer that:
‘a is larger than b’ means that a is larger than b.
What essential work does assigning the proposition to the sentence do? None
whatsoever! It turns out merely to be another way of matching an object language
sentence with a meta-language sentence that translates it. For in effect all we have
done is to associate with our object language sentence an expression, ‘ha, b, is larger
thani’, which we treat as coding for a metalanguage sentence we understand that,
relative to an additional body of knowledge, we know to translate the object
language sentence. For all the work that it does, the proposition might just as well
drop out of the picture altogether. In what way, then, is this supposed to constitute
an advance over Davidsonian semantics? We submit it has no advantage and that
23
Soames says, ‘‘One could … take propositions to be inherently and intrinsically representational, and
so sui generis. However, this is a council of despair. Davidson would not accept such obscuritanism, and
we should not either. If we posit structured propositions as meanings of sentences, we ought to explain
what they are, and how they are able to play the roles we assign to them’’ (Soames 2008, p. 17).
123
Truth and meaning redux
275
except insofar as we can extract out of the theory an interpretive truth theory, it
carries less information.24
13 Summary and conclusion
In conclusion:
(1)
(2)
(3)
Soames gets off on the wrong foot by taking Davidson’s project to be that of
explaining knowledge of meaning when in fact it is the project of explaining
meaning.
He compounds this mistake by supposing both Davidson and Davidsonians are
committed to claiming a truth theory is a meaning theory. This is a view
Davidson might have held in ‘‘Truth and Meaning,’’ though even there a
relatively close reading uncovers how much more he helps himself to than
what is stated by the truth theory. In any case, it need be no part of truththeoretic semantics to claim a truth theory, even one meeting various
constraints, is ipso facto a meaning theory. More pertinently, Davidson
explicitly revised his views between the publication of ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’
in 1967 and ‘‘Radical Interpretation’’ in 1973—thirty-seven years ago. In
‘‘Reply to Foster,’’ he explicitly writes, ‘‘A theory of truth, no matter how well
selected, is not a theory of meaning’’ (p. 179).25
The role of a truth theory vis-à-vis a compositional meaning theory is clarified
once we separate the initial project from the extended one of providing a
deeper illumination of meaning by showing how a theory sufficient to interpret
a speaker may be confirmed from an evidential base that excludes intensional
and intentional notions. The theory does its job if it meets an analog of
Convention T for its axioms; Convention A, as we have dubbed it, requires
meta-language expressions which translate object language ones in their
reference and satisfaction conditions. Meeting Convention A suffices to meet
Convention T, though not vice versa. It is a stronger requirement. If a theory
meets Convention A, we can cull from its axioms what the object language
expressions mean. We can track their contributions to fixing truth conditions of
object language sentences using a sentence that means the same as the object
language sentence through a canonical proof of the canonical theorem for the
sentence (with straightforward modifications for context sensitive languages).
24
For all we have said, natural language may involve terms that (putatively) refer to or denote
propositions (just as it may contain terms that (putatively) refer to or denote unicorns). In giving the
semantics, then, we may need terms in the metalanguage that correspond to those object language terms.
Our point is that the machinery of the compositional meaning theory need not itself introduce such terms
or endorse the existence of any entities of that type.
25
Davidson says, ‘‘nothing strictly constitutes a theory of meaning,’’ because the truth theory is not a
theory of meaning and the ‘‘statement that a translational theory entails certain facts is not, because of the
irreducible indexical elements in the sentences that express it, a theory in the formal sense’’ (Davidson
1976, p. 179). Davidson says this because of his paratactic analysis of ‘that’-clauses; if we do not follow
him, we need not shy from saying there is something that constitutes the meaning theory.
123
276
E. Lepore, K. Ludwig
(4)
The project of truth-theoretic semantics construed as providing compositional
meaning theories for natural languages is not committed to explaining
meaning in terms of concepts drawn from the theory of reference.
The project of truth-theoretic semantics is not committed to the success of
Davidson’s extended project; in particular, it is not committed to the success of
the project of Radical Interpretation.
Soames’s criticisms of truth-theoretic semantics evaporate once we appreciate
it is not committed to the theses he criticizes: namely, that the truth theory as
such is a meaning theory and that it seeks to explain meaning in terms of truth
and reference.
Truth-theoretic semantics is much more informative than a recursive
translation theory, for it informs us about how truth conditions are fixed by
the contributions of the components of sentences and their mode of
combination.
Soames’s suggestion for an alternative semantics, introducing entities to serve
as meanings, only manages to match object language sentences with codes for
meta-language sentences that translate them, and so fares no better than truththeoretic semantics, and unless it includes all the information contained in a
interpretive truth theory, it carries even less information.
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
Acknowledgements We would like to thank John Burgess, Gil Harman, and Miguel Hoeltje for
discussion and comments that have led to improvements in this paper.
References
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1981). Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations. Midwest Studies in
Philosophy, 6, 387–403.
Burge, T. (1992). Philosophy of language and mind: 1950–1990. The Philosophical Review, 101(1), 3–51.
Chihara, C. S. (1975). Davidson’s extensional theory of meaning. Philosophical Studies, 28, 1–15.
Church, A. (1951). The need for abstract entities in semantic analysis. In Proceedings of the American
Academy of Arts and Letters (p. 80).
Cummins, R. (2002). Truth and meaning. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & D. Shier (Eds.), Meaning
and truth: Investigations in philosophical semantics. New York: Seven Bridges Press.
Davidson, D. (1966). Theories of meaning and learnable languages. In Y. Bar-Hillel (Ed.), Proceedings of
the 1964 international congress for logic, methodology and philosophy of science. Amsterdam:
North Holland Publishing Co.
Davidson, D. (1967). Truth and meaning. Synthese, 17, 304–323.
Davidson, D. (1970). Semantics for natural languages. In Linguaggi nella Societa e nella Tecnica. Milan:
Comunita.
Davidson, D. (1973a). In defence of Convention T. In H. Leblanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax and modality.
Dordrecht: North-Holland Publishing Company.
Davidson, D. (1973b). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27, 314–328.
Davidson, D. (1976). Reply to Foster. In G. Evans & J. McDowell (Eds.), Truth and meaning: Essays in
semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation:
Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell.
Davidson, D. (1990). The structure and content of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(6), 279–328.
Davidson, D. (1994). The social aspect of language. In B. McGuinness & G. Oliveri (Eds.), The
philosophy of Michael Dummett. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
123
Truth and meaning redux
277
Davidson, D. (2001). Inquiries into truth and interpretation (2nd ed.). New York: Clarendon Press.
Original edition, 1984.
Glock, H.-J. (2003). Quine and Davidson on language, thought, and reality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Horwich, P. (2005). Reflections on meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Katz, J. (1982). Common sense in semantics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23(2), 174–218.
Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2005). Donald Davidson: Truth, meaning, language and reality. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1953). Notes on the theory of reference. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Soames, S. (1992). Truth, meaning, and understanding. Philosophical Studies, 65(1–2), 17–35.
Soames, S. (2008). Truth and meaning: In perspective. Truth and Its Deformities: Midwest Studies in
Philosophy, 32, 1–19.
Stich, S. (1976). Davidson’s semantic program. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6, 201–227.
Tarski, A. (1983). The concept of truth in formalized languages. In Logic, semantics, metamathematics.
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Original edition, 1934.
Wallace, J. (1978). Logical form, meaning, translation. In M. Guenthener-Reutter (Ed.), Meaning and
translation. London: Duckworth.
Wittgenstein, L. (1961). In D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness (Eds.), Tractatus logico-philosophicus.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
123