Original article
Integrity: is it still relevant to modern healthcare?
nup_486 107..118
Stephen Tyreman PhD, MA, DO
Dean of Osteopathic Education Development at the British School of Osteopathy (BSO), London, and Professor of Osteopathy and Philosophy, University of
Bedfordshire, Bedfordshire, UK
Abstract
Personal integrity is often seen as a core value for delivering ethical
healthcare.This paper will explore what this might mean and particularly
what place integrity has in a multi-professional healthcare system. Two
opposing arguments can be made: the first is that the multi-professional
nature of modern healthcare means that personal integrity is at best a
futile luxury and at worst, an obstacle to delivering affordable highquality care to large populations. The converse is that without personal
integrity healthcare loses its humanity and becomes mere biological and
social engineering. Part of the analysis rests on whether integrity is
primarily a personally held moral framework or whether it is a social
concept. Chester Calhoun’s analysis, in which she identifies the
integrated-self, personal identity, and (morally) clean-hands as three
pictures of integrity, is used as the basis for suggesting that integrity is a
rich and complex social virtue through which the individual is able to
demonstrate their relationship with the values and mores of the communities of which they are members. In addition, I will argue that integrity is not a value itself, but is a framework through which one or more
sets of those values that characterize the communities of which the
person is a part, can be expressed. Because a person may belong to many
communities – nation, gender, religion, family, profession, trade, sport,
etc. – each individual has their own unique meta-set of values that
informs their personal sense of integrity. However, in specific circumstances, conflicts may arise between this personal global sense and the
set of values associated with one community.
Keywords: integrity, value, Calhoun, social values, professional values,
personal values, authenticity, professional identity.
Correspondence: Professor Stephen Tyreman, Dean of Osteopathic Education Development at the British School of Osteopathy, 275 Borough High Street, London SE1 1JE, UK.Tel.: +44
207 407 0222; fax: +44 207 089 5300; e-mail:
[email protected]
Introduction
Integrity, both personal and professional, is regarded
as a precondition for individuals working autonomously with vulnerable patients. In addition to
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
107
108
Stephen Tyreman
ensuring ethical care, it also underpins the notion of
healthcare as a vocation rather than merely a ‘job’.
The person with integrity is assumed to be virtuous
with respect to the work they do, the regard they have
for patients under their care and in ensuring that they
provide the highest quality care. It might therefore
seem unnecessary and churlish to question whether it
still has a place in modern healthcare and, if it does,
whether it should be revisited and reviewed. But
there are good reasons for suggesting that this should
be done.
In the UK, a number of high-profile cases in health
and social work – such as that of Harold Shipman,
who murdered more than 200 elderly patients over
several years while working as a general practitioner –
shook public faith in health professionals always to
act with integrity in the best interests of their patients,
as well as confidence in the professions to monitor the
behaviour of their members. It raised the question of
whether people in need of healthcare are best served
by relying on the integrity of individual practitioners
or by introducing more rigorous codes of practice,
protocols and guidelines? The adoption of more procedures is rapidly becoming the norm; trust in professional integrity appears to be reducing. Writing and
policing policies to ensure ethical behaviour may be
replacing the individual’s integrity in acting ethically,
where integrity performs the work of personal motivation, or ‘conscience’, in ensuring good behaviour.
Underlying this development is the (perhaps naïve)
belief that professional values assimilated during
training, plus the individual’s original altruistic
motives for joining a healthcare profession, provide
practitioners with a moral framework that forms the
basis for acting with integrity throughout their
professional life.
What kinds of behaviours demonstrate integrity?
The nurse who refuses to clean up a soiled patient
because they find it unpleasant, or because there is a
risk of infection, is clearly not acting out of integrity.
In fact, integrity explicitly seems to exclude acts of
self-interest. But where should the line be drawn
between doing something that may be morally objectionable, such as assisting euthanasia or giving priority to wealthy patients, and doing something that one
believes to be futile or unnecessary such as collecting
data to complete government statistics, or persuading
(perhaps with coercion) patients to participate in
screening programmes or to take medication to
reduce the risk of cardiovascular problems when the
person has no illness and believes themselves to be
healthy?
A further reason for revisiting integrity concerns
the changing nature of Western healthcare. Modern
healthcare has become heavily reliant on multiprofessional and cross-disciplinary work. The roles of
individuals acting professionally is very different
today from how it was three or four decades ago.
Even in primary care, it is rarely one individual who
has sole responsibility for a patient; practice nurses,
pharmacists, physiotherapists, and so on, work with
doctors in a team to provide effective care. So is there
still a place for the individual to demonstrate integrity
or is it inevitable that healthcare behaviour should be
codified and good practice only defined in terms of
bureaucratic standards?
There are two issues here: the first concerns integrity itself; what it is and what work it performs in
healthcare. This is the aspect I will focus on in this
paper. The second issue is whether the work that
integrity is assumed to perform – ensuring safe, effective, and ethical care for patients – is best achieved
through integrity, or some other means such as rigorous enforcement of codes of practice.
Models of integrity
Integrity only raises its head when there is conflict.
This may be with another person, with ‘the system’, or
when professional values conflict with personal ones,
for example, in the medicalization of abortion. At
other times healthcare practitioners perform their
duties ethically, effectively and to the best of their
ability without recourse to notions of integrity, which
are implicit and assumed.
If this is the case, what is entailed when integrity is
an issue, when disobeying an order or performing an
act contrary to normal expectations is justified by the
claim that the person ‘acted with integrity’, meaning
that what they did was morally good; and specifically,
what does it mean in the context of healthcare? If it is
assumed that the good of patients is the first priority,
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
Integrity in Healthcare
how can two people disagree over the right action to
take, yet both claim to be acting ‘with integrity’, that
is, both be acting for the good of patients? For
example, a consultant and a manager may clash over
a decision to close an operating theatre; the former
because closing the theatre will lead to longer waiting
times and the other because the money could be
better used for more urgent needs, or to provide care
for more people. In pursuing their causes they may
support opposing actions with regard to going to the
press, say, in order to achieve what they both see as
good actions. In justification, both may appeal to professional and/or personal integrity. This goes beyond
merely doing one’s job or carrying out instructions; it
becomes an action that is felt to be justified at a personal and professional level. This tension has, in part,
been put down to a clash between deontological and
utilitarian ethical principles; the good of the individual versus the good of society, an issue that I will
return to later.
This raises four important questions about the role
of integrity: Is integrity legitimate moral justification
for taking a stand on something about which there is
disagreement, or is it self-indulgence, self-interest, or
bigotry? Is integrity a value equivalent to honesty or
truthfulness; is it a virtue, or at least virtuous? What
are the criteria defining what it is to act with integrity,
distinguishing it from wilfulness, for example? Finally,
is integrity a reasonable and ethical justification for,
say, defying authority?
In addition to these questions, there are two areas
of potential conflict: the first concerns the difference
(if any) between professional and personal values and
the extent to which they should be one; and the other,
already mentioned, concerns different outcomes that
might result from deontological and utilitarian/
consequentialist moral reasoning.
There are a number of terms related to integrity
and some of them will be important in distinguishing
what counts as acting with integrity. These include
authenticity, dignity, respect, honour, honesty, truthfulness, and sincerity.
These issues inform the agenda for this analysis.
Chester Calhoun identifies three pictures of integrity in her paper, Standing for Something: the
integrated-self picture (ISP), the identity picture (IP),
and the clean-hands picture (CHP). (Calhoun, 1995)
Although she admits valuable features in each of
them, she ultimately rejects them as identifying the
virtue of integrity on the grounds that they reduce to
other conditions, viz. the conditions for unified
agency, the conditions for consistency in being one’s
self, and the conditions for resisting some evil. I will
briefly outline each of the pictures, then add further
comments to Calhoun’s critique.
Integrated-self picture
Put simply, I act with integrity if my actions and my
declarations are consistent and coherent. The ISP is
based on the etymological roots of integrity and
integer. Derived from the Latin ‘integritas’ meaning
‘wholeness, completeness, unbroken’, the Oxford
English Dictionary provides three different meanings
for integrity:
1. The condition of having no part or element taken away or
wanting; undivided or unbroken state; material wholeness,
completeness, entirety. Something undivided; an integral
whole. 2. The condition of not being marred or violated;
unimpaired or uncorrupted condition; original perfect state;
soundness. 3. In moral sense. 3.a Unimpaired moral state;
freedom from moral corruption; innocence, sinlessness. Obs.
3.b Soundness of moral principle; the character of uncorrupted virtue, esp. in relation to truth and fair dealing;
uprightness, honesty, sincerity.
On this view, the person of integrity is a whole, undivided, fully integrated and complete individual in
whom there is consistency of views and actions; what
they say and what they do are one. The ‘integer’
person1 is not swayed by the crowd, but will stand up
for what they believe no matter what the consequences may be.
Amy Lavender Harris, using Webster’s Collegiate
Dictionary definition (10th Edition) identifies what
1
I am grateful to Jaoa and Maria Calinas Correia for bringing this
term to my attention. In Portuguese it is common to describe
someone as an ‘integer person’, that is, someone whose beliefs,
motives and actions are consistent. An integer person can be
trusted because what they do truly represents what they believe.
I will comment on this in the text.
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
109
110
Stephen Tyreman
she calls, ‘the three C’s of integrity: Compliance,
Coherence and Consistency.’ (Harris, 2008) She
argues that all three are necessary for integrity. I will
argue that while they may be necessary they are not
sufficient and that some behaviours, such as those of
an obsessive person, might meet the criteria but not
be regarded as having integrity. Nevertheless, consistency of belief and action is clearly important to our
understanding of integrity.
The point is that few people are wholly consistent
in what they say and do. I may not live up to my
beliefs and claims, not because I lack integrity, but
because I fear for my safety or the safety of someone
I hold dear, or because I do not apply the correct set
of beliefs to the situation I am in. It seems harsh to
accuse everyone who fails to live up to their ideals for
what might be good reasons, to be lacking integrity. It
also makes it unlikely that many people demonstrate
integrity, as it seems to permit no failure. Perhaps the
most famous recognition of this is from St. Paul (who
it might be difficult to accuse of lacking integrity) who
said,
For I have the desire to do what is good, but I cannot carry
it out. For what I do is not the good I want to do; no, the evil
I do not want to do – this I keep on doing.
(Romans 7:
18–19 NIV)
Recognizing that human beings have a propensity to
be inconsistent – what we might call human nature –
makes integrity as defined by the ISP a rare or unrealistic virtue. There are further reasons why consistency, as demonstrated in the ISP, cannot be the core
of integrity: the value of multiplicity, the need to
overcome wrong actions by behaving contrary to
psychological propensity, and the desirability of selfreflection and doubt in order to generate new and
better actions.
Multiplicity: Calhoun cites Maria Lugones’s example
to support ‘the value of conceptualizing oneself as a
duplicitous or multiplicitous being’. (ibid. p. 238)
Lugones is a Latina within Hispanic culture, but also
a lesbian. In Hispanic culture homosexuality is an
abomination. She cannot be an integrated coherent
individual – an integer person – and be true to both
her Hispanic roots and her homosexuality. This does
not mean, though that she lacks integrity. By recognizing the conflict and her inability to resolve the
irresolvable, she is demonstrating her integrity; she
acknowledges the value of each culture. Fudging the
conflict by devising some kind of compromise or justification would require her to lack integrity in one or
the other (and perhaps both) situations.
Resisting evil desires: A person may realize that their
desires or their psychological make-up may need to
be resisted. The person who is sexually attracted to
children, or over-controlling or compulsive, may demonstrate integrity by deliberately acting contrary to
their natural thoughts and desires. This ambivalence
between motives and actions, as Calhoun notes (p.
240) is a mark of integrity.
Development through self-reflection: Retaining the
right to refuse to conform to a single set of values and
cultural mores is a necessary precondition for moral
growth and development as Edgar and Pattison point
out in their paper (this issue). What we might call the
morbidly consistent person will not just be entirely
predictable, they will also lack the ability to reflect on
their beliefs and actions and to consider the possibility that they could be wrong, or that other values take
precedence in this case. This might be because their
original view was wrong, or, more commonly, because
they have failed to respond to changing circumstances
or acknowledge conflicting values in a complex situation. Such an individual would always be convinced
of the rightness of their actions, because they assume
that their set of values must always trump all others.
The result would be a failure to learn from mistakes
or adapt to changing circumstances and develop
moral maturity. Integrity is not about being right or
acting consistently no matter what, though clearly
some degree of consistency to avoid what Harry
Frankfurt refers to as wantonness (cited by Calhoun,
p. 238), that is, avoiding being someone who is fickle,
capricious and susceptible to public opinion (Frankfurt, 1971), is desirable.
The ISP also fails to define what are the good reasons
for acting with integrity. Power, money, or greed, for
example, could be motives, which would mean that
despots and tyrants as single-minded agents pursuing
their agendas could be said to be integer persons.
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
Integrity in Healthcare
The idea of the consistent integer person is probably better captured by the word ‘sincere’. Sincerity is
explicitly about being genuine though it does not necessarily require a moral basis. Someone who is
strongly racist, for example, may be very sincere in
that they genuinely believe that races are populated
by fundamentally different kinds of human being, but
it does not make them moral, merely consistent
within the limitations of what they (wrongly) believe;
they can be trusted to act in a racist way across a set of
circumstances.The person who sincerely believes they
are right does not necessarily act with integrity. Sincerity can be narrow and amoral in the sense that it is
not about morality, that is, enhancing goodness, just
consistency and a genuine belief that the act is right,
whether or not it is. It is possible to be sincere but
wrong, in a way that is less likely with integrity. Integrity entails a moral good, not just consistent intentions. Presumably Hitler sincerely believed he was
right to try and rid the world of Jews, but it is counterintuitive to suggest that he therefore acted with
integrity. I will return to the question of why Hitler
cannot be considered a person of integrity later.
This challenges the common assumption that the
person of integrity is also a person of principle. As I
will attempt to show, integrity is not just a matter of
remaining true to one’s beliefs or principles, it is a
question of having the right principles in the first
place.
The identity picture
The second picture that is used to describe integrity is
the IP. On this account, integrity means that my
actions express something that is central to who I am,
that I identify with wholeheartedly, that I believe in
and endorse. In other words, it is something that I
stand for, to use Calhoun’s expression. This answers
the criticism of the ISP that trivial actions can demonstrate integrity. It insists that integrity is at the core
of my identity. If I am a healthcare worker I have
integrity because caring for needy people is fundamental to who I am. The meaning of my life is
founded on certain things that I do and if I were to fail
to do them, or gave them up, my life would lose
meaning.
The IP captures the sense that the person of integrity would rather die than act against their core identity. This view, articulated by Bernard Williams, is, in
his opinion, opposed to both Kantian deontology and
utilitarianism because both require the moral agent to
give up their ‘ground projects’ for the sake of rational
good ordering, or to maximize the greater good. (Williams, 1981b) Williams’s criticism of these two familiar
moral systems is that both require too much of agents,
and that having to give up deeply held ground
projects for some impartial or greater good results in
those agents failing to identify at a personal level with
the moral choice. Calhoun questions this by asking
whether ‘integrity really is, and is nothing but, being
true to what one deeply identifies with.’ (op. cit.
p. 242)
Calhoun’s criticism is that the psychological sense
of self is incidental to behaving with integrity. Having
a psychological propensity to paedophilia, or pyromania is incidental to the judgement that acting in accordance with that propensity is morally wrong. To
demonstrate integrity may require someone to act
contrary to the core sense that they are a pyromaniac
or a paedophile. My psychological sense of self, even
when it is the core motivating force in my life, is
distinct from my moral sense of acting with integrity.
So how is integrity related to authenticity and sincerity (again)? With both of these, my identity is
expressed through my behaviour, which in turn will
match my beliefs and claims. Someone is authentic
and acts with sincerity when the way they live – the
decisions and choices they make – matches what they
claim to believe. On this account, living with integrity
is completely about expressing true identity. Someone
who has argued against abortion, for example, will fail
the test of authenticity as well as failing to act with
integrity if she herself has an abortion. There have
been many examples in political, religious, and sporting life, where the leaders’ behaviours have failed to
match their public portrayal. They have lacked
authenticity. The difference between authenticity and
integrity here is twofold: first, authenticity is about
consistency between my actions and what I claim to
believe (not what I secretly might really believe); and
second, that if, having been found out, a person sincerely admits their failure, resigns (if appropriate)
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
111
112
Stephen Tyreman
and tries to make amends, they will have acted with
integrity though still lacking authenticity.
Although the IP places the individual’s character
and deeply held beliefs at the centre of integrity, thus
nullifying the ISP’s problem of trivially held projects,
it is unable to make a moral distinction between good
and bad. On this account a despot or tyrant who passionately believes that he should destroy all who
oppose him, acts with integrity if he commits genocide
in achieving his ends. Hitler is still a man of integrity
because his core personality is fully and completely
expressed through his actions of genocide.
Although the IP of integrity seems to capture the
relationship between a person’s core sense of doing
what they strongly hold dear by providing a reason to
stand up for something, it fails to distinguish between
morally good and bad actions.
The clean-hands picture
The third picture that Calhoun identifies is the CHP.
Like the IP, it focuses on a person’s core beliefs, but
emphasizes the bottom-line with regard to what they
are prepared to do or not do. It identifies not just what
a person stands for and what is central to their sense
of identity, but what they endorse. The CHP does not
mean that the person of integrity avoids getting their
hands dirty doing unpleasant or disagreeable work; it
is much more precise than that. It draws a line in the
sand and says beyond this I cannot go without corrupting my identity. The CHP therefore seems to be
an advancement on the IP while also strengthening
the sense of being fully integrated.
A key problem still remains. There are times, particularly in complex and multi-faceted situations such
as healthcare, when whatever decision is made
involves some greyness, when keeping clean simply is
not possible. In such circumstances acting with integrity involves making a moral judgement that does not
just avoid doing something bad, but positively tries to
make the best of an inherently bad situation. Managers with limited resources have to make decisions that
involve a degree of harm to some patients or staff.The
simplistic approach is to take a naïve consequentialist
view and weigh harm against benefit or to apply
rigid deontological rules, to produce a defendable
outcome. The problem is that integrity is implicitly
personal. I am not acting with integrity when I do
what I am told to do, or when I simply respond to
external standards, which is Williams’s criticism of
both utilitarianism and deontology (Williams, 1981a).
The CHP is based on an externally imposed set of
principles and beliefs that the moral agent can point
to (or hide behind) as the reason for their action
rather than the action resulting from their personally
generated and owned moral reasons, which is implicit
in integrity.
It is not my principles or beliefs that are prompting
me to act with integrity in the sense that I generated
them and have moulded them to form my ground
project; they are imposed externally by the requirement to be rational. I may, of course, agree with the
principles, or adopt them as mine, but that does not
avoid the point that they originate externally rather
than being generated by my personal moral deliberation. It is also the case that I may agree with them as
rational, but fail to identify with them personally.
Integrity is not just a matter of keeping morally
clean. Calhoun concludes that the CHP devolves to
avoiding evil rather than positively doing good.
Acting with integrity should require a reason to do
something that is morally right, rather than a reason
for avoiding something evil. It is a stand that one
chooses to make because it is believed to be the
morally positive response. Refusing to do something,
such as participating in abortion for example, is not
just a question of avoiding evil – there may be good
utilitarian reasons for performing an abortion – it
should be a question of taking a positive stand
because it is the right thing to do. The next question is:
what is it that makes it the right thing to do?
Integrity as a social rather than a
personal concept
Although the three pictures of integrity identify
important elements, they fail separately and jointly to
fully capture its meaning. Calhoun, supported by
Harris, believes that the mistake is in assuming that
integrity is a personal virtue. She argues that integrity
only makes sense for matters that are morally significant in a social context. There is a further criticism
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
Integrity in Healthcare
that can be made: making integrity a personal value
assumes that the moral truth behind it is embedded
within the individual, that is, that person can look into
themselves to find the moral truth of the matter in
order to know what to do. Using one’s conscience, or
whatever, to guide moral behaviour presumes that
conscience is the repository of moral truth. This contrasts with the intellectual task of grappling with
complex, competing moral goods and coming to a just
and rational outcome.
Williams identifies Plato as the source of this (in
his view) mistaken idea. (Williams, 1972, p. 72). Plato
believed that the role of the creative philosophical
thinker is to discover through rational reasoning
transcendental a priori moral truths that make moral
action right or wrong. Once these truths have been
identified, the moral response is to adopt, personalize and act in accordance with them. Williams argues
that such moral truths do not exist a priori,2 but are
social and contextual and therefore subject to
debate and review. This necessitates shifting from
ensuring adherence to a putative standard of behaviour, to facilitating the best possible outcome in
terms of goods achieved. It is here, I believe, where
part of the argument about codes of practice versus
professional (not just personal) integrity lies, I will
return to this later.
The person of integrity exercises their moral
behaviour in the context of a community where
those kinds of behaviours are deemed significant. In
the case of integrity there is disagreement about
what ‘good’ behaviour entails. (There has to be disagreement, otherwise integrity is not an issue.) There
is therefore a tension between identifying with the
values of the community and behaving in accordance with them on one side, and legitimately
2
Williams argues that philosophical debate on defining the stan-
dard for the ‘good man’ has been either transcendental, that is,
by ‘an appeal to some framework which lies outside human life
and the empirical world’ (ibid. p. 68) as in religious or utopian
claims; or non-transcendental, in which certain characteristics of
human beings are identified as distinctive. The life of a good man
will exemplify these characteristics to the fullest degree. He
rejects both. (ibid. pp. 68–86)
challenging some or all of the values (or the way
they are interpreted), while still remaining a
member of the community on the other. It is in the
tension of this interface that integrity becomes significant. One of two things may be happening here:
(1) values may be given different weighting or priority, or (2) a different set of values are being identified as characterizing the community.
The 19th Century, Hungarian physician Ignaz Semmelweis is famous for identifying the causal link
between puerperal fever following childbirth and
obstetricians’ failure to wash hands and instruments
after performing an autopsy. Despite clearly demonstrating the effectiveness of basic hygiene procedures
on death rates, most of his contemporaries ignored his
recommendation because it went against accepted
custom and because they believed disease was unpreventable. Semmelweis eventually resigned from the
hospital in Vienna to return to Pest rather than take
up a non-clinical appointment. (Zoltan, 2010) Clearly,
Semmelweis did not share the same value set as some
of his colleagues: he was not resigned to the idea that
disease was unpreventable; he was driven by the
appallingly high death rates in the obstetric wards;
he placed innovation above tradition; he used
an evidence-based approach. Although the whole
medical community accepted the premise that obstetrics is based on safe and effective delivery of babies,
there were different interpretations of what that
entailed. Evidence was valued below custom as the
basis for praxis, for example.
If integrity depends on an issue being morally significant in a community, it also means (at least in part)
that a person’s identification of themselves as a
member of a community by supporting the values of
the community will also be a measure of their commitment to it. This does not necessarily mean that
they must be in accord with the majority view. The
history of the Christian Church, for example, provides
examples of individuals who stood up against the prevailing values because they were committed to a different set of values, which they believed more truly
represented the (Church) community and its reasons
for existing.
Clearly, it is the case that integrity is practised by
individuals in a personal way rather than by groups
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
113
114
Stephen Tyreman
acting collectively.3 In situations where a group of
people are described as acting with integrity, it is
usually as a collection of individuals. For example, it
might be said that doctors act with integrity when
they put the needs of their patients before those of
the institution for whom they work. But this only
means that all doctors (or the vast majority) individually put the needs of patients before those of the
institution. The problem is that the ways of describing
integrity as personal – the ISP, IP, and CHP – fail to
fully capture its meaning. Personal values are generated from a wide range of sources: family, culture,
religion, social class, geography, education, lifecircumstances, and so on, many of which are so
embedded that we are unaware of their significance.
What, then, is the relationship between personal and
social values and what bearing does it have for our
understanding of integrity?
Calhoun argues that personal values only have
significance when those values are shared and
agreed as significant in a social context. We are
social beings; we live in social groupings and relate
to one another in the context of those groups. Family
commitment, for example, is one of the strongest
bonds between people. Each group or community
has a set of values that define the identity of the
group and which are tacitly accepted to a greater or
lesser extent by individuals within the community.
The actions of an individual and the values that
underpin those actions are judged in the context of
the community’s values. Acting with integrity means
acting in accordance with the set of values that I
identify with, that is, those values that give me identity, and which, in turn, make me recognizable as a
committed member of that community.
Integrity is personal to the extent that it is my
judgement on where I stand in relation to a set of
values that I hold; but it is also about where I stand in
3
There can be occasions where integrity applies to the way a
community acts. For example, the Parliament may act with integrity by deciding as a collective to allow access to sensitive information that is in the public interest but potentially embarrassing
to individual members; the Roman Catholic Church was criticized for not acting with integrity over the alleged abuse of
children by priests.
relation to the community to which I have committed
myself, and on whose behalf I act.
Consider the example of someone who has an
obsessive compulsive disorder (OCD). For them it
may be of the greatest importance that their pencils
are lined up on the desk in size order and equally
separated; that they always go to work along the same
route and at the same time, etc. This behaviour seems
to meet the criteria of the ISP, IP, and CHP, in the
sense that it is at the core of their personality, it
defines their identity and unifies their belief with their
action, and sets a very clear boundary beyond which
they cannot go without undermining their sense of
self. But it is not clear that this person therefore acts
with integrity whenever they insist on straightening
their pencils before doing their work. This person is a
member of communities for which this behaviour has
no moral significance. Even if there was a group of
people with similar psychological propensities, there
would not be agreement about which particular
behaviours are significant. They would not be praised
for their integrity in insisting that all pencils are
straight and books lined up on their desk before they
will begin to do their work. This kind of behaviour
emanates from the individual rather than from
society – even a society of OCD persons. Such behaviours are only significant to the individuals displaying
them and do not generate a commonly held value.
This idea is very similar to Charles Taylor’s
account of authenticity where he believes personal
identity develops through ‘dialogical relations’ with
others. (Taylor, 1991) Our identity requires recognition by others through what Taylor calls ‘a horizon
of significance’. (ibid. pp. 31–41) He argues that
sense of personal identity only has meaning in a
social context. There is no identity in isolation; identity only has meaning in relation to a community
that recognizes that identity and agrees on its
meaning. On the same basis, integrity is personal
moral behaviour that only has significance in the
context of a known community for whom that
behaviour is widely agreed to be significant, even if
not all members are agreed on what the right behaviour is. In fact, for both Taylor and Calhoun, it is the
dialogue about it that makes it significant rather
than any fact about it being agreed.
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
Integrity in Healthcare
Human being is social; we exist in multiple communities consisting of family, race, gender, nation, profession, sport, hobby, social class, and so on, and we relate
within and across many of these at the same time.
Perhaps it is the case that a ‘well-rounded’ individual
needs to exist in multiple communities. The mature,
developed person is someone who relates within
several communities and the integrity (or lack of it)
they demonstrate will result from the way they personally identify themselves in relation to those communities and the value systems each represents. To
this extent, then, the IP is core to our understanding
of integrity, but not in the sense that integrity is an
expression of identity, but rather that our identity
grows out of our relating within family, school, geographical community, workplace, sport club, and so
on. On this account, integrity is the expression of our
commitment to those relationships. The more closely
someone identifies with the values and mores of a
community, the more likely they are to demonstrate
integrity in their acts.
This understanding of integrity resonates with
Alasdair MacIntyre’s contention that what he defines
as human practices, which includes professional practices, entail both internal and external goods, that is,
goods such as skills and knowledge that are internal
to and which define the practice, and external goods
such as monetary payment, prestige, and social status
that are contingent. (MacIntyre, 1985, pp. 186–189)
His point is that although both are necessary, it is the
internal values and the pursuit of excellence rather
than external values associated with effectiveness that
should take precedence. MacIntyre uses the example
of an artist whose life is that of a painter before being
the producer of any particular picture. (op. cit. p. 190)
What is important to a genuine, virtuous painter is the
internal goods of painting rather than an external
person’s judgement of effectiveness. The artist with
integrity will only produce good art, that is, art that
expresses the artist’s true artistic values. Producing art
that is popular just to make money is often criticized.
Derek Sellman takes MacIntyre’s idea and applies
it to current trends in nursing where, in his view, external goods such as evidence-based practice and adherence to codes of practice are gaining dominance over
nursing’s internal professional values and threatens to
undermine the fundamental integrity of the profession (Sellman, 2010). My argument is similar, that
is, that integrity entails commitment to an internal
set of values that are socially owned by a practice
community and which define the identity of that
community.
The final element that needs to be clarified is the
relationship between integrity and moral values.
Integrity as a moral value
At first sight, integrity looks to be a value like honesty
or truthfulness – something that one has or does not
have – but there are important differences. It is meaningful to say that someone acted honestly in the
context of what they knew at the time, but that with
hindsight, which is in a different context, they would
have acted differently. Or they might say that they
told the truth ‘as they saw it’, with the inference, first,
that it was not the (whole) truth and second, that in
different circumstances or with additional knowledge
they would have given a more truthful account. But
such conditions do not seem to apply to integrity.
Acting with integrity just is doing what is judged to be
right. While I may do or say something that I later
realize is dishonest or not the (whole) truth, I cannot
look back on something and say that because I was
mistaken I did not do it with integrity. I will always act
with integrity, even if what I did proves to have been
mistaken or wrong. It is therefore more akin to sincerity or honour than to truth and honesty. On the
other hand if I do something that goes against what I
believe to be right I will be acting without integrity. I
could, of course, delude myself by looking for excuses
or justification, but, if I am honest, I will acknowledge
that I was not actually acting with integrity. But perversely, this expression of remorse is itself an act of
integrity, which is only possible because integrity is
not itself a value, but the expression of a related (and
integrated) set of values.
Values like honesty and truthfulness can be partial
within a set of circumstances; someone can be more or
less honest, more or less truthful, either deliberately
or unknowingly, but it is not possible to have more or
less integrity. I might say that I always tell the truth,
but this claim will be conditional because truth is ‘as I
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
115
116
Stephen Tyreman
see it’. Integrity, though, seems to be something that
someone either has (or acts in accordance with) or
does not have.
If someone acts with integrity why is not integrity
an act-focused value like truth-telling or honesty? It
is, I believe, because the focus for integrity is not on
the object of the act, but the reasons for doing it, that
is, it is one step removed from the act itself. The truth
is the truth, whether or not we know it; an honest
action is not judged by the intention of the person, but
by the act itself – integrity on the other hand seems to
operate on a different level. It is possible for someone
to tell an untruth that they wrongly believe to be the
truth and to justify it with the claim that they did so
‘with integrity’. The ‘honest mistake’ is justified on the
grounds that it was done with integrity. Integrity can
make good a moral deficit resulting from such an act.
I therefore do not believe that integrity relates to
the action itself despite the fact that it is frequently
treated as such. You can have an honest, truthful,
sincere, honourable and so on statement or act, but it
does not make much sense to talk of an integrated act
– or whatever the adverb should be. Integrity is a
noun not an adverb or adjective. One acts with integrity; integrity is distanced from the act in a way that
honesty, truthfulness, courage, and so on are not. This
has the effect of enabling integrity to observe from a
distance and take in the bigger picture. So what does
‘with integrity’ mean in this case? It is now time to
draw together the various ideas I have been outlining.
a practitioner and the more embedded my profession’s values and mores are within my behaviour, the
more likely I am naturally to act with integrity to
expound those values. So when I act ‘with integrity’ I
am utilizing the set of values that define my profession in order to respond to a specific situation. My
responsibility as a member of that community is to
ensure that my behaviour is in accordance with the
profession’s value-set – or at least those that are relevant to the situation – in order to achieve the moral
purposes, or on MacIntyre’s account, the internal
goods of that community. As a novice I start by considering each value separately, but with experience
and familiarity the values become part of the natural
way that I act. Integrity only becomes overt when
conflicts emerge.
The richness and complexity of this may make it
difficult to predict exactly how integrity will be
expressed in any given situation. If I live my life with
integrity, it does not necessarily mean that I adhere to
a rigid code of practice in a predictable way without
deviation – that might make me an integer person
(and probably very boring). Integrity is a richer and
more complex concept than that. Integrity is the relational framework that enables sets of values to
operate together in order to realize the goods of a
community. And what are judged to be the goods of a
community will be contingent on the circumstances at
the time.4
4
As I write this we have an interesting political situation in the
UK with a coalition government made up of Conservative and
Integrity as relation
Liberal-Democrat members. Both parties, but the Liberal-
I am suggesting, along with Calhoun and Harris, that
integrity is not itself a value. Calhoun argues that it is
a social virtue. I do not want to deny that, but to add
that it becomes a social virtue by the way it frames
sets of values in the service of maintaining the internal goods of a profession. The point that I wish to add
to Calhoun’s account is that integrity represents a
complex set of values that have to be considered as a
whole, a relational framework of values that exist for
defined communities and individuals.
As a healthcare professional my integrity expresses
the internal values associated with my profession in a
connected holistic way. The more experienced I am as
Democrats in particular, have been accused of lacking integrity
because promises made in election manifestos and speeches
have been overturned in government. The Liberal-Democrats
promised not to increase tuition fees for university students, but
in power supported a trebling of fees. The party’s defence has
been that the context in which the promises were made was very
different from the situation they find themselves in now. Their
claim is along the lines of: the internal values that define liberaldemocratic principles are inviolable, but the way these principles
are interpreted is contingent on current circumstances. By contrast, specific policies and the promises that go with them are
external goods, context-specific, and subject to change as circumstances change. It is therefore possible to act with integrity, that
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
Integrity in Healthcare
It also means that integrity may have a different
meaning for the community and for the individual. In
a community integrity represents the explicit and
implicit core internal values that define that community, whether it be a nation, race, religion, sport or
whatever, and are related to the purposes of that community. In this it most closely follows the IP of integrity. But for the individual who is a (more or less)
committed member of several communities, integrity
is much more complex as he or she may be required to
make a judgement that entails different and potentially conflicting sets of values.
Integrity over codes of practice
Codes of practice define a set of behaviours that are
assumed to be right in a given situation. They are not
universal in that they apply to a given set of circumstances – care of children, say – but within that set, it
is assumed that they cover all, or at least the vast
majority of situations involving the care of children.
This means that most of the time what a code of
practice requires (assuming it is well designed) will be
what the majority of professionals would do anyway.
It is when a professional believes that a greater good
can be achieved (or an evil avoided) by acting contrary to the code, or where there is clear conflict
between internal and external values, that conflict
arises and the appeal to integrity is made. It is precisely here that I believe integrity – if it is properly
conceived – should take precedence over codes.
The weakness of codes is similar to the arguments
against the CHP, i.e., the implicit assumption that
there is a set of moral behaviours that have an independent existence; that there is an objective standard
that pre-exists the circumstance in which it is to be
applied, and which is good in and of itself. The
assumption that the standard is objective and independent is strengthened by the fact that codes of practice are written down with legal precision and used to
judge specific circumstances. Although a code may
have been designed originally with the explicit
is, to act in accordance with the fundamental internal value-set of
the party to achieve the broader goods of liberal-democracy,
even if specific policies, that is, external goods, change.
aim of ensuring a good outcome, once adopted it
inevitably becomes an end in itself because of the
implicit assumption that by following it, a good will be
achieved. In other words, internal values have become
external and contingent. The focus is shifted from the
specific situation that requires moral deliberation, to
the epistemological issue of identifying and applying
the right code of behaviour. The consequence is that
effectiveness in relation to external goods, that is, conformity to the code, rather than the morality of the
outcome becomes the central issue.
Integrity as a communitarian
relational framework
In conclusion then, I want to suggest that integrity
remains a necessary virtue in society generally and
healthcare in particular, but that the focus needs to
shift from personal integrity, in the sense that integrity
is all about the personal values and beliefs of the
individual, and more explicitly onto the community
the individual is representing (at that given time) and
from which they gain their identity, including professional identity.
Developing Calhoun’s idea, I believe that integrity
is a social virtue expressed through the individual,
determined both by the wider cultural community
entailed by nation, gender, or colour of which that
person is a member, and smaller communities such as
a profession, religious organization, etc., or a subgroup of any of these. Each community has its own
internal value-set that defines its identity and guides
the expected behaviour of its members. Integrity
entails a relational framework, a set of values that
operates on two levels: the first defines a community’s
goods and purposes and gives it identity; and the
second focuses on the individual member of that community who is called on to expedite those values, but
in the more complex context of the range of communities of which they are members. In so far as the
institution, profession, association, or whatever
manages to keep those values exercised in balance it
will be operating with integrity. But institutions are
reliant upon the individuals that comprise that community and the ways in which the set of values as a
whole are demonstrated in relation to other commu-
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118
117
118
Stephen Tyreman
nities of which the individual is a member and to
which they have allegiance.
The communitarian relational framework of values
that define the profession or sport or whatever, forms
the backdrop against which the individual defines
their own identity and particularly where they stand
in relation to that community. Integrity as the kinds of
actions the individual believes to be morally justified
will either reflect or challenge the set of values
expounded by the profession. This opens the way for
an individual to challenge the accepted values and
mores of the profession – entering into a dialogical
relation, to use Taylor’s term – or to comply wholeheartedly and willingly with them.
References
Calhoun C. (1995) Standing for something. The Journal of
Philosophy, 92(5), 235–260.
Frankfurt H. (1971) Freedom of the will and the concept of
a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.
Harris A.L. (2008) Integrity. Outer Sanctum. Retrieved 13
February 2011 from http://outersanctum.blogspot.com/
2005/12/on-integrity.html
MacIntyre A. (1985) After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory,
2nd edn. Duckworth, London.
Sellman D. (2010) Values and adult general nursing. In:
Emerging Values in Health Care: The Challenge of Professionals (eds S. Pattison, B. Hannigan & H. Thomas), pp.
129–140. Jessica Kingsley Publisher, London.
Taylor C. (1991) The Ethics of Authenticity. Harvard, Cambridge, MA.
Williams B. (1972) Morality: An Introduction to Ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Williams B. (1981a) Moral Luck. In: Moral Luck: Philosophical papers 1973–1980. pp. 20–39. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Williams B. (1981b) Persons, character, and morality. In:
Moral Luck: Philosophical Paper 1973–1980. pp. 1–19.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Zoltan I. (2010) Semmelweis, Ignaz Philipp Encyclopaedia
Britannica (Vol. Encyclopaedia Britannica Ultimare Reference Suite). Encyclopaedia Britannica, Chicago, IL.
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2011), 12, pp. 107–118