Journal of European Public Policy 10:1 February 2003: 81–83
Introduction: Political economy and
European integration
Erik Jones and Amy Verdun
There is something odd about celebrating political economy approaches to the
study of European integration at a time when non-economic factors appear to
hold sway over popular attention. The ‘war against terrorism’, enlargement,
the European Convention, and European identity are currently among the
most prominent issues of public debate. Meanwhile, conversation is more
muted in relation to trade, industrial policy and economic and monetary
union (at least inside the eurozone). European priorities were not always
arrayed in this manner.
Many authors from different points of departure have stressed the economic
basis for European integration. Ernst Haas’s original study of European
integration assumed mostly economic policies to be at the core of the
integration process (Haas 1958). Fritz Scharpf (1996) relaunched the concepts
of negative and positive integration, which typically refer to taking away rules
and regulations that obstruct economic integration, and the creation of
common rules and policies (which are usually in the area of economic
policies). Andrew Moravcsik (1998) famously (and controversially) argued that
economics and economic interests lie at the heart of integration in the
European Union (EU) culminating in the Treaty on European Union signed
in Maastricht in 1992. These and many other contributions have shaped our
understanding of the European integration process. But how far can such
emphasis on the political economy carry us in our understanding of contemporary developments in Europe?
Of course, any answer to the question depends on how the ‘emphasis’ is
structured and what we mean by ‘political economy’. The argument that unites
this collection of essays is that how we study the EU is as important as what
we choose to analyse. Throughout, what is at issue is not just the political
economy, but also the political economy approach. The aim here is to provide
the student of European integration with a framework for inquiry that can be
more general than one which merely analyses an individual case study of one
aspect of European integration. In a sense, we may also show the influence of
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046949
82
Journal of European Public Policy
work by Haas, Moravcsik and Scharpf as well as many others who are cited in
the articles which follow. We do not pretend to be original in positing this
argument but we do hope to illustrate and to persuade that such an understanding of the relevance of political economy has merit. In particular we hope to
offer a bridge between more specific accounts of European integration and the
more general approaches, with political economy representing the broader
literature.
The juxtaposition of methodological and substantive considerations makes
for a difficult division of labour. When we originally conceived of this
collection, we sought to get two representatives from international political
economy and two from comparative. For each subdivision, we asked for one
paper on agentic approaches and one on more structural or institutional
accounts. Almost immediately, however, the Cartesian elegance of that division
foundered on the more complicated reality of the methods and the subject we
hoped to analyse. We simply could not do justice to a comprehensive survey
of the existing literature of what might be categorized as political economy
approaches to the study of European integration and nor did we really want
to try.
The resulting papers offer extended illustrations of the more general point
we hope to make. ‘Political economy’ offers a useful lens for studying European
integration not just because it focuses attention on the intersection between
politics and economics but also, and more broadly, because it provides a range
of tools for analysing European integration issues. We claim that political
economy would offer useful tools both in the typical political economy fields
of study (trade, industrial policy, monetary integration) as well as in areas of
study where the political and economic overlap is less apparent (for example,
foreign policy, social policy, the construction of Europe, and European
identity). Rather than outlining political economy approaches as a whole, we
focus more narrowly on the nature of methodological divisions (Verdun), on the
importance of omitted variables (Cowles), on the analysis of institutionalized
relationships (Kassim and Menon), and on the implications of particular
notions of causality (Jones). At the same time, we touch on a range of
substantive concerns relating to analysis, decision-making, constitutional
design, and popular support.
The intended audience for these papers is not limited to students and
scholars of political economy. Although we hope to make some contribution
to debates that are taking place in the literature, our larger objective is to
provide a theoretical lens through which non-political economists can view
and hence understand and participate in these debates. Thus the literature
reviews in the following papers have a clear agenda which is to establish points
of departure for opening up the debate. We leave it to the reader to judge the
merits of this stylistic choice.
These papers constitute the first formal activity of the EU political economy
interest section of the European Union Studies Association (EUSA) in the
United States. The papers were all originally presented in draft form at the
E. Jones & A. Verdun: Introduction
83
1
May 2001 Biennial ECSA-USA Conference in Madison, Wisconsin. The
discussion of these papers was lively and the benefits derived by the authors
have been considerable. Our ambition is that this activity will be the first in a
long series of similar events. As editors, we would like to thank Jeremy
Richardson and our eight anonymous referees for their support and attention
throughout the review process. We would also like to thank our three other
contributors, Maria Green Cowles, Hussein Kassim and Anand Menon, for
participating and for agreeing to abide by our numerous requests. What lies
in front of you is a collection of papers which aim to start a dialogue on
political economy and European integration. We hope for a fruitful debate in
the years to come.
Addresses for correspondence: Erik Jones, Johns Hopkins Bologna Center,
via Belmeloro 11, 40126 Bologna, Italy. Tel: ò39 051 291 7833. Fax:
ò39 051 228 505. email:
[email protected]. Amy Verdun, Department
of Political Science, University of Victoria, PO Box 3050, Victoria, BC,
V8W 3P5, Canada. Tel: ò1 250 721 7491 or 7486. Fax: ò1 250 721 7485.
email:
[email protected]
NOTE
1 EUSA was called the European Community Studies Association (ECSA)-USA until
and including that conference. It changed its name immediately thereafter.
REFERENCES
Haas, E.B. (1958) The Uniting of Europe. Political, Social, and Economic Forces 1950–
1957, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Moravcsik, A. (1998) The Choice for Europe. Social Purpose and State Power from
Messina to Maastricht, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Scharpf, F.W. (1996) ‘Negative and positive integration in the political economy of
European welfare states’, in G. Marks, F.W. Scharpf, P.C. Schmitter and W. Streeck
(eds), Governance in the European Union, London: Sage, pp. 15–39.
Journal of European Public Policy 10:1 February 2003: 84–101
An American/European divide in
European integration studies:
bridging the gap with international
political economy
Amy Verdun1
ABSTRACT There appears to be a divide in the literature between American
and European approaches to European integration studies. This article discusses
the differences between the two types of approaches, and what problems occur
from having this divide. It is argued that IPE offers a venue for dialogue between
those who focus exclusively on the EU (labelled here as ‘European approaches’)
and those who see the EU case to be part of more general phenomena and who
seek to produce general theories (‘American approaches’). The article suggests that
IPE offers a useful body of literature to narrow the gap between ‘American’ and
‘European’ studies of European integration.
KEY WORDS American and European approaches; critical theory; European
integration theories; European Union; institutionalism; international political economy; international relations; neorealism; social constructivism.
INTRODUCTION
The field of European integration studies has gone through a turbulent fifteen
years in terms of its scholarly analysis and its implications for European
integration theory. Whereas the origins of European integration theory can be
traced back to American international relations (IR) literature, present day
theories are inspired by a wide range of approaches and case studies produced
on both sides of the Atlantic. Though we see many fascinating theoretical
approaches in the literature, the relationship between the empirical case studies
and theory is not always clear. Some scholars are mainly interested in describing
the phenomenon in which they are interested. They want to reflect on the
theoretical approaches available in order to place matters in perspective, but
are not necessarily interested in developing or improving existing theories.
Others use the case of European integration and policy-making in the European
Union (EU) as a way to develop new theoretical approaches or to amend
existing theories. As a result there appears to be a gap between these case
study-oriented and theory-oriented approaches. Furthermore, it seems to be
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046958
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
85
that the former often comes out of European schools whereas the latter
proliferates in the United States. Thus, one could provocatively claim that there
is a split between European and American scholarship, which is characterized by
how theory and empirics are treated.
This article examines why there is a gap between the more theoryoriented American and case study-oriented European scholarship in the field
of European integration/EU studies and how the gap can be narrowed. It
suggests that the international political economy (IPE) literature can serve as
a vehicle to bridge the gap. To develop this argument the article is structured
as follows. The first section offers an analysis of the split between American
and European scholarship in the field of European integration/EU studies.
The second introduces the field of IPE and reviews four of its schools of
thought: neorealism, institutionalism, social constructivism and a collection of
approaches critical of the status quo referred to here as the critical school.
Section three discusses how IPE can contribute to bridging the gap between
the two approaches in the field of European integration. The last section draws
some conclusions.
THE EU AS A SUI GENERIS CASE? VIEWS FROM BOTH SIDES
OF THE ATLANTIC
The developments in European integration theory mirror the rapid changes
that have occurred in contemporary Europe, in particular those that have
taken place since the late 1980s. In Europe this sea change has led scholars to
being interested in understanding this process, which to many observers seems
excessively complex and not easily comparable with other political processes at
the national level, or indeed elsewhere in the world. Frustrated with the
inability of the traditional integration theories to explain, predict or clarify the
outcome of the European integration process, numerous scholars have moved
to focusing more narrowly on the EU as a unique case and developing specific
theories about the European integration process (for a review of European
integration theories, see Verdun 2002).
It has long been questioned whether the European integration process
should be considered a sui generis case or a case that resembles others (cf.
Wallace 1983). A number of scholars – usually Europeans – tend to treat it as
the former (see inter alia Shaw 1999). These scholars argue that the integration
process is sufficiently distinct that it merits being conceptualized differently
and requires specific theories. In doing so, they offer explanations that are
often exclusively applicable to the EU. Others do not argue the case quite as
forcefully, but argue instead that the European integration process is in between
a sui generis case and a case like many others (see inter alia Kohler-Koch 1997).
Scholars on the other side of the Atlantic, however, tend to focus on the
European integration process as an example of a process of institution building
and policy-making not dissimilar to those in other parts of the world (see, for
example, the debate in a 1997 issue of ECSA Review, i.e. Caporaso et al.
86
Journal of European Public Policy
1997). They see the European integration process as a reaction to pressures
that many countries, also those outside Europe, are facing (see also Cohen
1998; Mattli 1999). Countries in some parts of the world may make different
choices from those in other parts, and hence do not proceed towards regional
integration in the way that Europe has done. These scholars would argue that
the EU is not fundamentally different from other forms of governance. It is
just in a different stage of institutionalization (see also Jupille and Caporaso
1999).
In terms of their contribution to the literature, the studies that adopt a sui
generis approach of the study of the EU tend to move away from contributing
to the wider political science literature.2 Instead, they develop theoretical
approaches that are derived from European integration studies, and typically
assume that their approaches are not necessarily applicable to studies beyond
those related to the EU. Even though there are notable exceptions, this
development has had the effect, in particular in American circles, of making
European integration studies less important because the connection between
it and the broader political science literature has become less obvious. As
Simon Bulmer has put it: ‘The sui generis assumptions of some political
integration theory and the lack of interdisciplinary dialogue have risked
confining European integration to an intellectual ‘‘ghetto’’ within the social
sciences’ (Bulmer 1997: 8).
As a result of their view of the European integration process as being
comparable to processes going on elsewhere, ‘American scholars’ tend to place
their study of the EU within a broader framework of theoretical approaches
that are of a more general nature. Their aim typically is to show that the
European integration process is yet another case with which they can show
that a particular theoretical approach can be proven to be right or wrong. In
other words, their aim is to contribute to the general theoretical literature
using the case of the EU.
By contrast, many ‘European scholars’ seem more inclined to invent a new
ad hoc approach, or label, to signal their specific approach, which they have
derived from their exclusive study of the European integration process. These
European scholars often aim at making a new contribution to the more narrow
literature on European integration. In doing so they do not concern themselves
too much with questions regarding what European integration studies can
contribute to the overall political science literature.
The categories ‘American’ and ‘European’, mentioned above, are introduced
here for purely analytical reasons and also to be provocative. The terms
‘American approach’ and ‘European approach’ (or ‘American scholar’ versus
‘European scholar’) should be seen as terms that are used to capture a group
of scholars who fit broadly into these categories. In this article we understand
a ‘European approach’ to be aiming at examining the European integration
process as separate from processes in other parts of the world. In the extreme
case this approach considers Europe to be a sui generis case. The theoretical
contribution to the literature that this approach makes applies only to the case
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
87
of Europe. It does not aim at taking the integration process to be an example
of a phenomenon that exists outside Europe. In turn, the ‘American approach’,
as we use it here, aims at fitting into the broader approaches of political science
literature. According to this approach, the European integration process is only
one case, and hence one should examine other cases as well. These studies aim
at contributing to the wider political science literature.
Though the dichotomy is clearly artificial and provocative, the names of
these categories are selected to reflect the apparent cultural differences in
academia on both sides of the Atlantic. There are, of course, Americans who
contribute to the European approach (Peterson 2001), and Europeans who
apply an American approach (Hix 2002).3 Furthermore, let us be clear that
there are indeed European integration scholars who adopt approaches that
speak to the general political science approaches and/or who make broader
comparisons in their studies (inter alia Börzel and Risse 2002; Hix 1994; Knill
and Lenschow 2001; Majone 1997, 2001a, 2001b; Scharpf 1997). Likewise,
there are numerous American trained scholars who have a keen interest in
European integration as such and who have incorporated European scholarship
in their research (inter alia Ingebritsen 1998; Mattli 1999; McNamara 1998;
Moravcsik 1998; Pierson 1996; Pollack 2001).
The above mentioned two trends – to examine European integration merely
from either a European perspective or an American perspective, i.e. too much
specificity or too much examining Europe as just another case study – are each
unrewarding. A criticism of the American approach is that these scholars are
so busy trying to prove to their fellow (American) political scientists that they
are eager to make a contribution to the general literature that they are unable
to appreciate the complexity, diversity and uniqueness of the European
integration process. Also, they often choose their case studies in such a way
that they can contribute most easily to that literature, rather than being
necessarily genuinely interested in the European integration process as such.
They shy away from the fact-finding, descriptive, explorative research or
research with inductive methodologies designed to gather information about
the integration process. By contrast, one can criticize the European approach
for being overly inward-looking or for reinventing the wheel. One sometimes
wonders to what extent the new approach is really all that new or significantly
different from what more general approaches offer. Furthermore, it is often
unclear how these theoretical approaches can be falsified or tested, as it is not
clear that they could apply to other cases. In fact, the authors of these
approaches often state that it is not their intention or ambition that their
theories be generalizable beyond the scope of the EU.
So why would authors stick to one or the other trend? Sometimes it appears
that scholars are merely signalling to one another to what body of literature
they belong rather than fully engaging with one another in a scholarly debate.
The process that seems to be going on is one in which debates are happening
in distinct academic territories. This behaviour can be found in the way the
research problem is identified, the literature to which one wants to make a
88
Journal of European Public Policy
contribution, the academic references cited, and the theoretical and methodological approaches chosen. It may be that this territorial divide is logical if one
takes into consideration the academic criteria in both Europe and North
America. In Europe it is broadly felt that one needs to contribute to the overall
literature, and preferably find a label/approach that will be associated with
one’s name, thus contributing to one’s fame in the field. In North America
one’s reputation depends on how well known one is in the general field study,
e.g. political science. In North America the field journals are typically rated
lower than general journals (i.e. American Political Science Review is considered
to be a ‘higher ranked’ journal than International Organization). More importantly, contributing to regional studies is considered even of less scholarly value
than contributing to a general field journal (i.e. a publication in IO is
considered to be of higher scholarly value than a publication in a regional
journal, such as Journal of Common Market Studies).
The divide in European integration studies seems to have also been taking
place in the area of IPE. Scholars in this field study the processes that lie in
the broad intersection of international politics and economics. IPE deals
with questions such as why actors (states, sub-state actors and international
institutions) collaborate. Research questions include regional integration, financial market integration, regulation (deregulation and re-regulation), transfer
of sovereignty, multilateralism and so on. We shall argue below that IPE offers
a venue for dialogue between those who focus exclusively on the EU and those
who see the EU case to be part of more general phenomena. It is, of course,
not the intention to profess that IPE is the only body of literature that can be
of use to studies of European integration, or that others would be less valuable.
Rather the aim is to address how we can make sure that the various approaches
continue to have a dialogue together. IPE is seen as ‘one’ route to get there.
Let us now turn to a brief introduction of that literature.4
THE FIELD OF IPE
The IPE literature has typically been composed of work by authors at the
crossroads of international politics and international economics, and as such
the field contributed importantly to the understanding of the integration
process (Lawton et al. 2000). Throughout the early post-war period IPE had
not yet been developed as a field of study of political science, but was occupied
by scholars in the economics discipline. With the increasing quantification of
the economics discipline and the increasing use of mathematics and formal
models in that discipline, the study of the intersection of international politics
and economics slowly became abandoned by economists and increasingly
occupied by political scientists. They included in particular scholars who
studied the realm of international trade, finance and regional economic cooperation. Among the early scholarly work we find Baldwin (1971), Cooper
(1968), Kindleberger (1970), Keohane and Nye (1972) and Strange (1970,
1971, 1972).5 IPE continued to grow particularly as the world experienced
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
89
global recession and hyperinflation in the 1970s, the debt crisis, and increasing
international interdependence. Before the word ‘globalization’ had gained
popularity, IPE scholars were already studying the effects of increasing interconnectedness of international economics and politics (Gilpin 1987). Topics that
remained of interest to IPE scholars were in particular international finance,
monetary policy, exchange rate policy, trade, economic co-operation, regional
economic integration and so on.
In the 1980s IPE became more attractive as a field owing to the eagerness
of scholars to understand prominent processes in the international domain:
the debt crises, increasing interdependence, policy learning, and slowly but
surely regional integration, and changes in policy-making signalled, for
example, by the prominence of neoliberal politics and its accompanying
processes of liberalization, deregulation and financial market integration. The
growth of financial markets was another important characteristic that had
taken off in the 1970s and continued to influence world politics throughout
the 1980s and beyond. In the 1990s, after the end of the Cold War and with
the rise of ‘globalization’, IPE obtained yet more popularity amongst political
scientists. The concept of globalization emerged even though it is often argued
that the world may not be quite as globalized as it was in the late nineteenth
and early twentieth centuries. Though the concept is often not carefully
defined, it is generally accepted that it includes three things: (1) internationalization, (2) the information and technological revolution, and (3) liberalization.
States, markets and non-state actors reacted to these phenomena in a number
of ways. Increasingly, national governments have been moving towards further
opening up of their economies to selected other countries and markets, while
at the same time not wanting to open up completely. The easiest way to open
up while protecting is by creating an institutional framework which includes
some states and/or markets, but excludes others. Non-state actors, such as large
corporations, have also gained importance in recent years. They too have been
keen to have an institutional framework of this nature (see Cowles 1995; this
issue). IPE deals with these topics, and the European integration process is a
typical example of a response to these challenges posed by globalization and
financial market integration. But before IPE started to take off in European
integration studies it was the field of IR that made the first major contribution
to the theorizing about the European integration process.
As is well known, IR theories, developed by scholars in the United States,
lay at the heart of the two most widely cited traditional integration theories:
neofunctionalism (Haas 1958, 1964, 1968) and intergovernmentalism
(Hoffmann 1966). Neofunctionalism tried to offer an alternative to the realist
school of thought. It saw the European integration process as a direct response
to functional needs of states. It also foresaw that domestic, transnational and
supranational actors would engage in regional integration to improve their
efficiency in governance given their relative close proximity and the various
possibilities for collaboration. In studying the European integration process, it
had in mind comparisons with other parts of the world. Ernst Haas’s
90
Journal of European Public Policy
neofunctionalist approach was soon challenged by Stanley Hoffmann’s intergovernmentalism. This approach, in contrast to neofunctionalism, belonged to
the realist school. It argued that the European integration process could only
be understood if one examined the interests and power positions of various
national state leaders and their interests. The obstructive behaviour of the
French President Charles de Gaulle in particular lay at the basis of Hoffmann’s
work. Another theoretical approach promoted in this period was an approach
developed by Karl Deutsch. He examined groups of élites, and the communication amongst them (Deutsch et al. 1957, 1967). Deutsch’s approach did not
attract the attention that neofunctionalism and intergovernmentalism did.
However, it has been argued that constructivism, which gained popularity
from the 1980s onwards, in fact follows in the footsteps of Deutsch. The two
dominant integration theories lost their appeal in the 1970s (Haas 1975, 1976;
Webb 1983).
In their overview of IPE literature since the 1950s Katzenstein et al. (1998)
argue that European integration theory was strongly influenced by American
scholars until the early 1980s. Since then American scholars have been less
inclined to create their own general theories of European integration based on
their own research, but rather have relied on the empirical work conducted by
the Europeans (Katzenstein et al. 1998: 655). Though fewer in number,
contributions to the European integration literature by American scholars have
been quite prominent, such as Moravcsik (1998), Pierson (1996), Tsebelis
(1994). Numerous publications, in fact, have come out in the IPE flagship
journal International Organization (inter alia Moravcsik 1991; Pollack 1997;
Sandholtz 1993). Since the early 1990s, both European and American scholars
have published scholarly pieces on European integration that have adopted
theoretical approaches which borrowed concepts and insights from comparative
politics, public policy, but also from IPE.
Four schools of thought in IPE
Although IPE scholars have traditionally been subdivided into three schools,
liberalism, mercantilism and Marxism (Woods 2001), this article will focus on
the schools of thought (and divisions amongst them) that have become more
dominant in the past decade. Based on the ongoing debates in the IPE
journals, such as International Organization, one could say that it is fairly
common to subdivide the IPE approaches into four categories: neorealism,
neoliberal institutionalism, social constructivism and the critical approaches.
Neorealism
The neorealist approaches are among the IPE approaches that take the state
as the dominant actor in determining the outcome of international politics.
The seminal work by Waltz (1979) argues that the international system can
only be understood by looking at the actions of states. They act in their own
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
91
self-interest, and try to maximize their interests based on fixed ex ante
preferences. The outside world is perceived as being in a state of chaos in
which anarchy prevails. At times a major player can impose order on this
chaos. But that state will only do so when it is in the interest of that major
player. The original work by Waltz did not allow for any role for domestic
politics or international organizations. However, in reply to its critics neorealism opened up to the possibility of domestic forces possibly affecting state
preferences and perceived interests (Keohane 1986). Yet, for the outcome of
international bargaining and co-operation the locus of attention remained the
state. Realist approaches have found their way into the study of the EU,
especially in explaining the behaviour of inter-state bargaining (Garrett 1993;
Grieco 1995).
Neoliberal institutionalism
The neoliberal institutionalist approaches accept that states are the primary
actors in the world and thus that neorealism ‘provides a good starting point
for the analysis of co-operation and discord [in the international system]’
(Keohane 1984: 245). However, in addition one should recognize that institutions can have an effect of their own. Institutions are defined by Keohane as
‘sets of practices and expectations’. They can facilitate inter-state agreements
and enable states to pursue their own interests through co-operation (Keohane
1984: 246). More recent institutionalist approaches have emphasized a larger
role for institutions. They have emphasized the importance of path dependence,
socialization and policy learning (Hall and Taylor 1994). Institutions, in this
more recent view, set the path for the development of policies, rules and
procedures. By having this historic precedent and standard operating procedures, the policy-making process is influenced. Sometimes emphasis is placed
on the fact that international institutions can be more effective in imposing
rules and regulations. Thus nation-states will be inclined to follow those rules
and regulations more frequently, consistently and without clear direct links to
self-interest, than realist accounts would lead us to believe. In recent years
institutionalism has been frequently adopted in studies of European integration
(inter alia Bulmer 1994a, 1994b; Pierson 1996).
Social constructivism
Since the second half of the 1990s the social constructivist school has gained
much terrain and has appeared to be a ‘new’ school of thought. However, as
always with so-called ‘novelties’, the approach had been around for quite some
time. Already in the 1960s Berger and Luckmann (1966) outlined their social
constructivist approach. They identified three core assumptions. The first
concerns the nature of the individual. He/she is taken to be a social creature
who creates and institutionalizes new knowledge about ‘reality’ and finds his/
her personal identity based on social processes. The second assumption is that
92
Journal of European Public Policy
our observation of ‘reality’ may be an artefact, as it is coloured by whoever
observes or interprets it. The third concerns how social scientists study social
action. They are involved in the process, and hence their action and previous
socialization colour their findings. Social constructivism was made more
prominent in IPE literature through the work of Ruggie (1975, 1998) and
others (inter alia Checkel 1998, 1999; Finnemore 1996; Risse 2000). More
recently European integration scholars have adopted the social constructivist
approach in their studies (Christiansen et al. 1999; Diez 1997; Marcussen
2000).
Critical approaches
There is not one uniform school of thought that encompasses the so-called
‘critical approaches’. Often reference is made to a number of them, such as
various forms of Marxism, the British critical school (Palan 1992), the
Amsterdam school (Van der Pijl 1998), the neo-Gramscians (Cox 1981,
1983, 1995), but also various forms of post-materialists, such as reflectivists
(Jørgensen 1997) and post-structuralists (Walker 1989). These approaches
all have in common that they criticize the traditional approaches of IPE and
IR. They argue that the traditional schools focus too much on the state and
fail to understand how the underlying structure divides power and wealth.
They are critical in that they see the status quo as benefiting the rich and
the already well-off. Moreover, they argue that the international structure
widens the gap between the ‘haves’ and the ‘have-nots’. These approaches
not only criticize the traditional approaches for their normative values and
their objects of study, they also criticize the academic method of rationalism
and causal models with hypotheses testing. They share with the social constructivists the assumption that there is no clear ‘reality out there’ but that
this world is to be interpreted, and that the researcher plays an important
role in that process. In recent years some European integration studies have
been inspired by these more critical approaches in their studies. In particular
the work of European scholars has been more open to these approaches
(inter alia Van Apeldoorn 2002).
These four approaches have in common that they focus on the questions
regarding the role of the state and the interaction between the state and the
system. The neorealists place most emphasis on the state. The neoliberal
institutionalists add to that the importance of institutions, as either rules and
regimes or more formal organizations. The social constructivists add to these
elements the fact that the actors (states, policy-makers, social scientists) are all
influenced and formed by their culture, education, socialization and identity,
and thus these will influence the role they play in this interplay between
states, institutions and the system. The critical schools underline that those
interactions are not value free, and that the outcome ought to be taken into
consideration when politics are made, and are studied.
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
93
IPE AND EUROPEAN INTEGRATION STUDIES
IPE approaches were a welcome addition to IR approaches. The latter typically
focused on foreign policies and on the policies of states vis-à-vis other states.
IPE offered to look at economic interactions between states which opened
up the ‘states’ and included many more actors and factors, in particular
the transnational and domestic actors (state and non-state actors). European
integration theories have built on the original two integration theories
in a number of ways, and in so doing have taken on important IPE
characteristics.
As mentioned above, intergovernmentalists were originally pure realists.
However, the most recent intergovernmental approach to European integration,
by Andrew Moravcsik, gradually took on a more liberal perspective on the
integration process. It incorporates the role of domestic interest groups in
helping to define national state preferences. Economic factors are taken very
seriously. However, even though the incorporation of domestic politics in this
approach is a real innovation compared to the traditional approach, the
approach still stresses that the states have ultimate influence over the process.
The effects on the process of the actions of institutions, supranational actors
and the like are dismissed (Moravcsik 1998). This approach is very useful in
studying treaty negotiations and intergovernmental bargaining as well as
examining the state preferences of EU member states. It offers scholars
conceptual tools to analyse the state-specific characteristics and interests as well
as the power-play that goes on among them.
The observation that EU member states have no longer felt the need to
protect sovereignty at all cost has puzzled many neorealists, and in turn has
given more ammunition to studies of institutionalism. Institutionalisms in all
kinds of guises have been used to explain why states give up their sovereignty
or ‘pool their sovereignty’ (Keohane and Hoffmann 1991). Regimes, sets of
rules and formal organizations are able to offer services to states that they in
turn would be unable to safeguard by merely focusing on national state
preferences. Neofunctionalism has some similarities with neoliberal institutionalism, focuses on the degree of ‘order’ in society. It hypothesizes under what
conditions societal actors, the state and the supranational actors would transfer
their loyalties to the supranational level. It theorizes about inter-state cooperation from a functional perspective. Thus it hypothesizes the transfer of
sovereignty on the basis of policy-making efficiency and effectiveness. In recent
years the study of the EU by those who are broadly favourable to the claims
of neofunctionalism increased dramatically (Burley and Mattli 1993; Stone
Sweet and Sandholtz 1997, 1998; Tranholm-Mikkelsen 1991). Various authors,
in a number of different ways, have each given persuasive accounts of the
European integration process by adopting an historical institutionalist approach
(inter alia Bulmer 1994a, 1994b; Pierson 1996; Wincott 1995). These
approaches are able to examine the European integration process that continues
to go on outside the grand bargaining and the intergovernmental conferences
94
Journal of European Public Policy
(see in this context also the multi-level governance approaches, Hooghe and
Marks 2001; Marks et al. 19966). It offers conceptual tools to examine the
role of institutions, be they actual organizations, a regime or a set of rules.
The concept of path-dependence offers us insights into how some processes
are influenced by decisions made in the past. It offers us an approach that is
suitable for examining the ongoing policy-making process, and the role of
supranational institutions in this process.
Social constructivists have further refined their object of study. They argue
that the integration process falls prey to the visions and images that the
politicians, policy-makers, but also social scientists have in mind. They also
argue that the role of socialization, knowledge and perceived reality is helping
to create the Europe of tomorrow. More recently scholars with this inclination
have been arguing forcefully against some of the assumptions of rationalist
approaches, in particular those of intergovernmentalism, arguing that much
socialization and preference formation occur in between the moments of
intergovernmental bargaining. In this view the bureaucratic politics and
interdepartmental politics (for example, competition between various Directorate Generals within the Commission) are as important as the grand bargains
that take place at Intergovernmental Conferences or at European Summits
(Christiansen et al. 2002). These approaches offer conceptual tools to examine
the process behind the process; that is, the subtleties within institutions,
member states, and the policy-making process. It questions the capacity of
the state-centric and institutionalist approaches to identify unambiguous
preferences, interests, policies and so on. These approaches are inclined to
consider more factors that aim at describing the process. In so doing, they
want to keep open the option that ideas, culture, language, personalities, subentities may be of crucial importance, thus leading to different variables (often
many variables) as being important.
The critical school argues that the integration process has become too much
focused on economic integration within the context of a neoliberal regime. It
also argues that the kind of integration created in Europe benefits the already
well-off. Critical approaches aim at correcting the imbalance. They also work at
conceptualizing how a fair and just Europe can be created. Critical approaches
are concerned that the European integration process will weaken state–society
relations. Numerous neo-Gramscian perspectives question the underlying hegemonic nature of the European integration project (Bieler and Morton 2001;
Van Apeldoorn et al. 2002). Finally, they call for the strengthening of democratic
processes in the EU and increasing the accountability, transparency and legitimacy of EU governance. These approaches are in many ways in opposition to
the ‘mainstream’ approaches. They question the rationality of market forces and
the ‘choice’ that it assumes. Instead they develop concepts that can assist the
analysis of how the integration process may be influenced by power relations
that have been built up in the course of the integration process.
Most of these IPE approaches, especially those applied to the EU, have also
managed to incorporate domestic factors, something for which the field of IR
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
95
has been strongly criticized (Hix 1994; Jupille and Caporaso 1999; Kassim
1994). IPE has for that matter been able to overcome the problems that
critiques have identified with ‘pure’ IR approaches. Each of these approaches
offers analytical tools and plausible suggestions (indeed sometimes hypotheses)
that social scientists interested in the integration process can reflect on. The
strengths and weaknesses of these approaches are quite different from one
another. But each of these approaches offers tools and concepts that are
generalizable within the context of the broader IPE approaches, and as such
offer a possible entry point for general discussion.
So what would be the benefit of adopting IPE approaches in European integration? First, IPE offers a range of diverse theoretical frameworks, which in
turn facilitate an implicit or explicit comparison of the European integration
process with other processes. Hence it offers tools for broader theorization.
Second, IPE is sensitive to insights from various fields, such as comparative
politics, IR, public policy literature and so on. As such it caters to the European
approach, in that it is sufficiently open to the specificity of the European integration process; the specificity or uniqueness of the European integration process
can be analysed and discussed with IPE approaches. To advocate IPE as a venue
for debate is to aim at finding a middle ground where the debate can take place.
In recent years there have been claims that IR would no longer be useful for
explaining European integration (Jachtenfuchs 2001: 259). What we argue here,
however, is that IPE would offer a suitable body of literature to explain European
integration. In another contribution to the literature there has been a move away
from the diversity set out above. It is not very useful that the debate in the
literature has moved to one on the dichotomy between the so-called ‘rationalists’
and the ‘constructivists’ (Pollack 2001) or the ‘rationalists’ versus the ‘reflectivists’ (Smith 2001). Pollack argues that rationalists broadly speaking hold the
same rationalist assumptions about research design:
I would argue that liberal intergovernmentalism, rational-choice institutionalist analyses and even Grieco’s purportedly neorealist voice opportunities
hypothesis are all part of an emerging rationalist research programme
which is rapidly establishing itself as the dominant paradigm in European
integration theory, at least in the United States.
(Pollack 2001: 233)
This debate obscures the fact that there are cultural differences, and fundamentally territorial divides about the theoretical culture and body of literature one
wants to belong to. The rules of the game in academia on both sides of the
Atlantic seem to differ, and this split does not benefit the genuine exchange of
ideas. But what that dichotomy also does not emphasize is the degree to which
some approaches do not reflect on the case of the EU/European integration
process to be informing the literature within a broader framework rather than
on the EU/European integration process alone. As we have seen in the review
of the IPE literature above, the constructivists are as legitimate an IPE approach
as are the rationalist approaches. What we want to argue here is that the case
96
Journal of European Public Policy
of the EU is just one among many cases. We argue here that IPE offers a good
body of literature for examining the integration process exactly because of its
openness to rationalist and constructivist approaches, its general interest in the
very thing that the integration process often deals with, i.e. international
economic co-operation.
CONCLUSION: BRIDGING THE GAP
This article has argued that ‘American’ and ‘European’ scholarship on the EU
and the European integration process is divided. It is argued that there is a
split between the cultures of scholarship on both sides of the Atlantic. Indeed,
a comparison could be made between the behaviour of scholars and that of
dogs peeing to demarcate their territory. The European approach has been
increasingly moving away from general theories and has been more inwardfocusing, thereby only seeing the case of Europe as the one that is interesting
to study because of its inherent characteristics. In order to appear on the radar
of the more general political scientists as well as American scholars with an
interest in EU studies, these approaches need to be more outward looking and
consider how their theories can be applicable to cases other than that of
Europe. The American approach by contrast has been moving toward less case
specificity in favour of contributing to the more general literature in political
science. The article is also critical of the American approach that is overly
preoccupied with theory and with making a contribution to the general
political science literature and in doing so fails to appreciate the specificities
of the case of Europe. The article suggests that an IPE approach will enable
American scholars to do justice to the uniqueness of the European integration
process while at the same time allow them to focus on more general theorization. Overall, the article argues that IPE as a field offers useful analytical and
theoretical tools for EU/European integration studies to become more visible
in the eyes of the generalists, while still respecting the diversity of theoretical
approaches that exist on both sides of the Atlantic.
The benefits of using IPE approaches in European integration studies are
threefold. First, IPE approaches focus the research design on seeing the EU/
European integration process as one case in the broader study of regional integration. They thereby transcend the sui generis or Nó1 debate. Second, IPE
approaches as applied to the EU have responded to the critics from comparative
politics and public policy in that their focus is on many more actors than on
states alone. IPE approaches allow for the study of both state and non-state actors
(domestic, transnational, supranational and international actors). Third, the
kinds of debate going on in the European integration literature are also present
in the IPE literature. These are the ones referred to above, i.e. rationalists versus
constructivists/reflectivists, but also the issue of generalizability and falsifiability
of theoretical approaches. The advantage of using IPE approaches is that it
continues to strive to place these debates within a broader framework, and not
only focus on the case of EU/European integration. It also means that similar
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
97
theoretical discussions regarding other areas of study can have their influence on
the debates taking place about the study of EU/European integration.
In conclusion, though it may be natural to be signalling to what body of
literature and what academic community one belongs, it would be beneficial
if the transatlantic debate remains lively. Let us hope that in the years to come
the two approaches will come closer together. This article has suggested that
IPE could offer a useful bridge across the emerging divide.
Address for correspondence: Amy Verdun, Department of Political Science,
University of Victoria, PO Box 3050, Victoria, BC, V8W 3P5, Canada. Tel:
ò1 250 721 7491/7486. Fax: ò1 250 721 7485. email:
[email protected]
NOTES
1 The author wishes to thank James A. Caporaso, Rachel Cichowski, Christine
Ingebritsen, Maria Green Cowles, Markus Jachtenfuchs, Erik Jones, John Keeler,
Mark Pollack, Mark Thatcher, Michael Webb and two anonymous referees for
comments, criticisms and suggestions on earlier versions of this article. The usual
disclaimer applies. The author wishes to acknowledge financial support from the
Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (Grant: 410-19990081).
2 This article reflects on how European integration studies contribute to the political
science literature, even though academic scholarship in the area of European studies
can and does contribute to interdisciplinary knowledge and thus will also contribute
to other disciplines such as law, economics, public administration, environmental
studies and so on.
3 An example of this inverse advocacy could be seen in action at a conference cosponsored by UACES and the Central European University held in Budapest in
April 2000. John Peterson (an American national) and Simon Hix (a British
citizen) were each advocating the virtues of respectively ‘European’ and ‘American’
approaches. At some point it was so amusing to see them profess the benefits of the
‘other’ approach that the Chair of that panel, Helen Wallace, jokingly suggested
that they should switch passports.
4 New journals have also been set up to try to bridge the gap. For example, the
journal European Union Politics was founded with the almost exclusive aim of
becoming a regional journal that will be taken seriously by mainstream American
political science. Thus it seeks to include pieces that discuss research on European
politics and adopt methodologies and theoretical approaches from mainstream
American political science.
5 It is generally argued that IPE is a subfield of IR – scholars such as Strange argued
that this statement should be reversed (see, for example, Strange 1988).
6 Note that multi-level governance approaches have much in common with these
institutionalist approaches. It is the view of this author that they can also be
considered IPE approaches in so far as they are aiming at a more generalizable
knowledge claim.
REFERENCES
Baldwin, D. (1971) ‘Money and power’, Journal of Politics 33: 578–614.
Berger, P.L. and Luckmann, T. (1966) The Social Constructivism of Reality – A Treatise
in the Sociology of Knowledge, London: Penguin Books.
98
Journal of European Public Policy
Bieler, A. and Morton, A.D. (eds) (2001) Social Forces in the Making of the New
Europe: The Restructuring of European Social Relations in the Global Political Economy,
London: Palgrave.
Börzel, T. and Risse, T. (2002) ‘Die Wirk ung internationaler Institutionen: Von der
Normanerkennung zur Normeinhaltung’ in M. Jachtenfuchs and M. Knodt (eds),
Regieren in internationalen Institutionen, Opladen: Leske & Budrich, pp. 141–81.
Bulmer, S. (1994a) ‘Institutions and policy change in the European Communities: the
case of merger control’, Public Administration 72(3): 423–44.
Bulmer, S. (1994b) ‘The governance of the European Union: a new institutionalist
approach’, Journal of Public Policy 13(4): 351–80.
Bulmer, S. (1997) ‘New institutionalism, the Single Market and EU governance’,
Arena Working Papers 97/25, Oslo: ARENA.
Burley, A.-M. and Mattli, W. (1993) ‘Europe before the Court: a political theory of
legal integration’, International Organization 47: 41–76.
Caporaso, J.A., Marks, G., Moravcsik, A. and Pollack, M.A. (1997) ‘Does the
European Union represent an n of 1?’, ECSA Review 10(3): 1–5.
Checkel, J. (1998) ‘The constructivist turn in international relations theory’, World
Politics 50(2): 324–48.
Checkel, J. (1999) ‘Social construction and integration’, Journal of European Public
Policy 6(4): 545–60.
Christiansen, T., Falkner, G. and Jørgensen, K.E. (2002) ‘Theorizing EU treaty reform:
beyond diplomacy and bargaining’, Journal of European Public Policy 9(1): 12–32.
Christiansen, T., Jørgensen, K.E. and Wiener, A. (eds) (1999) ‘The social construction
of Europe’, Journal of European Public Policy 6(4): special issue.
Cohen, B.J. (1998) The Geography of Money, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Cooper, R.N. (1968) The Economics of Interdependence, New York: Columbia University
Press (reprinted 1980).
Cowles, M.G. (1995) ‘Setting the agenda for a new Europe: the ERT and EC 1992’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 33(4): 501–26.
Cox, R. (1981) ‘Social forces, states and world orders’, Millennium 10: 126–55.
Cox, R. (1983) ‘Gramsci, hegemony and international relations: an essay in method’,
Millennium 12: 162–75.
Cox, R. (1995) ‘Critical political economy’, in B. Hettne (ed.), International Political
Economy: Understanding Global Disorder, Halifax: Fernwood Books, pp. 31–45.
Deutsch, K.W., Burrell, S.A., Kann, R.A., Lee, M. Jr., Lichterman, M., Lindgren,
L.E., Loewenheim, F.L. and Van Wagenen, R.W. (1957) Political Community and
the North Atlantic Area: International Organization in the Light of Historical
Experience, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Deutsch, K.W., Edinger, L.J. and Macridis, R.C. (1967) Study of Elite Attitudes on
European Integration and World Politics, New York: Charles Scribner & Sons.
Diez, T. (1997) ‘International ethics and European integration: federal state or network
horizon?’, Alternatives 22: 287–312.
Finnemore, M. (1996) National Interests in International Society, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Garrett, G. (1993) ‘The politics of Maastricht’, Economics and Politics 5(2): 105–25.
Gilpin, R. (1987) The Political Economy of International Relations, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Grieco, J.M. (1995) ‘The Maastricht Treaty, economic and monetary union and neorealist research programme’, Review of International Studies 21: 21–40.
Haas, E.B. (1958 and 1968) The Uniting of Europe, 1st and 2nd edn, London: Stevens
(1st edn); Stanford: Stanford University Press (2nd edn).
Haas, E.B. (1964) Beyond the Nation State. Political, Social, and Economic Forces 1950–
1957, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
99
Haas, E.B. (1975) The Obsolescence of Regional Integration Theory, Research Studies,
25, Institute of International Studies, Berkeley, California.
Haas, E.B. (1976) ‘Turbulent fields and the theory of regional integration’, International
Organization 30(2): 173–212.
Hall, P.A. and Taylor, R. (1994) ‘Political science and the three new institutionalisms’,
Political Studies 44: 936–57.
Hix, S. (1994) ‘The study of the European Community: the challenge to comparative
politics’, West European Politics 17(1): 1–30.
Hix, S. (2002) ‘Parliamentary behavior with two principals: preferences, parties, and
voting in the European Parliament’, American Journal of Political Science 46(3):
688–98.
Hoffmann, S. (1966) ‘Obstinate or obsolete? The fate of the nation-state and the case
of Western Europe’, Daedalus 95(3): 862–916.
Hooghe, L. and Marks, G. (2001) Multi-Level Governance and European Integration,
Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.
Ingebritsen, C. (1998) Nordic States and European Unity, Ithaca: Cornell University
Press.
Jachtenfuchs, M. (2001) ‘The governance approach to European integration’, Journal
of Common Market Studies 39(2): 245–64.
Jørgensen, K.E. (ed.) (1997) Reflectivist Approaches to European Governance, London:
Macmillan.
Jupille, J. and Caporaso, J.A. (1999) ‘Institutionalism and the European Union:
beyond international relations and comparative politics’, Annual Review of Political
Science 2: 429–44.
Kassim, H. (1994) ‘Policy networks, networks and EU policy making: a sceptical
view’, West European Politics 17(4): 15–27.
Katzenstein, P.J., Keohane, R.O. and Krasner, S.D. (1998) ‘International organization
and the study of world politics’, International Organization 52(4): 645–85.
Keohane, R.O. (1984) After Hegemony: Co-operation and Discord in the World Political
Economy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Keohane, R.O. (ed.) (1986) Neorealism and its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press.
Keohane, R.O. and Hoffmann, S. (1991) ‘Institutional change in Europe in the
1980s’, in R.O. Keohane and S. Hoffmann (eds), The New European Community:
Decisionmaking and Institutional Change, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 1–39.
Keohane, R.O. and Nye, J. (eds) (1972) Transnational Relations and World Politics,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kindleberger, C. (1970) Power and Money: The Economics of International Politics and
the Politics of International Economics, New York: Basic Books.
Knill, C. and Lenschow, A. (2001) ‘ ‘‘Seek and ye shall find!’’ Linking perspectives on
institutional change’, Comparative Political Studies 34(2): 187–215.
Kohler-Koch, B. (1997) ‘The European Union facing enlargement: still a system
sui generis?’, Working Paper, No. 20, Mannheimer Zentrum für Europäische
Sozialforschung, Arbeitsbereich III, ISSN 0948–0099.
Lawton, T.C., Rosenau, J.N. and Verdun, A.C. (2000) ‘Introduction: Looking beyond
the confines’, in T.C. Lawton, J.N. Rosenau and A.C. Verdun (eds), Strange Power:
Shaping the Parameters of International Relations and International Political Economy,
Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 3–18.
McNamara, K. (1998) The Currency of Ideas: Monetary Politics in the European Union,
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Majone, G. (1997) ‘The regulatory state and its legitimacy problems’, West European
Politics 22(1): 1–24.
Majone, G. (2001a) ‘Nonmajoritarian institutions and the limits of democratic
100
Journal of European Public Policy
governance: a political transaction-cost approach’, Journal of Institutional and
Theoretical Economics 157: 57–78.
Majone, G. (2001b) ‘Two logics of delegation: agency and fiduciary relations in EU
governance’, European Union Politics 2(1): 103–21.
Marcussen, M. (2000) Ideas and Elites: The Social Construction of Economic and
Monetary Union, Aalborg: Aalborg University Press.
Marks, G., Hooghe, L. and Blank, K. (1996) ‘European integration from the 1980s’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 34(3): 341–78.
Mattli, W. (1999) The Logic of Regional Integration: Europe and Beyond, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Moravcsik, A. (1991) ‘Negotiating the Single European Act. National interests and
conventional statecraft in the European Community’, International Organization
45(1): 651–88.
Moravcsik, A. (1998) The Choice for Europe, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Palan, R. (1992) ‘The second structuralist theories of international relations: a research
note’, International Studies Notes 17(3): 22–9.
Peterson, J. (2001) ‘The choice for EU theorists: establishing a common framework
for analysis’, European Journal of Political Research 39(3): 289–318.
Pierson, P. (1996) ‘The path to European integration: a historical institutionalist
approach’, Comparative Political Studies 29(2): 123–63.
Pollack, M.A. (1997) ‘Delegation, agency, and agenda setting in the European
Community’, International Organization 51: 99–134.
Pollack, M.A. (2001) ‘International relations theory and European integration’, Journal
of Common Market Studies 39(2): 245–64.
Risse, T. (2000) ‘Let’s argue: communicative action in world politics’, International
Organization 54(1): 1–40.
Ruggie, J.G. (1975) ‘International responses to technology: concepts and trends’,
International Organization 29: 557–84.
Ruggie, J.G. (1998) Constructing the World Polity, London: Routledge.
Sandholtz, W. (1993) ‘Choosing union: monetary politics and Maastricht’, International Organization 47(1): 1–39.
Scharpf, F.W. (1997) Games Real Actors Play, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Shaw, J. (1999) ‘Postnational constitutionalism in the European Union’, Journal of
European Public Policy 6(4): 579–97.
Smith, S. (2001) ‘Reflectivist and constructivist approaches to international theory’,
in J. Baylis and S. Smith (eds), The Globalization of World Politics. An Introduction
to International Relations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 224–49.
Stone Sweet, A. and Sandholtz, W. (1997) ‘European integration and supranational
governance’, Journal of European Public Policy 4(3): 297–317.
Stone Sweet, A. and Sandholtz, W. (eds) (1998) European Integration and Supranational
Governance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Strange, S. (1970) ‘International economics and international relations: a case of
mutual neglect’, International Affairs 46(2): 304–15.
Strange, S. (1971) Sterling and British Policy. A Political Study of an International
Currency in Decline, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Strange, S. (1972) ‘International economic relations I: The need for an interdisciplinary
approach’, in R. Morgan (ed.), The Study of International Affairs: Essays in Honour
of Kenneth Younger, London: RIIA/Oxford University Press.
Strange, S. (1988) States and Markets: An Introduction to International Political Economy,
London: Francies Pinter.
Tranholm-Mikkelsen, J. (1991) ‘Neofunctionalism: obstinate or obsolete? A reappraisal
in the light of the new dynamism of the European Community’, Millennium 20:
1–22.
A. Verdun: Bridging the gap with IPE
101
Tsebelis, G. (1994) ‘The power of the European Parliament as a conditional agenda
setter’, American Political Science Review 88(1): 128–42.
Van Apeldoorn, B. (2002) Transnational Capital and the Struggle over European
Integration, London: Routledge.
Van Apeldoorn, B., Overbeek, H. and Ryner, M. (2002) ‘Theories of European
integration: a critique’, in A. Cafruny and M. Ryner (eds), The Political Economy
of the European Union: Critical Studies of a Neo-liberal Hegemonic Project, Chapter
1, unpublished manuscript.
Van der Pijl, K. (1998) Transnational Classes and International Relations, London:
Routledge.
Verdun, A. (2002) ‘Merging neofunctionalism and intergovernmentalism: lessons from
EMU’, in A. Verdun (ed.), The Euro: European Integration Theory and Economic
and Monetary Union, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 9–28.
Walker, R.B.J. (1989) ‘History and structure in the theory of IR’, Millennium 18(2):
163–83.
Wallace, W. (1983) ‘Less than a federation, more than a regime: the Community as a
political system’, in H. Wallace, W. Wallace and C. Webb (eds), Policy-Making in
the European Community, 2nd edn, Chichester: Wiley, pp. 403–36.
Waltz, K. (1979) Theory of International Politics, New York: Random House.
Webb, C. (1983) ‘Theoretical perspectives and problems’, in H. Wallace, W. Wallace
and C. Webb (eds), Policy-Making in the European Community, 2nd edn, Chichester:
Wiley, pp. 1–41.
Wincott, D. (1995) ‘The role of law or the rule of the Court of Justice? An
‘‘institutional’’ account of judicial politics in the European Community’, Journal of
European Public Policy 2(4): 583–602.
Woods, N. (2001) ‘International political economy in an age of globalization’, in
J. Baylis and S. Smith (eds), The Globalization of World Politics. An Introduction to
International Relations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 277–98.
This article was downloaded by: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge]
On: 17 January 2009
Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 791963552]
Publisher Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,
37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Journal of European Public Policy
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713685697
Non-state actors and false dichotomies: reviewing IR/IPE approaches to
European integration
Online Publication Date: 01 March 2003
To cite this Article (2003)'Non-state actors and false dichotomies: reviewing IR/IPE approaches to European integration',Journal of
European Public Policy,10:1,102 — 120
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046967
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350176032000046967
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Journal of European Public Policy 10:1 February 2003: 102–120
Non-state actors and false
dichotomies: reviewing IR/IPE
approaches to European integration
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
Maria Green Cowles1
ABSTRACT Many IR and IPE theories marginalize non-state actors in a manner
inconsistent with their role in EU integration, governance, and policy-making. Yet
multinational firms, NGOs, and advocacy networks are increasingly important
players in today’s global economy. This review article examines four theories/
approaches that tend to ignore this development: neorealism, institutionalism,
constructivism, and the critical school. To shed light on the literature’s marginalization of non-state actors, I identify three false dichotomies: (1) the international
versus domestic, (2) the public versus private, and (3) the ‘good’ versus ‘bad’. The
article provides empirical evidence to demonstrate why these dichotomies must be
transcended and discusses theoretical developments that better account for nonstate actors. Finally, I recognize a fourth false dichotomy between the American
IR/IPE theories and the European comparative, political economy, and governance
approaches. Rather than adopting one approach over another, this paper suggests
that both schools of thought can benefit from one another.
KEY WORDS Advocacy networks; constructivism; critical school; dichotomies;
firms; governance; institutionalism; liberal intergovernmentalism.
INTRODUCTION
There is a temptation to argue that the heyday of firms and other nonstate actors in European Union (EU) integration theories and policy-making
occurred during the Single Market years.2 The political role of multinational
firms behind the 1992 program (Cowles 1995; Sandholtz and Zysman 1989;
Van Tulder and Junne 1998) and the subsequent mobilization of other interest
organizations produced a flurry of writing, often in the pluralist vein, on these
non-state actors (Anderson and Eliasson 1993; Coen 1997; Cowles 1996;
Greenwood 1997; Greenwood et al. 1992; Mazey and Richardson 1993).
Scholarly accounts of ‘history-making events’ (Peterson 1995) since the Single
Market Program, however, have not involved these non-state actors to the
same extent. Today, the sole focus of many international relations (IR) and/or
international political economy (IPE) scholars analyzing the EU is on the
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046967
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
103
nation-state. Indeed, if one only looks at the ‘historic decisions’ – the
Maastricht, Amsterdam, and Nice Treaties and the current convention on the
future of Europe – as the summation of European integration since 1992, one
might question the importance of non-state actors in our theoretical and
methodological approaches to the EU today.
As Verdun notes in this issue, IR and IPE theories are crucial to our
understanding of international economic co-operation and the EU integration
process itself. Yet the scope of non-state actors in these IR/IPE theories and
approaches remains somewhat marginalized or, more precisely, ‘ghetto-ized’.
There is a tendency to narrow non-state actors’ functions by limiting their
activity to a single level of governance, by confining certain roles to the realm
of traditional state and institutional actors, by pre-assigning normative labels
to them, and/or by restricting our analysis to certain kinds of policy analysis.
This ghetto-ization of non-state actors is nothing new. The role of the firm,
for example, has been largely under-theorized in IR and IPE theories in general
(Eden 1991; Sally 1995; Strange 1988, 1996). Yet, the increasingly global
economy, the transnationalization of markets (Newman and Bach 2002a), and
the role of the EU as both a promoter of and bulwark against this transnational
and global economy suggest the need to incorporate firms and other non-state
actors more explicitly in our political economy approaches to the EU. Indeed,
while the literature on globalization is vast, one of its common strands is the
recognition that global economic change creates new and different kinds of
alignments of non-state actors around core issues and across borders (Weber
2001: 289).
This article reviews a specific set of IR/IPE literature in terms of its
incorporation of non-state actors given their relatively new and varied roles in
the EU today. There are, of course, many IPE theories and approaches that
focus on state and non-state actors. Examples would include the hegemonic
stability theories surrounding international monetary policy (Krasner 1976),
the classic work beginning with Dunning (1958) on the impact of foreign
direct investment by multinational firms, and the more recent work on
transnationalism (cf. Risse 2002). My focus is on those IR/IPE theories and
approaches discussed by Verdun in her article: neorealism, institutionalism,
social constructivism, and the critical school. Scholars have applied all four
theories and/or approaches – individually or in various pairings – to European
integration and EU studies in recent years.
The purpose of the article is not to suggest that one or more of these
theories/approaches are better than another, or to suggest an alternative
theoretical framework (e.g. transnationalism). Rather, the purpose is to explain
how this literature marginalizes non-state actors in a manner inconsistent with
their roles in EU integration, governance, and policy-making today. I focus
on three false or artificial dichotomies, inherent in one or more of the theories/
approaches, as a mechanism to explore this ‘ghetto-ization’.3 The first is the
international/domestic dichotomy which appears in neorealist accounts. The
second dichotomy is the public vs. private debate, upheld in the rational-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
104
Journal of European Public Policy
choice strand of institutionalism and its off-shoot, principal–agent theory. The
third dichotomy is that of ‘good vs. bad’ found in the constructivist and
critical school approaches
The article concludes with a fourth false or artificial dichotomy – the
debate between IR/IPE approaches versus comparative and public political
economy approaches to the EU. Many of these European governance
approaches (Jachtenfuchs 2001) have made important advances in moving
the study of non-state actors beyond the pluralist discussions of the 1990s.
While one might be tempted to simply set aside the IR/IPE approaches in
favor of the EU governance theories, I argue that such action would be
premature. Indeed, this articles suggests that both schools of thought can
benefit from one another.
NEOREALISM AND THE INTERNATIONAL/DOMESTIC
DICHOTOMY
Realists and neorealists focus their attention on states and their power to
explain international co-operation. Liberal intergovernmentalism, the EU
variant, argues that domestic actors, including non-state actors, inform the
preferences of member states.4 The Putnam model of two-level games, for
example, focuses on the chiefs of government (COGs) or negotiators who
bargain with their foreign counterparts to reach international agreements
(Moravcsik 1993a). The COGs’ ‘win-sets’ – their bargaining margin of
maneuver – are determined by domestic interests alone.
Liberal intergovernmentalism makes a careful distinction between the functions of domestic and transnational interests/social groups. First, transnational
interests can strengthen or undermine domestic support of a chief of government, but, unlike domestic actors, cannot impact the COGs’ bargaining
positions per se (Moravcsik 1993a: 32; 1993b). Second, when domestic
interests are not able to organize themselves effectively, transnational actors
may provide support to ‘supranational entrepreneurs’ who, under certain other
conditions, influence EU history-making events (Moravcsik 1999).
There are, however, two basic problems with this line of reasoning. The
first problem centres on the capacity of non-state actors at the transnational
level. To argue that transnationally organized interests matter only when
domestic interests are disorganized is misleading. To maintain that the only
role these transnational actors can then play is one of supporting supranational
entrepreneurs is simply wrong. Transnationally organized interests, in fact,
may have a greater incentive – and thus work to organize and represent
themselves more effectively than domestic interests to encourage government
co-operation. The supranational governance approach, for example, emphasizes how the firms’ transnational market activity brings about pressures for
governments to co-operate – with or without the participation of supranational entrepreneurs. Firms have an interest in seeking decisions being made
at the supranational (EU) as opposed to the national level (Stone Sweet and
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
105
Sandholtz 1998). Walter Mattli (1999) makes similar arguments and his
political economy approach clearly suggests that the role of firms in EU cooperation and decision-making need not be limited to domestic or meso-level
activity. Firms themselves may be part of the history-making phases of EU
integration.
Indeed, transnationally organized actors will likely figure in the future
development of European security and defense policy (ESDP). Put another
way, one cannot ignore the restructuring of the European defense industry
and the subsequent creation of new transnational actors when assessing the
future of defense co-operation. German DaimlerChrysler Aerospace, French
Aérospatiale Matra, and Spanish CASA created the European Aerospace,
Defense, and Space Company (EADS) – the second largest private aerospace
company in the world. While domestic constituencies like European taxpayers
and lawmakers might influence COGs’ decisions to ‘buy European’, decisions
made by transnational corporate actors ‘may well be the cement which will
make permanent, or irreversible, the watershed decisions on defense integration’
(Collester 2001: 386).
The false domestic vs. international dichotomy
A second related problem with this line of reasoning is the false dichotomy
between national and transnational/international interests. What liberal intergovernmentalism does not address is that consumer groups, environmental
organizations, multinational firms, and transnational advocacy groups can
participate simultaneously in international and domestic politics (Cowles 1995;
Keck and Sikkink 1998). To claim that domestic social groups matter but
transnational interests do not misses the point that, increasingly, these two
groups are one and the same. For example, as domestic regulatory issues such
as beef hormones and genetically modified organisms are placed on the EU
and international negotiating table, domestic consumer groups mobilize at the
European level or even at the transatlantic level, i.e. the Transatlantic Consumers’ Dialogue (Pollack and Shaffer 2001). EU and US businesses with
extensive transatlantic investment meet in the Transatlantic Business Dialogue
(TABD) to develop a ‘transatlantic consensus’ on key regulatory issues. This
transnational consensus is, in effect, the firms’ domestic consensus as well
(Cowles 2001a).
To recognize this false dichotomy means to acknowledge the changing
dynamics of state–society relations. In the first place, interest groups mobilize
at different levels at various times in history. European multinational firms,
for example, did not organize themselves in Brussels until the late 1970s to
early 1980s. Thus, the creation of a group like the European Round Table of
Industrialists (ERT) and its support of the Single Market Program was a
watershed event (Cowles 1994). It is not surprising, therefore, that one finds
no evidence of large corporations influencing ‘history-making events’ prior to
the Single Market Program. Since then, however, companies and other non-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
106
Journal of European Public Policy
state actors have increasingly promoted their interests simultaneously in
national, European, and international arenas.
While liberal intergovernmentalists rightly call on scholars to better specify
the conditions under which non-state actors’ representation matters, liberal
intergovernmentalism in turn would be strengthened if it developed a more
robust understanding of the multiple arenas in which non-state actors participate. This theory must also recognize that non-state actors do more than
articulate their preferences or support supranational entrepreneurs. Increasingly,
these actors set agendas, participate in negotiations, implement and/or have
the authority to make policy in the first place. In other words, one must
recognize the second false dichotomy between public vs. private actors.
INSTITUTIONALISM AND THE PUBLIC/PRIVATE DICHOTOMY
Institutionalism explains why and how formal organizations, regimes, and rules
can facilitate inter-state co-operation and, at times, encourage countries to
pool their sovereignty. The three strands of institutionalism – rational-choice,
sociological, and historical (Steinmo et al. 1992; Hall and Taylor 1996) – have
all been applied to the EU. As discussed later, sociological and historical
institutionalism are often coupled with the constructivist approach in various
EU studies, and have been incorporated into many European governance and
public policy approaches. Rational-choice institutionalism remains more firmly
anchored in the IR theoretical approach, and it is the institutionalist strand
examined here.
Rational-choice institutionalism and its off-shoot, principal–agent theory,
focus on why member states delegate powers to these supranational agents or
institutions. It has been applied, for example, to explain why EU member
states might confer certain powers and programs to the European Commission.5
Principal–agent models generally identify four key functions for which member
states might delegate authority to supranational institutions: (1) to monitor
member state compliance, (2) to solve problems of ‘incomplete contracting’,
(3) to serve as a genuinely independent regulator, and (4) to initiate policy
proposals and set the agenda for the principals (Pollack 1997). Yet nowhere in
this discussion of institutionalism and the delegation of authority is there a
stated role for non-state actors.
However, non-state actors – organized below and/or above the state in
transnational groups or coalitions – also participate in important ways in the
principal–agent model. First, non-state actors, together with institutions, can
influence the calculus of principals to delegate authority, to carry out ‘incomplete contracting’, and to serve as independent regulators. At noted above, the
ERT publicly supported the Commission’s Single Market Program. While the
companies did not influence the Single European Act negotiations per se, they
threatened to move their operations out of Europe if member states did not
support effective institutional changes to carry out the 1992 project (Cowles
1995).
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
107
Second, non-state actors also participate in the shaping of policy proposals
and agendas prior to, during, or even after the delegation of authority has
been conferred. Transnational coalitions and actors have been critical in
shaping proposals and changing policy outcomes in East Asian economic
dynamism, then-Soviet security policy, and African ivory conservationism
(Risse-Kappen 1995). Multinational corporations have mobilized to shape the
international agendas of international institutions such as the World Trade
Organization (WTO), the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO),
and the Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD).
Key firms, for example, influenced the creation of the Trade-Related Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPs) agreement during the Uruguay Round (Sell
1995). Indeed, the TRIPs agreement would probably not have been achieved
without the ‘active agency’ of these companies (Higgott et al. 2000: 8). In
the EU, the ERT led efforts to promote the open method of co-ordination
as part of the Lisbon European Council, and fostered the larger Lisbon goal
of making the EU the most competitive and dynamic knowledge-based
economy in the world (Hodson and Maher 2001; Sisson and Marginson
2001; Wallace 2001).
Third, non-state actors increasingly assume the traditional state or international institution responsibility of monitoring and enforcing international
agreements (Keck and Sikkink 1998). International institutions often lack
adequate monitoring and centralized enforcement mechanisms. Non-state
actors can appeal to international institutions to promote compliance, serve
as ‘watchdogs’ to report non-compliance, form transnational networks, and
create global public campaigns against negligent states (Börzel 2002). The
work of the International Coalition to Ban Landmines did not end with the
awarding of the Nobel Peace Prize. Rather, the non-governmental organization
(NGO) now monitors compliance of the treaty (Florini 2000: 213). These
same actors can go before the courts to demand enforcement. Women’s groups
have done this rather effectively in the United Kingdom as a means to ensure
that EU law is properly carried out and enforced at the national level (Mazey
1998).
Fourth, although not strictly part of the principal–agent theory, non-state
actors can provide legitimacy to the supranational institutions which have
received these powers. In recent years, a number of international institutions
have brought in NGOs and firms to build transnational coalitions around key
agenda items. The World Health Organization has forged partnerships with
both NGOs and companies to promote key global public policies. In the EU
where the issue of legitimacy or the democratic deficit is pronounced, the
Trade Directorate General has engaged in an ambitious civil society program
to shore up support for its own trade agenda (Meunier 2002).6 In short, nonstate actors are now key players in creating global public policy (Reinicke
1998) and in participating in global governance in general (e.g. Clark 1995;
Keck and Sikkink 1998; Price 1998; Ronit and Schneider 1999; Smith et al.
1997).
108
Journal of European Public Policy
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
The false public vs. private dichotomy
As M.J. Peterson pointed out a decade ago, the state – and, for that matter,
international institutions – do not monopolize the public sphere (Peterson
1992). Firms and other non-state actors increasingly ‘do’ what traditional
public actors do. An important contribution of European governance and
public policy theory in recent years is the recognition of the public and private
interaction in EU policy-making (cf. Héritier 1999; Kohler-Koch 1996;
Kohler-Koch and Eising 1999; Kooiman 1993). Yet, many IR institutionalist
and global governance approaches persist in upholding the false dichotomy
between public and private actors who are largely overlooked.7
State delegation of authority, however, is not only conferred on public actors
(i.e. EU institutions), but on private actors as well. The work of Cutler et al.
(1999), for example, challenges traditional IR approaches to explore how
governments confer ‘private authority’ on firms and other non-state actors to
set agendas, address incomplete contracting, monitor compliance, and selfregulate or co-regulate. Sometimes this takes place precisely because states and
public institutions do not have the proper mechanisms to cope with globalization (Cutler et al. 1999: 19). While governments have yet to establish clear
rules on the protection of intellectual property rights on the Internet, for
example, private firms such as IBM are working with other software and
hardware companies to create their own rules and inter-operable standards to
promote digital intellectual property rights worldwide (Spar 1999: 40).
Standards-setting is another area where private actors play an increasingly
important role (Abbott and Snidal 2001; Mattli 2002). Indeed, with the shift
in regulatory policy following the Single Market Program, firms have become
dominant players in the policy-making process (Egan 2001). Private rulemaking is also found in the form of new trading codes – the lex mercatoria
moderna or new merchant law – that provide ‘a set of principles and customary
rules . . . [guiding] economic transactions at the national and transnational
level’ as well as private commercial arbitration to solve disputes (Lehmkuhl
2000; see also Mattli 2001; Stone Sweet 2002). Indeed, private forums for
international commercial dispute resolution are becoming increasingly popular
(Mattli 2001). For example, the Global Business Dialogue on e-commerce
(GBDe), a coalition of e-commerce firms from Europe, the United States,
and Asia, is developing on-line alternative dispute resolution (ADR) mechanisms and trustmark guidelines to obviate or at least lessen the need for
commercial and private consumers to use national courts for redress (Cowles
2001b).
In addition to the lex mercatoria moderna, firms as well as other non-state
actors have been a growing force behind the development of soft law in
international and global governance (Abbott and Snidal 2000). Soft laws are
‘rules of conduct which, in principle, have no legally binding force but which
nevertheless may have practical effect’ (Snyder 1993: 2). Soft law has been
used in EU policy-making in the motor vehicle and state aid policy areas (Cini
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
109
2001). More recently, soft law, along with self-regulation, have been featured
in the White Paper on European governance. The extent to which the White
Paper is ultimately incorporated could revolutionize EU rule-making by
promoting ‘policy-making without legislation’ (Héritier 2001). The result will
be a greater shift from public to private policy-making in key areas such as the
‘new’ or the ‘digital’ economy.
Of course, the recognition that non-state actors are important authoritative,
rule-making actors in global governance does not imply that state actors are
not. Some scholars have expressed concerns, however, that the delegation of
authority to private actors ‘implies a decline in state capacity’ (Kahler and
Lake 2002: 15) or a ‘hollowing out of the state’ (Rhodes 1996: 661). One
could argue that the reality is rather different. The effectiveness of transnational
coalitions, for example, often depends on their access to ‘key targets’ or
international institutions. Whether or not a firm or NGO has access to the
domestic polity and, therefore, the means to create ‘winning coalitions’ may
ultimately determine its success (Cram 2001; Risse-Kappen 1995). Similarly,
the ability of non-state actors to monitor and enforce international agreements
can vary according to the access to state legal systems (Conant 2001). Nonstate actors will likely experience greater success in countries with institutions
that facilitate firm and NGO access to the courts. Of course, the success of
self-regulation may depend on the ‘shadow of the state’ – the threat of state
intervention should self-regulation fail (Lehmkuhl 2000; Newman and Bach
2002b; Scharpf 1997). While firms may develop self-regulatory codes of
conduct in the United States, for example, the Federal Trade Commission will
intervene, enforce, and punish if unfair trade practices occur. Thus, there are
limits to the roles and capacities of firms and other non-state actors. Indeed,
for some scholars, state sovereignty itself sets those very limits (Clark et al.
1998: 33–5).
Yet the recognition of traditional state power and sovereignty in these
scenarios does not relegate non-state actors to some form of subservient
status. While one can readily agree that ‘private governance does not stand
independent of public governance’ (Kahler and Lake 2002), one could also
argue that public governance increasingly does not stand independent of
private governance. Focusing only on the former risks pushing aside and
ghetto-izing the role of non-state actors. In reality, one increasingly finds a
complementary relationship between public and private actors – the existence
of public and private management of international markets, and the development of public and private mechanisms to co-ordinate the global political
economy. Indeed, there is a ‘blurring of public–private spheres’ of action
(Cowles 2001a: 214). Thus, it is not merely an augmentation of public
governance, but a qualitatively different kind of governance.
Higgott et al. suggest that this coexistence of public/private actors signifies
‘a new way of sustaining capitalist accumulation in an era of global structural
change’ (2000). The new relationship between states, firms, and non-state
actors is part and parcel of the current historical phase of political economy
110
Journal of European Public Policy
(cf. Héritier 2002). The challenge remains, therefore, for rational-choice
institutionalism and other IR theories to address this new reality.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
CONSTRUCTIVISM, THE CRITICAL APPROACH, AND THE
‘GOOD’ VS. ‘BAD’ DICHOTOMY
Constructivism is an ontological approach to social inquiry – not a theory per
se – that is relatively new to European integration theory. Applied to the EU,
constructivism provides a rich understanding of the rules and norms in
European governance, political community and identity formation in the
Euro-polity, as well as discourses, communication action and the role of ideas
in European integration (Christiansen et al. 1999).
Touted as a middle ground and not a grand theory, constructivism is based
on two assumptions: ‘(1) the environment in which agents/states take action
is social as well as material; and (2) this setting can provide agents/states with
understandings of their interests (it can ‘‘constitute’’ them)’ (Checkel 1998:
325–6). Constructivism often provides a framework in which one embeds
other IR/IPE theories. Thus, its range includes radical post-modernism to
near-rational choice approaches that take the formation of preferences and the
role of discourse seriously. Constructivism has also been closely interwoven with
the historical and sociological strands of institutionalism, thus distinguishing
between the ‘thin’ vs. ‘thick’ understanding of norms and institutions in social
life (Checkel 2001). Indeed, new institutionalist and constructivist approaches
are sometimes the same.
Constructivist approaches are not without criticism. One is that constructivists sometimes lack a theory of agency. Checkel, for example, argues that early
constructivist approaches (Finnemore 1996; Katzenstein 1996; Klotz 1995)
tended to over-emphasize ‘the role of social structures and norms at the expense
of the agents who help create and change them in the first place’ (1998: 324).
A second criticism is the tendency of early ‘statist’ constructivists to focus
primarily if not solely on the norms and discourses of public actors, institutions,
and élites – thus reinforcing the public vs. private dichotomy discussed above.
In recent years, liberal constructivists have recognized private actors – or at
least certain private actors – in their ontological approach (cf. Keck and
Sikkink 1998). In the EU literature, while some scholars tend to look primarily
at public actors (cf. Christiansen et al. 1999), other constructivists examine
non-state actors as well (cf. Marcussen 1998; Schmidt 2001, 2002; Verdun
1996). The growing literature on EU social movements – while not explicitly
constructivist – is also in this vein (cf. Imig and Tarrow 2001).
The false dichotomy between ‘good’ and ‘bad’
A third criticism of constructivism is its relative weakness in transcending the
false dichotomy between ‘good’ and ‘bad’ in the literature. This dichotomy
exists in two forms: (1) the subject of inquiry (norms, discourses, ideas), and
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
111
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
(2) the demarcation of agents. Referring to the former, Checkel points out
that constructivists need to ‘give equal attention to the bad things in world
[or EU] politics that are socially constructed’ (Checkel 1998). There is a
pattern – though changing – in the literature to only look at the ‘ethically
good norms’.
In terms of agents, however, there appears to be an unwritten rule to give
recognition only to those who are deemed ‘ethically good’. Keck and Sikkink
make this clear in their own work. They distinguish between three different
categories of transnational actors based on their motivations:
(1) those with essentially instrumental goals, especially transnational corporations and banks; (2) those motivated primarily by shared causal ideas, such
as scientific groups or epistemic communities; and (3) those motivated
primarily by shared principled ideas or values (transnational advocacy
networks).
(Keck and Sikkink 1998: 30; italics in the original)
This classification is convenient but hardly encompassing. While multinational
firms may be guided by instrumental goals, they are not devoid of shared
principled ideas or values. Yet traditional constructivist theorists have generally
neglected to theorize and document the role of firms in creating norms.
Indeed, many constructivist scholars are leery of touching IPE in general (cf.
Kirshner 2000). This neglect nonetheless implies that one group (i.e. NGOs
and transnational societal groups) have values and moral authority, whereas
another group (namely firms) do not. Hence, the ‘good’ vs. ‘bad’ dichotomy.
The neo-Gramscian school – also known as the transnational historical
materialism approach in the critical school – brings together both the constructivist and critical elements of IR/IPE theory (Bieler and Morton 2001; Cox
1995; Gill 1993; Jørgensen 1997; Palan 1992; Van Apeldoorn 2002; Van der
Pijl 1998).8 Indeed, neo-Gramscians such as Van Apeldoorn set themselves
apart from the liberal constructivists’ preoccupation with NGOs and societal
groups precisely by focusing on multinational firms and their social construction of norms and discourse. Van Apeldoorn’s ERT study, for example, reveals
how the group’s discourse production shaped EU socio-economic governance
and policy-making in the 1990s (Van Apeldoorn 2002). The critical element
of this approach, relating back to its Marxist roots, is the explicit assertion
that the structure of society, especially in today’s global capitalism, is inherently
biased in favor of capitalist groups such as firms and banks. In Gramsci’s
terms, it is the hegemony of the firms’ discourse production, the firms’ ability
to appeal to others, that further enables capital to dominate to the detriment
of other societal actors (Bieler and Morton 2001).
Whereas neo-Gramscians implicitly refer to firms’ negative impact on society,
other critical school approaches are more explicit. The British critical school,
the normative school (also known as the ‘humane governance school’), and
many post-modernists often emphasize these ‘bad’ non-state actors.
In the end, the inability or unwillingness of constructivists and critical
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
112
Journal of European Public Policy
school approaches to adequately address firms and other state actors respectively
results in this false dichotomy between ‘good’ and ‘bad.’ This false dichotomy
becomes untenable, however, in the face of empirical observations and theoretical developments. For example, not all NGOs and transnational advocacy
networks have moral authority all the time. Norms and practices may be
mutually constitutive (Keck and Sikkink 1998: 35), and sometimes bad
practices harm the norms which one claims to uphold. Greenpeace International, for example, suffered a normative setback in 1995 when the multimillion-dollar group lost sight of its principled ideas, worrying more about the
confiscation of its high-priced ships than its anti-nuclear agenda (Johnson
2000). Similarly, anti-globalization protesters who smash windows and throw
stones at police in the streets of Seattle, Göteborg, and Genoa might do more
harm than good to their cause.
The false dichotomy also becomes more difficult to uphold when one
recognizes that NGOs, transnational advocacy groups, and multinational firms
increasingly work together to develop new discourse, ideas, and norms within
international and EU institutions. Within the EU, for example, BP-Amoco
has been an active participant in the climate change discourse with NGOs and
Commission officials.
The literature on multinational firms and norms outside the critical school
approach is slowly emerging in IR theory (cf. Haufler 2000, 2001; Prakash
2000). Haufler, for example, focuses on firms’ self-regulation, arguing that
these business norms structure ‘the environment within which political action
takes place, thus affecting both the direct participant in a business regime, and
also structuring activity outside of it’ (Haufler 2000: 199–200). Recognizing
that it is methodologically and theoretically possible to examine firms’ social
construction of norms from a liberal perspective – as opposed to solely a
critical one – is important. In the past, theorists could easily pigeon-hole
multinational corporations into the critical school as ‘the bad guys’ of IR
theory. The recent work by Haufler, Prakash and others allows one to avoid
this ghetto-ization of non-state actors in the IR/IPE literature.
A FOURTH DICHOTOMY? IR/IPE VERSUS COMPARATIVE/
POLITICAL ECONOMY APPROACHES
For some scholars, the relevance in reviewing the literature on the role or nonrole of non-state actors in IR/IPE theories/approaches may not be immediately
apparent. A number of scholars, after all, have collapsed many of these false
dichotomies in their treatment of the EU as a polity and in their application
of comparative and political economy approaches (Hix 1994). The growing
work on policy network analysis has added to our understanding of regulatory
policy-making and the meso-level or day-to-day decision-making in the EU
(Börzel 1998; Jordan and Schubert 1992; Kohler-Koch and Eising 1999). The
EU ‘governance’ literature (cf. Jachtenfuchs 2001) has embraced the sociological
and historical strands of institutionalism and developed accounts of EU policy-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
113
making that emphasize the interaction between public and private actors
(Héritier 1999; Kohler-Koch 1996). Armstrong and Bulmer, for example,
convincingly argue that the Single Market Program – and the non-state actors
engaged in it – matter more today than fifteen years ago (1998). Public policy
theorists point out how societal, technological and scientific developments
pose significant new challenges for EU governance that, in turn, necessitate
new public/private dynamics (Kooiman 1993). As Beate Kohler-Koch notes,
given the new actors, new strategies, and multi-levels of governance in the EU
today, different theoretical approaches were needed to take into account the
‘real world’ (Kohler-Koch 1996).
What then is the value of IR/IPE theory and approaches when the
governance, comparative politics, and political economy approaches have
emerged as powerful alternatives, arguably more attune to the realities of EU
integration and policy-making?
In examining the state of both literatures today, three arguments emerge for
revisiting the role of non-state actors in IR/IPE theory and approaches. The
first is that the governance literature tends to limit itself to ‘everyday’ policymaking (Héritier 1999: 13–14; see also Peterson 1995). The explanatory
power for ‘high politics’ or ‘history-making decisions’ such as intergovernmental
conferences is largely deferred to neorealist or liberal intergovernmentalist
theoretical accounts where ‘ ‘‘national preference formation and intergovernmental decisionmaking . . .’’ is strictly observed’ (Héritier 1999: 14). Thus, by
automatically turning to this literature, the false dichotomies of international
vs. domestic, public vs. private continue to be promulgated in the liberal
intergovernmentalism approach.
A second argument for continuing to examine the IR/IPE literature is that
the national experience – and the dominant comparative politics and public
policy approaches that theorize about it – do not always correspond adequately
to the European experience. EU scholars might correctly point out, for
example, that the governments’ willingness to confer private authority on firms
and NGOs to set agendas, monitor compliance, and self-regulate was well
established by neocorporatism in the 1970s (Lehmbruch and Schmitter 1982;
Schmitter 1974), and the related Organization of Business Interests project in
the early 1980s (Streeck and Schmitter 1985). Yet, the make-up of many
European interest groups and their relationship with EU institutions is rather
different than that found in most European capitals. Indeed, the business–
government relationship in Brussels is modelled on a more pluralist AngloSaxon model – not the neocorporatist relationship found in many continental
countries (Coen 1997; Cowles 1996). It is not surprising to find, therefore,
that when discussing self-governance and business associations in EU policymaking today, Knill refers to the ‘private governance’ work of Cutler et al. as
most relevant in explaining these ‘everyday’ developments in Brussels (Knill
2001). Importantly, Knill also notes the contribution of Lehmbruch’s work on
administrative interest intermediation to explain the Commission’s active
support of certain business associations.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
114
Journal of European Public Policy
That scholars such as Knill refer to both the IR/IPE and governance
literatures leads to the third argument. Just as IR/IPE approaches can benefit
from a better understanding of the dynamics behind the comparative politics,
political economy, and public policy approaches to EU studies, so too can this
European literature learn from the evolving IR/IPE literature. After all, one
can discuss the EU as a polity and an international actor, a process of
integration and a policy-making body. Moreover, those who look at the two
sets of literature recognize that there is a growing convergence between the
two. Indeed, the two literatures often use different terminologies for similar
phenomena, while still not taking sufficiently into account the contributions
of other literatures.9
Clearly, one must move beyond this schism in the literature. Rather than
setting up a false dichotomy between the IR/IPE and governance approaches,
one can consult both to guide and understand one’s empirical work and
findings. For example, one could examine how the operation of non-state
actors at various levels impacts the formation of preferences that shape
government leaders’ bargaining margin of maneuver. To what extent do the
strategies of non-state actors differ from one level to another to define the
parameters of negotiation? What are the resulting implications for those groups
who do not operate at multiple levels? One could also identify the conditions
under which states confer private authority at the national, European, and
international levels. Are these conditions vastly different? Why or why not?
One could also examine the manner in which norms are constituted at the
national, European, and international levels. How do these various settings
inform agents with an understanding of their interests? What does this tell us
about norm creation in the EU as compared to the national level?
CONCLUSION: REFLECTING ON REALITY
This review paper identifies some of the weaknesses in the IR/IPE theory and
approaches to the EU today. It does so through the identification of three false
or artificial dichotomies in the IPE literature that delimit and, indeed, ghettoize non-state actors in European integration and policy-making: (1) the
international vs. domestic, (2) the public vs. private, and (3) the ‘good’ vs. the
‘bad’ false dichotomies. The purpose in reviewing this literature is not to claim
that firms and other non-state actors are all-powerful, all-pervasive, or allimportant actors. Rather, it is to suggest that our scholarship would likely be
enhanced and enriched if we became more cognizant of how these actors fit
in the reality of the EU as polity and global actor today.
Of course, the governance literature that embraces comparative politics, public policy, and political economy approaches also challenges these false dichotomies. The EU governance approach incorporating historical institutionalism
in particular has developed important insights into public/private interaction in
the EU. While it might be tempting to forsake the IR/IPE scholarship and, in
turn, embrace the governance literature, I have argued that it is not necessary to
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
115
set up yet another artificial dichotomy between the two. Indeed, by consulting
both sets of literature, one can better guide and understand one’s empirical work
and findings and contribute to a more comprehensive understanding of how all
actors influence, are constrained by, and are constituted in the national, European, and international settings in which they operate.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
Address for correspondence: Maria Green Cowles, School of International
Service, American University, 4400 Massachusetts Avenue, NW, Washington,
DC 20016–8071, USA. Tel: ò1 202 885 1819. Fax: ò1 202 885 2494.
email:
[email protected]
NOTES
1 I am grateful to Jan Beyers, Tanja Börzel, Jeffrey Checkel, David Bach, Barbara
Haskel, Erik Jones, Christoph Knill, Sophie Meunier, Vivien Schmidt, Mitchell
Smith, Paul Taggart, Bastiaan van Apeldoorn, Amy Verdun, and two anonymous
reviewers who provided comments on subsequent versions of this article. Of course,
any errors or omissions are mine.
2 By non-state actors, I am referring to profit-oriented actors such as firms and banks,
to public-interest-oriented non-governmental actors such as consumer organizations
and environmental groups, and, more broadly, to social movements. I do not
include intergovernmental organizations in this definition (cf. Arts et al. 2001).
3 I am not arguing that each dichotomy is found in each of the four theories/
approaches under review. Indeed, neorealist theories largely sidestep the ‘good’ vs.
‘bad’ dichotomy; the historical and sociological strands of institutionalism generally
avoid the public vs. private dichotomy. The neo-Gramscian approach, by focusing
on transnational agency, moves beyond both the international vs. domestic and
public vs. private dichotomies.
4 Scholars disagree with the characterization of liberal intergovernmentalism as part
of the neorealist school (cf. Pollack 2001). While liberal intergovernmentalism
differs from neorealism on several accounts, it is ‘realist’ in terms of its focus on
state sovereignty, bargaining, and power (cf. Verdun 1999).
5 See Kassim and Menon in this issue.
6 Critics point out that international institutions’ performance may also suffer from
the inclusion of non-state actors if the organizations are ‘captured’ by NGOs and
firms – a criticism leveled at domestic institutions as well. Non-state actors thus can
legitimize as well as delegitimize international organizations.
7 As noted above, the neorealist approach also promotes this artificial dichotomy by
only recognizing the role of domestic non-state actors in preference formation.
8 As noted above, this approach transcends many of the false dichotomies found in
traditional IR/IPE literature, including the public vs. private debate. The neoGramscian ontological primacy of transnational social forces over states, however,
opens it to a different kind of criticism – namely, the failure to adequately address
the role of public actors. I thank Bastiaan van Apeldoorn for his valuable comments
on the neo-Gramscian approach in this article.
9 I thank Christoph Knill for expanding on this point. See also Knill and Lehmkuhl
(2002).
REFERENCES
Abbott, K.W. and Snidal, D. (2000) ‘Hard and soft law in international governance’,
International Organization 54(4): 421–56.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
116
Journal of European Public Policy
Abbott, K.W. and Snidal, D. (2001) ‘International ‘‘standards’’ and international
governance’, Journal of European Public Policy 8(3): 345–70.
Anderson, S. and Eliasson, K. (1993) Making Policy in Europe, London: Sage.
Armstrong, K. and Bulmer, S.J. (1998) The Governance of the Single European Market,
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Arts, B., Noortmann, M. and Reinalda, B. (eds) (2001) Non-state Actors in International
Relations, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Bieler, A. and Morton, A.D. (eds) (2001) Social Forces in the Making of the New
Europe: The Restructuring of European Social Relations in the Global Political Economy,
Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Börzel, T.A. (1998) ‘Organizing Babylon. On the different conceptions of policy
networks’, Public Administration 76: 253–73.
Börzel, T.A. (2002) ‘Non-state actors and the provision of common goods. Compliance
with international institutions’, in A. Héritier (ed.), Common Goods: Reinventing
European and International Governance, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield,
pp. 155–78.
Checkel, J.T. (1998) ‘The constructivist turn in international relations theory’, World
Politics 50(2): 324–48.
Checkel, J.T. (2001) ‘The Europeanization of citizenship?’, in M.G. Cowles, J.A.
Caporaso and T. Risse (eds), Transforming Europe: Europeanization and Domestic
Change, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 180–97.
Christiansen, T., Jørgensen, K.E. and Wiener, A. (1999) ‘The social construction of
Europe’, Journal of European Public Policy 6(4): 528–44.
Cini, M. (2001) ‘The soft law approach: Commission rule-making in the EU’s state
aid regime’, Journal of European Public Policy 8(2): 192–207.
Clark, A.-M. (1995) ‘Non-governmental organizations and their influence on international society’, Journal of International Affairs 48: 507–25.
Clark, A.-M., Friedman, E.J. and Hochstetler, K. (1998) ‘The sovereign limits of
global civil society’, World Politics 52(1): 1–35.
Coen, D. (1997) ‘The evolution of the large firm as a political actor in the European
Union’, Journal of European Public Policy 4(1): 91–108.
Collester, J.B. (2001) ‘How defense ‘‘spilled over’’ into the CFSP’, in M.G. Cowles
and M. Smith (eds), The State of the European Union, Vol. 5, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 369–89.
Conant, L. (2001) ‘Europeanization and the Courts: variable patterns of adaptation
among national judiciaries’, in M.G. Cowles, J.A. Caporaso and T. Risse (eds),
Transforming Europe: Europeanization and Domestic Change, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 97–115.
Cowles, M.G. (1994) The Politics of Big Business in the European Community, Ph.D.
dissertation, American University.
Cowles, M.G. (1995) ‘Setting the agenda for a new Europe: the ERT and EC 1992’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 33(4): 501–26.
Cowles, M.G. (1996) ‘The EU Committee of AmCham: the powerful voice of
American firms in Brussels’, Journal of European Public Policy 3(3): 339–58.
Cowles, M.G. (2001a) ‘The transatlantic business dialogue: transforming the new
transatlantic dialogue’, in M. Pollack and G. Schaffer (eds), Transatlantic Governance
in a Global Economy, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 213–33.
Cowles, M.G. (2001b) ‘Who writes the rules of e-commerce? A case study of the
global business dialogue on e-commerce (GBDe)’, Policy Paper No. 14, Washington,
DC: American Institute for Contemporary German Studies. Downloadable from
http://www.aicgs.org/publications/pubonline.shtml#policypapers
Cox, R. (1995) ‘Critical political economy’, in B. Hettne (ed.), International Political
Economy: Understanding Global Disorder, Halifax: Fernwood Books, pp. 31–45.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
117
Cram, L. (2001) ‘Governance ‘‘to go’’: domestic actors, institutions and the boundaries
of the possible’, Journal of Common Market Studies 39(4): 595–618.
Cutler, A.C., Haufler, V. and Porter, T. (1999) Private Authority and International
Affairs, Albany, NY: Suny University Press.
Dunning, J.H. (1958) American Investment in British Manufacturing Industry, London:
George Allen & Unwin; revised edition, London: Routledge, 1998.
Eden, L. (ed.) (1991) ‘Special section: Sovereignty at bay: an agenda for the 1990s’,
Millennium 20(2): 187–8.
Egan, M. (2001) Constructing a European Market: Standards, Regulation, and Governance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Finnemore, M. (1996) National Interests in International Society, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Florini, A. (ed.) (2000) The Third Force: The Rise of Transnational Civil Society,
Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace: Brookings Institution Press.
Gill, S. (ed.) (1993) Gramsci, Historical Materialism, and International Relations,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Greenwood, J. (1997) Representing Interests in the European Union, Basingstoke:
Macmillan.
Greenwood, J., Grote, J. and Ronit, K. (1992) Organised Interests and the European
Community, London: Sage.
Hall, P.A. and Taylor, R.C.R. (1996) ‘Political science and the three new institutionalisms’, Political Studies 44(5): 936–57.
Haufler, V. (2000) ‘Private sector international regimes: an assessment’, in R.A.
Higgott, G.R.D. Underhill and A. Bieler (eds), Non-State Actors and Authority in
the Global System, London/New York: Routledge, pp. 121–38.
Haufler, V. (2001) A Public Role for the Private Sector: Industry Self-Regulation in
a Global Economy, Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International
Peace Press.
Héritier, A. (1999) Policy-Making and Diversity in Europe: Escaping Deadlock, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Héritier, A. (2001) ‘New modes of multi-arena governance in Europe: policy-making
without legislation’. Paper presented at the conference ‘Linking Law and Politics’,
1–2 February, Bonn.
Héritier, A. (ed.) (2002) Common Goods: Reinventing European and International
Governance, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Higgott, R.A., Underhill, G.R.D. and Bieler, A. (eds) (2000) Non-State Actors and
Authority in the Global System, London: Routledge.
Hix, S. (1994) ‘The study of the European Community: the challenge to comparative
politics’, West European Politics 17(4): 1–30.
Hodson, D. and Maher, I. (2001) ‘The open method as a new mode of governance:
the case of soft economic policy co-ordination’, Journal of Common Market Studies
39(4): 719–46.
Imig, D. and Tarrow, S. (eds) (2001) Contentious Europeans: Protest and Politics in an
Emerging Polity, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Jachtenfuchs, M. (2001) ‘The governance approach to European integration’, Journal
of Common Market Studies 39(2): 245–64.
Johnson, R. (2000) ‘Toward democratic governance for sustainable development:
transnational civil society organizing around big dams’, in A. Florini (ed.), The
Third Force: The Rise of Transnational Civil Society, Washington, DC: Carnegie
Endowment for International Peace: Brookings Institution Press.
Jordan, G. and Schubert, K. (eds) (1992) European Journal of Political Research 21:
special issue: Policy Networks.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
118
Journal of European Public Policy
Jørgensen, K.E. (ed.) (1997) Reflectivist Approaches to European Governance, London:
Macmillan.
Kahler, M. and Lake, D.A. (eds) (2002) Globalizing Authority: Economic Integration
and Governance, manuscript.
Katzenstein, P.J. (1996) Cultural Norms and National Security: Police and Military in
Postwar Japan, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Keck, M.E. and Sikkink, K. (1998) Activists beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in
International Politics, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Kirshner, J. (2000) ‘The study of money’, World Politics 52: 407–36.
Klotz, A. (1995) Protesting Prejudice: Apartheid and the Politics of Norms in International
Relations, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Knill, C. (2001) ‘Private governance across multiple arenas: European interest associations as interface actors’, Journal of European Public Policy 8(2): 227–46.
Knill, C. and Lehmkuhl, D. (2002) ‘Private actors and the state: internationalization
and changing patterns of governance’, Governance 15(1): 41–63.
Kohler-Koch, B. (1996) ‘Catching up with change: the transformation of governance
in the European Union’, Journal of European Public Policy 3(3): 359–80.
Kohler-Koch, B. and Eising, R. (eds) (1999) The Transformation of Governance in the
European Union, London: Routledge.
Kooiman, J. (1993) ‘Social-political governance: introduction’, in J. Kooiman (ed.),
Modern Governance. New Government–Society Interactions, London: Sage, pp. 1–9.
Krasner, S. (1976) ‘State power and the structure of international trade’, World Politics
28(3): 317–47.
Lehmbruch, G. and Schmitter, P.C. (1982) Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making,
London: Sage.
Lehmkuhl, D. (2000) ‘Commercial arbitration – a case of private transnational selfgovernance?’, Working Paper, Max-Planck Group on ‘Common Goods: Law,
Politics and Economics’, Bonn.
Marcussen, M. (1998) Central Bankers, the Ideational Life-Cycle and the Social Construction of EMU, EUI Working Papers, 98/33, Florence: European University Institute.
Mattli, W. (1999) The Logic of Regional Integration, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mattli, W. (2001) ‘Private justice in a global economy: from litigation to arbitration’,
International Organization 55(4): 919–47.
Mattli, W. (2003) ‘Globalization and the changing world of transnational standards
governance’, in M. Kahler and David A. Lake (eds), Governance in a Global
Economy: Political Authority in Transition, Princeton: Princeton University Press,
forthcoming.
Mazey, S. (1998) ‘The European Union and women’s rights: from the Europeanization
of national agendas to the nationalization of a European agenda?’, Journal of
European Public Policy 5(1): 131–52.
Mazey, S. and Richardson, J. (eds) (1993) Lobbying in the European Community,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Meunier, S. (2002) ‘Trade policy and political legitimacy in the European Union’,
manuscript.
Moravcsik, A. (1993a) ‘Introduction: Integrating international and domestic theories
of international bargaining’, in P.B. Evans, H.K. Jacobson and R.D. Putnam (eds),
Double-Edged Diplomacy, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 3–42.
Moravcsik, A. (1993b) ‘Preferences and power in the European Community: a liberal
intergovernmentalist approach’, Journal of Common Market Studies 31(4): 473–524.
Moravcsik, A. (1999) ‘A new statecraft? Supranational entrepreneurs and international
co-operation’, International Organization 53(2): 267–306.
Newman, A. and Bach, D. (2002a) ‘The transnationalization of regulation’. Paper
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
M.G. Cowles: Non-state actors and false dichotomies
119
presented at the Thirteenth International Conference of Europeanists, Chicago, IL,
14–16 March 2002.
Newman, A. and Bach, D. (2002b) ‘Self-regulatory trajectories in the shadow of the
state: resolving digital dilemmas in Europe and the United States’. Unpublished
manuscript.
Palan, R. (1992) ‘The second structuralist theories of international relations: a research
note’, International Studies Notes 17(3): 22–9.
Peterson, J. (1995) ‘Decision-making in the European Union: towards a framework
for analysis’, Journal of European Public Policy 2(1): 69–93.
Peterson, M.J. (1992) ‘Whalers, cetologists, environmentalists, and the international
management of whaling’, International Organization 46(1): 147–86.
Pollack, M. (1997) ‘Delegation, agency and agenda setting in the European Community’, International Organization 51(1): 99–135.
Pollack, M. (2001) ‘International relations theory and European integration’, Journal
of Common Market Studies 39(2): 221–44.
Pollack, M. and Shaffer, G. (eds) (2001) Transatlantic Governance in a Global Economy,
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Prakash, A. (2000) The Greening of the Firm, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Price, R. (1998) ‘Reversing the gun sights: transnational civil society targets land
mines’. International Organization 53(3): 613–44.
Reinicke, W. (1998) Global Public Policy: Governing Without Government?, Washington,
DC: Brookings Institution Press.
Rhodes, R.A.W. (1996) ‘The new governance: governing without government’, Political
Studies 44: 652–67.
Risse, T. (2002) ‘Transnational actors and world politics’, in W. Carlsnaes, T.
Risse and B. Simmons (eds), Handbook of International Relations, London: Sage,
pp. 255–75.
Risse-Kappen, T. (ed.) (1995) Bringing Transnational Relations Back In: Non-State
Actors, Domestic Structures and International Institutions, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Ronit, K. and Schneider, V. (1999) ‘Global governance through private organisations’,
Governance 12(3): 243–66.
Sally, R. (1995) States and Firms: Multinational Enterprises in Institutional Competition,
London: Routledge.
Sandholtz, W. and Zysman, J. (1989) ‘1992: recasting the European bargain’, World
Politics 42(1): 95–128.
Scharpf, F. (1997) Games Real Actors Play, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Schmidt, V.A. (2001) ‘The politics of economic adjustment in France and Britain:
when does discourse matter?’, Journal of European Public Policy 8(2): 247–64.
Schmidt, V. (2002, forthcoming) The Futures of European Capitalism, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Schmitter, P.C. (1974) ‘Still the century of corporatism?’, Review of Politics 36: 85–131.
Sell, S. (1995) ‘Intellectual property and antitrust in the developing world: crisis,
coercion, and choice’, International Organization 49(2): 315–49.
Sisson, K. and Marginson, P. (2001) ‘Bench marking and the ‘‘Europeanisation’’ of
social policy’, ESRC One Europe or Several? Programme Briefing Note, 3/01.
Smith, J., Pagnucco, R. and Chatfield, C. (1997) Transnational Social Movements and
World Politics: Solidarity beyond the State, Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
Snyder, F. (1993) ‘Soft law and institutional practice in the European Community’,
European University Institute Working Paper, LAW No. 93/5, Florence: European
University Institute.
Spar, D.L. (1999) ‘Lost in (cyber)space’, in A. Claire Cutler, V. Haufler and T. Porter
(eds), Private Authority and International Affairs, Albany, NY: Suny University Press.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:08 17 January 2009
120
Journal of European Public Policy
Steinmo, S., Thelen, K. and Longstreth, F. (eds) (1992) Structuring Politics: Historical
Institutionalism in Comparative Analysis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stone Sweet, A. (2002, forthcoming) On Law, Politics, and Judicialization, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Stone Sweet, A. and Sandholtz, W. (1998) ‘Integration, supranational governance, and
the institutionalization of the European polity’, in W. Sandholtz and A. Stone
Sweet (eds), European Integration and Supranational Governance, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 1–26.
Strange, S. (1988) States and Markets, New York: Blackwell.
Strange, S. (1996) The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of Power in the World Economy,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Streeck, W. and Schmitter, P.C. (1985) Private Interest Government: Beyond Market
and State, London: Sage.
Van Apeldoorn, B. (2002) Transnational Capital and the Struggle over European
Integration, London: Routledge.
Van der Pijl, K. (1998) Transnational Classes and International Relations, London:
Routledge.
Van Tulder, R. and Junne, G. (1998) European Multinationals in Core Technologies,
New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Verdun, A. (1996) ‘An ‘‘asymmetrical’’ economic and monetary union in the EU:
perceptions of monetary authorities and social partners’, Journal of European
Integration/Revue d’intégration européenne 20(1): 59–81.
Verdun, A. (1999) Book review of Andrew Moravcsik, The Choice for Europe, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1998, ECSA Review 12(1): 14–15.
Wallace, H. (2001) ‘The changing politics of the European Union: an overview’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 39(4): 581–94.
Weber, S. (ed.) (2001) Globalization and the European Political Economy, New York:
Columbia University Press.
This article was downloaded by: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge]
On: 17 January 2009
Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 791963552]
Publisher Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,
37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Journal of European Public Policy
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713685697
The principal-agent approach and the study of the European Union: promise
unfulfilled?
Online Publication Date: 01 March 2003
To cite this Article (2003)'The principal-agent approach and the study of the European Union: promise unfulfilled?',Journal of European
Public Policy,10:1,121 — 139
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046976
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350176032000046976
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Journal of European Public Policy 10:1 February 2003: 121–139
The principal–agent approach and
the study of the European Union:
promise unfulfilled?
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
Hussein Kassim and Anand Menon1
ABSTRACT The principal–agent model holds great promise for understanding
the institutional complexities of the EU and for moving beyond the sterile debate
between intergovernmentalism and neofunctionalism. As yet, however, scholars
have failed to exploit the insights that this construct affords. After a brief discussion
of the principal–agent model, this article offers a critical examination of the way that
the principal–agent approach has been deployed by liberal intergovernmentalism,
institutional intergovernmentalism, historical institutionalist supranationalism, and
rational-choice supranationalism. It argues that, in all four cases, the a priori
commitments of the theorists, in support either of the view that the member states
effectively control their supranational agents and dominate EU governance or of
the belief in an inevitable trend towards greater integration, led by supranational
institutions, prevent them from making the most effective use of the model. It
proposes alternative applications that may prove more fruitful.
KEY WORDS Agent; Commission; integration; member states; principal.
INTRODUCTION
The principal–agent model and the theory of delegation, which originated in
the new economics of organization, have been increasingly applied in the
study of the European Union (EU).2 This article critically examines these
applications. It argues that the principal–agent model holds significant promise
for understanding the complex relationships and interactions that characterize
the Union, not least on account of its greater institutional sensitivity over
traditional theories of integration. However, its potential has as yet not been
fully realized. This is due partly to the prior theoretical commitments of the
EU scholars who have used these models, partly to misunderstandings of the
complexity and implications of the approach.
The discussion below is divided into three parts. The first offers a brief
overview of, and background to, the principal–agent model.3 The second
discusses the promise that the model offers for understanding European
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046976
122
Journal of European Public Policy
integration and governance, then examines in detail its deployment by authors
writing from four theoretical perspectives – liberal intergovernmentalism (LI),
institutional intergovernmentalism (II), historical institutionalist supranationalism (HIS) and rational-choice supranationalism (RCS).4 The final section
discusses general weaknesses in how the principal–agent model has been
applied to the EU and suggests future research possibilities.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
THE PRINCIPAL–AGENT MODEL IN ECONOMICS AND
POLITICAL SCIENCE
From its origins in the new economics of organization as a theoretical construct
devised to examine relations within the firm (Moe 1984), the principal–agent
model became the dominant framework for examining the difficulties that
arise from contracting in any setting. Agency relationships are created when
one party, the principal, enters into a contractual agreement with a second
party, the agent, and delegates to the latter responsibility for carrying out a
function or set of tasks on the principal’s behalf. In the classic representation,
the principal is the shareholder of a company that contracts an executive to
manage the business on a day-to-day basis. However, the principal can be any
individual or organization that delegates responsibility to another in order to
economize on transactions costs, pursue goals that would otherwise be too
costly, or secure expertise.
Difficulties arise on account of the asymmetric distribution of information
that favours the agent (Kiewiet and McCubbins 1991; Holmstrom 1979),
including adverse selection and moral hazard. The asymmetry of information
can allow the agent to engage in opportunistic behaviour – shirking – that is
costly to the principal, but difficult to detect. The likelihood of shirking is
increased by slippage, when the very structure of delegation ‘provides incentives
for the agent to behave in ways inimical to the preferences of the principal’
(Pollack 1997: 108). Assuring control and limiting shirking is the ‘principal’s
problem’ (Ross 1973). The challenge is to find ways of ensuring perfect
compliance, so that agents cannot exploit the costs of measuring their
characteristics and performance to act contrary to the preferences of the
principal. Economists have focused on incentive structures that discourage
opportunistic behaviour on the part of the agent. Contractual restrictions on
the agent’s operational purview (Doleys 2000) or monitoring the agent are
alternative possibilities, but can be costly. Their effectiveness is limited by the
extent to which the agent’s actions can be observed.
The new economics of organization has been very influential in political
science. Rational-choice institutionalism, in particular, has drawn from its
toolkit in its explanations of how institutions emerge and interact.5 Scholars of
US politics have used the principal–agent model to investigate the relationship
between Congress and executive agencies, and the tasks performed by congressional committees.6 In international relations, delegation has been used to
explain why sovereignty-conscious states create international organizations.7
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
123
The basic model has been used to assess the efficacy of mechanisms devised to
ensure agent compliance, and extended, elaborated upon and adapted to take
account of cases where there are multiple principals.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
Why delegate?
A rich literature has explored the motivations that lead principals to delegate
functions and confer authority to agents in the political world. Pollack (1997:
102) suggests that, fundamentally, delegation is a question of institutional
design and that ‘the question of institutional choice is functionalist’: institutions
are chosen or created because of their intended effects. The decision is usually
motivated by a desire to minimize transaction costs.8 Delegation also provides
a means:
Ω
Ω
Ω
Ω
Ω
Ω
to overcome problems of collective action, where actors anticipate benefits
from long-term co-operation (Axelrod 1984), but want to ensure that the
transaction costs involved in monitoring compliance do not outweigh the
benefits of the agreement and that the terms of the contract are respected
by other parties (Keohane 1984; Shepsle 1979; Weingast and Marshall
1988);
to deal with the problem of ‘incomplete contracting’ (Williamson 1985),
which arises in situations where the interaction envisaged by an agreement
is long term, the bargain complex, the negotiating process difficult, and
‘the realization of mutual gain . . . contingent upon the durability of the
contract’ (Doleys 2000: 535). Rather than writing a fully contingent claims
contract, parties prefer a ‘framing agreement’ or ‘incomplete contract’, in
which they state general goals, establish criteria for decision-making in
unforeseen circumstances (Milgrom and Roberts 1992) and may create an
agent that can ‘fill in the details of an incomplete contract and adjudicate
future disputes’ (Pollack 1997: 104);
to improve the quality of policy in technical areas by delegating responsibilities to an agent with specialist knowledge (Egan 1998);
to overcome regulatory competition and avoid market failure where interdependent states have incentives to treat their own firms leniently (Majone
1994; Egan 1998);
to displace responsibility for unpopular decisions (Fiorina 1977; Epstein
and O’Halloran 1999);
to ‘lock in’ distributional benefits. In contrast to information-based
accounts, where the agent is impartial, a second perspective interprets
delegation as a mechanism for ‘locking in’ distributional benefits. Thus,
the ‘industrial organization of Congress’ (Weingast and Marshall 1988) is
best understood as an efficient way of facilitating ‘pork-barrelling’ and ‘logrolling’. Members of Congress sit on committees where they are best placed
to secure benefits for their constituents. Similarly, an alternative to Majone’s
‘search for independence’ contests the view that regulators are neutral,
124
Ω
Journal of European Public Policy
arguing instead that the creation of institutions is intrinsically distributive
and that the choice of institutions may be motivated by the desire to
institutionalize a preferred set of preferences (Stetter 2000);
to resolve the problem of policy-making instability. The delegation of
agenda-setting powers to an agent may prevent the problem of policy
‘cycling’ that besets systems of majoritarian decision-making (Pollack 1997;
McKelvey 1976; Riker 1980).
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
After delegation: coping with the ‘principal’s problem’
Political scientists investigating delegation have focused on how principals have
designed institutions that ensure favourable outcomes (Kiewiet and McCubbins
1991; Moe 1987). Studies commonly begin with the assumption that incentive
incompatibility between principals and agents is ‘an inherent feature of
contracting relationships’ (Doleys 2000: 537; Moe 1989), and that asymmetric
information allows shirking, leading to agency losses (Weingast and Moran
1983). They examine ex ante controls and ex post oversight mechanisms that
can be used to mitigate this tendency, and assess the cost to the principal of
various sanctioning strategies.
Ex ante control typically takes the form of administrative procedures,
designed ‘to limit the scope of agency activity, the legal instruments available
to the agency, and the procedures it must follow’ (Pollack 1997: 108). They
can be more or less restrictive, and altered in response to agency loss.
Such restrictions come, however, at the cost of the agent’s flexibility and
comprehensiveness of action (McCubbins and Page 1987; McCubbins et al.
1987, 1989), and can diminish the effectiveness and overall capacity of the
system. Ex post oversight falls into two broad categories (Pollack 1997): the
imposition of sanctions, where principals attempt to control agency loss
through budgetary restrictions, appointments or revising the agent’s mandate
through legislative or regulatory means; and monitoring, whereby an attempt
is made to rebalance the asymmetry of information by surveillance of agent
behaviour. McCubbins and Schwartz (1984) famously distinguish two strategies: ‘police patrol’ oversight, where the principal engages in continuous and
detailed vigilance of agent action; and ‘fire alarm’ oversight, where the principal
relies on third parties to alert it to agency transgressions. The second is less
costly and imposes fewer demands on the principal than the first, but the
comparison highlights a fundamental point: all methods of agency control
imply costs to the principal and their cost traded-off against the benefits from
limiting non-compliance (McCubbins et al. 1987, 1989).
The cost of monitoring is likely to be substantially higher where there are
multiple principals. To the cost of co-ordination is added the risk that the
imposition of sanctions will involve action that exposes long-standing differences between principals (McCubbins et al. 1987). A review of the literature
leads Pollack (1997) to identify three factors affecting the likelihood that
sanctions will be imposed: the extent to which principals’ preferences converge;
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
125
the decision rules governing the application of sanctions; and the ‘default
condition’ where there is no agreement among the principals. Pollack suggests
that a knowing, opportunistic agent can exploit situations where these barriers
are high.
A further issue concerns the type of agency behaviour that the principal is
trying to control. Control can be exercised to ensure that agents stay within
the remit laid out in the original contract (McCubbins et al. 1989). Control
can be more intrusive, however, when principals are authorized to interfere in
the operation of the agent, even within its contractually defined sphere of
competence (Epstein and O’Halloran 1999). The choice of approach is an
important decision. Specifying agency powers ‘in excruciating detail . . . leaving
as little as possible to the discretionary judgment of bureaucrats’ is obviously
‘not a formula for creating effective organisations’ since ‘cumbersome, complicated, technically inappropriate structures . . . undermine their capacity to
perform their jobs well’ (Moe 1990: 228). At issue, in other words, is the
effectiveness of delegation: the choice is either minimize the risk of agency loss
or allow the agent the independence to carry out its responsibilities efficiently.
The use of budgetary cuts may enable principals to thwart the budgetmaximizing ambitions of agents, but is likely to hinder agents in performing
the tasks for which they were created (Moe 1987).
A related complication arises when delegation is utilized as a means to
establish credible commitments to long-term aims. In such cases, for example,
the creation of independent central banks, delegation to an agent is motivated
by a concern to secure advantages that depend upon the independence of that
agent. Institutional choice has been governed by a concern to protect against
coalitional or principal drift (Shepsle and Bonchek 1997; Shepsle 1992; Horn
and Shepsle 1989). Where the short- and long-term interests of principals
conflict, a decision may be taken to insulate the agent from interference.
However, the ‘civil servants and political appointees of bureaus insulated from
political overseers are . . . empowered to pursue independent courses of action.
Protection from coalitional drift comes at the price of an increased potential
for bureaucratic drift’ (Shepsle and Bonchek 1997: 375).
PRINCIPAL–AGENT APPROACHES TO THE EU
In recent years, a growing number of scholars have used the principal–agent
model in the study of the EU.9 The principal–agent approach holds considerable promise. First, it is explicitly concerned with complex inter-institutional
interactions and need not systematically privilege the role played by one
institution or class of actor over others – a trap into which many theoretical
approaches have fallen (Menon 2002). It can generate more nuanced hypotheses
than the theories that have historically dominated the field. Pollack’s use of
the model to analyse the power of the European Commission and the European
Court of Justice, for example, leads him to the conclusion that the ‘autonomy
of a given supranational institution depends crucially on the efficacy and
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
126
Journal of European Public Policy
credibility of control mechanisms established by member state principals, and
that these vary from institution to institution – as well as from issue-area to
issue-area and over time – leading to varying patterns of supranational
autonomy’ (1997: 101). This is a more subtle thesis than neofunctionalism or
intergovernmentalism can provide. Indeed, Pollack explicitly attempts to
‘transcend the intergovernmentalist–neofunctionalist debate’ (Pollack 1997:
101) in this way.10 Second, the principal–agent model offers a way of grasping
the institutional complexity of the EU. As Moe has argued, the model ‘cuts
through the inherent complexity of organizational relationships by identifying
distinct aspects of individuals and their environments that are most worthy of
investigation, and it integrates these elements into a logically coherent whole’
(1984: 757). Third, the employment of theoretical constructs and models that
are in more general use may enable EU scholarship to benefit from belonging
to the mainstream (see Moravcsik 1998; Menon 2002).
In this section, we review four applications – LI, II, HIS and RCS – of the
principal–agent approach to the EU. All four proceed from the assumption
that delegation to supranational agents is grounded in the interests of member
state principals, but reach different conclusions about the ability of governments
to retain their control and the extent to which the Commission and the Court
are willing and able to act independently. The first two approaches – LI and
II – contend that the member states remain in control of European governance
and integration; the third and fourth – HIS and RCS – that the influence of
supranational institutions cannot be explained solely in terms of member state
preferences.
Liberal intergovernmentalism
LI explains the creation of the EU’s ‘strong supranational institutions’
(Moravcsik 1993: 507) in terms of the interests of states, which, under
conditions of economic interdependence, recognize the benefits of, and enter
into, long-term co-operation, but need to overcome problems of collective
action. Drawing on regime theory, Moravcsik argues that international institutions are ‘deliberate instruments to improve the efficiency of bargaining
between states’ (p. 507) and that ‘[m]uch of the institutional structure of the
EC can be readily explained by the functional theory of regimes’. He contends
that member states decide on the basis of a cost–benefit analysis of the ‘stream
of future substantive decisions expected to follow from alternative institutional
designs’ whether to adopt qualified majority voting (QMV) or to delegate to
supranational institutions (p. 509). The calculation involves trading-off efficient
collective decision-making against the risk of being outvoted or overruled. He
argues that member states are influenced by the ‘potential gains from cooperation’, the ‘level of uncertainty regarding the details of specific delegated
or pooled decision’, and the ‘level of political risk for individual governments
or interest groups with intense preferences’ (pp. 510–11). These calculations
led to the delegation of agenda-setting, enforcement, and external representa-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
127
tion. With respect to agenda-setting, Moravcsik (1993: 511) argues that the
interests of the member states are served because the Commission ‘assures that
[the] technical information necessary for decision is available’ and that ‘as a
neutral arbiter, it provides an authoritative means of reducing the number of
proposals to be considered’. In relation to enforcement, Moravcsik (1993: 511)
asserts that ‘[t]he possibilities for co-operation are enhanced when neutral
procedures exist to monitor, interpret and enforce compliance’.
There are, however, several difficulties with the way that LI deploys the principal–agent approach. A fundamental problem concerns the functional theory
of delegation. Functional explanation is itself inherently problematic owing to
its ex post facto attribution of motives without empirical investigation, its stress
on interests that remain unelaborated, and its lack of precision in identifying
the mechanism that links cause to effect.11 In the case of LI, no empirical
evidence is offered in support of the contention that member states engage in a
cost–benefit analysis or even that the supranational institutions were created for
the reasons that LI alleges. Moreover, the problems that occur with delegation
(e.g. conflicting interests or agency loss) are not addressed. The possibility that
member state principals and supranational agents may develop divergent preferences, that the Commission may draw on its own resources to pursue its own
policy agenda, or that the Court may evolve into a more powerful institution
than the original contract envisages is not contemplated.
More importantly, LI assumes that, although the supranational institutions
may continue to perform the formal functions that Moravcsik identifies –
itself a questionable assumption – there is no reason to suppose that the initial
calculations of the original Six about the stream of substantive policy decisions
still hold true decades after the Treaty of Rome was signed. Although he
acknowledges that behaviour on the part of the European Court of Justice
represents ‘an anomaly for the functional explanation of delegation as a
deliberate means by national governments of increasing the efficiency of
collective decision-making’ (Moravcsik 1993: 513),12 and appears to endorse
an explanation put forward by Burley and Mattli (1993), which explains the
expansion of the role of the Court in terms of ‘a number of factors idiosyncratic
to the EC [European Community]’, Moravcsik does not explain how this view
might be reconciled with the key tenets of LI. Nor does he account for why
supranational institutions continue to serve the interests of the member states
or are kept in check by them.
The view that the member states have been able to control the direction of
integration is difficult to sustain for reasons identified by Pierson (1996) (see
below). There are also empirical grounds for challenging this assumption. The
monitoring capacities of the national administrations are frequently overstated.
Recent research on the national co-ordination of EU policy (Kassim et al.
2000, 2001) reveals considerable differences in the ambitions and administrative resources of member states, as well as evidence of ‘bureaucratic politics’
and problems in constructing coherent action. In this light, the image of evervigilant principals is difficult to uphold.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
128
Journal of European Public Policy
Turning to the supranational agents, LI underestimates the Commission’s
ability to act as a policy entrepreneur. Although the Commission is small and
fragmented, it has significant resources at its disposal. As well as its formal
monopoly over policy initiation, the Commission has accumulated considerable
expertise, technical and legal,13 occupies a strategic location at the heart of
Community decision-making as ‘process manager’ (Eichener 1993), and enjoys
access to information that would be difficult for even the best organized
and most motivated national administrations to gather (Kassim 2000). A
Commission official in a functional Directorate-General might not know more
about a sector in a member state than a civil servant from that state, but he
or she may well know more about the sector across fifteen member states than
any national official.
Finally, it does not follow from the assumption that the member states
prefer an independent supranational body to a randomly chosen national
government (Moravcsik 1993: 512) that the Commission will in practice act
neutrally.14 In theory, the Commission embodies the interest of the Community – one could debate whether this represents, in Rousseaunian terms, the
general interest, the sum of the particular interests of the member states, or
the average interest – but in practice, in seeking to implement the treaties, it
acts as a ‘purposeful opportunist’ (Cram 1993). This often involves partisan
behaviour, favouring, for example, free market solutions over protectionist
policies, or more Europe rather than less. In several policy areas, including
telecommunications and air transport, the Commission has forced the introduction of policy at the European level against some, or even a majority of
the, member states by using its competition powers. In other areas, for example,
environmental policy, the Commission has actively constructed coalitions with
like-minded member states to press a particular agenda. Action of this type is
hard to reconcile with the view that it acts as a neutral arbiter.15 LI adopts an
information-based approach to delegation, ignoring ways in which delegation
can produce distributive gains for some member states at the expense of others,
thus serving to ‘institutionalize partiality’ (Menon 2002).
Institutional intergovernmentalism
II (Garrett 1992; Garrett and Weingast 1993), by contrast, directly addresses
the distributive implications of delegation. Though it also deploys the functional theory of delegation to explain the EU’s institutional arrangements (see,
e.g., Garrett 1992: 533–4), it takes a more critical approach. Garrett (1992:
534–5) argues that functional theory overemphasizes the informational advantages of co-operation and thereby disregards the distributional consequences
of the institutions chosen by the member states, when it is precisely these
latter considerations that account for why one equilibrium position is selected
among the many that are possible.16 Functional theory takes the view that
institutions are constructed as ‘informational clearing houses’, not as ‘governing
structures’, but the nature of the post-1992 institutions agreed by the member
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
129
states does more than simply provide the information that allows the states to
further their own interests. They challenge nation-state sovereignty and alter
the ‘political structure of the international system’. The adoption of QMV in
the Council abolishes the national veto, while the constitutionalization of the
founding treaties by the European Court of Justice has wrought a legal system
(Garrett 1992: 535–6).
These changes have not compromised member state control over the EU,
according to II, since governments play a decisive role in the legislative process,17
and the Court does not threaten state autonomy. Indeed, the interests of the
Court and the member states coincide. Governments have delegated the task
of monitoring compliance and resolved the problem of incomplete contracting
by empowering the Court to apply the rules of the Treaty in specific areas
(Garrett 1992: 557–8). As an agent, the Court has not struck out independently, aware, like all courts, that its powers are subject to revision by elected
politicians and conscious of its particular vulnerability, given that ‘its position
is not explicitly supported by a written constitution’ (Garrett 1992: 558).
Evidence of the Court’s quiescence can be found in its jurisprudence. II claims
that the Court’s decisions are ‘consistent with the preferences of France and
Germany’ (1992: 558, 589). Should a Court ruling go against a particular state,
moreover, II contends that that government is likely not to comply (Garrett
1992: 555–6).
II presents a more sophisticated account of institutional arrangements at the
European level than LI,18 but is similarly afflicted by tension between its a
priori commitment to member state primacy and the potential problems that
arise from principal–agent relationships. Like LI, II discounts the possibility
of agency loss, but on different grounds. While recognizing its influence in
decision-making, II emphasizes that the Commission ultimately depends on
the member states among whom it must find a majority, and stresses the
Council’s decisive influence as last mover.19 Though, on the one hand, II
stresses the uniqueness of the Community’s legal system, on the other, it posits
the subservience of the Court to the member states – a somewhat blatant
contradiction. It provides neither an adequate account of the constitutionalization process, nor convincing evidence that Court jurisprudence is congruent
with the interests of France and Germany. It fails to show how the Court
serves the interests of the member states by ensuring compliance with the
Treaty, while at the same time favouring two of its number in its jurisprudence.20 Moreover, II has not answered satisfactorily the objection of legal
theorists that member states are unlikely to defy the Court on account of the
damage that their reputations would suffer (Burley and Mattli 1993).
A historical institutionalist approach
The influence of the principal–agent approach is evident in HIS’s critique of
intergovernmentalism, even if the terminology is not always used explicitly.21
In an account that ‘stresses the difficulties of subjecting institutional evolution
130
Journal of European Public Policy
to tight control’, HIS argues that the intergovernmentalist approach to
integration is flawed, because ‘the current functioning of institutions cannot
be derived from the aspirations of the original designers’ (Pierson 1996: 126–7).
Pierson contends that the member states lose control over the integration
process, because gaps emerge that are difficult for them to close. These gaps
develop for four reasons:
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
Ω
Ω
Ω
Ω
the ‘autonomous actions of European institutional actors’: EC institutions
are new actors, with their own interests, which are likely to ‘diverge from
those of [their] creators’, and have significant resources – ‘expertise and
delegated authority’ (Moe 1990: 121) – of their own;
the ‘restricted time horizons of national decision-makers’: politicians in the
member states are likely to give greater priority to the short term (Pierson
1996: 136) owing to the demands of the electoral cycle and their relatively
short periods in office compared to the long-term missions of the supranational institutions;
the potential for unintended consequences: issue density in the European
context generates ‘overload’ and ‘spillover’, producing ‘interaction effects’
that lead to outcomes that are unlikely to have been anticipated at the
outset (Pierson 1996: 136–9);
shifts in the policy preferences of national governments: the institutional
and policy preferences of the member states change over time, while
successive enlargements alter policy coalitions.
Once gaps emerge, ‘change-resistant decision rules and sunk costs associated
with societal adaptations make it difficult for member states to reassert their
authority’ (Pierson 1996: 123).
Although HIS reveals important weaknesses in the intergovernmentalist
approach, it is not without its problems. First, HIS’s account of why member
state control cannot be sustained over the long term needs qualification. While
governments may have short-term horizons, it does not follow that they neglect
developments at the European level. Member states have established specialist
mechanisms to co-ordinate their European policies and to manage their inputs
into EU decision-making (Kassim et al. 2000; Kassim et al. 2001). With
respect to unintended consequences, though issue densities and overload may
make spillover possible, national administrations are present at key stages of
the policy process, enabling them to intervene to defend their interests (Kassim
and Wright 1991; Kassim 2003; Dogan 1997). In addition, the European
policies of the member states do not betray the kind of instability that HIS
suggests. On the contrary, the outlook of many member states at the polity
and policy level has been remarkably stable.
On the other hand, HIS overstates the inability of the member states to reassert their control. The supranational institutions certainly do not control the
EU’s constitutional agenda, as the European Commission and the European
Parliament have discovered at successive intergovernmental conferences (IGCs).
Even the power of the Court should not be exaggerated. The Barber Protocol,
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
131
agreed by member governments at Maastricht, was specifically aimed at limiting
the impact of a Court decision. In addition, the institutional barriers to
member state directed reform are often not insurmountable. At Maastricht,
Amsterdam and Nice, member state principals have reined in the Commission
and Court in European monetary union, in the common foreign and security
policy, in the development of the European security and defence policy, and
in the third pillar. The Lisbon Process and the ‘open method of co-ordination’
further limit the influence of the Commission. These are powerful counterexamples to the claim that the member states are unable to re-assert their
control (Menon 2002; Kassim and Menon 2003).
Finally, Pierson’s sunk-costs argument is not altogether persuasive in that he
underestimates the extent to which radical revision of even established policy
is impossible. Reform in preparation for the accession of countries from
Central and Eastern Europe within the rubric of Agenda 2000, for example,
has brought about significant reform in the budget, structural policy and the
common agricultural policy. Moreover, the way in which ‘lock in’ operates is
not adequately elaborated. HI needs to explain specifically how the member
states are constrained by domestic actors and ‘societal adaptations’.
Rational-choice supranationalism
Arguably, RCS makes the most sophisticated use of the principal–agent
model in the EU literature in its exploration of the conditions under which
‘supranational institutions will be delegated authority and will enjoy autonomy
from and exert influence on the member governments of the Community’
(Pollack 1997: 100–1).22 Pollack’s test of the functional theory of delegation
leads him to the conclusion that it can explain the functions attributed to the
Commission and the Court – monitoring compliance and enforcing treaty
provision, solving problems of incomplete contracting, independent regulation
and agenda-setting – if not the Parliament. He challenges the theory’s assumptions that ‘the institutions adopted are those that most efficiently perform the
tasks set out for them’ (1997: 107) and argues that institutions can assume
roles that were not originally anticipated.
In his analysis of member state control over the Commission, Pollack
identifies and assesses the efficacy of four mechanisms:
Ω
Ω
Ω
comitology (a form of police patrol monitoring), whereby the member
states monitor and control the exercise by the Commission of its executive
function, but where effectiveness depends on which of the three committee
types is in place;
fire alarm oversight, involving the EC legal system, the European Parliament’s power of dismissal, and the European Court of Auditors, which are
designed to enforce Commission accountability;
ex post sanctions, including cutting the budget – costly to member states,
since it may have adverse effects on their domestic constituencies; the
132
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
Ω
Journal of European Public Policy
power of appointment – relatively ineffective, since it can only be exercised
every five years (Commission) or six years (judges in the Court); the
introduction of new legislation – costly, because it requires mustering a
winning majority under QMV or the support of all other member states,
where the unanimity rule applies; and unilateral non-compliance – too
costly to a member state’s reputation.
revising an agent’s mandate through revision of the treaty – ‘the ‘‘nuclear
option’’ – exceedingly effective, but difficult to use – and . . . therefore a
relatively ineffective and noncredible means of member state control’
(Pollack 1997: 118–19).
On agenda-setting, Pollack argues that the Commission has formal power
where it has the exclusive right of initiative and where it ‘is easier to adopt
than to amend a Commission proposal . . . differences in member state
preferences can be effectively exploited, and . . . member states are dissatisfied
with the status quo and impatient to adopt a new policy’ (Pollack 1997: 124).
Its informal agenda-setting influence depends on ‘member state uncertainty
regarding the problems and policies confronting them and on the Commission’s
acuity in identifying problems and policies that can rally the necessary
consensus among member states in search of solutions to their policy problems’
(Pollack 1997: 128).
Pollack’s conclusion is that supranational autonomy is determined by four
factors: the distribution of preferences among member state principals and
supranational agents; the institutional decision rules for applying sanctions,
overruling legislation, and changing agents’ mandates; the role of incomplete
information and uncertainty in principal–agent relationships with autonomy
greater where the Commission has more information about itself than do
others; and the presence or absence of transnational constituencies of subnational institutions, interest groups or individuals within the member states,
which can act to bypass the member governments and/or place pressure directly
on them (Pollack 1997: 129–30).
Despite its subtlety and sensitivity, in particular, to agent- and sector-specific
variation, RCS’s deployment of the principal–agent model is problematic.
There is, for example, no place for ‘learning’ on the part of the member states,
even though, since Maastricht, governments have found various ways of
limiting the influence of the Commission and the Court. The frequency of
IGCs, moreover, contradicts the view that re-contracting is a ‘nuclear option’.
Most importantly, these developments tend to counter the subtext of Pollack’s
analysis – that the trend towards further integration is inevitable.
A second point concerns Pollack’s reading of comitology, which he sees as a
site for a struggle over competence. There is an alternative view, however,
which holds that the participants in these committees engage, not in a political
battle about the appropriate locus of decision-making, but in problem-solving
discussion about technical points.
Finally, Pollack’s emphasis on the conditions under which supranational
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
133
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
agents can elude member state control leads him to overlook the resources
that these institutions command. Studies of EU policy emphasize, for example,
the leverage that the Commission can exert by using its competition powers
to prise open sectors where national governments prefer a protectionist status
quo. Paradoxically, Pollack also overstates the inclination and ability of the
member states to control their supranational agents (see above). RCS does not,
in other words, accurately represent the respective powers and resources of
principals and agents.
CONCLUSIONS: THE PRACTICE AND PROMISE OF PRINCIPAL–
AGENT APPROACHES TO THE EU
The four approaches considered above use delegation theory and, in the case
of II and two versions of supranationalism, the principal–agent model to
present a more sophisticated analysis of European integration than their
intellectual forebears, intergovernmentalism and neofunctionalism. These constructs offer greater leverage in understanding the motivation of the member
states in creating the European Communities and their preparedness to entrust
supranational institutions with key responsibilities, and provide a valuable
heuristic for approaching the relationship between governments and those
institutions, as well as for assessing the extent to which the Commission and
Court have developed independent interests and a capacity for action.
Yet the above discussion draws attention to particular weaknesses in the four
accounts. An important difficulty with LI and II, for example, lies in the
tension between recognizing the fact of delegation and commitment to a belief
in continued member state control. HIS, by contrast, tends to overstate the
power of the Commission, while underestimating the ability of the member
states to assert influence in European integration and governance. More
generally, though, there are weaknesses in the way that these insights have
been applied that lead us to conclude that the promise of the principal–agent
model in the study of the EU has not yet been fulfilled.
A first problem concerns the degree to which the four approaches simplify
the complexity of the EU in their application of these constructs. The
assumption that either member states or supranational institutions are unitary
actors is extremely questionable. The level of analysis selected by the authors
discussed may make this assumption attractive, but even as a convenient fiction
it is problematic. Moreover, the focus on member state control of process and
institutions – Garrett is the exception – precludes from the outset the possibility
of trans-institutional alliances, such as the coalitions constructed with the
Commission by member states that are keen to multilateralize their national
policy preferences (Héritier et al. 1996).
More problematic is the inclination to give a linear reading of integration.
LI and II privilege the role of national governments, while HIS and RCS stress
the influence of the Commission and Court and emphasize the inability of
the member states to assert their control. The danger is that subtleties of analysis
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
134
Journal of European Public Policy
promised by the principal–agent model are lost when a prior commitment is
made to a view that either national or supranational actors are likely to
predominate in the long term. The danger is not only a collapse into the
intergovernmentalism–neofunctionalism rivalry, but that intergovernmentalists
will continue to disregard evidence that the organizational capacities of national
governments are less than perfect, while supranationalists will overlook member
state abilities to ‘learn’, re-contract and restrict the Court and Commission, and
both will construe the relationship between member states and supranational
institutions in conflictual terms – a view that neglects the policy dimension
and asserts the transfer of sovereignty is always the central issue (Menon 2002)
and disregards the image of EU decision-making, increasingly championed by
scholars and practitioners, as co-operative (Wessels 1996; Lewis 1998, 1999)
and consensual (Mazey and Richardson 1995).
A second problem is what theorists ignore when they apply the principal–
agent approach. The limited focus – on the Commission and the Court of
Justice, and to a lesser extent, the Parliament, but not the Court of Auditors
or European agencies – is one illustration. The issues that arise from the
existence of multiple principals is, similarly, not fully explored – a major failing
given the importance of the question of the extent to which EU membership
circumscribes the autonomy of individual states.23 Only Garrett addresses the
question of multiple agents and how they interact. Nor does discussion of
principal drift – or what Sokolowski has called (in another context) ‘the
opportunist principal’ (2001)24 – figure in the approaches discussed above,
despite the relevance of principal drift to agency efficiency and independence.
The extent to which the efficiency of the Commission is diminished by
comitology or its neutrality threatened by infiltration by national officials,
typically, at the level of the cabinets, also merits closer attention. However, the
approaches surveyed above have been more concerned with agency discretion
than they have with agency efficiency.25
Moreover, the approaches surveyed above – II excepted – are biased
towards an interpretation of delegation and principal–agent that focuses on
informational aspects. The distributional consequences of institutional design
tend to be overlooked. The problem here is that distribution is a far more
important aspect of European integration and the EU – indeed of all
institutional structures (Knight 1992) – than is generally appreciated. Member
states are inclined to support the transfer of competences to the EU or back
the Commission, for example, when they are likely to win, but distribution
also has implications for continued willingness on the part of principals to
delegate significant power. Garrett and Weingast (1993: 186) observe that the
influence of an informal agenda-setter should be greatest when the distributional consequences of the policy are small. However, the scope, and importance, of Community action has expanded dramatically since 1991 with clear
implications, according to such reasoning, for the potential influence of the
Commission. Indeed, the sheer longevity of the EC/EU itself poses a serious
problem for those interested in utilizing the principal–agent model to explain
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
135
its development and functioning. Since 1957, various functions have been
delegated to Community institutions and the degree of autonomy from
member state control varies significantly between different policy fields and
functions. Inevitably, there are tensions between these various roles, and hence
attempting to utilize one specific form of principal–agent approach – for
instance, information based – is likely to provide at best only a partial
explanation.
Finally, delegation raises the issue of legitimacy. Delegation may improve
decision-making in valuable ways, but it may complicate or erode well-established lines of democratic accountability. In 1969, Ted Lowi launched a scathing
attack on Congress for delegating excessive power to unelected bureaucrats who
were entrusted with ever-increasing discretion over their areas of responsibility.
In the recent past, however, Majone (1993) has argued that the creation of
non-majoritarian institutions is entirely compatible with democratic decisionmaking. Legitimacy is of course related to efficiency, since the effectiveness of
an agent and, therefore, of the system as a whole, is usually at least partially a
function of the agent’s status and the way that it is perceived. Neglect of this
question is surprising, not only because of its intrinsic importance, but also in
view of widespread concern, especially since Maastricht, to enhance the democratic credentials of the EU (Menon and Weatherill 2002).
The question of effectiveness, the notion of delegation for distributional as
opposed to informational purposes, as well as the implications of delegation
for legitimacy and democratic accountability, are all, therefore, promising
avenues for future research on the EU based on the principal–agent model.
Such research could complement those approaches outlined above, and help
students of the EU to ensure that the scholarly achievements of those working
with this model match its early promise.
Addresses for correspondence: Hussein Kassim, School of Politics and
Sociology, Birkbeck College, University of London, Malet Street, London
WC1E 7HX, UK. Tel: ò44 (0) 20 7631 6788. Fax: ò44 (0) 20 7631 6787.
email:
[email protected]. Anand Menon, The European Research Institute,
University of Birmingham, Edgbaston, Birmingham B15 2TT, UK.
Tel:ò44 (0) 121 414 4058. email:
[email protected]
NOTES
1 We would like to thank Damian Chalmers, Sara Connolly, Dionyssis Dimitrakopoulos, Morten Hviid, Erik Jones, Bill Tompson, Catherine Waddams-Price,
Canice Prendergast, and two anonymous reviewers for many helpful suggestions.
Any errors are our own. Anand Menon gratefully acknowledges the support of
British Academy small Grant SG-31906.
2 See, for example, Egan (1998); Franchino (2001); Garrett (1992); Garrett and
Weingast (1993); Menon (2002); Moravcsik (1993 1998); Pierson (1996); Pollack
(1996, 1997); Stetter (2000).
3 Space constraints permit no more than a cursory treatment. Useful discussions are
to be found in Moe (1984) and Kassim and Menon (2002).
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
136
Journal of European Public Policy
4 We follow Doleys’ distinction between approaches that emphasize the influence
of supranational institutions on EU decision-making (‘supranationalism’) and
neofunctionalism, which makes additional claims about the process of integration
and the inevitability of integration (2000: note 4).
5 See Hall and Taylor (1996).
6 See Moe (1987) for a critical overview.
7 See Keohane (1984). For application in European politics, see Bergman et al.
(2000); Thatcher and Stone Sweet (2002).
8 See also Hall and Taylor (1996: 945–6).
9 See above, note 2.
10 This debate has, in recent years, generated more heat than light and has imposed
a straitjacket on theoretical inquiry (Schmidt 1996; Branch and Øhrgaard 1999).
11 See Sandholtz (1996) for a discussion of this problem in relation to LI.
12 Quite unanticipated by the member states, ‘the ECJ has constitutionalized the
Treaty of Rome, built alliances with domestic courts and interest groups, preempted national law in important cases, and opened new avenues for Commission
initiative, as in cases like ERTA in common commercial policy, and Cassis de Dijon
in technical harmonization’ (Moravcsik 1993: 513).
13 We owe this point to Damian Chalmers.
14 Exactly the reverse is true in the case of the Council Presidency, where the
incumbent member state is expected to play the role of ‘honest broker’.
15 See Hooghe (2002) on the orientation of Commission officials.
16 Moravcsik acknowledges this point when he argues that member states take into
account the likelihood that future streams of substantive decisions resulting from
the pooling or delegation of sovereignty will be to their benefit when deciding on
institutional design, but does not discuss the tension between information-based
and distributional consequence views.
17 See Garrett (1992, 1995a, 1995b); Garrett and Tsebelis (1996); Tsebelis and
Garrett (2001).
18 See note 17.
19 See note 17.
20 We owe these points to Damian Chalmers.
21 In fact, in the first section of his article, Pierson (1996) takes the view that the
projection of supranational institutions as agents implies their subservience to the
member states. However, he later uses a more familiar construal where asymmetric
information enables agents to escape the control of the principal (p. 139).
22 Our reading of Pollack as a supranationalist reflects the position he adopts in his
theoretical writings. Although his empirical work (e.g. 2000) highlights the power
of the member states, it is not grounded in the perspective elaborated in his
theoretical writings.
23 Although Pollack (1997) discusses how divergent interests between the member
states enable supranational agents to behave opportunistically, he does not explain
how and under what conditions this might occur, and he certainly does not address
the question, raised by Marks et al. (1996), of the impact of European integration
on individual, as opposed to collective, sovereignty of the member states.
24 We thank Bill Tompson for drawing this concept to our attention.
25 Though Pollack (1997: 115) does make a passing reference to this issue.
REFERENCES
Axelrod, R. (1984) The Evolution of Cooperation, New York: Basic Books.
Bergman, T., Müller, W.C. and Strøm, K. (2000) ‘Parliamentary democracy and the
chain of delegation’, European Journal of Political Research 37(3): special issue.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
137
Branch, A.P. and Øhrgaard, J.C. (1999) ‘Trapped in the supranational–
intergovernmental dichotomy: a response to Stone Sweet and Sandholtz’, Journal
of European Public Policy 6(1): 123–43.
Burley, A.-M. and Mattli, W. (1993) ‘Europe before the Court: a political theory of
legal integration’, International Organization 49(1): 171–81.
Cram, L. (1993) ‘Calling the tune without paying the piper? Social policy regulation’,
Policy and Politics 21(2): 135.
Dogan, R. (1997) ‘Comitology: little procedures with big implications’, West European
Politics 20(3): 31–60.
Doleys, T.J. (2000) ‘Member states and the European Commission: theoretical insights
from the new economics of organization’, Journal of European Public Policy 7(4):
532–53.
Egan, M. (1998) ‘Regulatory strategies, delegation and European market integration’,
Journal of European Public Policy 5(3): 485–506.
Eichener, V. (1993) ‘Social dumping or innovative regulation?’, EUI Working Paper
No. 92/28, Florence: European University Institute.
Epstein, D. and O’Halloran, S. (1999) Delegating Powers, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Fiorina, M.P. (1977) Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment, New Haven:
Yale University Press.
Franchino, F. (2001) ‘Delegation and constraints in the national execution of the EC
policies’, West European Politics 24(4): 169–92.
Garrett, G. (1992) ‘International cooperation and institutional choice: the European
Community’s internal market’, International Organization 46: 533–58.
Garrett, G. (1995a) ‘From the Luxembourg compromise to codecision: decisionmaking in the European Union’, Electoral Studies 14(3): 289–308.
Garrett, G. (1995b) ‘The politics of legal integration in the European Union’,
International Organization 49(1): 171–81.
Garrett, G. and Tsebelis, G. (1996) ‘Agenda setting power, power indices, and decisionmaking in the European Union’, International Review of Law and Economics 16:
345–61.
Garrett, G. and Weingast, B. (1993) ‘Ideas, interests, and institutions: constructing
the European Community’s internal market’, in J. Goldstein and R.O. Keohane
(eds), Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, pp. 173–206.
Hall, P.A. and Taylor, R.C.R. (1996) ‘Political science and the three new institutionalisms’, Political Studies 44(5): 936–57.
Héritier, A., Knill, C. and Mingers, S. (1996) Ringing the Changes in Europe, London:
Walter de Gruyter.
Holmstrom, B. (1979) ‘Moral hazard and observability’, Bell Journal of Economics 10:
74–91.
Hooghe, L. (2002) The European Commission and the Integration of Europe, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Horn, M.J. and Shepsle, K.A. (1989) ‘Administrative process and organizational form
as legislative responses to agency costs’, Virginia Law Review 75: 499–509.
Kassim, H. (2000) ‘Conclusion’, in H. Kassim, B.G. Peters and V. Wright (eds), The
National Co-ordination of EU Policy: The Domestic Level, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 235–64.
Kassim, H. (2003, forthcoming) ‘The European administration: between Europeanisation and domestication’, in J. Hayward and A. Menon (eds), Governing Europe,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kassim, H. and Menon, A. (2002) ‘The principal–agent approach and the study of
the European Union: a provisional assessment’, manuscript.
Kassim, H. and Menon, A. (2003, forthcoming) ‘Europe in the 1990s: the re-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
138
Journal of European Public Policy
assertion of member state control’, in Dionyssis Dimitrakopoulos (ed.), The Prodi
Commission, Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Kassim, H. and Wright, V. (1991) ‘The role of national administrations in the
decision-making processes of the European Community’, Rivista Trimestrale di
Diritto Pubblico 3: 832–50.
Kassim, H., Menon, A., Peters, B.G. and Wright, V. (eds) (2001) The National Coordination of EU Policy: The European Level, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kassim, H., Peters, B.G. and Wright, V. (eds) (2000) The National Co-ordination of
EU Policy: The Domestic Level, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Keohane, R.O. (1984) After Hegemony, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kiewiet, D.R. and McCubbins, M.D. (1991) The Logic of Delegation: Congressional
Parties and the Appropriations Process, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Knight, J. (1992) Institutions and Social Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Lewis, J. (1998) ‘Is the ‘‘hard bargaining’’ image of the Council misleading?’, Journal
of Common Market Studies 36(4): 457–77.
Lewis, J. (1999) ‘Administrative rivalry in the Council’s infrastructure: diagnosing the
methods of Community in EU decision-making’. Paper delivered at the Sixth
Biennial ECSA International Conference, 2–5 June 1999.
Lowi, T.J. (1969) The End of Liberalism, New York: Norton.
McCubbins, M.D. and Page, T. (1987) ‘A theory of Congressional delegation’, in
M.D. McCubbins and T. Sullivan (eds), Congress: Structure and Policy, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 409–25.
McCubbins, M.D. and Schwartz, T. (1984) ‘Congressional oversight overlooked:
police patrols versus fire alarms’, American Journal of Political Science 28: 165–79.
McCubbins, M.D., Noll, R. and Weingast, B. (1987) ‘Administrative procedures as
instruments of political control’, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 3:
242–79.
McCubbins, M.D., Noll, R. and Weingast, B. (1989) ‘Structure and process, politics
and policy: administrative arrangements and the political control of agencies’,
Virginia Law Review 75: 431–83.
McKelvey, R.D. (1976) ‘Intransitivities in multidimensional voting: models and some
implications for agenda control’, Journal of Economic Theory 12: 472–82.
Majone, G. (1993) ‘The European Community: an ‘‘independent fourth branch of
government?’’ ’, EUI Working Paper SPS 93/9, Florence: European University
Institute.
Majone, G. (1994) ‘The rise of the regulatory state in Europe’, West European Politics
17(3): 77–101.
Marks, G., Hooghe, L. and Blank, K. (1996) ‘European integration from the 1980s’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 34(3): 341–78.
Mazey, S. and Richardson, J. (1995) ‘Promiscuous policymaking: the European policy
style?’, in C. Rhodes and S. Mazey (eds), The State of the European Union: Vol. 3,
London: Longman, pp. 337–59.
Menon, A. (2002) ‘Member states and international institutions: institutionalizing
intergovernmentalism in the European Union’, manuscript.
Menon, A. and Weatherill, S. (2002) ‘Legitimacy, accountability and delegation in the
European Union’, in A. Arnull and D. Wincott (eds), Accountability and Legitimacy
in the EU after Nice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Milgrom, P. and Roberts, J. (1992) Economics, Organization and Management, New
York: Prentice Hall.
Moe, T.M. (1984) ‘The new economics of organization’, American Journal of Political
Science 28: 739–77.
Moe, T.M. (1987) ‘An assessment of the positive theory of ‘‘Congressional
dominance’’ ’, Legislative Studies Quarterly 12: 475–520.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:14 17 January 2009
H. Kassim & A. Menon: The principal–agent approach and the EU
139
Moe, T.M. (1989) ‘The politics of bureaucratic structure’, in J.E. Chubb and P.E.
Peterson (eds), Can the Government Govern?, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, pp. 267–329.
Moe, T.M. (1990) ‘The politics of structural choice: toward a theory of public
bureaucracy’, in O.E. Williamson (ed.), Organization Theory: From Chester Barnard
to the Present and Beyond, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 116–53.
Moravcsik, A. (1993) ‘Preferences and power in the European Community: a liberal
intergovernmentalist spproach’, Journal of Common Market Studies 31(4): 473–524.
Moravcsik, A. (1998) The Choice for Europe, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Pierson, P. (1996) ‘The path to European integration: a historical institutionalist
analysis’, Comparative Political Studies 29(2): 123–63.
Pollack, M.A. (1996) ‘The new institutionalism and EU governance: the promise and
limits of institutionalist analysis’, Governance 9(4): 429–58.
Pollack, M.A. (1997) ‘Delegation, agency and agenda setting in the European
Community’, International Organization 51(1): 99–134.
Pollack, M.A. (2000) ‘The end of creeping competence? EU policy-making since
Maastricht’, Journal of Common Market Studies 38(3): 519–38.
Riker, W. (1980) ‘Implications from the dis-equilibrium of majority rule for the study
of institutions’, American Political Science Review 74: 432–47.
Ross, S.A. (1973) ‘The economic theory of agency: the principal’s problem’, American
Economic Review 63(2): 134–9.
Sandholtz, W. (1996) ‘Membership matters: limits of the functional approach to
European institutions’, Journal of Common Market Studies 34(3): 403–29.
Schmidt, S.K. (1996) ‘Sterile debates and dubious generalisations: European integration
theory tested by telecommunications and electricity’, Journal of Public Policy 16(3):
233–71.
Shepsle, K.A. (1979) ‘The institutional foundations of committee power’, American
Economic Review 81: 85–104.
Shepsle, K.A. (1992) ‘Bureaucratic drift, coalitional drift and time consistency’, Journal
of Law, Economics and Organization 8: 111–18.
Shepsle, K.A. and Bonchek, M.S. (1997) Analysing Politics: Rationality, Behavior, and
Institutions, New York: Norton.
Sokolowski, A. (2001) ‘Bankrupt government: intra-executive relations and the politics
of budgetary irresponsibility in Yeltsin’s Russia’, Europe-Asia Studies 53(4): 541–72.
Stetter, S. (2000) ‘Regulating migration: authority delegation in justice and home
affairs’, Journal of European Public Policy 7(1): 80–103.
Thatcher, M. and Stone Sweet, A. (eds) (2002) ‘Delegation to non-majoritarian
institutions’, West European Politics 25(1): special issue.
Tsebelis, G. and Garrett, G. (2001) ‘The institutional foundation of intergovernmentalism and supranationalism in the European Union’, International Organization
55(2): 357–90.
Weingast, B.R. and Marshall, W.J. (1988) ‘The industrial organization of Congress;
or, why legislatures, like firms, are not organized as markets’, The Journal of Political
Economy 96(1): 132–63.
Weingast, B.R. and Moran, M.J. (1983) ‘Bureaucratic discretion or Congressional
control?’, Journal of Political Economy 91: 765–800.
Wessels, W. (1996) ‘An ever closer fusion?’, Journal of Common Market Studies 34(1):
128–45.
Williamson, O.E. (1985) Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York: Free Press.
This article was downloaded by: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge]
On: 17 January 2009
Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 791963552]
Publisher Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,
37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Journal of European Public Policy
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713685697
Idiosyncrasy and integration: suggestions from comparative political economy
Online Publication Date: 01 March 2003
To cite this Article (2003)'Idiosyncrasy and integration: suggestions from comparative political economy',Journal of European Public
Policy,10:1,140 — 158
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046985
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350176032000046985
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Journal of European Public Policy 10:1 February 2003: 140–158
Idiosyncrasy and integration:
suggestions from comparative
political economy
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
Erik Jones1
ABSTRACT There is a growing consensus in comparative political economy that
‘globalization’ is not eliminating the distinctive character of specific nation-states.
Even in Europe, where formal integration between countries is most profound,
nation-states remain idiosyncratic. Starting from this consensus, the questions I ask
are: (a) how can we explain the coincidence of national idiosyncrasy and international integration; (b) what does our explanation tell us about processes of European
integration? The answers, I argue, lie in two theoretical traditions – one stemming
from Karl Polanyi’s (1957) insistence on the social embeddedness of market
institutions and the other from Gunnar Myrdal’s (1956) interpretation of the
cumulative causality behind integration at the national and international levels.
Although well received in other areas, neither tradition has played much of a role
in the study of the European Union. The article concludes by suggesting a research
program that could develop from the interface between idiosyncrasy and integration.
KEY WORDS Convergence; divergence; globalization; integration; Myrdal;
Polanyi.
INTRODUCTION
Students of comparative political economy have reached a consensus that the
world’s advanced industrial societies are not growing any more alike – at least
not necessarily. Globalization, technological development, de-industrialization,
demographic change, and a host of other factors all press upon welfare states
and social institutions. Nevertheless, the result of this pressure is little or no
necessary convergence on some common set of norms, institutions, or practices
across countries.2 Of course, parallels do emerge from one case to the next.
Yet these are more incidental than indicative in nature. The subtitle of Scharpf
and Schmidt (2000b) captures the essence of the argument: ‘diverse responses
to common challenges.’
The absence of necessary convergence is nowhere more surprising than in
Europe, where the remarkable development of the European Union (EU) must
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/1350176032000046985
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
141
be added to the list of exogenous and endogenous challenges to national
distinctiveness. The countries of Europe nevertheless provide the richest source
of empirical support for the persistence of differences. For comparative
political economists this juxtaposition of European integration and national
distinctiveness underscores the relative importance of other causal factors
affecting the varieties of capitalism in evidence. For students of European
integration, the confluence of factors is more fundamentally significant: if
integration in Europe does not coincide with some form of necessary convergence between the member states, then what does ‘integration’ really mean?
The purpose of this article is to reflect the consensus in comparative political
economy against the backdrop of European integration. My goal is not to
survey the application of new institutionalist approaches to the study of the
EU; nor is it to provide some deep methodological critique of the competing
frameworks used for analysis. Such arguments have already been pursued
comprehensively by authors like Aspinwall and Schneider (2000) and Peterson
(2001). In contrast with these authors’ efforts to survey the breadth of the
literature, my ambitions are limited more to illustrating some of the principal
causal mechanisms at work and to suggesting some of the implications of
focusing attention on those mechanisms. The questions I ask are two: How
can we explain the persistence of national diversity within the common
institutional framework of the EU? What does the explanation tell us about
the process of European integration? The answer to the first question conforms
closely to the consensus view (albeit in simplified form): using Karl Polanyi’s
(1957) analysis of the ‘double movement’ behind the social embeddedness of
market institutions it is possible to suggest both why countries differ and how
European unity might contribute to national diversity.
The answer to the second question represents a departure from the existing
consensus in comparative political economy. Rather than bracketing national
diversity as something to be explained, it opens up the possibility that the
idiosyncratic character of this diversity may be part of the explanation for the
pattern of integration witnessed in Europe. The challenge is to develop a
framework for analyzing the interaction between idiosyncrasy and integration.
Gunnar Myrdal’s (1956) interpretation of the cumulative causal forces behind
integration at the national and international level offers one possible solution.
More important, Myrdal’s analytic framework provides a basis for research on
Europe that is different from the canon of integration theory and yet consistent
with the consensus view in comparative political economy.
The article is developed in five sections. The first surveys the comparative
political economy consensus in order to explain the idiosyncratic nature of
national diversity. The second demonstrates the use of Polanyi’s ‘double
movement’ in explaining the causality that runs from integration to idiosyncrasy. The third introduces Myrdal’s cumulative causality as a means of bringing
idiosyncrasy and integration into dynamic interaction. The fourth suggests a
research program that could develop at the interface between idiosyncrasy and
integration. The fifth section concludes.
142
Journal of European Public Policy
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
FROM DIVERSITY TO IDIOSYNCRASY
The consensus among comparative political economists is at the same time
deep and eclectic. It is deep insofar as most comparative political economists
agree that countries have remained distinctive despite the many common
forces acting upon them. Yet it is eclectic in the sense that different authors
tend to highlight different areas of distinctiveness. Hence any broad survey of
the literature would turn up a host of resilient ‘differences’ between countries
that are important to economic performance, international competitiveness,
institutional adaptiveness, or democratic stability.
The variety is most easily evident when viewed in terms of horizontal strata.
Wage-bargaining institutions, monetary authorities (including central banks),
distributive policies, tax regimes, political ideologies, and patterns of partypolitical competition constitute the focus of concern for macro-analysis.
Corporate governance, supply networks, infrastructure, labor organization,
labor market regulations, and skills development provide a meso-layer for
attention. Social capital, interpersonal trust, popular values, and the economics
of the family lie at the micro-layer.
The vertical concerns cutting across these strata are less immediately tangible
and yet fundamentally no less diverse. For example, prevailing conceptions of
distributive justice and patterns of distributive conflict necessarily stretch from
the micro- to the macro-level of aggregation. Yet how are we meant to translate
‘the spirit of co-operation’ or ‘the notion of fairness’ or even ‘social democracy’
from one national context to the next without pointing to specific combinations
of stratified characteristics – this type of family, this level of interpersonal trust,
this pattern of industrialization, this form of corporate governance, these skills,
this infrastructure, these policies, these policy institutions, and so forth? The
easy answer is to invoke some essential characteristic – Asian values, German
inflation aversion, Dutch consensus, and the American work ethic. The more
difficult (and yet fortunately more common) answer is to bracket a set of
necessary or indicative features for analyzing particular problems. Wage bargaining and unemployment, central banks and inflation, social capital and
democratic stability, and so forth. Such work has undoubtably enriched our
understanding of why difference matters. Yet it has also had the inadvertent
effect of creating a set of functionally specific vertical pillars that are every bit
as diverse in content as the horizontal strata they intersect.
The eclecticism at the heart of the comparative political economy consensus
derives not from the observation that countries are diverse but from the reality
that this diversity is idiosyncratic. It is possible to connect a particular structure
of the family with a particular form of corporate governance and a particular
pattern of party-political competition – as is often done in studies of French
industrialization during the Third Republic. Yet the connections are historically
contingent or, more generally, sensitively dependent upon initial conditions.
So, for example, if we hoped to recreate French bourgeois capitalism in one of
the transition countries in Central Europe, we would have to control for much
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
143
more than the structure of the family, the form of corporate governance, or
the pattern of party-political competition. Indeed, we would have to control
for so many factors that inevitably the effort would prove futile. This was the
lesson learned by Soviet economists in Central Europe during the 1950s and
rediscovered by Western economists in Central Europe during the 1990s.
Countries will develop idiosyncratically or not at all.
The use of the term idiosyncrasy in this context is deliberate. My point is
not simply that countries are different in certain respects. Rather it is that
even similarities across countries are likely to have arisen for different reasons,
along differing trajectories, and with different implications or effects. The scale
of these differences need not be tremendous and in metaphorical terms it is
easy to imagine that countries will bear family resemblances. However, the
significance of the family metaphor should not be overestimated. Even two
countries with a long heritage in common – such as Belgium and the
Netherlands – should not be expected to resemble one another or even to hold
common features – such as consociational democracy – for the same or similar
reasons.
The idiosyncratic basis of national distinctiveness is unsurprising insofar as
it reflects another deep and yet eclectic consensus in comparative political
economy (and elsewhere) known broadly as the ‘new institutionalism’.3 The
consensus is that institutions matter. The eclecticism lies in how institutions
matter and why. Without digressing too far, suffice it to say that the
new institutionalism constitutes a cross-hatch of direct and circular causal
mechanisms implicating institutions both in particular outcomes and in their
own reproduction. Moreover, this cross-hatch of causal mechanisms is every
bit as complicated as the horizontal strata and vertical pillars for national
difference suggested above. Institutions matter in ways and for reasons that
both reflect and impact upon their broader environment including actors,
other institutions, and themselves.
The link between the new institutionalism and the consensus on resilient
national distinctiveness is analytic and not accidental. Countries remain
different because institutions matter. And national differences are idiosyncratic
because institutions matter for reasons and in ways that are sensitively
dependent upon initial conditions, on context, on timing, and on the beliefs
or attitudes of the actors that interact through them or within them. At a
macro-level this explains why the notion of diverse responses to common
challenges has such appeal. The alternative would be inconsistent with the
new institutionalist consensus. In order to anticipate that common challenges
should engender common responses, it would be necessary to assume that any
response to globalization, demographic change, and so forth, could be fashioned
as though differences in institutional context (and therefore institutions) do
not matter.
The implications here extend beyond the notion of diverse responses to
common challenges and encompass the correlation between institutional form
and institutional function. In order to insist that only one institutional
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
144
Journal of European Public Policy
configuration can guarantee a particular economic outcome it would be
necessary to assume that some institutions matter and yet others do not. For
example, an equivalent assertion might be that a politically independent central
bank can guarantee price stability no matter how politics or markets may be
organized. Even the framers of Europe’s economic and monetary union could
not make that leap of faith and so invested considerable resources in flanking
the European Central Bank with a variety of institutional and procedural
supports.
The link between the consensus on national diversity and the consensus
that institutions matter extends all the way down to the micro-motivational
or cultural level as well. In order to regress any type of performance – such as
economic growth or political stability – back to some prior or fundamental
characteristic – such as interpersonal trust – it would be necessary to assume
that institutions matter in some areas but not in others: continuing with the
same example, institutions can reflect or channel interpersonal trust but they
cannot shape it, create it, or diminish it.
The reason for highlighting the interconnections between the consensus on
resilient distinctiveness and the consensus on the new institutionalism is not
to suggest that countries are idiosyncratic and therefore there is no basis for a
comparative analysis of institutions, performance, or the link between the two.
Nor can my argument be read in any way as some comprehensive survey of
new institutionalism and the convergence–divergence debate in comparative
political economy. Rather my goal is to suggest only that idiosyncrasy matters
as a persistent feature for analysis both in its own right and with reference to
the impact it has on institutional arrangements which cross national boundaries.
Recognition of idiosyncrasy offers insights both as an effect and as a cause.
IDIOSYNCRASY AND POLANYI’S ‘DOUBLE MOVEMENT’
In order to illustrate the analytic significance of national idiosyncrasy, I need
first to resuscitate Polanyi’s (1957) ‘double movement’ as an explanation for
the emergence of distinctively national political economies. The reason for
going back to Polanyi is that his analysis of The Great Transformation which
ushered in the welfare state has had a seminal influence on the study
of comparative political economy generally and on the development of
institutionalism in particular. Not every comparative political economist agrees
with Polanyi in every detail and few regard him as holding the last word.
Nevertheless, Polanyi’s argument lies at the foundation of the current consensus.
Hence, for example, Hollingsworth and Boyer (1997) dedicate their collection
of essays to Polanyi, while Scharpf and Schmidt (2000a) invoke his argument
in the first sentence of their introduction. In this sense, Polanyi’s ‘double
movement’ is a greatest common denominator among comparative political
economists who might otherwise differ on the specifics of how they believe
the welfare state has developed subsequently or what they hold to be the most
important explanatory mechanisms behind that development.
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
145
As an empirical claim, Polanyi’s ‘double movement’ is descriptive and refers
to the observation that:
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
While on the one hand markets spread all over the globe [during the
nineteenth century] and the amount of goods involved grew to unbelievable
proportions, on the other hand a network of measures and policies was
integrated into powerful institutions designed to check the actions of the
market relative to labor, land, and money.
(Polanyi 1957: 76)
The vast spread of markets was the globalization of the nineteenth century.
The emergence of the welfare state was the response. And, in this cause–effect
relationship, the paradox for Polanyi (p. 141) was that: ‘while laissez faire
economy was the product of deliberate state action, subsequent restrictions
on laissez faire started in a spontaneous way.’ To paraphrase closely (but
anachronistically) the next sentence in Polanyi’s argument, the globalization of
markets was planned but the structure and functioning of the welfare state
was not. From an empirical standpoint, then, it is possible to anticipate the
idiosyncratic origins of the welfare states as a prior expression of Scharpf and
Schmidt’s ‘diverse responses to common challenges’. The point to note,
however, is that to some extent at least the common challenges were a result
of state action.
But Polanyi’s ‘double movement’ is more than just an empirical claim. It is
also a theoretical proposition about the politics of economic adjustment. The
mechanism at work behind the double movement develops from the logic of
distributive politics. Any economic adjustment imposes costs as well as providing
benefits. And the distribution of costs and benefits is often inequitable across
different groups in society. Hence we should anticipate that groups adversely
affected by a change will mobilize in search of redress. As Polanyi explains:
Sectional interests are thus the natural vehicle of social and political change.
Whether the source of change be war or trade, startling inventions or shifts
in natural conditions, the various sections in society will stand for different
methods of adjustment (including forcible ones) and adjust their interests
in a different way from those of other groups to whom they may seek to
give a lead; hence only when one can point to the group or groups that
effect a change is it explained how that change came about.
(Polanyi 1957: 152)
Moreover, Polanyi is insistent that the motives of these sectional groups cannot
be reduced to some objective economic calculation. Rather distributive politics
takes place within cultural and institutional environments wherein the values
attached to particular strategies or outcomes have a strong subjective component. ‘To employ a metaphor, the facts of the economy were originally
embedded in situations that were not in themselves of an economic nature,
neither the ends nor the means being primarily material’ (Dalton 1968: 120).
The implication of Polanyi’s argument is that sectional interests necessarily
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
146
Journal of European Public Policy
reflect at least some of the idiosyncrasy of their local environment. ‘[In] any
given case, the societal effects of individual behavior depend on the presence
of definite individual conditions, these conditions do not for that reason result
from the personal behavior in question’ (Dalton 1968: 150). In this way,
Polanyi’s argument does not collapse into a tautology within which societal
difference is the necessary product of its own creation. Rather it suggests only
that environmental factors influence any calculation of ‘rationality’. The more
diverse these factors are from one context to the next, the more likely we
should expect differences to emerge in separately ‘rational’ responses to
common challenges. Of course there is an element of path dependence
leading from difference in one time period to difference in another as the
institutionalized responses to one challenge influence the calculation of rationality in responding to another. However, the mechanism behind this path
dependence derives from calculations (and understandings) of rationality and
not from history per se.4
History matters for our interpretation of Polanyi more in the structure of
the argument than in its content or implications. The force of Polanyi’s
claim about the strong subjective component of sectional motivation lies in
opposition to the ‘class-based interests’ that predominated in the Marxist
political economy of his day. His assertion that sectional interests are the
natural vehicle of social and political change underscores that class interests
are not. Crucially, the distinction between a ‘section’ and a ‘class’ lies in the
sensitive dependence of sectional interests on local institutional, social, and
cultural factors. Where Marxists might claim that class structures transcend
national boundaries, Polanyi would counter that sectional interests resist strong
categorical aggregation or extrapolation from one context to the next.
The politics of economic adjustment working behind the double movement
is distributive, and yet the rationality at its basis is contextually specific.
Moreover, the context of distributive politics encompasses more than market
institutions to include a range of institutions without explicit economic
rationale. In this way, Polanyi not only explains the institutional reaction to
the emergence of world markets but also the growing diversity of responses to
the common challenges that world markets represent. In Polanyi’s empirical
account, this diversity ultimately spells the demise of world markets and so
ushers in the Great Depression. And, in turn, the collapse of the world
economy facilitated the ‘rise of a variety of new societies’ (Polanyi 1957: 252).
However, that great transformation that culminated in the 1930s was but a
transitory phase in history. In Polanyi’s theoretical account, the diversity of
national institutional environments constitutes the defining characteristic of
political economics. ‘Nothing is more obvious to the student of social
anthropology than the variety of institutions found to be compatible with
practically identical instruments of production’ (Dalton 1968: 71). Moreover,
the ubiquity of such variety constitutes the link for Polanyi between idiosyncrasy and integration. The problem of integration is not to ensure a strong
form of mechanistic determinism in the form of comprehensive market rules
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
147
or laws of economic behavior, nor is it to impose institutional conformism
around a single set of structures or principles. Rather Polanyi invokes the term
‘integration’ to describe the use of institutions to structure patterns of behavior
so as to create a sustainable and self-propagating balance between collective
interdependence and individual freedom in a given context (Dalton 1968:
139–74). Moreover, his use of the term is explicitly normative and contingent:
political actors should strive to strike a balance between interdependence and
freedom; they should do so in full awareness of the contextual specificity
within which they operate; and they should accept that it is possible to fail.
Polanyi’s empirical claim about the origins of the welfare state clearly
antedates the process of European integration. However, Polanyi’s theoretical
argument has both positive and normative implications for our understanding
of the integration process. In positive terms, European integration lies behind
a new double movement for Europe’s welfare states. It is a common impetus
to which the countries of Europe should be expected to respond differently,
contingently, even idiosyncratically. Hence from Polanyi’s perspective, the
consensus among comparative political economists concerning the resilience
of national differences is unsurprising. Indeed, the link between integration
and idiosyncrasy in Europe is causal.
In normative terms, Polanyi’s theoretical argument suggests that European
integration should result in the achievement of some dynamic and yet sustainable balance between interdependence and freedom for the participating
member states. Once Europe’s heads of state and government accept the social
embeddedness of institutions (including market institutions), they must also
accept variation across societies as a necessary constraint on the use of power
to ‘ensure . . . that measure of conformity which is needed for the survival of
the group’ (Polanyi 1957: 258).
The challenge for theorists of European integration is to reconcile the
tension between the positive and normative implications of Polanyi’s argument.
If the effect of integration is to encourage diversity, and the effect of diversity
is to constrain the inducement of that measure of conformity which is necessary
for the survival of the group as a group, then how is the dynamic balance at
the heart of ‘integration’ to be achieved? Moreover, what will be the impact of
efforts to balance integration at the European level (which is not actually the
focus for Polanyi’s analysis) on efforts to balance integration at the national or
societal level (which is)? These are not questions for which Polanyi has a clear
answer. The answers are not manifest in the comparative political economy
consensus on resilient diversity or on the new institutionalism. And the answers
are almost entirely absent from the theoretical canon concerning European
integration. Almost.
INTEGRATION AND MYRDAL’S ‘CUMULATIVE CAUSALITY’
One theorist who has addressed the dynamic balance implicit in Polanyi’s
conception of integration both generally and in relation to Europe is Gunnar
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
148
Journal of European Public Policy
Myrdal (1956). In his book, An International Economy: Problems and Prospects,
Myrdal sets out a framework for analyzing integration as a process that is at the
same time cumulative, causal, multi-level, and reversible. Moreover, Myrdal’s
framework builds explicitly upon the normative contrast between conformity
and diversity that is analyzed by Polanyi. The tension between conformity and
diversity exists and the goal of integration is to move toward a particular
understanding of balance between these competing forces.5
The complementarity between Polanyi and Myrdal is as much analytic and
empirical as normative. Both writers are institutionalists who accord a central
role in all accounts of social development and political reform to the interaction
between individual values and collective institutions. And both predicate much
of their analysis on the overwhelming significance of the Great Depression of
the 1930s as an episode of international disintegration. The difference between
them is that where Polanyi posits the Great Depression at the end of his
narrative account, Myrdal places it at the beginning. Both agree that the
development of national economic institutions fragmented world markets.
Polanyi’s focus is on how this came about. Myrdal’s is on what should be the
appropriate response. Hence where Polanyi reserves his normative arguments
until the end of The Great Transformation, Myrdal posits his normative
emphasis up front. Economic integration, he asserts, is ‘the realization of the
old Western ideal of equality of opportunity’, and ‘ ‘‘international economic
integration’’ is the realization of the same ideal of equality of opportunity in
the relations between peoples of different nations’ (Myrdal 1956: 11, 13).
The overtly normative emphasis in Myrdal’s conception of integration is
likely to put off many contemporary analysts of Europe. Nevertheless, it is
important not to be distracted by Myrdal’s own insistence on the normative
or ideological basis of his claim. In the context of more contemporary analysis,
the force of Myrdal’s normative claim derives from his analytic dependence on
the interaction between values and institutions. For Myrdal, institutional
reform cannot have effect unless it is somehow accompanied (or even preceded)
by a change in values. Hence it makes little sense to analyze processes of
institutional development – like integration – without identifying the normative framework within which they are embedded. The resonance here between
Myrdal and Polanyi is acute.
Nevertheless, readers familiar with Polanyi and not with Myrdal may
anticipate a contradiction in their respective normative frameworks. As a
further point of introduction, therefore, it is useful to note that Myrdal’s
reliance on ‘equality of opportunity’ and classical Western liberalism does not
contradict Polanyi’s own rejection of liberal market ideology. Indeed, the
similarities between the two authors are striking – particularly given the
absence of cross-reference. Myrdal (1956: 25) suggests that ‘a purely liberal –
i.e. nondiscriminatory and ‘‘impartial’’ – national community is almost a
contradiction in terms’; that ‘in all advanced countries the secular trend has
been away from a free market economy governed by the interplay of market
forces’; and that:
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
149
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
It is a paradox that only a well-integrated community can abide by the rules
of economic competition; but that an integrated community will modify
the rules if changes in prices impose too drastic a decline in the income of
any one sector, or require too sudden shifts of resources or, more generally,
if the community favors a course of economic development other than the
one that would result from the free play of market forces.
(Myrdal 1956: 25)
Indeed, Myrdal (1956: 32–3) even has his own version of Polanyi’s double
movement, within which a principal (though not exclusive) stimulus for the
elaboration of many of the institutions of the welfare state can be found in
the reaction of social groups within national communities to the risks and
adjustments implied by world market forces. For Myrdal as for Polanyi, the
result is that ‘cultural differences between populations on different sides of
state boundaries, which were originally minor, are steadily accentuated as
interests are focused on national issues and increasingly institutionalized within
the state framework’ (1956: 35).
The value that Myrdal adds to Polanyi’s argument lies in his elaboration of
the ‘cumulative causation’ behind processes of integration and disintegration.
As already indicated, much of the causal force in the argument derives from
the relationship between values and institutions. In turn, this linkage is
underpinned by Myrdal’s assessment of the structure of distributive conflict
within conditions of relative scarcity and relative surplus. And, it is in the
assembly of institutional, attitudinal, and economic forces that the utility of
Myrdal’s liberal emphasis becomes apparent.6
The origins of integration for Myrdal are predominantly attitudinal. Actors
choose to equalize opportunities within a group through the elimination of
barriers, the redistribution of resources, or (more usually) some combination
of the two. The choice may be motivated by collective or complementary selfinterest, and yet it must also be underpinned by some more general commitment to the virtues of collective action (in what readers may recognize as an
early form of the argument for social capital [p. 22]). Once the choice for
equalization becomes institutionalized, the success of the reform measure is
contingent upon an identification with the institutions and a willingness to
abide by the new rules they imply – two factors which Myrdal describes as
comprising ‘solidarity’ within the given context. Actors must accept to participate in a competitive market and they must agree to contribute to
redistribution.
Beyond this point, Myrdal’s emphasis shifts from attitudes and institutions
to economics and back again. The economic effect of the equalization of
opportunity within a group should be welfare enhancing – this is the liberal
premise. In turn, the effect of welfare enhancement should be to mitigate the
obstacles to a further extension of equality of opportunity while at the same
time reinforcing the appeal of engaging in collective institution-building.
Distributive conflict is less disruptive and collective action is more attractive
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
150
Journal of European Public Policy
in conditions of relative surplus. This is how Myrdal closes the cycle for
cumulation. However, given the central significance of attitudes and institutions
in the process, the end result is idiosyncratic and not economically (or
ideologically) predetermined: ‘From this point of view of their cumulative
effects upon attitudes and, therefore, possibilities for further advance, even
small institutional accomplishments become potentially important’ (Myrdal
1956: 55). Processes of integration are path dependent.
A similar cumulation lies behind processes of disintegration. However, the
origins of disintegration are predominantly economic rather than attitudinal.
Unexpected economic hardship or dislocation undermines the willingness of
groups to engage in institutional commitments to equality of opportunity and
heightens the significance of distributive conflict. Instead of solidarity, different
groups come to struggle over the control of institutions, whether in the form
of markets or redistributed resources. Such conflict in turn impacts upon
aggregate welfare and accentuates the unwillingness of groups to commit to
equality of opportunity. Here too the process manifests institutionally and so
exhibits idiosyncratic path dependence.
The cumulative element of these processes is only part of the story. The
other part is the fact that the process of integration and disintegration can
exist independently in different areas of institutional activity and that it can
play out across many different levels of aggregation at the same time. Within
a given level of analysis – an individual welfare state, for example – the
existence of an institutional arrangement that integrates some members of
society while disintegrating others presents no necessary paradox. There may
be a normative contradiction between the equalization of opportunities to one
group simultaneous to the exclusion of another, but there is no logical or
empirical obstacle to such coincidence. The same is true across levels of
analysis. A trade union may integrate its own members even if this has adverse
implications for other workers outside. And the elaboration of the welfare state
can disrupt the functioning of the world economy. Indeed, for Myrdal as for
Polanyi that is precisely the point. As Myrdal explains:
I do not imply the existence of logical elements in conflict between the
ideals of national and international integration. I am more convinced than
ever that, on the contrary, national economic progress can reach the
highest possible levels only in a well-integrated world. But in the severely
disintegrated world in which we actually live, there is an obvious lack of
institutional balance that works forcefully against international solutions
that would satisfy people’s cravings for economic progress, equality, and
security.
(Myrdal 1956: 33)
The locus for this tension between integration at the national and international
levels lies in the interaction between economic institutions – macroeconomic,
regulatory, and market. As different social groups have turned to the state in
defense of their welfare, the result has been to elaborate a wide variety of
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
151
different institutional structures in response to specific problems. And given
the territorial boundaries of the state, these institutions have tended to operate
only at the national level. Internationally, the effect of these various regimes
has been to create obstacles to interaction and to exchange – both institutional
and attitudinal – regardless as to the explicit intentions behind the original
institutional design. Hence the problem is not nationalism or protectionism
per se. Rather it is the idiosyncratic manner in which national political
communities have addressed shared and complementary values. Hence, ‘the
ordinary citizen is apt to believe – and very largely with good reason – that
the national policies by which [national integration] has been brought about
are good, even if they are exactly those which are here pictured as the causes
of international disintegration’ (Myrdal 1956: 44).
Resolution of the tension between integration at the national and international levels depends upon the reconciliation of institutional regimes and
the preservation of values. In this way, ‘international integration becomes . . .
a matter of coordination’, wherein ‘[what] is needed is an internationalization
of these national policy structures themselves, preserving the essential values they
represent to the several nations’ (Myrdal 1956: 50; italics in original). In this
way, Myrdal anticipates the ‘new approach’ to voluntary industrial standards
that operates at the heart of the internal market program of the late 1980s as
well as the ‘open method of co-ordination’ around which the Lisbon European
Council built its strategy for welfare state reform in the late 1990s (Hodson
and Maher 2001). For Myrdal, such developments should not constitute a
departure from the pattern of international integration – they are the pattern,
at least insofar as integration is identified with the equalization of opportunity
between the member states. Some measure of conformity may be essential,
but a wide element of diversity cannot be avoided.
The next phase in Myrdal’s analysis of An International Economy uses this
understanding of integration to explain why efforts to unite Europe during
the early to mid-1950s failed to yield the desired result. For Myrdal, the
tension between national and international integration was only part of the
problem. The other part lay in the excessive ambition of his contemporaries
in their efforts to force the pace of integration ahead of the development of
popular attitudes and beyond the reconciliation of institutional regimes. Such
efforts, he suggests, were doomed to failure. Only a more specific, practical,
and incremental project could hope to succeed.
With the benefit of hindsight we might be tempted to agree. The dramatic
proposal of a European defense community and its concomitant European
political community could never hope to overcome the attitudinal and
institutional obstacles that were present during the first decade of the Cold
War. By contrast, a more specific, practical, and incremental pursuit of
economic integration might, however, succeed. And it did. But we do not
need to appeal to Myrdal to know that. The evidence of the success of
European economic integration is all around us. What Myrdal adds to this
empirical record is an understanding of the coincidence between the progress
152
Journal of European Public Policy
of European economic integration and the persistence of national distinctiveness. For Myrdal, the one could not have been possible without the other.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
IDIOSYNCRASY AND INTEGRATION
The insights taken from Polanyi and Myrdal can be drawn together in a
research program that complements the existing work on European integration
by emphasizing some of the analytic strengths of comparative political economy – strengths related to the analysis of institutional effects, distributive
coalitions, and dynamic systems. The purpose of this section is to suggest how
such a research program could come about and it is organized along some of
the guiding themes suggested in the work by Polanyi and Myrdal.7
From Polanyi, the emphasis in the research program can be summarized in
terms of reactive diversity and distributive politics. When examining any
particular facet of European integration, the first step is to look where reactions
differ across member states and the second is to attempt to analyze plausible
distributive accounts for these differences in reaction. The point is not that
integration and idiosyncrasy covary in some direct or linear sense. Rather it is
that any aspect of integration may give rise to reactions that differ from one
member state to the next for distributive reasons which are strongly influenced
by the local structural environment.
Consider, for example, the effects of capital market integration and monetary
integration. The predominant expectation in the literature is that these will
have a strongly convergent influence on Europe’s member states. However, the
implications of Polanyi’s double movement are that the effect will be divergent
and will depend upon domestic distributive politics. In part, this line of
reasoning is already well documented in Garrett (1995, 1998), who analyzes
the flexibility afforded to left-wing political groups under conditions of high
capital mobility. What Garrett (2000) has tended to avoid is the impact of
monetary integration, which he concedes will have a convergent influence on
fiscal policy.
By contrast, Jones (2003) finds the differential responses to monetary
integration anticipated in the logic of Polanyi’s ‘double movement’ in comparative national performance on international current accounts. Simply, the
variation in current account performance across countries increases first with
capital market integration and again with monetary integration. In turn, this
variation in current account performance can be explained with reference to
the adoption of differing macroeconomic policy mixes which are possible only
under conditions of capital market liberalization and which are reinforced
(rather than undermined) by monetary unification. Finally, these differing
macroeconomic policy mixes have important distributive consequences which
can be traced back to underlying policy coalitions. In the language of Polanyi,
we can regress this story about diverse reactions to capital market integration
and monetary union through the macroeconomic data and back into those
sectional interests that are the natural vehicles for social and political change.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
153
The identification of diverse reactions to common policies or common
institutions should not be taken as a challenge to assertions of ‘commonality’.
With the previous example, my point is not that capital market integration
and monetary union have no convergent impact. Rather it is to suggest that
they have divergent implications as well. This change in emphasis is important
to help round out debates about European integration. For example, where
the predominant emphasis in discussions of capital market integration and
monetary union is on the convergent features of these policies, the addition
of rules governing fiscal behavior as in the Stability and Growth Pact can only
be viewed as an added constraint. When the emphasis shifts to focus on
divergent reactions – and so highlights, for example, the fact that Portugal has
run a current account deficit of approximately 8 percent of gross domestic
product for each of the past five years on top of a consistent run of deficits
stretching back to the late 1980s – the importance of agreeing standards for
fiscal performance increases.
In Polanyi’s analysis, distributive politics is mediated not only by institutions
but also by ideas. Moreover, the ideational influences on distributive politics
are at least partially endogenous insofar as they change over time and as a result
of the evolution of political competition. This point is slightly complicated but
can be illustrated in the contrast between two prominent accounts of the role
of ideas and preferences in the process of European monetary integration. In
McNamara’s (1998) account, preferences converge across countries under the
influence of capital market liberalization. States (or governments) become
aware of the implications of high capital mobility for monetary policy
autonomy and so come to accept the inevitability (in structural terms) of a
neoliberal turn in macroeconomic policy-making. In Moravcsik’s (1998)
account, the result is much the same and yet the process is more highly
contested in the form of distributive negotiations between countries and
between competing interest groups within countries. Viewed together, these
two accounts suggest differing degrees of endogenous influence and therefore
differing degrees of convergence across countries: McNamara’s account is
dominated more fully by the lessons learned from the collapse of Keynesianism;
Moravcsik’s account incorporates a series of smaller lessons learned by individual
countries or groups within countries from myriad events that take place
throughout the integration process including the process of negotiating over
institutional design.
If we follow the path of contestation to its logical conclusion, multiplying
the actors involved and increasing the endogenous influences of past conflicts
on current perspectives, it is possible to restructure much of our understanding
of the stability of monetary integration. The predominant assumption in the
theory of optimal currency areas is that the choices for entering and leaving a
monetary union are symmetrical. Countries (or governments) opt for irrevocably fixed exchange rates when the distributive consequences are favorable –
as when trading relations between prospective members are preponderant. But
countries (or governments) may also choose to leave the monetary union and
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
154
Journal of European Public Policy
opt for flexible exchange rates when the distributive consequences of membership become unfavorable – as under the influence of an asymmetric exogenous
demand shock. Assuming that Polanyi is correct in his analysis of the ‘double
movement’, however, this expectation of symmetry in the choices to join and
to leave a monetary union should not hold.
Joining a monetary union represents the choice for an exchange rate regime
with important consequences for monetary policy. Leaving the monetary union
represents a choice for monetary policy with important consequences for the
exchange rate regime. The distinction is more than just a semantic one for
three reasons implicit in the ‘double movement’: First, domestic actors will
have changed their institutional environments in order to adapt to the
consequences of participation in the monetary union. Second, these actors will
have reordered their prioritization of policy instruments by ease of use, with
efforts to seek fiscal redress always proving easier than efforts to reestablish a
national currency. And third, actors will face a completely different set of
distributive calculations – although still difficult, it is far easier to establish the
distributive consequences of changing the exchange rate regime than to identify
the distributive consequences of changing either the direction or character of
monetary policy. Each of these three reasons is endogenous to the process of
monetary integration. And what is important is not only recognizing the
precise mechanisms for this endogenous influence of integration on institutions
and ideas, but also recognizing the implications of its existence for our
understanding of integration as a process.
This discussion of endogenous influences helps to move the research program
from Polanyi to Myrdal, and from the distributive politics of institutionally
bounded arenas (like national polities) to the distributive implications of
interactions across levels of analysis. What Myrdal emphasizes is the importance
of the competition between national and international forms of integration.
In practical terms, we should look for this competition to play out in
the interaction between systems. As policy-making competencies become
institutionalized at the European level, what is the impact on national
performance?
One example of research posited in answer to a question like this can be
found in Peter Hall’s analysis of the implications of monetary integration for
German price stability. Hall’s (1994) argument is that German price stability
during the post-war period is not solely a result of policies of the German
central bank – the Bundesbank – but rather results from the complex signaling
between the Bundesbank and those actors engaged in wage bargaining. The
force of this claim is that price stability derives not from some readily
identifiable institutional attribute like political independence, but rather from
a more ambiguous distributive equilibrium between powerful forces in German
society, namely labor and capital. By implication, Hall speculates as to whether
attempts to replace the Bundesbank with a European central bank would
somehow eliminate the signaling between monetary authorities and those
actors engaged in wage bargaining and thereby disrupt the distributive equilib-
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
155
rium behind Germany’s stable prices (Hall 1994: 17). In turn, such speculation
has fed into a well-spring of analyses that have looked at the implications of
monetary integration for domestic patterns of distributive conflict, policymaking and policy adjustment both in Germany and elsewhere.8 As Hall and
Franzese (1998: 526–30) point out, such analysis holds the key to understanding the future of European economic integration.
Myrdal’s emphasis on the dynamic interactions between levels of analysis
provides a useful window for analyzing the relationship between unity and
diversity. Not only does it highlight systemic interdependence – such as
between the stability of an exchange-rate or monetary regime and the interaction between domestic institutions – but it also suggests the importance of
identifying operational constraints. As the pattern of European integration
adapts to accommodate ever greater diversity among its member states, the
importance of such constraints can only be expected to grow. Hence, for
example, it is not enough to acknowledge that enlargement will take place on
the basis of a ‘principle of differentiation’, that welfare state reform will be
undertaken within an ‘open method of co-ordination’, or that the EU may
evolve along lines of ‘enhanced co-operation’ between subsets of participants.
What is also required is more general analysis of where differentiation ceases
to facilitate progress, where open co-ordination ceases to encourage reform,
and where enhanced co-operation exacerbates conflict rather than mitigating
it (Jones 2001). These are the types of questions which Myrdal encourages us
to analyze, and in ways that retain our focus on the importance of distributive
conflict as influenced by domestic political and economic institutions.
SUGGESTIONS FROM COMPARATIVE POLITICAL ECONOMY
Students of comparative political economy have arrived at something of a
consensus that national economic institutions are embedded in complex and
interdependent networks which differ both historically and constitutionally
from one country to the next. Moreover, even though countries are integrating
within the world economy and within regional groupings such as the EU,
such integration does not entail that the countries themselves are necessarily
becoming less distinctive. Existing research on European integration (and
globalization more generally) has focused on the conditions within which
convergence does take place, on the institutional features that underwrite
specific forms of distinctiveness, and on the conditional nature of convergence
across national systems. Such research has added much to our understanding
of integration in Europe. However, taken as a whole, this body of research
also highlights the idiosyncratic character of national political economies.
The persistence of national idiosyncrasy forces us to reconsider processes of
integration, particularly within the context of the EU. Using the insights of
authors like Karl Polanyi and Gunnar Myrdal it is possible to construct an
interpretation of events in Europe within which idiosyncrasy and integration
are two elements in the same larger process of interaction. The great virtue of
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
156
Journal of European Public Policy
such an interpretation is that it focuses attention on the diverse reactions of
groups within countries to common features at the European level. The
interpretation suggested by Polanyi and Myrdal highlights the significance of
distributive politics to understanding the forces behind Europe and it underscores the role of specific environmental factors in shaping this distributive
politics. Finally, this interpretation signals the need to analyze the complementarity between levels of integration and it does so in a manner which
should allow us to structure case studies that will not only answer discrete
questions but that can be relied upon to inform future research. These focal
points are all present in the existing research and yet they are not unified
within a common understanding of the basic causal mechanisms at work. The
suggestions I draw from comparative political economy are about how such
insights can be unified and researched on the basis of the standard causal
patterns described by Polanyi and Myrdal.
The vice of this interpretation of the political economy of European
integration is that any acceptance of idiosyncrasy invites complexity into the
analysis. For most comparative political economists this tension between
parsimony and complexity is a longstanding feature of research design. And
there is no reason why it should not be the same for students of integration.
Indeed if we accept the framework posited here, there is a certain poetic justice
to the plight of the analyst. For analysis, as for integration, the challenge is to
ensure that conformity necessary for survival without sacrificing the diversity
which is manifest in the world around us.
Address for correspondence: Erik Jones, Johns Hopkins Bologna Center, via
Belmeloro 11, 40126 Bologna, Italy. Tel: ò39 051 291 7833. Fax: ò39 051
228 505. email:
[email protected]
NOTES
1 A preliminary version of this paper was presented at the European Research Institute
of the University of Birmingham. There and elsewhere I was grateful to receive
constructive feedback from Robert Elgie, Paul Heywood, Dave Marsh, Anand
Menon, Jonathon Moses, Amy Verdun, and two anonymous referees. The usual
disclaimer applies.
2 See, for example, Berger and Dore (1996); Esping-Andersen (1999); Hall and
Soskice (2001); Hollingsworth and Boyer (1997); Kitschelt et al. (1999); Scharpf
and Schmidt (2000a, 2000b).
3 See, for example, Goodin (1996); March and Olsen (1989); Peters (1999); Weaver
and Rockman (1993).
4 Note here the contrast between Polanyi and Pierson (2000: 264–5).
5 Note here the contrast with Puchala (1975) who argued that the concept of
‘integration’ should be understood explicitly in terms of harmonization.
6 See particularly Myrdal (1957: 1–55).
7 See also Jones (2002).
8 See, for example, Franzese (2002); Iversen (1998, 1999); McNamara and Jones
(1996); Soskice and Iversen (1998).
E. Jones: Idiosyncrasy and integration
157
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
REFERENCES
Aspinwall, M.D. and Schneider, G. (2000) ‘Same menu, separate tables: the institutionalist turn in political science and the study of European integration’, European
Journal of Political Research 38: 1–36.
Berger, S. and Dore, R. (eds) (1996) National Diversity and Global Capitalism, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Dalton, G. (ed.) (1968) Primitive, Archaic, and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl
Polanyi, Boston: Beacon Press.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999) Social Foundations of Postindustrial Economies, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Franzese, R.J. Jr. (2002) Macroeconomic Policies of Developed Countries, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Garrett, G. (1995) ‘Capital mobility, trade, and the domestic politics of economic
policy’, International Organization 49(4): 657–87.
Garrett, G. (1998) Partisan Politics in the Global Economy, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Garrett, G. (2000) ‘Capital mobility, exchange rates and fiscal policy in the global
economy’, Review of International Political Economy 7(1): 153–70.
Goodin, R.E. (1996) The Theory of Institutional Design, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hall, P.A. (1994) ‘Central bank independence and coordinated wage bargaining: their
interaction in Germany and Europe’, German Politics and Society 31: 1–23.
Hall, P.A. and Franzese, R.J. Jr. (1998) ‘Mixed signals: central bank independence,
coordinated wage bargaining, and European monetary union’, International Organization 52(3): 505–35.
Hall, P.A. and Soskice, D. (eds) (2001) Varieties of Capitalism: The Institutional
Foundations of Comparative Advantage, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hodson, D. and Maher, I. (2001) ‘The open method as a new mode of governance’,
Journal of Common Market Studies 39(4): 719–46.
Hollingsworth, J.R. and Boyer, R. (eds) (1997) Contemporary Capitalism: The Embeddedness of Institutions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Iversen, T. (1998) ‘Wage bargaining, central bank independence, and the real effects
of money’, International Organization 52(3): 469–504.
Iversen, T. (1999) Contested Economic Institutions: The Politics of Macroeconomics and
Wage Bargaining in Advanced Democracies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jones, E. (2001) ‘The politics of Europe 2000: unity through diversity’, Industrial
Relations Journal 32(5): 362–79.
Jones, E. (2002) The Politics of Economic and Monetary Union: Integration and
Idiosyncrasy, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Jones, E. (2003) ‘Liberalized capital markets, state autonomy, and European monetary
union’, European Journal of Political Research 42(2): 111–36.
Kitschelt, H., Lange, P., Marks, G. and Stephens, J.D. (eds) (1999) Continuity and
Change in Contemporary Capitalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McNamara, K. (1998) The Currency of Ideas: Monetary Politics in the European Union,
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
McNamara, K. and Jones, E. (1996) ‘The clash of institutions: Germany in European
monetary affairs’, German Politics and Society 14(3): 5–30.
March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis
of Politics, New York: The Free Press.
Moravcsik, A. (1998) The Choice for Europe: Social Purpose and State Power from
Messina to Maastricht, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Myrdal, G. (1956) An International Economy: Problems and Prospects, New York:
Harper & Brothers.
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution - Routledge] At: 01:12 17 January 2009
158
Journal of European Public Policy
Peters, G.B. (1999) Institutional Theory in Political Science: The ‘New Institutionalism’,
London: Pinter.
Peterson, J. (2001) ‘The choice for EU theorists: establishing a common framework
for analysis’, European Journal of Political Research 39: 289–318.
Pierson, P. (2000) ‘Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics’,
American Political Science Review 94(2): 251–67.
Polanyi, K. (1957) The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of
Our Time, Boston: Beacon Press.
Puchala, D.J. (1975) ‘Domestic politics and regional harmonization in the European
communities’, World Politics 27(4): 496–520.
Scharpf, F.W. and Schmidt, V. (eds) (2000a) Welfare and Work in the Open Economy,
Vol. 1: From Vulnerability to Competitiveness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Scharpf, F.W. and Schmidt, V. (eds) (2000b) Welfare and Work in the Open Economy,
Vol. 2: Diverse Responses to Common Challenges, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Soskice, D. and Iversen, T. (1998) ‘Multiple wage-bargaining systems in the single
European currency area’, Oxford Review of Economic Policy 14(3): 110–24.
Weaver, R.K. and Rockman, B.A. (eds) (1993) Do Institutions Matter? Government
Capabilities in the United States and Abroad, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.