II For Evocriticism: Minds Shaped to Be Reshaped
Author(s): Brian Boyd
Reviewed work(s):
Source: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 38, No. 2 (Winter 2012), pp. 394-404
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/662750 .
Accessed: 15/12/2011 21:37
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical
Inquiry.
http://www.jstor.org
Critical Inquiry
II
For Evocriticism: Minds Shaped to
Be Reshaped
Brian Boyd
Evolutionary criticism argues that evolution has shaped human minds
to be partially reshapable, not least by our species-wide predisposition to
culture, to art in general, and to literature in particular. Evocritics1 show
how the fact that human minds owe their structure to evolutionary pressures makes a difference to literature—to features of human minds and
behaviors that literature deploys, represents, appeals to, engages, and
modifies.2
At least, that’s how I understand what we do. Jonathan Kramnick understands “literary Darwinists” differently: as committed to (1) a narrow
1. Not for the first time, I wish to resist the term literary Darwinism. Evolutionary biologists
and psychologists do not call themselves biological Darwinists or psychological Darwinists, and
for good reason; theirs are open, scientific, relentlessly critical research fields, not discipleships
of a foundational sage such as Marx or Freud. I will refer to the research program others and I
advocate as evocriticism and leave the program that Jonathan Kramnick (see n. 3) deprecates as
literary Darwinism. The term evocriticism also allows room for others interested in evolutionary
approaches to the arts, such as anthropologists of art (like Ellen Dissanayake), film critics (like
David Bordwell, Torben Grodal, and Murray Smith), and philosophers of art (like Denis
Dutton and Stephen Davies).
2. Dozens of books have been published in the area; to save space, I omit full references.
The Wikipedia entry for “Darwinian literary studies” currently lists thirty-five books; a recent
bibliographic survey can be found in Joseph Carroll, Reading Human Nature: Literary
Darwinism in Theory and Practice (Albany, N.Y., 2011) and an extended bibliography in
Evolution, Literature, and Film: A Reader, ed. Brian Boyd, Carroll, and Jonathan Gottschall
(New York, 2010), which also includes some of the best work (to 2008) in the field.
Critical Inquiry 38 (Winter 2012)
© 2012 by The University of Chicago. 0093-1896/12/3802-0005$10.00. All rights reserved.
394
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012
and controversial evolutionary psychology, whose controversial nature we
ignore; (2) an untenable modular view of the mind, whose modules were
shaped in the Pleistocene and have not changed since; (3) the adaptive
value of a modular “literary competence”; and beyond that (4) a purely
thematic approach to literature incapable of attending to form, variation,
or history.3 I do not recognize our work in his version.
Since much of what follows will perforce be negative, in negating Kramnick’s negative account of evocriticism, let me first just offer a sampler of
the positive, from the opening of an essay “On the Origin of Comics,”
which, with the help of evolutionary and cognitive principles, explains the
emergence of comics as a mass art in the 1890s and explores other possibilities for comics in the twenty-first-century avant-garde, for instance:
Evolution lets us see comics, like almost anything human or even
alive, in a panoramic context but also in extreme close-up, as close as
a comics artist trying to grab readers’ attention in this frame or with
that angle. And it can zoom smoothly between these two poles. Evolution offers a unified and naturalistic causal system from the general
to the very particular. Far from reducing all to biology and then to
chemistry and physics, it easily and eagerly plugs in more local factors—in a case like comics, historical, technological, social, artistic
and individual factors, for instance—the closer we get to particulars.
Evolution accepts multilevel explanations, from cells to societies, and
allows full room for nature and culture, society and individuals.4
In what follows I will show first, with respect to (1), that what Kramnick
reports as controversial in biology has long ceased to be so but that he has
ignored the real continuing controversy within the evolutionary sciences
3. See Jonathan Kramnick, “Against Literary Darwinism,” Critical Inquiry 37 (Winter 2011):
315– 47; hereafter abbreviated “ALD.”
4. Brian Boyd, “On the Origin of Comics: New York Double-Take,” Evolutionary Review 1,
no. 1 (2010): 97.
B R I A N B O Y D , University Distinguished Professor of English at the University
of Auckland, is best known as a Nabokov scholar (eight solo books, including a
two-volume biography, and eight edited volumes). Since 2000 he has also
worked on evolutionary approaches to literature, including On the Origin of
Stories: Evolution, Cognition, and Fiction (2009) and the coedited Evolution,
Literature, and Film: A Reader (2010). He has completed a follow-up to On the
Origin of Stories, on Shakespeare’s sonnets and lyric verse in general, entitled
Why Lyrics Last: Evolution, Cognition, and Shakespeare’s Sonnets (2012), and is
also working on On the Ends of Stories.
395
396
Brian Boyd / Critical Response
of the mind, where the most active evocritics occupy a position quite different from the one he assigns to us in (2). He turns up to the wrong
battlefield; no wonder he finds it easy to attack opponents who aren’t even
there.
Kramnick has at least taken the trouble to read much of the material he
mischaracterizes before dismissing it. This offers an advance on earlier
reactions, like that of Louis Menand, who in 2004, after asking what was
needed to stir literary studies from what he described as their doldrums,
affirmed that what they do not need is “consilience, which is a bargain with
the devil.”5
Kramnick’s most insistent rebuke to literary Darwinists is that they
ignore the controversy within the evolutionary sciences of the mind, presenting it “as ordinary and agreed-upon science,” when, however, it is no
more than “one particular view of the mind” (“ALD,” p. 317). In fact he
himself ignores the central and active disagreement within the field of
evolutionary psychology and therefore places evocritics right where they
do not belong.
In order to suggest that there is still a live controversy about adaptationism at the center of evolutionary biology, a controversy that “literary Darwinists” supposedly ignore, Kramnick has to adduce the critique of
adaptationism by Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin in 1979 against
E. O. Wilson and Richard Dawkins.6 But this is no longer a controversy.
Even those critical of evolutionary psychology, like David Buller, whose
critique Kramnick welcomes, conclude: “Gould’s arguments fail to show
that there is anything wrong with adaptive reasoning in Evolutionary Psychology.”7 A sympathetic summary of Gould’s career recognizes that
“Gould does not leave behind an alternative to Darwinian orthodoxy.”8 A
5. Louis Menand, “Dangers within and Without,” Profession (2005): 14. Kramnick calls my
response to Menand “quite intemperate” (“ALD,” p. 343 n. 73)—as opposed to the
temperateness of the dismissal, without argument or evidence, of “a bargain with the devil”?
6. See Stephen Jay Gould and Richard C. Lewontin, “The Spandrels of San Marco and the
Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme,” Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London 205, no. 1161 (1979): 581–98. For perspectives on the debate, from the sociology
of science, see Ullica Segerstråle, Defenders of the Truth: The Sociobiology Debate (Oxford, 2000),
and, from the philosophy of biology, see Kim Sterelny, Dawkins versus Gould: Survival of the
Fittest (Cambridge, 2001).
7. David J. Buller, Adapting Minds: Evolutionary Psychology and the Persistent Quest for
Human Nature (Cambridge, Mass., 2005), p. 91.
8. David F. Prindle, Stephen Jay Gould and the Politics of Evolution (Amherst, Mass., 2009),
p. 219.
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012
recent compendium on evolution notes: “Adaptation is being studied at
least as intensely as ever.”9
Far from ignoring the adaptationist controversy, as Kramnick claims,
evocritics have dealt with it repeatedly.10 Gould earned renown for vivid,
memorable examples and analogies, like the spandrels of San Marco, and,
although these have made much less difference to evolutionary theory
than he hoped, evocritics have been aware they have been “influential”
outside biology, and may well be known to many readers who have not
heard both sides of the debate and do not realize it was resolved within
biology against Gould and in favor of adaptationism.
Not only does Kramnick wrongly claim that literary Darwinists ignore
this old controversy, he himself ignores an ongoing and far more relevant
controversy within the evolutionary study of human nature. He aligns
literary Darwinists with “scientists like Leda Cosmides and John Tooby,
David Buss, Steven Pinker” (“ALD,” p. 317; see also pp. 328 –29, 334, 346);
he declares that we “squeeze from the school of Pinker and Buss” our
“story about literature” (“ALD,” p. 344). In fact for many years people
working in the area have distinguished between a broad field of evolutionary inquiry into human nature, evolutionary psychology (ep), and a much
narrower patch within that field, Evolutionary Psychology (EP; also called
narrow school or High Church Evolutionary Psychology), defined best by
the work of Cosmides, Tooby, and Buss.11 Kramnick misleadingly obscures
the state of the field by overlooking this distinction and this debate.
He cites Buller as offering “a balanced critique” (“ALD,” p. 328 n. 32) of
evolutionary psychology. Buller emphasizes that he is criticizing narrow
EP, not broad EP. He accepts EP as a valid field, like others who have been
prominent critics of EP, such as Frans de Waal, who affirms in the midst of
a critique of EP that nevertheless there is “no way around an evolutionary
approach to human behavior” and predicts that “50 years from now every
psychology department will have Darwin’s bearded portrait on the wall.”12
9. Joseph Travis and David N. Reznick, “Adaptation,” in Evolution: The First Four Billion
Years, ed. Michael Ruse and Joseph Travis (Cambridge, Mass., 2009), p. 129.
10. See Carroll, Literary Darwinism: Evolution, Human Nature, and Literature (New York,
2004), pp. 227– 45, and Boyd, On the Origin of Stories: Evolution, Cognition, and Fiction
(Cambridge, Mass., 2009), pp. 36 –37.
11. See The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, ed.
Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby (New York, 1992); David M. Buss, The
Evolution of Desire: Strategies of Human Mating (New York, 2003); The Handbook of
Evolutionary Psychology, ed. Buss (Hoboken, N.J., 2005); and Cosmides and Tooby,
“Neurocognitive Adaptations Designed for Social Exchange,” in The Handbook of Evolutionary
Psychology, pp. 584 – 627.
12. Frans B. M. de Waal, “Evolutionary Psychology: The Wheat and the Chaff,” Current
Directions in Psychological Science 11 (Dec. 2002): 187, 190.
397
398
Brian Boyd / Critical Response
Another advocate of broad EP who criticizes narrow EP is biologist
David Sloan Wilson.13 Wilson has worked with evocritics for almost fifteen
years, as the PhD advisor for one of the most active, Jonathan Gottschall, as
the coeditor of The Literary Animal,14 which Kramnick calls a “manifesto”
of literary Darwinism (“ALD,” p. 316 n. 1), and as the first biologist invited
to give a keynote at a literature and evolution conference.15 No biologist has
worked more closely with evocritics, yet no biologist has more persistently
criticized the key tenets of narrow EP.
The most active evocritics have themselves contrasted ep and EP for
many years and, along with others, have criticized central tenets of EP for
more than a decade.16 How has Kramnick not noticed all this, or why has he
seen fit not to mention it?
The key tenets of EP questioned by evocritics and others include, especially, the notions of the “massively modular” mind and of the Pleistocene
as the prime Era of Evolutionary Adaptedness (so that we therefore have
Stone Age minds), both stressed by Cosmides and Tooby.17 In criticizing
these and other EP claims, evocritics have joined biologists such as de
Waal, Sarah Blaffer Hrdy, psychologists and neuroscientists such as David
Geary, Michael Tomasello, and Jaak Panksepp, anthropologists such as
Robert Boyd and Steven Mithen, and philosophers such as Buller and Kim
Sterelny.18 Wilson’s essay “Evolutionary Social Constructivism,” which explains culture as an evolved means for responding more quickly to environmental change than genes can allow, appeared both in The Literary
Animal and in Evolution, Literature, and Film.19 He declares that as a con-
13. See David Sloan Wilson, Darwin’s Cathedral: Evolution, Religion, and the Nature of
Society (Chicago, 2002), p. 238 n. 17.
14. See The Literary Animal: Evolution and the Nature of Narrative, ed. Gottschall and
Wilson (Evanston, Ill., 2005).
15. At the Lorentz Center, University of Leiden, Dec. 2007.
16. See references to Carroll’s, the earliest (from 1998), in his “An Open Letter to Jonathan
Kramnick,” pp. 406 –7.
17. See Cosmides and Tooby, “Evolutionary Psychology: A Primer,” www.psych.ucsb.edu/
research/cep
18. See De Waal, “Evolutionary Psychology”; Sarah Blaffer Hrdy, Mother Nature: Maternal
Instincts and How They Shape the Human Species (New York, 1999); Wilson, Darwin’s
Cathedral; David C. Geary, The Origin of Mind (Washington, D.C., 2005), hereafter abbreviated
OM; Michael Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication (Cambridge, Mass., 2008); Jaak
Panksepp and Jules B. Panksepp, “The Seven Sins of Evolutionary Psychology,” Evolution and
Cognition 6, no. 2 (2000): 108 –31; Peter J. Richerson and Robert Boyd, Not by Genes Alone: How
Culture Transformed Human Evolution (Chicago, 2005); Steven Mithen, The Prehistory of the
Mind: The Cognitive Origins of Art and Science (London, 1996); Buller, Adapting Minds; and
Sterelny, Thought in a Hostile World: The Evolution of Human Cognition (Oxford, 2003).
19. See Wilson, “Evolutionary Social Constructivism,” in The Literary Animal, pp. 20 –37
and in Evolution, Literature, and Film, pp. 111–22.
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012
sequence of culture, humans, far from being stuck with Stone Age minds,
“experience evolution in hyperdrive,” a phrase I happily appropriate.20
Carroll and I have especially favored the model of David Geary, with its
steady incline from hard mental modularity to soft, reshapeable modules
to general intelligence. In a chapter on “The Evolution of Intelligence” I
spend one paragraph on Cosmides and Tooby’s Swiss Army knife model
and the rest of the chapter summarizing Geary’s much more flexible view
of the mind.21 The flexibility of the mind (in Mithen and Geary) has been
central to Carroll for over a decade,22 and the plasticity of the mind (in
Norman Doidge, Stanislas Dehaene, Oliver Sacks, and “evo-devo,” evolutionary developmental psychology) has become increasingly focal for my
work.23
Evolutionary developmental psychology has moved away from nativism toward seeing initial predispositions or learning biases develop into
specialized subroutines or behaviors,24 a position that has been eagerly
adopted by evocritics. Evocritics have also been receptive to the affective
neuroscience of Panksepp, which challenges EP for its overly computational model of the mind.25 Sociobiology and evolutionary psychology
were made possible by the new recognition of the centrality of the gene,
rather than the organism or the species, in natural selection. Although they
focused often on cooperation, Evolutionary Psychologists have tended to
resist the idea of multilevel selection, of selection at the level of groups as
well as organisms and genes (as proposed by Sober and Wilson; Wilson
and Wilson; Boyd and Richerson).26 Multilevel selection is now recognized
as “clearly important for understanding many adaptations in diverse sys20. Wilson, “Foreword,” in Barbara Oakley, Evil Genes (Amherst, N.Y., 2007), p. 16; see
Boyd, The Origin of Stories, p. 27.
21. See Boyd, The Origin of Stories, pp. 42–50.
22. See references in Carroll, “An Open Letter to Jonathan Kramnick.”
23. See Norman Doidge, The Brain That Changes Itself: Stories of Personal Triumph from the
Frontiers of Brain Science (New York, 2007); Stanislas Dehaene, Reading in the Brain: The
Science and Evolution of a Human Invention (New York, 2009); and Oliver Sacks, The Mind’s
Eye (New York, 2010).
24. See David F. Bjorklund and Anthony D. Pellegrini, The Origins of Human Nature:
Evolutionary Developmental Psychology (Washington, DC, 2002), and Tomasello et al.,
“Understanding and Sharing Intentions: The Origins of Cultural Cognition,” Behavioral and
Brain Sciences 28 (2005): 675–735.
25. See Jaak Panksepp, Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal
Emotions (New York, 1998).
26. See Elliot Sober and Wilson, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish
Behavior (Cambridge, Mass., 1999); Wilson, Darwin’s Cathedral; Wilson, Evolution for Everyone:
How Darwin’s Theory Can Change the Way We Think about Our Lives (New York, 2007);
Wilson and Edward O. Wilson, “Rethinking the Theoretical Foundations of Sociobiology,”
Quarterly Review of Biology 82, no. 4 (2007): 327– 48; and Richerson and Boyd, Not by Genes
Alone.
399
400
Brian Boyd / Critical Response
tems; research in this area is leading to far more nuanced and sophisticated
interpretations of the evolution of sociality.”27 Evocritics have eagerly
taken to multilevel selection for its role in explaining the power that stories, overtly fictional or the unrecognized fictions of religion, can exercise
on social cohesion.28
Kramnick, then, rebukes us for ignoring a no longer live controversy
that in fact we do address yet himself fails to acknowledge (a) the controversy between ep and EP, (b) the role of evocritics in critiquing the key
tenets of EP, or (c) the extent to which evocritics have taken ideas from
broader notions of evolutionary biology, psychology, and anthropology
often at odds with EP assumptions.
To move to point (3) in my second paragraph, Kramnick also claims
that the crucial question in literary Darwinism is the adaptive function of
literature and that literary Darwinists argue for a modular “literary competence” (“ALD,” pp. 320 n. 13, 325, and throughout) that is universal, and
therefore innate, and therefore adaptive and modular.
Some evocritics have indeed focused some of the time on the question
of the possible adaptive function of literature,29 but this has never been
seen as the fundamental question for evocritics, just one of an open-ended
quiver of questions. Some prominent evocritics, like Gottschall and Marcus Nordlund, have given it little attention—and, conversely, many nonevocritics from Aristotle on have, perfectly reasonably, also asked why we
engage in literature and what benefits, if any, it confers.
“Literary competence,” a notion Kramnick attacks, is his term (and
Jonathan Culler’s),30 not ours. He presents it as a focus of literary Darwinism’s enquiry into the adaptive value of literature, as equivalent to the kind
of modular mental capacity he says constitutes the main focus of literary
Darwinist endeavors. But “literary competence” is not a prime focus of
evocritics. What we have tended to focus on, when we consider adaptive
value, is the human predilection for engaging in stories, from pretend play
to full-fledged fiction, whether oral, written, enacted, filmed, drawn, or
programmed.
Evocritics do not equate literature with stories or, in careful formulations, label literature universal or adaptive. They do tend to find stories
27. Travis and Reznick, “Adaptation,” p. 129.
28. See Boyd, The Origin of Stories, pp. 99 –108, and Carroll et al., “Human Nature in the
Nineteenth-Century British Novel: Doing the Myth,” Philosophy and Literature 33 (2009): 50–72.
29. See Carroll, Literary Darwinism, pp. 63– 68, “An Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary
Study” and “Rejoinder to the Responses,” Style 42 (Summer–Fall 2008): 103–35, 119–28, 349–68;
Boyd, The Origin of Stories, pp. 69 –125, 188 –208; and Michelle Scalise Sugiyama, “ReverseEngineering Narrative: Evidence of Special Design,” in The Literary Animal, pp. 177–96.
30. See Jonathan Culler, Structuralist Poetics (London, 1975).
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012
universal and adaptive, but there are other aspects of literature, like verse
and essays, that may be universal (as in the case of verse) or not (as in the
case of essays). Against Kramnick’s claims, evocritics do not assert that
universality implies innateness and adaptiveness. Rather, universals satisfy
one criterion for adaptiveness and may then be investigated to see if they
satisfy the other criteria: if they (a) develop spontaneously, (b) show evidence of biological design, and (c) offer, on average, reproductive benefit.
Verse, for instance, I argue is universal but neither adaptive nor innate,
merely what Daniel Dennett calls a “good trick”31 that may be discovered,
often independently, in culture after culture—in this case, because the
verse line (spoken or written) as a unit of attention matches so closely the
constraints of human working memory.32
For some reason Kramnick chooses to advance, as a criticism of “literary Darwinist” claims that storytelling is adaptive, the fact that it involves
and depends on other faculties of the mind or body (see “ALD,” pp. 332,
340, 343). Of course it does. Our proclivity for storytelling depends on
many other capacities of the mind, like perception, emotion, memory, and
imagination. No evocritic I know would deny that many capacities of the
mind feed into literature, any more than any biologist would deny that
many capacities of body and mind, like respiration, digestion, circulation,
perception, and attention, feed into locomotion—which hardly stops locomotion being adaptive. In the same way, the fact that many mental
functions feed into, say, storytelling has no bearing on whether storytelling
itself is adaptive.
Contrary to Kramnick’s insinuations, no evocritic claims there is a separate module of literary competence sealed from other aspects of the mind.
Indeed I make it quite explicit, to the point of treating them in successive
chapters, that the capacity for fiction depends on capacities (shared to
some extent by many species) for event comprehension, capacities (shared
by fewer species) for event recall, and capacities (shared to a still more
limited extent, and by still fewer species) for event representation before I
address the unique capacity for event invention in humans.33
Kramnick returns repeatedly to the claim that “it’s a great deal easier to
make a case for adaptive and other functions of mind feeding into a disposition to create and consume works of literature than it is for such a
disposition itself to be an adaptation” (“ALD,” p. 332; see also pp. 335, 336,
343, 346). But dispositions can be crucially adaptive—like the widespread
31. Daniel Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea (London, 1996), p. 77.
32. Brian Boyd, “Verse: Universal? Adaptive? Aversive?“ Evolutionary Review 2 (2011).
33. See Boyd, On the Origin of Stories, chaps. 10 –12.
401
402
Brian Boyd / Critical Response
animal disposition to play, or the greater disposition for physical fighting,
serious or play, among boys than girls, even before the onset of puberty
starts to sharply differentiate male and female upper body strength. In the
case of fiction, all that is needed is a predisposition and capacity to engage
in fiction. That predisposition and that capacity are evident in the spontaneous emergence and the continued compulsiveness of childhood pretend
play.
A predisposition can make all the difference—like a predisposition for
proximity to others; less social animals in many species, such as canids, are
at much higher risk of early deaths. Tomasello, whose work on the comparative cognitive development of chimpanzees and humans has been extremely influential among ep researchers, shows the cascade of effects,
including language itself, that can arise from the unique human disposition to joint attention—yet another precondition for art that an evolutionary approach has been able to bring to light.34 The fact that there are
preconditions for art does not make art any less to some degree a matter of
biology. On the contrary, without that unique evolved predisposition to
joint attention, art could not have developed beyond the solipsism of early
play. Yet art is not reducible to joint attention or to any other set of enabling conditions.
A slight disposition to play firmed, over many millions of years, into the
compulsiveness play has throughout the mammalian line. Play motivates
animals with flexible behavior to practice key responses like flight and fight
in nonurgent situations so that their sheer present pleasure ensures that
they refine their control and expand their flight-or-fight options in urgent
situations. Other animals thrive by their physical skills— humans,
uniquely, mostly by our mastery of information, especially social information. For any species, information can be handled efficiently in real time
only when it falls into patterns of the kinds they naturally recognize. Just as
animals, including humans, refine flexible physical skills through play,
humans uniquely, naturally, compulsively refine their most important
cognitive skills through art, through cognitive play with pattern, in their
most important information modes: in sight, in sound, and in social information. In the particular art of fiction, from pretend play onwards, we
learn to understand events and shift perspectives at a faster clip than usual,
to enjoy simulations of a wide range of social situations, and to generate a
wider range of options.35
34. See Tomasello et al., “Understanding and Sharing Intentions,” and Tomasello, Origins
of Human Communication.
35. See Boyd, On the Origin of Stories, chaps. 6, 12–13.
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012
All fiction needs is that deep-rooted human disposition to engage in
narrative—an already established competence—as play and as therefore
compulsively inviting. Then present pleasure can train us for future needs,
preparing the effects that recent research has begun to show fiction has on
minds, on social cognition, perspective taking, and empathy.36 Through
playing with props and action as children and switching, as we grow older,
to stories that may no longer need physical enactment—through our disposition to the social simulation of fiction—we learn the more rapid, efficient, and powerful comprehension of events, especially social events, and
enable the more rapid generation of options. We reshape our minds,37 as
our evolved disposition to pretend play and fiction had shaped us to do.
Now to the last point, (4), in my second paragraph. Kramnick’s final
criticism of “literary Darwinism” is that it “has surprisingly little to say
about literary texts or forms” (“ALD,” p. 343). Kramnick certainly has
surprisingly little to say about what evocritics have in fact written about
literary texts and forms. He continues: “Anything it could say about such
forms would have to be appropriate for a prehistoric culture whose language and stories are lost forever” (“ALD,” p. 344). If this were true it
would have been impossible for evocritics to write, as they have, about
comics, film, and dystopian, utopian, and slash fiction. Something must be
seriously wrong with Kramnick’s position. And it is; see points (1) to (3)
above.
Kramnick seems reluctant to name examples lest people seek them out
and find something of value. He does not indicate that there are evocritical
monographs on individual authors and genres from Homer and Shakespeare to Zamyatin and Wharton and essays on works by writers from
Homer and Shakespeare, again, to Austen, Charlotte Bronte, Thomas
Hardy, Oscar Wilde, Zora Neale Hurston, Vladimir Nabokov, Dr. Seuss,
J. M. Coetzee, and Art Spiegelman, and studies of epic, drama, the novel,
satire, verse, the sonnet, science fiction, and slash fiction.
Kramnick declares, “Were the disposition to create or consume literature innate in the way argued by the literary Darwinists, it would be just as
invariant across the species and across time as they maintain” (“ALD,” p.
36. See Jèmeljan Hakemulder, The Moral Laboratory: Experiments Examining the Effects of
Reading Literature on Social Perception and Moral Self-Concept (Amsterdam, 2000); Maja Djikic
et al., “On Being Moved by Art: How Reading Fiction Transforms the Self,” Creativity Research
Journal 21, no. 1 (2009): 24 –29; Raymond Mar, Keith Oatley, and Jordan B. Peterson,
“Exploring the Link between Reading Fiction and Empathy Ruling out Individual Differences
and Examining Outcomes,” Communications 34, no. 1 (2009): 407–28.
37. Evidence has shown that simulation improves performance in nonartistic contexts, too;
see Chris Frith, Making up the Mind: How the Brain Creates Our Mental World (Oxford, 2007),
p. 106.
403
404
Brian Boyd / Critical Response
346). His confidence suggests a thorough knowledge of literary Darwinism, evolutionary biology, and evolutionary psychology. But where do
literary Darwinists claim that literature is invariant across the species?
Where does even narrow-school EP claim that any form of culture is invariant across the species? Why because something is innate would it have
to be invariant in its expression? Head hair is innate in humans, in a
uniquely human pattern, even down to species-typical (yet highly variable) patterns of male balding, yet is not uniform across the species, either
in genetic expression or in cultural modulation. Genes encode for individual variation as well as species-typical features, and without that variation
evolution by natural selection could not occur. Genes may also, as in the
case of head hair, be subject to local selective pressures and, as long as
geographical isolation persists, to lasting local variations. Many phenotypic features are a result of polygenic combinations that will result in the
wide range of a normal distribution spread, and many traits, including
psychological traits, have stable or frequency-dependent polymorphisms.
Kramnick tries in the sentence above to infer a conclusion from biological principles, but his multiple misunderstandings of evolutionary biology show he cannot do so. This is bad enough, but worse still is that he
attempts to argue in theory how limited literary Darwinism must be while
refusing to acknowledge the diversity of their practice, which he must
know contradicts his abstract dictum. Evolutionary literary and film critics
have often done work on literary variation, often at a fine-grained level, in
local social and historical conditions, in Gottschall’s work on The Iliad or
Nordlund’s on Shakespeare, or technological and economic conditions, in
my work on comics, or individual authorial variation, in Carroll’s work on
Hardy or Wilde or mine on Seuss or Nabokov, or from specific technical
devices, like my work on free indirect discourse or Bordwell’s on shotreverse shot editing or the cinematic gaze. Just what is Kramnick afraid
that readers may discover if they read the work he prefers not to mention?
That evolution offers unique insights into the emotions, or into the intricate entanglements of cooperation and competition, or into the costs as
well as the benefits of evolving an imagination? That there might be something to learn from the idea that biology helps shape us, and shapes us,
inter alia, to be reshaped by arts like literature and film?