HUSSERL AND CARNAP ON REGIONS AND FORMAL
CATEGORIES
ANSTEN KLEV
Abstract. Husserl, in his doctrine of categories, distinguishes what he calls
regions from what he calls formal categories. The former are most general
domains, while the latter are topic-neutral concepts that apply across all domains. Husserl’s understanding of these notions of category is here discussed
in detail. It is, moreover, argued that similar notions of category may be
recognized in Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt.
As conceived of in the Ideas,1 phenomenology is what Husserl calls an eidetic
science: it deals not with matters of fact, but with Wesen or eidē, what in the
English literature on Husserl are usually called essences. Clarification of the nature
of phenomenology therefore requires clarification of what is understood by such
essences, something Husserl sets out to provide in the first section of the Ideas,
constructively in its first chapter (§§ 1–17) and critically in its second chapter
(§§ 18–26). In the course of that constructive clarification Husserl introduces the
distinction between regions and formal categories. The distinction is meant to
capture the different senses that the word ‘category’ has when one speaks on the
one hand about the categories of the physical and the mental and on the other
hand about the categories of individual and property: the former are most general
domains, most general topics, while the latter are topic-neutral concepts that apply
across all domains. In the words of Ryle (1954, p. 116), who coined the term ‘topicneutral’, regions may be said to provide “the fat and the lean,” and formal categories
the “joints and tendons,” of thought. In the following pages I wish to take a closer
look at this distinction, concentrating on how Husserl understood it around the
time of the Ideas and on how Rudolf Carnap in his Der logische Aufbau der Welt
(Carnap, 1928) may have understood it.
To deal with categories in an anthology on the philosophy of logic and mathematics in Husserl is justified not only on the grounds that Husserl appears to
have regarded the general theory of categories as belonging to logic,2 but also on
the grounds of the close ties that have existed between logic and the doctrine of
categories throughout the history of philosophy. Although Aristotle may not have
1
That is the abbreviation used here for Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und
phänomenologische Philosophie (Husserl, 1913). References to this work are of the form Ideen +
paragraph number. References to the two other books of the Ideas, (Husserl, 1952a) and (Husserl,
1952b), not published during Husserl’s lifetime, are of the form Ideen + book number + paragraph number. References to the Logische Untersuchungen (Husserl, 1901) are of the form LU
+ investigation number + paragraph number. Its first volume, Prolegomena zur reinen Logik
(Husserl, 1900), is abbreviated Prolegomena.
2
See the title of Ideen § 17 and also Prolegomena § 67. Husserl included a general discussion
of regions and formal categories in his lectures on the theory of science; see Husserl (1996, pp.
274–286).
1
2
ANSTEN KLEV
regarded the piece of writing now known as his Categories as belonging to logic,
his ancient commentators since Andronicus of Rhodes in the 1st century bc did so
regard it.3 The reason given for this, for instance by the commentator Simplicius
(6th century ad), is that the Categories deals with the doctrine of terms, which—
since syllogisms are composed of judgements, and judgements of terms—has to be
taught as the first part of logic.4 Kant’s doctrine of categories falls under his socalled transcendental logic, and is intrinsically tied to the notion of judgement in
general and to the so-called forms of judgement in traditional logic in particular.5
That type theory, a cornerstone of modern logic, may be regarded as a doctrine of
categories was noted already by Ryle (1938, p. 189).
I shall concentrate on the general theory of regions and formal categories, and
hence avoid questions about the specific nature of the various regions and formal
categories that come up for discussion in Husserl’s work. Such questions would be
proper to a different kind of study, dealing for instance with the notions of nature
and spirit (Geist) in Husserl’s work.6 The distinction between regions and formal
categories is not intrinsically tied up with phenomenology or Husserlian doctrine;
indeed, I think it is of use to anyone reflecting on the notion of category. The
second part of this paper will investigate how the distinction can be understood
in the context of simple type theory. This is where Carnap’s Aufbau enters the
picture, since that work can be seen as suggesting one way in which regions can be
mapped onto a simple type hierarchy.
Carnap attended Husserl’s advanced seminar Phänomenologische Übungungen
für Fortgeschrittene in the winter semester of 1923/24,7 and the influence of Husserl
on Carnap’s dissertation, Der Raum (Carnap, 1922), is obvious.8 Husserl’s influence on the Aufbau is more difficult to assess. Mayer (1991) argues for “numerous
systematical and terminological parallels” between the Aufbau and the Ideas. According to Roy (2004), Carnap regarded the Aufbau as a realization of Husserl’s
idea of a mathesis of experience, an axiomatic counterpart to phenomenology (cf.
Ideen §§ 71–75). Rosado Haddock (2008) likewise claims that Husserl’s influence
on the Aufbau was decisive. The understanding of an important aspect of Carnap’s
Aufbau in terms of a distinction from Husserl’s Ideas suggested in the present paper
can indeed be taken as an indication of the influence of the latter on the former. In
3
It was Andronicus who placed the Categories first in the Organon and the Organon first in the
list of Aristotle’s works (cf. Gottschalk, 1990, p. 66).
4
For a critical reading of Simplicius’s argument, see Morrison (2005).
5
For the background of Kant’s table of judgements in traditional logic, see Tonelli (1966).
6
A good place to begin such a study is the Einleitung des Herasugebers in (Husserl, 2001c).
7
This is clear from Carnap’s diaries of this period: on 21.11.1923 Carnap reports that Husserl has
allowed him to participate in his seminar, meeting at 11.00 every Wednesday (cf. Schumann, 1977,
p. 273); after that date and until the end of February 1924 Carnap regularly mentions ‘Husserl’ on
Wednesdays. What the topic of the seminar was, I do not know. On 13.11.1923 Carnap attended
Husserl’s class on Erste Philosophie; Husserl’s notes for the lecture that day (cf. Schumann, 1977,
p. 275) can be found in (Husserl, 1956, pp. 44–51). In his diary Carnap writes ‘nicht sehr gefallen’.
Landgrebe reported in 1976 to Schumann that Carnap followed Husserl’s seminars “SS 1924–SS
1925” (Schumann, 1977, p. 281). By considering Carnap’s diary entries on Wednesdays during
that year—when, as in the previous years, the seminar met—one sees that this cannot be correct.
8
For more details, see especially Stone (2010), but also Sarkar (2003) and Rosado Haddock (2008,
ch. 1).
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
3
the final section of this paper I shall nevertheless express some reservations against
making too much of the proposed parallels between these works.
1. Husserl on regions and formal categories
1.1. Region. It is a fundamental philosophical problem, according to Husserl, both
to find out what regions there are (Ideen § 17) and to understand the nature of a
given region and the interdependence of various regions on each other (ibid. § 152).
Husserl is, as far as I have seen, never quite definite on what regions he takes there to
be. It is clear that he regards physical or material nature and (pure) consciousness
as two regions. An individual falling under the first of these is a physical thing and
an individual falling under the second is an experience (Erlebnis), hence Husserl also
speaks of these regions as the regions of physical thing and experience, respectively.
Other regions Husserl mentions in the three books known as the Ideas include the
region of the body (cf. Ideen III §§ 2–3), living nature (animalische Natur ), and
the region of society and culture (die Geistige Welt). But it is not clear from the
discussion in those works whether these are all distinct, nor whether any of them
encompasses several regions. Is the region of the body separate from the region of
living nature? Persons, which Husserl distinguishes from living human beings, are
individuals of the region of culture and society, as are institutions and nations, and
also works of art; should not these be taken to belong to separate regions? It lies
outside the scope of this paper to discuss these questions as well as the question of
how the region of pure consciousness relates to the other regions.
Before considering Husserl’s rather technical definition of the notion of region,
let us look at three important characteristics he takes regions to have. Especially
important is the connection Husserl sees between regions and modes of original
awareness of objects. For each region there is an original mode of awareness of objects of that region, a type of act in which items of that region are, as Husserl would
say, “self-given.” There is, in other words, for each region a mode of consciousness
in which one has direct access to objects of that region. This connection is stated
especially succinctly in Experience and Judgement § 4:
every kind of object has its kind of being self-given.9
Similar formulations are found at many other places (e.g. Ideen §§ 1, 138). That
Husserl assumes this connection is also clear from the individual discussions of the
various regions, since he there typically states what is the mode of access to the
region in question. We access the region of nature through ordinary perception
(e.g. loc. cit.). Such perception is in fact the paradigmatic instance of a mode of
original awareness, and other original modes of awareness may by analogy be called
perception of objects of the kind in question. Being an original mode of awareness,
perception contrasts with, for instance, remembrance and phantasy, in which the
object is not present before one. The original mode of awareness of experiences,
i.e., the objects of the region of pure consciousness, is phenomenological reflection
(ibid. §§ 77–78). That this reflection is qualified as phenomenological means that it
involves the phenomenological reduction; only when the reduction has been carried
out can pure consciousness be disclosed to us (ibid. § 50). One becomes originally
9
Husserl (1939, p. 12): “jede Art der Gegenständen hat ihre Art der Selbstgebung.”
4
ANSTEN KLEV
aware of the body in what Husserl calls bodily apprehension (Ideen II § 36; Ideen
III § 2). The individuals in the region of the body are localized sensations, namely
sensations localized in the body (Husserl calls such sensations “Empfindnisse”).
In order to apprehend these sensations a special form of apprehension is required,
since usually sensations are apprehended as things in the outer world.10 I touch this
table; I then speak of the sensations in my fingers on the basis of bodily sensations,
but of the surface of the table on the basis of a perceptive apprehension. It is in
the former sort of apprehension that I am aware of the body as a region. For the
region of living beings, and that of society and culture, empathy (Einfühlung) plays
an important role, but it is not clear to me whether Husserl regards empathy as an
original mode of awareness; the question need not be settled here.
A region is, furthermore, said to prescribe a rule for how we may vary an individual of that region in imagination so that it still remains an individual, in other
words, so that we still have a unitary course of experience of an individual (Ideen
§§ 142, 149, 150; Ideen III § 7). Less general concepts, for instance the concept of
a diamond, may also be regarded as prescribing a rule for the course of experience,
for instance that the thing posited as a diamond does not bounce back in our hands
in the manner of a bouncy ball when we let it fall to the ground. But we can still
imagine a continuous transformation of the diamond into a bouncy ball without
our experience falling apart into a series of disconnected appearances; in fact we
can imagine the diamond being continuously transformed into any other physical
thing, namely so long as we remain inside the region of material nature. Husserl’s
discussion of imaginative variation in the cited paragraphs relies on the region in
question being that of nature, but he appears to have thought that the discussion
would generalize to other regions.11
A third characteristic of regions concern their relation to sciences. A region gives
rise to several “ontologies,” that is, to eidetic sciences of concepts that compose
the region (Ideen §§ 9, 16). In the case of nature, there is for instance geometry
as the ontology of space, and there should likewise be ontologies of time (pure
chronology), of movement (pure phoronomy), and of matter, since space, time,
and matter are all involved in the constitution of physical objects. As a matter of
fact, most ontologies have not been developed in any systematic fashion, but such
developments are in principle possible. Indeed, ontologies are indispensable to the
foundations of empirical sciences: any such science studies objects of some region,
and so assumes the results of the ontologies associated with that region. Natural
science, for instance, assumes the results of geometry and of all the other ontologies
of nature (ibid. §§ 8, 9).
Let us now consider Husserl’s technical definition of the notion of a region (Ideen I
§ 16):
10
This is the so-called content/apprehension scheme; see Klev (2013) for more details.
The so-called method of eidetic variation is discussed in more detail by Husserl in lecture notes
from 1925 (Husserl, 1968, 69–87). Husserl notes there how the notion of genus is reached through
such variation (ibid. 81–84).
11
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
5
A region is nothing but the total highest genus-unity belonging to
a concretum, that is, the essential unity of the highest genera to
which the lowest differentiae within the concretum belongs.12
Several glosses are needed in order to make sense of this.13 In particular, it must be
clarified what is here meant by a highest genus, a lowest differentiae, a concretum,
and by the belonging of lowest differentiae to a concretum. For the purposes of
this paper we may think of Husserlian essences as objectified concepts. Essences,
according to Husserl, fall into an ordering of genera and species (ibid. § 12); thus,
one essence is a genus of another essence if it is more general than it; it is the
species of another if it is more specific than it. That concepts, or terms, may
be ordered in this way is a traditional idea, found already in Aristotle’s Topics
and often associated with the philosopher Porphyry (3rd century ad), who in his
so-called Isagoge remarked that14
Substance is itself a genus. Under it is body, and under body animate body, under which is animal; under animal is rational animal,
under which is man; and under man are Socrates and Plato and
particular men.
Another, related, traditional doctrine in the logic of concepts is that of the content
and extension of a concept: the content of a concept are all the various concepts that
compose it, its marks (Merkmale); by the extension of a concept C one understood
either all concepts of which C is a mark or all individuals falling under C.15 Husserl
takes over this doctrine as well. Thus, an essence is said to contain all essences that
are marks of it (Ideen § 12); as we shall see in more detail below, the use of the
verb ‘to belong’ in Husserl’s definition of region refers to this notion of essence
containment. Among the marks of an essence are its genera; hence an essence
contains all of its genera.16 Not all essences contained in an essence are genera of it,
12
Husserl (1976, p. 36): “Region is nichts anderes als die g e s a m t e z u e i n e m K o n k r e t u m
g e h ö r i g e o b e r s t e G a t t u n g s e i n h e i t, also die weseneinheitliche Verknüpfung der obersten
Gattungen, die den niedersten Differenzen innerhalb des Konkretums zugehören.”
13
The only extended discussion of Husserl’s definition of region of which I am aware is Stone
(2000, pp. 97–131). A brief discussion of Husserl’s technical definition can also be found in Null
(1989, pp. 93–95).
14
The translation is taken from Barnes (2003, p. 6).
15The doctrine is found, for instance, in the Port-Royal Logique (I.vii):
J’appelle comprehension de l’idée, les attributs qu’elle enferme en soi, & qu’on
ne lui peut ôter sans la détruire, comme la comprehension de l’idée du triangle
enferme extension, figure, trois lignes, trois angles, & l’égalité de ces trois angles
à deux droits, &c.
J’appelle étendue de l’idée, les sujets à qui cette idée convenient, ce qu’on
appelle les inferieurs d’un terme general, qui à leur égard est appelleé superieur,
comme l’idée du triangle en general s’étend à toutes les diverses especes de
triangles.
Here extension appears to be understood in the first sense. Leibniz considered extension also
in the second sense (cf. Kauppi, 1971). The doctrine seems to be have been much discussed by
German logicians in the 19th century and was well known to Husserl; it is, for instance, taken for
granted in (Husserl, 1891a) and it plays an important role in his 1896 logic lecture notes (Husserl,
2001b).
16This doctrine can be found in Aristotle; see Metaphysics ∆ 25, 1023b 24: “the genus is called a
part of the species.”
6
ANSTEN KLEV
however; in Husserl’s terminology, these are the differentiae of the essence.17 Quite
in line with the tradition, Husserl further distinguishes two notions of extension of
an essence (Ideen § 13). The eidetical extension of an essence g is the collection of
all the essences of which g is a genus. The other notion of extension—which Husserl
does not give a name—is the collection of all possible instances—be they existent or
not—of the essence, the collection of all the various “thisnesses” (Diesheiten) that
instantiate the essence.18 Thus, a particular human being instantiates the essence
human being, and a particular green inhering in the cover of a particular copy of a
book instantiates the essence green.
A lowest species in the ordering of genera and species is called an eidetic singularity by Husserl. Let s be an eidetic singularity falling under the essence g; calling
s an eidetic singularity is motivated by the fact that any two instances of s are
essentially identical g’s.19 For instance, if s is an eidetic singularity falling under
the essence colour, then any two instances of s are essentially identical colours. An
eidetic singularity s is either dependent or independent (LU III §§ 13, 21; Ideen
§ 15). It is dependent if there is another essence s′ , not contained in s, such that
an instance of s cannot exist without an instance of s′ .20 For instance, the shape
of this table cannot exist without some colour, that is without an instance of the
essence colour. It is also true that this table itself cannot exist without some colour,
but the essence colour is contained in the essence table, hence that fact does not
make an eidetic singularity falling under the essence table dependent. An eidetic
singularity is independent if it is not dependent. An independent essence is called a
concretum and a dependent essence an abstractum.21 An instance of an abstractum
is thus what is often called a trope in the contemporary literature.22 Husserl defines
an individual to be the instance of a concretum (Ideen § 15).
An abstractum may be said to have several instances, differentiated by what
they inhere in. Thus, a most specific shade of green has an instance in the cover of
two books on my desk, and these instances, although they are essentially identical
colours, differ in that they inhere in different books. Since an instance of a concretum does not inhere in anything else, it is unique: it cannot be differentiated from
some other instance of the same concretum by reference to the individual it inheres
in. Thus, to each individual there is associated a concretum that is unique to it,
17
In traditional terms, these are the so-called constitutive, rather than the divisive, differentiae of
the essence in question. This distinction seems to have been introduced by Porphyry.
18Instead of ‘thisness’ Husserl more frequently (Ideen § 14) employs ‘this-here’ (Dies-da), which
he takes as a translation of Aristotle’s tode ti. ‘Thisness’ has the advantage of allowing a plural
form. The distinction between thisnesses and essences is discussed in several research manuscripts
from 1917/18, in particular in (Husserl, 2001a, Texte Nr. 16–17) and (Husserl, 2012, pp. 112–154).
19The assertion that there are concepts under which at most one object fall (which does not have
to be an individual) can be found already in Husserl’s 1896 logic lecture notes (Husserl, 2001b,
124). On this topic, see also the texts cited in the previous footnote 18.
20This definition is adapted from LU III §§ 13, 21. The requirement that s′ not be contained in
s is not stated by Husserl, but Simons (1982, p. 125) states something like it in his gloss on the
definition of the related notion of foundation from LU III § 14. The definition given at Ideen § 15
is that s is dependent when it founds together with another essence s′ “the unity of one essence”;
I shall not discuss the relation of this definition to the ones found in LU III.
21
This terminology was introduced in LU III § 17. For Husserl’s use of the word ‘abstract’ see
also LU II §§ 40–42.
22
The use of the term ‘trope’ in this sense originates in (Williams, 1953); Stout (1923) had spoken
about the same things as ‘abstract particulars’, in line with Husserl’s use of the word ‘abstract’.
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
7
and which may be identified with the essence of that individual. Because of the potential infinity of individuals, there are also potentially infinite eidetic singularities.
At this point Husserl is in disagreement with the tradition, since according to it
the “division” of a concept into species should be dichotomous or at least finite,23
while the potential infinity of lowest species requires that at least one division in
the ordering be potentially infinite.
A differentia is itself an essence, hence it itself falls into an ordering of genera and
species; whence it makes sense to speak of lowest differentiae contained in a concretum: these are differentiae that within their respective genus/species-orderings
are lowest species. To each aspect of an individual there is a differentia contained
in the concretum c that the individual instantiates. Under this differentia d there
falls a lowest species s, which also must be contained in the concretum c, since it
is only by virtue of c’s containing s that it contains d. For instance, any physical
thing is coloured, whence any concretum instantiated by a physical thing contains
the essence colour; but since the physical thing is coloured only by virtue of having
some specific colour, the concretum also contains an eidetic singularity falling under the essence colour. Thus a concretum may be thought of as a union of lowest
differentiae, each such differentia corresponding to a specific characteristic of the
individual that instantiates the concretum. Husserl appears to assume that if the
essence m is a characteristic mark of the essence s, and the essence m′ a genus of
m, then m′ is also a characteristic mark of s. In terms of essence containment that
is to say that, if m is contained in s and if m′ is a genus of m, then m′ is contained
in s. Hence, the highest genus of a lowest differentia contained in a concretum is
itself contained in the concretum.
We are now better equipped for understanding Husserl’s definition of region.
It says that a region is the unification of all the highest genera contained in a
concretum. A concretum contains all its characteristic marks; to each of these
marks there is associated a highest genus, also contained in the concretum; the
unification of all of these highest genera is a region. Husserl is unclear whether
the unification of highest genera making up a region is itself an essence—that is,
whether the region itself is an essence—but he appears to assume as much at least
for the regions of nature and pure consciousness: the region of nature is associated
with the essence of physical or material thing, while the region of pure consciousness
is associated with the essence of experience (Erlebnis). If a region in general is itself
an essence, then a region may simply be defined as the highest genus of a concretum,
that is, as the highest genus of an independent eidetic singularity. In any event we
can say that a region consists of several essences, each of which is the highest genus
within their orderings, and each of which is a characteristic mark of that region.24
1.2. Formal category. Let us now move to the notion of a formal category. As an
intuitive description of this notion we may say that it is the form of an object. An
23
See the citations and references provided by (Barnes, 2003, pp. 132–133).
24This idea is spelled out quite explicitly in a short research manuscript apparently written some
time between 1924 and 1928 (Husserl, 2012, p. 254): “Jedes Konkrete steht unter einer konkreten
“Kategorie”—das ist die “Region.” Jedes Abstrakte als reine Möglichkeit unter einer abstrakten
Kategorie, unter einem reinen Wesensbegriff stehend, der Komponente ist der Region.” From
elsewhere in the manuscript it is clear that what is here called categories are highest genera.
8
ANSTEN KLEV
individual differs in form from a property; a property differs in form from a state
of affairs; a state of affairs differs in form from a set. Individual, property, state
of affairs, and set may themselves be thought of as forms of object. According to
Husserl they are formal categories (e.g. Ideen § 10). Formal categories are topicneutral in the sense that they crosscut the regions, they apply across all regions; for
instance, there are individuals and properties in all of the regions. Husserl’s official
definition of the notion of formal category relies on the idea of a formal ontology.
Formal ontology is the theory of topic-neutral concepts; in Husserl’s words, it is
the theory of the notion of an object in general (Gegenstand überhaupt). It studies,
for instance, the part-whole relation and the formation of objects by means of
categorial forms. A regional ontology is, in contrast to formal ontology, tied to a
specific region. A regional ontology is the most general theory of objects falling
under a region. Thus, the regional ontology of nature is the most general theory
of physical, or material, objects; as already noted, it includes geometry and what
Husserl calls phoronomy, the theory of movement. A formal category is defined as
a primitive concept of formal ontology (Prolegomena § 67; Ideen § 10). A material
or regional category is defined as a primitive concept of a regional ontology (LU
III § 11; Ideen § 16). I mention this latter notion here only in order to exhibit the
parallel between its definition and that of a formal category. In Husserl’s discussions
it features much less prominently than both the notion of region and the notion of
formal category.
Husserl thinks of an object as a form-matter composite, its material elements
being provided by the regions and its formal elements by the formal categories. The
picture suggested in the Ideas is that regions consist of certain urelements (Husserl
calls them Urgegenständlichkeiten), namely the individuals of that region, together
with derivations of those urelements, obtained by means of the formal categories,
these derivations being called syntactical objects (ibid. § 11).25 The original mode
of awareness associated with the regions, discussed in the previous subsection, are
primarily modes of awareness of individuals, that is, of the urelements of the region.
Thus, what we are aware of in ordinary perception are the individuals of nature.
The syntactical, or categorially formed, objects of nature are not displayed in such
acts. Husserl’s doctrine of categorial intuition, developed in the sixth Logical Investigation (LU VI §§ 40–66), is meant to explain how we are originally aware of
categorially formed objects.26 There is, for instance, a way of forming, on the basis
of a simple perception of a pine tree, a perception of the state of affairs that the
pine tree is green (ibid. § 48). There is also a way of forming a perception of finite sets; indeed, the first part of the Philosophy of Arithmetic (Husserl, 1891b) is
mainly concerned with describing the nature of such set perception (see also LU VI
§ 51). Husserl also regarded so-called eidetic intuition—acts in which one perceives,
or otherwise intuits, an essence—as an instance of categorial intuition (ibid. § 52);
accordingly, he appears to have regarded essence as a formal category (cf. Ideen
§ 13).
25Note that the Greek word suntaxis simply means a putting together of certain elements, be
they words or soldiers or whatnot.
26Lohmar (2008) provides a helpful discussion.
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
9
Regions and formal categories are highly general concepts; but they are general in different ways. Husserl captures this difference with his distinction between
generalization and formalization: generalization stands to regions as formalization
stands to formal categories. In generalization one passes from an essence to a genus
of it; in formalization one passes from an object to its formal category. Continued
generalization leads to a highest genus, that is, either a region (provided a region
is itself an essence), or a highest genus contained in a region. Thus, from yellow
we pass to colour and from there, perhaps via some further steps, to sense quality,
which according to Husserl is a highest genus (Ideen § 13). The reverse process of
generalization is specialization. Continued specialization leads to an eidetic singularity, which may be a concretum or an abstractum. Thus, from colour we pass to
blue, and from there, perhaps via some further steps, to a most specific shade of
blue. In formalization (Ideen § 13; cf. LU III § 24), or what Husserl also calls pure
categorial abstraction (LU VI § 60), we pass from an object to its formal category
purely as a form or schema. In formalization we thus replace the material elements
of the object by “empty forms” (Leerformen). Perhaps the best illustration of this
process is the passage from a presentation of geometry in which the primitive terms
have their intuitive, geometrical meaning to a presentation in the style of Hilbert
(1899), in which the primitive terms are replaced by variables and the theory becomes “schematic.”27 (Carnap 1922, 7–8 obtains his notion of formal space from
the space of traditional Euclidean geometry precisely by this process.) The reverse
operation of formalization, in which the empty forms are “filled” again, Husserl
calls de-formalization (Entformalisierung) or materialization (Versachlichung). In
the geometrical case this corresponds to the passage from the schematic theory to
a “model” of it.
Husserl also calls formal categories ‘analytic categories’ and material categories
‘synthetic categories’. This terminology derives from his definition of analytic and
synthetic laws and propositions (LU III §§ 11–12).28 An analytic law is a true
proposition (Satz ) composed only of formal categories (or of concepts signifying
formal categories), while a synthetic law is a true proposition whose only material
elements are highest genera (or concepts signifying highest genera). An analytic
proposition is one that results from an analytic law by materialization, that is, by
filling the “empty forms” signifying formal categories with matter; while a synthetic
proposition is one that results from a synthetic law by specialization of the highest
genera signified in a synthetic law. Husserl gives as an example of an analytic law
the proposition that the existence of a whole implies the existence of its parts; an
analytic proposition derived from this law is that the existence of a particular house
27Cf. the following remark of Hilbert from lecture notes dated 1894 (Hallett and Majer, 2004,
p. 104):
Unsere Theorie liefert nur das Schema der Begriffe, die durch die unabänderliche
Gesetze der Logik mit einander verknüpft sind. Es bleibt dem menschlichen
Verstande überlassen, wie er dieses Schema auf die Erscheinung anwendet, wie
er es mit Stoff anfüllt.
For more on the relation between Hilbert and Husserl, see Hartimo’s contribution to this volume.
28Husserl made significant revisions in these paragraphs in the second edition of the Logical
Investigations, the relevant part of which was published in the same year as the Ideas. For the
definition of analytic and synthetic, see also (Husserl, 1996, pp. 227–229).
10
ANSTEN KLEV
implies the existence of its roof. An example of a synthetic law would perhaps be
that a colour cannot exist without an extension; a synthetic proposition derived
from this law is that the brown of this table top cannot exist without the extension
of the table top. Among the more well-known definitions of analyticity29—Kant’s,
Bolzano’s, Frege’s—Husserl’s is perhaps closest to the latter (cf. Frege, 1884, § 3),
since both rest on the distinction between general logical laws and truths pertaining
to a specific domain of knowledge, the notion of analyticity being related to the
former and that of the synthetic to the latter. Husserl was dissatisfied with, and so
tried to avoid, the terms ‘a priori’ and ‘a posteriori’ (cf. Ideen, Intro).
According to a traditional interpretation Aristotle’s categories are highest genera.30 Kant’s categories, by contrast, are described as forms of thought (KrV
B150, B305). Here we could thus speak of regions and formal categories respectively. It would be mistaken, however, to think that Husserl with his distinction
of regions and formal categories synthesizes the doctrines of Aristotle and Kant.
Firstly, none of Aristotle’s categories could be regarded as Husserlian regions. In
the greater scheme of things Aristotle’s primary substances correspond to Husserlian individuals;31 hence the Aristotelian category of substance splits into all the
various Husserlian regions, since these are precisely the highest genera under which
individuals fall. The Aristotelian category of quality would presumably be divided
between the regions of nature and consciousness. Number is in the Aristotelian
category of quantity (Categories, 4b 22), but for Husserl it is a formal category.
Secondly, the role categories play in Kant’s philosophy differs from the role formal
categories play in Husserl’s philosophy.32 For Kant the categories are concepts of
“pure synthesis” (KrV A78/B104). For Husserl, as well, the formal categories are
concepts of synthesis. The synthesis corresponding to Husserl’s formal categories,
however, has a much narrower scope than the synthesis corresponding to Kant’s
categories. The latter is involved in any act; in order, for instance, to perceive objects at all the mind must synthesize a “manifold of intuition,” namely by bringing
it under the categories. According to Kant, the unity of an object does not lie in
the object itself, to be extracted from it by perception, but is an “achievement of
the understanding,” by virtue of which the object has unity in the first place.33
The synthesis corresponding to Husserl’s formal categories, by contrast, is involved
only in acts whose objects are higher-level, such as sets and states of affairs. The
mind is in general not active in bringing about the unity of objects. The colour and
the spatial form of this table, for instance, are not connected by the mind, but are
given to it already connected. Likewise, the many “snapshots” I make of the table
as I regard it from different sides are not synthesized in the way higher-level objects
are synthesized from other objects. We may think of the latter as an active form
29See Sundholm (2013) for a discussion of these.
30A critical discussion of this interpretation can be found in Klev (2014, pp. 15–28).
31Stone (2000, p. 129) accepts this identification.
32On this point, see De Palma (2010).
33E.g. KrV B134–135: “Verbindung liegt aber nicht in den Gegenständen, und kann von ihnen
nicht etwa durch Wahrnehmung entlehnt und in den Verstand dadurch allererst aufgenommen
werden, sondern ist allein eine Verrichtung des Verstandes, der selbst nichts weiter ist, als das
Vermögen, a priori zu verbinden, und das Mannigfaltige gegebener Vorstellungen unter Einheit
der Apperzeption zu bringen.” Cf. B129–130.
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
11
of synthesis, while the former is passive (LU VI § 47; Ideen II § 9). Kant does not
have this distinction between active and passive synthesis.34 He therefore regards
all experience as categorially formed; for Husserl, by contrast, only the experience
of higher-level objects is categorially formed.
2. Regions in type theory: Carnap’s Aufbau
By a simple type hierarchy I shall understand a hierarchy of types or domains
of entities of the following design. At the bottom of the hierarchy there are one
or more types of individuals. At the next level there is for each natural number
n > 0 a type of n-ary relations (a 1-ary relation is a class). Then comes n-ary
relations between relations of individuals, and between relations of individuals and
individuals, and so on. Such a hierarchy may be recognized in the ideography
of Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Frege, 1893), but Frege there described
only its first few levels without giving a general definition. It seems to have been
Carnap who first provided such a general definition in his logic textbook, Abriss
der Logistik (Carnap, 1929).35 Following Frege as well as Russell and Whitehead,
who in their Principia Mathematica (Russell and Whitehead, 1910) had developed
a more complicated type hierarchy nowadays known as a ramified type hierarchy,
Carnap takes there to be only one domain of individuals, which we may denote
by ι. The type of classes of individuals is denoted by (ι), that of binary relations of
individuals by (ι, ι), the type of ternary relations of individuals by (ι, ι, ι), etc. The
type of classes of classes of individuals is denoted by ((ι)), that of binary relations
whose first place is a binary relation of individuals and whose second place is an
individual is denoted by ((ι, ι), ι), etc. We get the following inductive definition: ι
is a type; and if τ1 , . . . , τn are types, then (τ1 , . . . , τn ) is a type, namely the type of
n-ary relations whose k-th place is of type τk .
It requires little imagination to see that a hierarchy of types offers a system of
categories in the sense of general domains of entities. Indeed, from the point of
view of modern logic, with its basic form of proposition F (a)—function F applied
to argument a—simple types are the first domains of entities one sees, namely
as the objectual correlates of the categories of symbols employed in that logic:
individual symbols, namely individual variables and constants, perhaps of different
sorts; unary functors of individual symbols; binary functors of individual symbols;
unary functors of unary functors of individual symbols; and so on.36 It is therefore
natural to ask how the distinction between formal categories and regions can be
understood against the backdrop of a simple type hierarchy. The related distinction
between form and matter is not a part of the doctrine of types, just as it is not a
part of the doctrine of modern logic in general. But the form/matter-distinction
34Cf. the criticism of Kant found already in the Philosophy of Arithmetic (Husserl, 1891b, 41):
Kant übersah, daß viele inhaltliche Verbindungen uns gegeben sind, bei denen
von einer synthetischen, die inhaltliche Verbundenheit schaffenden Tätigkeit
nichts zu merken ist.
35Carnap’s role in the dissemination of the simple type hierarchy is discussed in Reck (2004,
pp. 163–166).
36The meaning categories (Bedeutungskategorien) of Ajdukiewicz (1935) are of course just simple
types.
12
ANSTEN KLEV
does suggest a useful distinction between kinds of type hierarchy. Namely, a type
hierarchy may be built over the “formal” ground type of individuals—that is, the
only information provided about the elements of the ground type is that they are
individuals; or it may be built over a “material” ground type, namely some specific
domain, like the domain of natural numbers, or the domain of real numbers, or some
empirical domain, like that of living beings—in this case more specific information
is provided about the nature of the elements of the ground type or types.
Distinguishing formal from material ground types is not yet to locate formal and
material categories in simple type hierarchies. Husserl’s conception of a region as
subsuming individuals together with derivations of these by means of formal categories is in fact readily adapted to the setting of simple types. Namely, we can
simply identify a region with a simple type hierarchy built over a single material
ground type; thus, each region will be its own type hierarchy. The ground type of
each hierarchy is the type of individuals of the region. The higher types contain
precisely all the various categorial derivations of the individuals. As formal categories we should therefore recognize ‘individual’ and the forms by means of which
higher-type objects—that is, relations—are formed. Precisely which forms these
are depends on technical details, but logical operators and an abstraction form,
such as lambda-abstraction, will need to be among them.
Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt (Carnap, 1928) suggests another way
of mapping regions onto a simple type hierarchy. The stated goal of that work is
to provide on the basis of a few primitive concepts a system of definitions of all
scientific concepts (§ 1), where science is not to be equated with natural science,
but must be taken to include the social sciences, including psychology, and the
humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). Such a system of definitions is called a constitution system. Carnap sets out to construct, albeit only in outline, a constitution
system by means of a simple type hierarchy with a material ground type. Two
kinds of ground type are, according to Carnap, adequate for the task of yielding
a constitution system, namely types whose elements are physical and types whose
elements are psychological. As Carnap wishes the order of definitions in the constitution system to mirror the order of epistemic priority among concepts (§ 54),
he settles on the latter kind of ground type (§ 64), and in particular on a ground
type whose elements are my experiences (Erlebnisse) taken “in their totality and
complete unity” (§ 67), what Carnap calls elementary experiences (Elementarerlebnisse). That these elements are experiences (in contrast to, say, electrons) and that
they are my, the constitution-system-building subject’s, experiences can, however,
be seen only after a significant portion of the system has been erected, namely
when the domain of the physical has been been constituted, and my psyche has
been distinguished from that of other subjects (§ 65).
In order to be able to define objects in this type hierarchy one or more primitive
relations must be given at the outset (§ 61). According to Carnap it is enough,
at least for the outlines of a constitution system he sketches, to assume one such
primitive relation, namely a binary relation over the ground type, holding between
elementary experiences x and y if the recollection or retention of x is in part similar
to y, that is, if a part of y is similar to a part of the recollection or retention of
x (§ 78). From this relation, which is asymmetric and irreflexive, it is easy to
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
13
define a relation that is symmetric and reflexive and that holds between elementary
experiences x and y if these are in part similar to each other, that is, if a part of
x is similar to a part of y (§ 77). With these two relations in hand Carnap goes
on to define classes and relations of various types that are to serve as “rational
reconstructions” of scientific concepts. The definitions quickly get complicated. So
called quality classes are to serve as rational reconstructions of particular sense
qualities, such as the sensation of a particular shade of red at a particular point in
the visual field, or a particular tactile sensation at a particular point on the body.
The definition of a quality class is one of the first provided (§ 112), but it already is
rather complex and requires several pages of motivation (§ 81). Carnap then defines
similarity between quality classes (§ 114) and obtains what he calls sense classes as
the transitive closures of quality classes under similarity (§§ 85, 115): two quality
classes belong to the same sense class if there is a path of similarity leading from
the one to the other; there is, for instance, for any two colour sensations such a path
between them. This definition may be straightforward enough, but in order to single
out the various sense classes as the visual field, the tactile field, etc., Carnap must
appeal to the technically non-trivial topological notion of (inductive) dimension
(§§ 86, 115). It is in fact questionable whether all of these initial definitions capture
what Carnap intends them to capture, as Goodman (1951, ch. V) noted.
Our current interest in the Aufbau stems from the fact that Carnap there takes
scientific concepts to be of different kinds, namely, he takes there to be different
kinds of object (Gegenstandsarten) (§§ 17–25). These kinds of objects may in the
greater scheme of things very well be regarded as regions more or less in the sense
of Husserl. Indeed, the kinds of object that mainly concern Carnap are, in his
terminology, the self-psychological (das Eigenpsychische), the physical, the otherpsychological (das Fremdpsychische), and the cultural and social (das Geistige),
and these may well be taken to correspond to Husserl’s regions of consciousness,
nature, living nature, and culture (die geistige Welt). In what follows I shall therefore also call Carnap’s kinds of object ‘regions’. According to Carnap an order
of epistemic priority obtains between the various regions: the self-psychological is
epistemically prior to the physical, the physical is epistemically prior to the otherpsychological, and the other-psychological is epistemically prior to the cultural and
social (§ 58). The constitution system has to reflect this order. Hence we are to
think of the regions as forming strata or segments within the type hierarchy. At
the bottom of the hierarchy is the region of the self-psychological; then comes a
segment with the physical, then a segment with the other-psychological, and finally a segment with the cultural and social region. The formal categories of the
hierarchy will be the category of individuals together with the logical forms used in
constructing objects of higher types. The latter include the Sheffer stroke, universal
quantification over any type, and an abstraction form (§ 107); the abstraction form
takes a propositional function ϕ(x) and yields, as the case may be, the proposition
or propositional function x̂ϕ(x), where x is no longer free. These logical forms,
or formal categories, Carnap calls the Stufenformen of his hierarchy (§ 26): “the
recurring forms by which the passage from one level to the next is achieved.”
14
ANSTEN KLEV
Let us now consider how the conception of regions as segments in the type
hierarchy is to be made precise. It seems to me that in order for the described
structure to be realized, the following two requirements must be met.
(i) It need not, and usually will not, be the case that all elements of a type are
used in a constitution system. That is, within any type, if it is employed at all in
the system, there will, in general, be some objects that do serve and some that do
not serve as rational reconstructions of concepts. Let us write u(τ ), the use of τ ,
for those elements of type τ that do in fact serve as rational reconstructions. The
first requirement says that all elements of u(τ ) belong to the same region. This is a
requirement of typical homogeneity: no type is to be separated by two regions. Let
us, for instance, consider the type ((ι)) of classes of classes of elementary experiences. The so-called sense classes mentioned above belong to this type. Since sense
classes serve as rational reconstructions of concepts from the self-psychological region, the requirement says that within the type ((ι)) there should not be another
object that serves as the reconstruction of a concept belonging to some other region,
for instance the region of the physical.
If u(τ ) is non-empty, then let us say that the type τ is used. The main rationale
for requirement (i) is that, provided it is met, we can define an order on used types
as follows: σ ≤ τ if and only if no element of u(τ ) is epistemically prior to an
element of u(σ). Thus, if requirement (i) is met, then the relation of epistemic
priority among the four regions induces a partial order on used types. For instance,
if the elements of u(σ) belong to the region of the physical and the elements of u(τ )
to the region of the other-psychological, then we have σ ≤ τ . If the elements of
u(τ ) belong to the region of the self-psychological, however, then we have τ ≤ σ.
(ii) Let us call the trace of a type the set of all types involved in its construction
from the ground type. For instance, the types involved in the construction of the
type ((ι)) are ι and (ι); these are, as it were, the building blocks of that type. The
types involved in the construction of the slightly more complicated type (((ι), ι), ι)
are ((ι), ι), (ι), and ι. Continuing to employ ι as a name of the ground type, the
trace tr(τ ) of a type τ can be defined inductively as follows:
tr(ι)
tr((τ1 , . . . , τn ))
:=
:=
∅
S
{{τ1 , . . . , τn }, tr(τ1 ), . . . , tr(τn )}
Thus the trace of a type (τ1 , . . . , τn ) is a set consisting of each of the types τ1 , . . . , τn
together with the traces of each of these types. Employing the definition we find
for instance that
tr (((ι), ι), ι) = {((ι), ι), (ι), ι}.
Recall the order ≤, just defined, of epistemic priority among used types. The second
requirement says that we should have σ ≤ τ for all used types σ in tr(τ ). Spelling
out the definition of ≤, this is to say that, if σ ∈ tr(τ ), then the objects in u(τ )
are not to be epistemically prior to the objects in u(σ). This requirement gives
mathematical expression to the idea that in the definition of an object a that is to
serve as a rational reconstruction of some concept c we shall not need to refer to
an object serving as the rational reconstruction of some concept c′ that, in view
of its region, is epistemically posterior to c. No concept is built up from concepts
epistemically posterior to it.
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
15
Carnap does not spell out these requirements in the Aufbau. That he entertained
a picture of the construction of the world in which they are met is, however, suggested by what he says about levels of constitution (§ 41). The level of constitution
of a concept is the level in the type hierarchy at which a rational reconstruction of it
is defined. Carnap had defined the notion of level in a simple type hierarchy in the
Abriss.37 The level ℓ of the ground type is 0; the level of a higher type (τ1 , . . . , τn )
is defined by
ℓ (τ1 , . . . , τn ) := max{ℓ(τ1 ), . . . , ℓ(τn )} + 1
Those familiar with the cumulative hierarchy of sets will see the parallel to the
notion of rank defined in that context. In the picture Carnap appears to entertain
the regions respect levels: for used types, σ, τ , it holds that
if ℓ(σ) < ℓ(τ ), then σ ≤ τ .
We thus have a situation as in Figure 1. The first few levels make up the region
Type hierarchy
level k + l + m + n
level k + l + m
level k + l
level k
level 0 (ground domain)
..
.
—
..
.
—
..
.
—
..
.
—
..
.
Elementarerlebnisse
Regions
?
Culture
Other-psychological
Physical
Self-psychological
Figure 1. Carnap’s construction of the world?
of the self-psychological. The levels afterwards make up the region of the physical,
the following levels make up the region of the other-psychological, and finally come
the levels of the cultural and social. Whereas each region thus takes up only finitely
many levels, the type hierarchy continues into infinity; at levels above those making
up the region of culture the romantics among us can therefore imagine a region that
is yet to be discovered.
While Carnap structures his sketch of a constitution system in the Aufbau according to what he takes to be the regions the self-psychological, the physical, the
other-psychological, and culture and society, he also maintains that the possibility
of erecting a constitution system shows that there is fundamentally only one region
(§ 4): “objects do not fall into different, unconnected domains, rather there is just
one domain of objects.” Carnap seems to hold in particular that a constitution
system with a self-psychological basis shows that the self-psychological region is,
fundamentally, the only region. This view must be based on the assumption that
if the ground type of a type hierarchy belongs to a given region, then the whole
37See Carnap (1929, p. 32).
16
ANSTEN KLEV
hierarchy belongs to the same region; the region of any type is inherited from the
region of the types out of which it is constructed and at the base there is only
the one region of the self-psychological. There seems thus to be a tension between
ideas such as those expressed in Figure 1 and what Carnap takes constitution theory to show, namely that there is just one region. To relieve this tension it seems
to me best to distinguish between concepts before and after constitution. What
Carnap calls rational reconstruction is a relation between between these, namely
between ordinary scientific concepts on the one hand and relations in a certain
type hierarchy on the other. The constituted concepts are ultimately to replace
the ordinary scientific concepts, since only of the former do we know the precise
definition in terms of elementary experiences (cf. § 179). Ultimately, therefore, it
will be seen that there is only one region. For, while we can say of ordinary scientific concepts that they fall into different regions, we should not, according to
Carnap, say the same about the constituted concepts. Figure 1 above thus does
not show how regions actually live inside a constitution system; rather it shows the
type hierarchy of a constitution system through the prism of a division into regions
of ordinary scientific concepts; the order of epistemic priority holding between the
regions is reflected by the order holding between the relations serving as rational
reconstructions of the ordinary scientific concepts falling into those regions.
3. Carnap and Husserl
Carnap had studied the Ideas thoroughly. That is clear from the detailed references to different sections of this work not only in the Aufbau but also in Carnap’s
dissertation, Der Raum (Carnap, 1922).38 From references in the latter in particular one sees that Carnap was conversant with the distinction between regions and
formal categories as well as with the related distinction between generalization and
formalization, indeed with all the important notions from the first chapter of the
first section of the Ideas.39 It is, however, difficult to say whether Carnap thought
of what he called kinds of object (Gegenstandsarten) as Husserlian regions. In the
Aufbau Carnap tends to be quite generous with references to the works of others,
so if he had Husserlian regions in mind with his notion of kind of object, one would
have expected some reference to Husserl at the relevant places, but that is not to be
found. It has, however, been noted by Mayer (1991, p. 301, fn. 11), and with greater
emphasis by Rosado Haddock (2008), that several apparently Husserlian influences
are not indicated as such by Carnap. In § 25 of the Aufbau Carnap lists several
kinds of object apart from those already discussed: logical objects, mathematical
objects, spatial forms, colours, tones, biological objects, and ethical objects. Neither of these correspond to Husserlian regions (perhaps apart from the logical and
38Christian Damböck, who has studied Carnap’s reading lists, reported in a talk at the HOPOS
2014 meeting at Ghent, 4 July, 2014 that between 1920 and 1923 Carnap worked through the
Ideas three times.
39See especially (Carnap, 1922, 60–61), where Carnap compares the relation between the geometries related to the three kinds of space he has been studying with the relation between formal
ontology, regional ontology, and factual science (Tatsachenwissenschaft), and where he also employs the distinction between formalization and generalization. The Husserlian notions of essence
and eidetic intuition are fundamental to Carnap’s treatment of what he calls intuitive space (ibid.
22–31).
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
17
the mathematical objects, which Husserl sometimes (e.g. Ideen § 11) says belong
to a formal region), a fact which suggests that Carnap’s notion of kind of object is
independent of Husserl’s notion of region; but spatial form, colour, and tone are all
essences in the region of nature, which Husserl discusses in the first chapter of the
Ideas, so Carnap may have drawn inspiration from those discussions.
One should in any event be careful not to make too much of the parallels between
the Aufbau and the Ideas. A proper assessment of the relation between these works
would require more space than what I have available here, but it should be clear, I
think, that the Aufbau in no way can be regarded as a work in phenomenology.40
Carnap’s conception of what he calls constitution is telling. It is not unlikely
that he had the term ‘constitution’ from Husserl,41 but his understanding of it
is very far from Husserl’s. For Carnap ‘constitution’ means the definition of an
object in the simple type hierarchy in terms of others (§ 38). For Husserl, however,
‘constitution’ indicates how an object presents itself to consciousness;42 to describe
the constitution of material individuals, for instance, means to describe the various
components, or layers, that make up our experience of such objects (cf. Ideen II
§§ 12–17). An object in Carnap’s constitution system is to serve as a rational
reconstruction of a concept. Carnap emphasizes that the constitution system need
not reflect “the syntheses and formations of knowledge as they actually occur in
the process of knowledge” (§ 54); rational reconstructions are to preserve only the
“logical value” of the original concepts, they need not preserve their “cognitive
value” (Erkenntniswert), not their sense (§§ 50–51). One of the more important
methods of the Aufbau is called quasi -analysis and the result of an instance of
quasi-analysis is said to be a formaler Ersatz for the components that a proper
(eigentliche) analysis would yield (§§ 69–71). Such ideas are of course quite foreign
to phenomenology, with its emphasis on giving a true description of experience and
what is experienced, on merely explicating what originally gives itself in eidetic
intuition.
References
Ajdukiewicz, K. (1935). Die syntaktische Konnexität. Studia Philosophica, 1:1–27.
Arnauld, A. and Nicole, P. (1662/1683). La Logique, ou l’art de penser. Iaen Guignart/Guillame
Desprez, Paris. Critical edition: Vrin, Paris, 1981.
Barnes, J., editor (1984). The Complete Works of Aristotle. Revised Oxford Translations. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Barnes, J. (2003). Porphyry. Introduction. Translated with an Introduction and Commentary.
Clarendon Later Ancient Philosophers. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Brockhaus, K. (1976). Konstitution. III. Neuzeit. In Gründer, K. et al., editors, Historisches
Wörterbuch der Philosophie, volume 4, pages 997–1004. Schwabe, Basel.
40I take Roy (2004) and Ryckman (2007, pp. 95–98) to argue for the same stance.
41In Kant it is the adjective ‘constitutive’ rather than the noun ‘constitution’ that is prominent (cf.
Brockhaus, 1976); ‘constitution’ is apparently employed by the Marburger neo-Kantians Cohen
and Natorp (ibid. 1002–1003); but Carnap distances his use of ‘constitution’ from Marburgerschool doctrine in § 5 of the Aufbau. The word features prominently in the Ideas, especially in
its final sections, and it may very well have come up in the Husserl seminar Carnap attended;
Carnap may also have been familiar, through Ludwig Landgrebe, with the contents of the second
book of the Ideas (cf. Stone, 2010, fn. 48).
42Constitution is, as far as I know, not a technical term for Husserl and his employment of it is
not so easy to circumscribe.
18
ANSTEN KLEV
Carnap, R. (1922). Der Raum. Reuther & Reichard, Berlin.
Carnap, R. (1928). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Weltkreis Verlag, Berlin.
Carnap, R. (1929). Abriss der Logistik. Springer, Vienna.
De Palma, V. (2010).
Die Kategorien des Sinnlichen. Zu Husserls Kategorienlehre.
Phänomenologische Forschungen, 15 (NF):23–39.
Frege, G. (1884). Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Verlag von Wilhelm Koebner, Breslau.
Frege, G. (1893). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik I. Hermann Pohle, Jena.
Goodman, N. (1951). The Structure of Appearance. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Gottschalk, H. B. (1990). The earliest Aristotelian commentators. In Sorabji, R., editor, Aristotle
Transformed. The ancient commentators and their influence, pages 55–82. Duckworth, London.
Hallett, M. and Majer, U., editors (2004). David Hilbert’s Lectures on the Foundations of Geometry. Springer, Heidelberg.
Hilbert, D. (1899). Grundlagen der Geometrie. Teubner, Leipzig.
Husserl, E. (1891a). Der Folgerungskalkül und die Inhaltslogik. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 15:168–189. Reprinted in Husserl (1979).
Husserl, E. (1891b). Philosophie der Arithmetik. C.E.M. Pfeffer, Halle. Cited from Husserl (1970).
Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Theil: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Max
Niemeyer, Halle.
Husserl, E. (1901).
Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Theil:
Untersuchungen zur
Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Max Niemeyer, Halle.
Husserl, E. (1913). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie.
Erstes Buch. Max Niemeyer, Halle. Cited from Husserl (1976).
Husserl, E. (1939). Erfahrung und Urteil. Academia Verlagsbuchhandlung, Prague.
Husserl, E. (1952a). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie.
Zweites Buch, edited by Biemel, M., volume IV of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1952b). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie.
Drittes Buch, edited by Biemel, M., volume V of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1956). Erste Philosophie (1923/24). Erster Teil, edited by Boehm, R., volume VII
of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1968). Phänomenologische Psychologie, edited by Biemel, W., volume IX of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1970). Philosophie der Arithmetik. Mit ergänzenden Texten (1890-1901), edited by
Eley, L., volume XII of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie
I, edited by Schumann, K., volume III/1 of Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1979). Aufsätze und Rezensionen (1890–1910), edited by Rang, B., volume XXII of
Husserliana. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Husserl, E. (1996). Logik und Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie. Vorlesungen 1917/18, mit
ergänzenden Texten aus der ersten Fassung von 1910/11, edited by Panzer, U., volume XXX
of Husserliana. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Husserl, E. (2001a). Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein, edited by Bernet, R. and
Lohmar, D., volume XXXIII of Husserliana. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Husserl, E. (2001b). Logik. Vorlesung 1896, edited by Schumann, E. Husserliana Materialen.
Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Husserl, E. (2001c). Natur und Geist. Vorlesungen Sommersemeseter 1927, edited by Weiler, M.,
volume XXXII of Husserliana. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Husserl, E. (2012). Zur Lehre vom Wesen und zur Methode der eidetischen Variation, edited by
Fonfara, D., volume XLI of Husserliana. Springer, Dordrecht.
Kant, I. (1781/1787). Kritik der Reinen Vernunft. Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, Riga.
Kauppi, R. (1971). Begriffsinhalt/Begriffsumfang. In Ritter, J. et al., editors, Historisches
Wörterbuch der Philosophie, volume 1, pages 808–809. Schwabe, Basel.
Klev, A. (2013). Form of apprehension and the content-apprehension model in Husserl’s Logical
Investigations. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 16:49–69.
Klev, A. (2014). Categories and Logical Syntax. PhD thesis, Leiden University.
HUSSERL AND CARNAP
19
Lohmar, D. (2008). Kategoriale Anschauung (VI. Logische Untersuchung, §§ 40–66). In Mayer,
V., editor, Edmumd Husserl. Logische Untersuchungen, Klassiker Auslegen, pages 209–237.
Akademie Verlag, Berlin.
Mayer, V. (1991). Die Konstruktion der Erfahrungswelt: Carnap und Husserl. Erkenntnis, 35:287–
303.
Morrison, B. (2005). Les Cátegories d’Aristote comme introduction à la logique. In Brun, O. and
Corti, L., editors, Les Catégories et leur histoire, pages 103–120, Paris. Vrin.
Null, G. T. (1989). Husserl’s doctrine of essence. In Mohanty, J. N. and McKenna, W. R., editors,
Husserl’s Phenomenology: A textbook, pages 69–105. University Press of America, Washington,
D.C.
Reck, E. H. (2004). From Frege and Russell to Carnap: Logic and logicism in the 1920’s. In
Awodey, S. and Klein, C., editors, Carnap Brought Home: The View from Jena, pages 151–
180. Open Court, Chicago.
Rosado Haddock, G. (2008). The Young Carnap’s Unknown Master. Ashgate, Aldershot.
Roy, J.-M. (2004). Carnap’s Husserlian reading of the Aufbau. In Awodey, S. and Klein, C.,
editors, Carnap Brought Home: The View from Jena, pages 41–62. Open Court, Chicago.
Russell, B. and Whitehead, A. N. (1910). Principia Mathematica, volume 1. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Ryckman, T. (2007). Carnap and Husserl. In Friedman, M. and Creath, R., editors, The Cambridge Companion to Carnap, pages 81–105. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Ryle, G. (1938). Categories. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 38:189–206.
Ryle, G. (1954). Dilemmas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Sarkar, S. (2003). Husserl’s role in Carnap’s Der Raum. In Bonk, T., editor, Language, Truth
and Knoweldge. Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, pages 179–190. Kluwer,
Dordrecht.
Schumann, K. (1977). Husserl-Chronik. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
Simons, P. (1982). The formalisation of Husserl’s theory of wholes and parts. In Smith, B., editor,
Parts and Moments, pages 113–159. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.
Stone, A. (2000). On Husserl and Cavellian Skepticism, With Reference to the Thomistic Theory of Creation. PhD thesis, Harvard University. Available at http://www.abocalypse.com/
papers/skep.pdf.
Stone, A. (2010). On the sources and implications of Carnap’s Der Raum. Studies in the History
and Philosophy of Science, 41:65–74.
Stout, G. F. (1923). Are the characteristics of particular things universal or particular? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 3:114–122.
Sundholm, B. G. (2013). Containment and variation; two strands in the development of analyticity
from Aristotle to Martin-Löf. In van der Schaar, M., editor, Judgement and the Epistemic
Foundation of Logic, Heidelberg. Springer.
Tonelli, G. (1966). Die Voraussetzungen zur Kantischen Urteilstafel in der Logik des 18. Jahrhunderts. In Kaulbach, F. and Ritter, J., editors, Kritik und Metaphysik. Heinz Heimsoeth zum
achtzigsten Geburtstag, pages 134–158. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin.
Williams, D. C. (1953). On the elements of being. Review of Metaphysics, 7:3–18, 171–192.