Proc. R. Soc. B
doi:10.1098/rspb.2010.2342
Published online
The ‘spiteful’ origins of human cooperation
Frank W. Marlowe1,*, J. Colette Berbesque2, Clark Barrett3,
Alexander Bolyanatz4, Michael Gurven5 and David Tracer6
1
Department of Anthropology, University of Durham, Dawson Building, South Road, Durham DH1 3LE, UK
2
Centre for Research in Evolutionary Anthropology, Department of Life Sciences, Roehampton University,
Holybourne Avenue, London SW15 4JD, UK
3
Department of Anthropology, UCLA, 341 Haines Hall, Box 951553, Los Angeles, CA 90095, USA
4
Department of Anthropology, College of DuPage, Glen Ellyn, IL 60137, USA
5
Department of Anthropology, University of California Santa Barbara, CA 93106, USA
6
Department of Anthropology, University of Colorado at Denver and Health Sciences Center, PO Box 173364,
Campus Box 103, Denver, CO 80217-3364, USA
We analyse generosity, second-party (‘spiteful’) punishment (2PP), and third-party (‘altruistic’)
punishment (3PP) in a cross-cultural experimental economics project. We show that smaller societies
are less generous in the Dictator Game but no less prone to 2PP in the Ultimatum Game. We might
assume people everywhere would be more willing to punish someone who hurt them directly (2PP)
than someone who hurt an anonymous third person (3PP). While this is true of small societies, people
in large societies are actually more likely to engage in 3PP than 2PP. Strong reciprocity, including generous offers and 3PP, exists mostly in large, complex societies that face numerous challenging collective
action problems. We argue that ‘spiteful’ 2PP, motivated by the basic emotion of anger, is more universal
than 3PP and sufficient to explain the origins of human cooperation.
Keywords: altruism; cooperation; experimental economics games; punishment; spite
1. INTRODUCTION
The origins of human cooperation are the subject of
vigorous debate [1– 3]. Drawing on experimental economics games some propose that humans exhibit ‘strong
reciprocity’ [4 –7]. This is defined as, ‘a predisposition
to cooperate with others and to punish those who violate
the norms of cooperation, at personal cost, even when it is
implausible to expect that these costs will be repaid either
by others or at a later date’ [8, p. 153]. Strong reciprocity
proponents argue that ‘. . .under conditions plausibly
characteristic of the early stages of human evolution, a
small fraction of strong reciprocators could invade a
population of self-regarding types’ [8, p. 154]. If we
found that people cooperate with cooperators, defect on
defectors (second party punishment) and punish those
who defect on others (third party punishment), we
might conclude that strong reciprocity explains the origins
of human cooperation. However, we present results here
that cast doubt on that explanation of the origins of
human cooperation.
In a previous paper, we reported that there is less third
party punishment (3PP) in small societies than in large
societies [9]. Here we show that small societies are also
less generous than large societies. Most importantly, however, we show that small societies do engage in as much
second party punishment (2PP) as large societies. We
argue that it is second party, ‘spiteful’ punishment that
explains human cooperation in small-scale foraging
societies while strong reciprocity is more relevant for
understanding the cultural evolution of large, complex,
agricultural societies.
A common assumption in the cooperation literature is
that small, foraging societies are more cooperative than
larger societies [4,6,8]. This is somewhat understandable
given the ethnographic description of routine food sharing among foragers [10 – 14]. Reciprocal altruism [15]
in the form of in-kind, delayed reciprocity is often
assumed to explain this sharing. However, nepotism
[16] can explain sharing within the household. Given
the uniquely human sexual division of foraging labour,
the sharing of foods between spouses could be mate provisioning or trade (e.g. meat for fruit) [17]. Some of the
food sharing across households may be explained by
scrounging or forced cooperation [18 – 21]. Still, food
sharing and other forms of cooperation may be partly
explained by direct or indirect reciprocity [11,12]. Results
from economics games played in a wide range of societies
show that people in small-scale societies behave less like
strong reciprocators than people in large societies.
The data come from a cross-cultural project conducted
in a wide range of societies, including hunter – gatherers,
horticulturalists, pastoralists, farmers and city dwellers
[22] (electronic supplementary material, table S1).
Three anonymous, one-shot games were played with
real money. In the dictator game (DG), player one (P1)
decides how much (from 0 to 100%) to give player two
(P2) from a stake the researcher provides and says is to
be divided between P1 and P2. P1 keeps the remainder
for himself. The DG offer is a simple, straightforward
measure of altruism and generosity [23,24].
There is no reason P1 has to give P2 anything, so how
should we interpret positive offers? P1 may recognize or
feel that his role is similar to that of a person who wants
* Author for correspondence (
[email protected]).
Electronic supplementary material is available at http://dx.doi.org/
10.1098/rspb.2010.2342 or via http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org.
Received 27 October 2010
Accepted 25 November 2010
1
This journal is q 2010 The Royal Society
2 F. W. Marlowe et al.
‘Spiteful’ origins of human cooperation
Box 1. Strong reciprocity’s three components, predictions and test results.
components
predictions
results in small societies
1. cooperate
2. punish
(a) second-party punishment
(b) third-party punishment
high DG offers (approx. 50%)
low DG offers
high UG MAO
high 3PPG MAO
high UG MAO
low 3PPG MAO
to initiate direct or indirect reciprocity. The DG is a oneshot, anonymous game with no way for P2 to reciprocate.
In real life, however, people accustomed to initiating reciprocal exchanges with ‘partners’ should cooperate on the
first move without knowing whether there will be subsequent interactions or not. For delayed reciprocity to
evolve, someone has to make the first move and
cooperate. If people behave as strong reciprocators, we
should expect DG offers to be high, something approaching 50 per cent. An even split on the first move would best
convey the intent to cooperate in a reciprocal relationship.
2PP is measured with the ultimatum game (UG) [25].
In the UG, P1 again decides how to divide the stake with
P2 and if P2 accepts the offer she gets that amount and
P1 gets the remainder. However, if P2 rejects the offer
both players get nothing. P2’s rejection is her way of
employing 2PP to punish stingy P1’s. Alternatively, it
could be a by-product of a partner choice strategy [26].
3PP is measured with the third-party punishment
game (3PPG) [27], in which P1 can give whatever
amount of the stake to P2. Just as in the DG, P2 can
do nothing about it. However, there is a player 3 (P3)
who can return 20 per cent of her allotment (half as
much as the stake) to the researcher in order to take
away three times that amount from P1.
When P2 rejects an offer of 30 per cent in the UG, presumably out of moral outrage [28 – 30], she thereby
punishes P1 (who wanted to keep 70%). Given that she
gets zero instead of 30 per cent, it costs her as well as
her stingy partner. We can therefore say her rejection is
spiteful. Whether natural selection can favour spite has
been the subject of debate, clouded by different definitions of spite [31 – 37] (electronic supplementary
material, appendix S1.1). In the context of these anonymous, one-shot games 2PP is spiteful. P2 gains
nothing, yet just to punish P1 pays a cost by taking zero
rather than accepting a low offer. In real life, however,
2PP probably eventually results in a benefit to punishers
because others learn they cannot easily get away with
defecting on them [38]. This explains the single quotes
around ‘spiteful’ in our title.
The same can be said of ‘altruism’. In the 3PPG, when
P3 gives back to the researcher 20 per cent of her allotment to take money away from P1 who slighted P2, she
is being altruistic, presumably feeling that P2 suffered
an injustice according to the local social norm. In the context of these anonymous, one-shot games 3PP is altruistic,
since P3 stands to gain nothing. In real life, however, such
punishers may get a reputation as good citizens and might
be rewarded for enforcing standards of fairness for the
larger group, hence our single quotes around ‘altruism’
in our previous paper [9]. While 2PP and 3PP are not
perfectly comparable (electronic supplementary material,
Proc. R. Soc. B
appendix S1.2), we might assume that costly, altruistic
punishment by a person who has not been wronged
directly would be less common than spiteful punishment
by an angry person who has been directly wronged. We
show here that this is true of small societies but surprisingly it is not true of large societies. We also investigate
whether generosity varies with population size. Box 1
shows what we should expect if strong reciprocity explains
the origins of human cooperation.
2. METHODS
The UG and 3PPG were played using the strategy method
[39] as reported in Barr et al. [40] and Henrich et al. [22]
(electronic supplementary material, appendix S1.3). This
allowed us to calculate the minimum acceptable offer
(MAO), that is, the minimum amount that the offer must
be to avoid punishment. The UG MAO is our measure of
2PP. 3PPG MAO is our measure of 3PP. We took MAO
values from Henrich et al. [22] (appendices 1.1 and 1.4).
Our measure of generosity is the mean DG offer. We took
DG, UG and 3PPG offers from Barr et al. [40].
We analysed the variation in DG offers and MAO’s in
relation to two measures of population size. Local group
population refers to the typical group size people live in,
whether that be a camp among mobile foragers, a village
among horticulturalists, or a city among industrialized
societies (electronic supplementary material, appendix
S1.4). Ethnic population is the number of people in the
ethno-linguistic group. Ethnic populations were obtained
from the Ethnologue database of world languages online
[41], or when available from the researcher’s own reports
[9,42]. In all cases, we use the rank order of these two
types of population.
3. RESULTS
As previously reported, the 3PPG MAO was correlated
with rank orders of both local group and ethnic population [9]. Ethnic population alone accounted for 56 per
cent of the variance in the 3PPG MAO. The same was
not true of the UG MAO. UG MAO was not significantly
correlated with rank of mean local group size (r ¼ 0.315,
p ¼ 0.319, n ¼ 12) or ethnic population (r ¼ 0.209, p ¼
0.537, n ¼ 11) with Spearman’s rank correlations.
A linear regression, controlling for continent produced
the same results: UG MAO by local group population (b ¼ 0.355, p ¼ 0.353, d.f. ¼ 8); UG by ethnic
population (b ¼ 0.348, p ¼ 0.407, d.f. ¼ 7) (electronic
supplementary material, appendix S1.5).
Figure 1a shows local group population and figure 1b
ethnic population for each society in order of increasing
size. In local group populations there is a clear jump in
Maragoli
Gusi
Accra
Samburu
Shuar
Isanga
Au
Tsimane
Sursuranga
Yasawa
Hadza
ethnic population
Accra
Maragoli
Samburu
Sanquianga
Isanga
Au
Tsimane
Sursuranga
Yasawa
Shuar
Hadza
mean local group population
rank of local group population
5 000 000
140 000
130 000
120 000
110 000
100 000
90 000
80 000
70 000
60 000
50 000
40 000
30 000
20 000
10 000
0
1 300 000
(b) 150 000
197 000
2 000 000
2800
2600
2400
2200
2000
1800
1600
1400
1200
1000
800
600
400
200
0
3 580
(a) 3000
Gusi
‘Spiteful’ origins of human cooperation F. W. Marlowe et al.
3
rank of ethnic population
Figure 1. Societies ranked by (a) local group population and (b) ethnic population.
mean per cent of stakes (MAO)
(a) 30
*
(b)
*
20
10
0
six smallest societies
six largest societies
local group population
five smallest societies
five largest societies
ethnic population
Figure 2. UG MAO (grey bars) and 3PP MAO (black bars) by smallest versus largest societies as measured by (a) local group
population (3PPG MAO: U ¼ 4, p ¼ 0.026); (UG MAO: U ¼ 15, p ¼ 0.699) and (b) ethnic population (3PPG MAO: U ¼ 3,
p ¼ 0.030); (UG MAO: U ¼ 15, p ¼ 1). Asterisks indicate p , 0.05.
size between 242 and 1500 and in ethnic populations
between 8000 and 45 000. In both cases the break is
between the Au and Isanga (electronic supplementary
material, appendix S1.6). We used this break to define
two groups, the small versus large societies. 3PPG
MAO was significantly higher in the large societies than
in the small societies. This was true whether we look at
the local group population (U ¼ 4, p ¼ 0.026, n1 ¼ 6,
n2 ¼ 6) or the ethnic population (U ¼ 3, p ¼ 0.030,
n1 ¼ 5, n2 ¼ 6), using Mann-Whitney two-sample, nonparametric tests (figure 2a,b).
There was not a significant difference between the small
and large societies in the UG MAO. Again, this was true
of both local group (U ¼ 15, p ¼ 0.699, n1 ¼ 6, n2 ¼ 6)
and ethnic population (U ¼ 15, p ¼ 1, n1 ¼ 5, n2 ¼ 6;
figure 2a,b).
We analysed the relationship between UG and 3PPG
MAO’s by subtracting the 3PPG MAO from the UG
Proc. R. Soc. B
MAO for all societies (electronic supplementary material,
appendix S1.7). There was a significant difference in the
two amounts of punishment between the small and large
societies (U ¼ 2, p ¼ 0.017, n1 ¼ 5, n2 ¼ 6) (figure 3).
Large societies engaged in significantly more 3PP than
2PP (local pop: Wilcoxon’s Z ¼ 22.201, p ¼ 0.028,
n ¼ 6; ethnic pop: Wilcoxon’s Z ¼ 22.201, p ¼ 0.028,
n ¼ 6). Small societies engaged in more 2PP than 3PP
but the difference was not significant (local pop:
Wilcoxon’s Z ¼ 20.524, p ¼ 0.600, n ¼ 6; ethnic pop:
Wilcoxon’s Z ¼ 21.214, p ¼ 0.225, n ¼ 5).
Finally, we examined whether larger or smaller
societies made more generous offers in the DG. In a
linear regression, controlling for continent, DG offers
were lower in societies with a smaller local group population (b ¼ 0.746, p ¼ 0.042, d.f. ¼ 8) and with a
smaller ethnic population (b ¼ 0.801, p ¼ 0.014, d.f. ¼ 7)
(see the electronic supplementary material, figure S1a,b
4 F. W. Marlowe et al.
‘Spiteful’ origins of human cooperation
20
UG MAO–3PPG MAO
15
10
5
0
–5
–10
–15
–20
–25
five smallest ethnic groups six largest ethnic groups
small versus large societies
Figure 3. UG MAO minus 3PPG MAO by ethnic population
(U ¼ 2, p ¼ 0.017).
Table 1. Pearson correlations between DG, UG and 3PPG
offers.
DG
UG
3PPG
DG
UG
3PPG
—
0.794**
0.681*
0.794**
—
0.577*
0.681*
0.577*
—
* p , 0.05.
** p , 0.005.
n ¼ 12.
and appendix S1.8). DG, UG and 3PPG offers were all
correlated with each other (table 1).
4. DISCUSSION
Societies were either generous in all three games or stingy
in all three. Since P1’s role in all three games is to decide
how much to cooperate with P2 we can say that
smaller societies were less cooperative on the first move
(electronic supplementary material, appendix S1.9).
The small half of our societies (using local group population) tend to be part- or full-time foragers, while the
larger half are either pastoralists, farmers, or wage earners. The societies that should most resemble our more
distant ancestors are warm-climate hunter –gatherers,
and in the ethnographic literature their median ethnic
population is 565 [43]. They tend to live in small,
mobile groups of about 30 individuals, many of whom
are closely related [43 –45]. There is little privacy, little
property and no such thing as anonymity. They are
usually described as egalitarian [44,46]. They are also
described as immediate return societies, who strongly discount the future [47]. Evidence from economics games
reveals that people who discount the future more heavily
are less cooperative than people who do not [48].
Although they were not very generous, people in small
societies were no less likely to engage in 2PP than people
in larger societies, suggesting they expect to get a fair
share even when they do not want to give a fair share.
This is more consistent with demand sharing than reciprocity. Such a demand for equity is what explains the
Proc. R. Soc. B
egalitarianism of hunter – gatherers. A notable downside
to egalitarianism is the inability to solve many collective
action problems [49]. Stratification can emerge in
response to falling per capita benefits resulting from
increasing group size [50]. The levels of political organization familiar to anthropologists (bands, tribes,
chiefdoms, states) correspond to increasing population
and stratification, along with the cooperation and punishment norms that help manage the increasing number of
collective action problems [51].
In contrast to our expectation that ‘altruistic’ 3PP would
be less common than the impulsive, ‘spiteful’ reaction of
2PP across all societies, our results tell a different story.
Not only did larger societies engage in significantly more
3PP than small societies, 3PP was actually significantly
higher than 2PP in large societies. 3PP appears to be the
purest expression of social norm enforcement. We suggest
that signalling one’s generosity and cooperativeness pays
off in large societies.
Some foragers have been described as strong norm
enforcers who go so far as to carry out third-party
executions [52]. It appears, however, that hunter –
gatherers do much less of this than all other kinds of
societies [46,53 –57]. The cases cited nearly always turn
out to be people killing someone who is trying to boss
them around and are, therefore, 2PP rather than 3PP,
even when the killing is carried out by a group [46]. To
see why, consider the example of cueing in line. When
someone breaks in line in front of you and you reprimand
them, this is 2PP even if others in line behind the cheater
subsequently join in the punishment (group 2PP). On the
other hand if you reprimand someone who breaks in
line behind you, this is purely ‘altruistic’ 3PP. Hunter–
gatherers have much more individual autonomy than
people in larger societies—and when they do enforce
norms it is more often 2PP than 3PP.
Those who propose that strong reciprocity (or group
selection) explains the origins of human cooperation
view the costly rejection of low UG offers (2PP) as altruistic. They suggest that 2PP benefits other group members
by discouraging future defections more than it benefits
the punisher herself (altruistic spite) [8]. However,
hunter –gatherer local groups tend to be ephemeral
because group membership is fluid, so any benefits
going to group members from someone punishing a
defector are short-lived as camp membership changes.
The reputation of the ‘spiteful’ punisher, on the other
hand, follows her from group to group. We therefore
view such 2PP as selfish ‘spite’ that is likely to benefit
the punisher who gets a reputation as someone who will
not tolerate defection and is therefore less likely to be
the target of future defections [58 – 60]. We think ethnic
population is more meaningful than local group population in terms of norms (especially among foragers)
because members of a local group frequently change
but one belongs to one’s ethnic group for life.
The conditions for cooperation are more challenging
in larger societies owing to the greater temptation to
defect when there is greater status variation and wealth
disparity, and when anonymity means defectors may go
undetected. It is also more difficult to keep track of interactions with more people [61]. We propose that larger
societies which hit upon 3PP institutions had an advantage solving collective action problems (electronic
‘Spiteful’ origins of human cooperation F. W. Marlowe et al.
supplementary material, appendix S1.10). The resulting
cooperation raised the limits on manageable population
size preventing such societies from fissioning, allowing
them to expand and exterminate or assimilate other
groups.
Unlike humans, chimpanzee show no altruism or spite
in these games—only selfishness [62]. When people play
the UG against a computer, P2’s will accept much
lower offers because the computer has no social norms
and there is no way to influence it to cooperate through
spiteful rejections [63]. The frequent 2PP in all human
societies, small and large, illustrates that what is special
about humans is the willingness to be spiteful to force
cooperation. We include the single quotes around spiteful
because we do think it probably results in a reputation
that pays in the long-run, possibly as part of a
partner-switching strategy of dealing with unfair partners.
In summary, we show that people in very small-scale
societies are less generous and are less willing to engage
in 3PP than people in large societies. However, they are
no less willing to engage in 2PP (see the electronic
supplementary material, appendix S1.11). Despite foragers’ relative inability to solve some collective action
problems, life in small societies is not Hobbesian (see
the electronic supplementary material, appendix S1.12).
2PP (in addition to nepotism and mutualism) is enough
to ensure cooperation where there are fewer demanding
collective action problems. It is mainly ‘spiteful’ 2PP
that is relevant for understanding the origins of human
cooperation.
We thank the National Science Foundation (grant no.
0136761 to Jean Ensminger and Joe Henrich) for
supporting the cross-cultural project. We also thank two
anonymous reviewers for their very helpful comments.
REFERENCES
1 Gintis, H., Henrich, J., Bowles, S., Boyd, R. & Fehr, E.
2008 Strong reciprocity and the roots of human morality.
Social Justice Res. 21, 241 –253. (doi:10.1007/s11211008-0067-y)
2 Hagen, E. H. & Hammerstein, P. 2006 Game theory
and human evolution: a critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games. Theor. Popul. Biol. 69,
339 –348. (doi:10.1016/j.tpb.2005.09.005)
3 Price, M. E. 2008 The resurrection of group selection as
a theory of human cooperation. Social Justice Res. 21,
228 –240. (doi:10.1007/s11211-008-0064-1)
4 Boyd, R., Gintis, H., Bowles, S. & Richerson, P. J. 2003
The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proc. Natl
Acad. Sci. USA 100, 3531–3535. (doi:10.1073/pnas.
0630443100)
5 Fehr, E., Fischbacher, U. & Gachter, S. 2002 Strong
reciprocity, human cooperation and the enforcement of
social norms. Hum. Nat. 13, 1– 25. (doi:10.1007/
s12110-002-1012-7)
6 Fehr, E. & Gachter, S. 2002 Altruistic punishment in
humans. Nature 415, 137– 140. (doi:10.1038/415137a)
7 Gintis, H. 2000 Strong reciprocity and human sociality.
J. Theor. Biol. 206, 169–179. (doi:10.1006/jtbi.2000.2111)
8 Gintis, H., Bowles, S., Boyd, R. & Fehr, E. 2003 Explaining altruistic behavior in humans. Evol. Hum. Behav. 24,
153–172. (doi:10.1016/S1090-5138(02)00157-5)
9 Marlowe, F. W. et al. 2008 More altruistic punishment in
larger societies. Proc. R. Soc. B 275, 587– 590. (doi:10.
1098/rspb.2007.1517)
Proc. R. Soc. B
5
10 Bahuchet, S. 1990 Food sharing among the Pygmies of
Central Africa. Afr. Study Monogr. 11, 27–53.
11 Gurven, M. 2004 To give and to give not: the behavioral
ecology of human food transfers. Behav. Brain Sci. 27,
543 –583.
12 Kaplan, H. & Hill, K. 1985 Food sharing among Ache
foragers: tests of explanatory hypotheses. Curr. Anthropol.
26, 223–246. (doi:10.1086/203251)
13 Kitanishi, K. 1998 Food sharing among the Aka hunter–
gatherers in northeastern Congo. Afr. Stud. Monogr. 25,
3 –32.
14 Winterhalder, B. 1986 Diet choice, risk, and food
sharing in a stochastic environment. J. Anthropol.
Archaeol. 5, 369–392. (doi:10.1016/0278-4165(86)
90017-6)
15 Trivers, R. L. 1971 The evolution of reciprocal altruism.
Q. Rev. Biol. 46, 35–57.
16 Hamilton, W. D. 1964 The genetical evolution of social
behavior. J. Theor. Biol. 7, 1–16. (doi:10.1016/00225193(64)90038-4)
17 Marlowe, F. W. 2007 Hunting and gathering: the
human sexual division of foraging labor. Cross Cult. Res.
41, 170–195. (doi:10.1177/1069397106297529)
18 Blurton Jones, N. G. 1987 Tolerated theft: suggestions
about the ecology and evolution of sharing, hoarding,
and scrounging. Soc. Sci. Info. 26, 31–54. (doi:10.1177/
053901887026001002)
19 Peterson, N. 1993 Demand sharing: reciprocity and the
pressure for generosity among foragers. Am. Anthropol.
95, 860–874. (doi:10.1525/aa.1993.95.4.02a00050)
20 Winterhalder, B. 1996 Marginal model of tolerated theft.
Ethol. Sociobiol. 17, 37–53. (doi:10.1016/01623095(95)00126-3)
21 Woodburn, J. 1998 Sharing is not a form of exchange: an
analysis of property-sharing in immediate-return hunter–
gatherer societies. In Property relations: renewing the
anthropological tradition (ed. C. M. Hann), pp. 48–63.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
22 Henrich, J. et al. 2006 Costly punishment across human
societies. Science 312, 1767–1770. (doi:10.1126/science.
1127333)
23 Forsythe, R., Horowitz, J. L., Savin, N. E. & Sefton, M.
1994 Fairness in simple bargaining experiments. Games
Econ. Behav. 6, 347–369. (doi:10.1006/game.1994.
1021)
24 Zak, P. J., Stanton, A. A. & Ahmadi, S. 2007 Oxytocin
increases generosity in humans. PLoS ONE 2, 5.
25 Guth, W., Schmittberger, R. & Schwarze, B. 1982
An experimental-analysis of ultimatum bargaining.
J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 3, 367 –388. (doi:10.1016/01672681(82)90011-7)
26 Sylwester, K. & Roberts, G. 2010 Cooperators benefit
through reputation-based partner choice in economic
games. Biol. Lett. 6, 659 –662. (doi:10.1098/rsbl.2010.
0209)
27 Fehr, E. & Fischbacher, U. 2004 Third-party punishment and social norms. Evol. Hum. Behav. 25, 63–87.
(doi:10.1016/S1090-5138(04)00005-4)
28 Abbink, K., Bolton, G. E., Sadrieh, A. & Tang, F. F.
2001 Adaptive learning versus punishment in ultimatum
bargaining. Games Econ. Behav. 37, 1 –25. (doi:10.1006/
game.2000.0837)
29 Pillutla, M. M. & Murnighan, J. K. 1996 Unfairness,
anger, and spite: emotional rejections of ultimatum
offers. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Processes 68, 208 –
224. (doi:10.1006/obhd.1996.0100)
30 Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. K., Aronson, J. A., Nystrom,
L. E. & Cohen, J. D. 2003 The neural basis of economic
decision-making in the ultimatum game. Science 300,
1755– 1758. (doi:10.1126/science.1082976)
6 F. W. Marlowe et al.
‘Spiteful’ origins of human cooperation
31 Foster, K. R., Wenseleers, T. & Ratnieks, F. L. W. 2001
Spite: Hamilton’s unproven theory, pp. 229 –238.
Helsinki, Finland: Finnish Zoological Botanical
Publishing Board.
32 Gardner, A. & West, S. A. 2004 Spite and the scale of
competition. J. Evol. Biol. 17, 1195– 1203. (doi:10.
1111/j.1420-9101.2004.00775.x)
33 Hamilton, W. D. 1970 Selfish and spiteful behaviour in
an evolutionary model. Nature 228, 1218–1220.
(doi:10.1038/2281218a0)
34 Hamilton, W. D. 1971 Selection of selfish and altruistic
behaviour in some extreme models. In Man and beast:
comparative social behavior (eds J. F. Eisenberg & W. S.
Dillon), pp. 51–91. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Press.
35 Lehmann, L., Bargum, K. & Reuter, M. 2006 An evolutionary analysis of the relationship between spite and
altruism. J. Evol. Biol. 19, 1507–1516. (doi:10.1111/j.
1420-9101.2006.01128.x)
36 Trivers, R. L. 1985 Social evolution. Menlo Park, CA:
Benjamin Cummings Publishing Co, Inc.
37 Wilson, E. O. 1975 Sociobiology: the new synthesis.
Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press.
38 Johnstone, R. A. & Bshary, R. 2004 Evolution of spite
through indirect reciprocity. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 271,
1917–1922. (doi:10.1098/rspb.2003.2581)
39 Selten, R. 1967 Die Strategiemethode zur Erforschung
des eingeschränkt rationalen Verhaltens im Rahmen
eines Oligopolexperiments. In Beiträge zur experimentellen
Wirtschaftsforschung (ed. H. Sauermann), pp. 136 –168.
Tübingen: Mohr.
40 Barr, A. et al. 2009 Homo aequalis: a cross-society experimental analysis of three bargaining games. Discussion
Paper Series, 422. Department of Economics, University
of Oxford, Oxford, UK.
41 Grimes, B. F. 2000 Ethnologue: languages of the world.
Dallas, TX: SIL International.
42 Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Gintis, H., Camerer,
C. & Fehr, E. (eds) 2004 Foundations of human sociality:
economic experiments and ethnographic evidence from fifteen
small-scale societies. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
43 Marlowe, F. W. 2005 Hunter– gatherers and human
evolution. Evol. Anthropol. 14, 54–67. (doi:10.1002/
evan.20046)
44 Kelly, R. L. 1995 The foraging spectrum. Washington, DC:
Smithsonian Institution Press.
45 Lee, R. B. & DeVore, I. 1968 Man the hunter. Chicago,
IL: Aldine.
46 Woodburn, J. 1982 Egalitarian societies. Man 17,
431 –451. (doi:10.2307/2801707)
47 Woodburn, J. 1980 Hunters and gatherers today and
reconstruction of the past. In Soviet and western
Proc. R. Soc. B
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
anthropology (ed. E. Gellner), pp. 95–117. London,
UK: Duckworth.
Curry, O. S., Price, M. E. & Price, J. G. 2008 Patience is
a virtue: cooperative people have lower discount rates.
Pers. Individual Differ. 44, 780–785. (doi:10.1016/j.
paid.2007.09.023)
Marlowe, F. W. 2009 Hadza cooperation: second-party
punishment yes, third-party punishment no. Hum. Nat.
20, 417 –430. (doi:10.1007/s12110-009-9072-6)
Boone, J. L. 1992 Competition, conflict, and the development of social hierarchies. In Evolutionary ecology and
human behavior (eds E. A. Smith & B. Winterhalder),
pp. 301 –337. New York, NY: Aldine de Gruyter.
Johnson, A. W. & Earle, T. 1987 The evolution of human
societies. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.
Boehm, C. 1993 Egalitarian behavior and reverse
dominance hierarchy. Curr. Anthropol. 34, 227 –254.
(doi:10.1086/204166)
Black, D. 2000 On the origin of morality. J. Conscious.
Stud. 7, 107– 119.
Daly, M. & Wilson, M. 1988 Homicide. New York, NY:
Aldine de Gruyter.
Kelly, R. C. 2000 Warless societies and the origin of war.
Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Wiessner, P. 2005 Norm enforcement among the Ju/
’hoansi bushmen: a case of strong reciprocity? Hum.
Nat. 16, 115 –145. (doi:10.1007/s12110-005-1000-9)
Woodburn, J. 1979 Minimal politics: the political organization of the Hadza of north Tanzania. In Politics in
leadership (eds W. A. Shack & P. S. Cohen), pp. 244 –
266. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Fehr, E. & Schneider, F. 2010 Eyes are on us, but nobody
cares: are eye cues relevant for strong reciprocity?
Proc. R. Soc. B 277, 1315 –1323. (doi:10.1098/rspb.
2009.1900)
Barclay, P. 2006 Reputational benefits for altruistic
punishment. Evol. Hum. Behav. 27, 325 –344. (doi:10.
1016/j.evolhumbehav.2006.01.003)
Rockenbach, B. & Milinski, M. 2006 The efficient
interaction of indirect reciprocity and costly punishment.
Nature 444, 718 –723. (doi:10.1038/nature05229)
Boyd, R. & Richerson, P. J. 1988 The evolution of reciprocity in sizeable groups. J. Theor. Biol. 132, 337 –356.
(doi:10.1016/S0022-5193(88)80219-4)
Jensen, K., Hare, B., Call, J. & Tomasello, M. 2006
What’s in it for me? Self-regard precludes altruism and
spite in chimpanzees. Proc. R. Soc. B 273, 1013–1021.
(doi:10.1098/rspb.2005.3417)
Blount, S. 1995 When social outcomes aren’t fair: the
effect of causal attributions on preferences. Organ.
Behav. Hum. Decis. Processes 63, 131–144. (doi:10.
1006/obhd.1995.1068)