REVIEW STUDY
FILOZOFIA
Volume 79, Number 10, 2024
DOI: https://doi.org/10.31577/filozofia.2024.79.10.9
Between Dewey, Social Movements and Critical Philosophy
ŠTĚPÁN RAŠKA, Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Faculty of Arts,
Charles University, Prague, Czech Republic
RAŠKA, Š.: Between Dewey, Social Movements and Critical Philosophy
FILOZOFIA, 79, 2024, No 10, pp. 1186 – 1196
This review study deals with the 2021 book by the Spanish philosopher
Justo Serrano Zamora Democratization and Struggles against Injustice: A
Pragmatist Approach to the Epistemic Practices of Social Movements. The aim
is primarily to show how Zamora deals with Dewey’s thought in the
context of social critical philosophy. At the same time, it highlights the
value of Zamora’s approach both in the context of contemporary debates
on democracy and in the context of reflections on the intrinsic connection
between social movements and democratization. The reviewer
simultaneously situates the book in the context of contemporary
pragmatic philosophy and points out, among other things, the
phenomenon of the gradual convergence of pragmatism with contemporary critical theory of society.
Keywords: Dewey – social movements – democracy – critical theory –
contemporary pragmatism
Introduction
Nowadays there are several reasons to pay attention to the philosophical
relevance of issues of democratic legitimacy and participation. In recent years,
various theoretical frameworks have already been conceived or revised to
interpret political events following the economic, migrant, and pandemic crises
of 2008, 2015, and 2020 respectively. Reflections concerning so-called populist
movements, widely shared resistance to immigration, or the expertocracy have
entered the public discourse.
In this context, there is much talk of a “crisis” or even an “end” of democracy
(see, e.g., Ercan – Gagnon 2014). These reflections are often based on some specific
understanding of democracy, which in many cases does not hide its liberal or
pseudo-liberal roots. This “end” is often a proxy term for the uncertainty that
arises from a weakening of various forms of liberalism (see e.g., Moyn 2023).
1186
It can sometimes seem that pragmatism, despite democracy being one of its
privileged concerns, remains somewhat reticent not only in relation to these
debates and through them to public policies but also to more general questions
about the epistemic dimension of democracy. Pragmatism is – in the public and
partly in the philosophical discourse as well – often reduced to its semantic level,
or to its ability and flexibility to converge with the authors of the analytic tradition.
However, there has been in pragmatic philosophy during recent years and
decades – which is related, among others, to Richard Rorty’s thought – a
renewed discussion of some of the neglected issues of the movement.
Richard Bernstein, in his now classic 2010 book Pragmatic Turn (Bernstein
2010), talks however about a different, more fundamental change taking place
in the context of pragmatism. Quoting from Rorty, he responds to the now
hard-to-defend notion of the provinciality of authors like Peirce and Dewey.
Currently there is no doubt, in Rorty’s words, that the first generation of
pragmatic authors undoubtedly deserve their place not only in “global
philosophical discourse” but also “in the story of Western intellectual progress”
(Bernstein 2010, VI).
Bernstein’s assertion of this pragmatic revival can be briefly developed for
the purposes of this review. For the historical-philosophical irony1 of this
gradual emergence from provincialism is that pragmatic authors have also been
discovered or appreciated by critically-oriented philosophers, especially Germans:
Robin Celikates, Axel Honneth, and Rahel Jaeggi (see, e.g., Frega 2014).
It could be possible to create a kind of “bridge.” This, of course, means to
develop Bernstein’s claim. At least since Dewey, pragmatism has been linked
to considerations of the epistemic dimension of political processes, especially
democratic ones. As is well known, Dewey creates a conceptual and
methodological framework through which the democratic politics can be
grasped form non-liberal positions. This makes it possible to think with Dewey
not only about the classical questions of normative democratic theory, but also
about issues that go beyond the epistemic dimension and approach the
general goals of critical philosophy: demystifying ideological schemes,
creating pressure for social change, and liberating the individual. Surely not
by accident is it that authors like Honneth and Jaeggi build on this largely
undeveloped aspect of Dewey’s work.
1 I am alluding especially to the misunderstanding or aversion that some authors of the first
generation of the Frankfurt School manifest (see, very illustratively, Särkelä 2021). However,
Särkelä shows that this misunderstanding is not wholesale, and it is wrong to understand it
only in this way (Särkelä 2021, 149).
FILOZOFIA
79, 10
1187
And it is in this, let me say it once again, “pragmatic revival” that the new
book by the Spanish philosopher Justo Serrano Zamora Democratization and
Struggles against Injustice: A Pragmatist Approach to the Epistemic Practices of
Social Movements could be included.
I. General Classification
I think that the book’s primary goal is to connect and rethink the aforementioned
thematic fields. Yet or perhaps because of this I believe that it should be understood
primarily as part of a contemporary pragmatist philosophical tradition.
In general, the book responds to Dewey’s conception of democracy and
attempts to develop it in a thematic area that belongs standardly to critical
philosophy. In the author’s words, it is primarily concerned with: “the political
potential of the epistemic dimension of democracy” (Zamora 2021, 14). More
specifically, it is about assessing the importance that social movements have for
democratic politics, either in terms of its proper realisation or even its deepening.
It is against the background of Dewey’s reflections on democracy, or his theory
of experimentalism, that this potential is to be illuminated. In this sense,
Zamora’s approach is pragmatical. Systematically and historically.
As for the social-critical aspect of the book, it is at this point that Zamora
simultaneously offers his own reinterpretation of Dewey’s concept. It is
precisely the absence of the importance of social movements for
democratization that Zamora identifies as a task to “fill an existing gap in
Dewey’s work” (Zamora 2021, 77).
Thus, it is primarily in the linking of the general issue of political
participation with the resolution of specific social problems that Zamora’s
contribution can be seen.
To both elaborate and support this main thesis of the book, Zamora
proceeds in three basic steps or sections. These are also divided into individual
chapters. The first two sections have three chapters, the last section two. Each
section, and at the same time each chapter, then offers a short recapitulation at
the end, which facilitates orientation in an otherwise very complex and
systematically developed argument.
Before moving on to Zamora’s argument, however, the book can also be
generally classified in other ways. For example, as a distinctive contribution to
contemporary democratic theory or political epistemology, as an original
historical study of Dewey’s experimentalism, or as an attempt to interpret the
nature and meaning of social movements or conflicts in general.
1188
II. First Part: Epistemic and Value Dynamics of Democracy
In the first part, Zamora outlines contemporary discussions of democratic
theory. In doing so, he uses a typology of democratic practices and institutions
inspired by Bernhard Peters. This typology is based on both the fact that these
can embody certain values and that through them we identify, define, and
solve certain problems. Subsequently, Zamora divides some contemporary
theorists of democracy into compatibilists and incompatibilists according to
whether for these “intrinsic-value” and “epistemic-value” dimensions are
compatible or not.2
However, Zamora himself seems to be moving towards a claim of a
“hermeneutic interaction” (Zamora 2021, 3 – 4) of the value and epistemic
aspects. In other words, to the value based “improvement of democracy through
the epistemic” (Zamora 2021, 11) that means that the identification of a social
problem enables, deepens, or even transforms the understanding of certain
values. Again, I claim, that this statement is just another description for the
book’s main thesis above: social movements have democratizing potential.
In the first section, however, this division is so far only a specific
methodological tool that allows a better grasp of specifically Honneth’s and
especially Dewey’s theory of democracy.
While, according to Zamora, both are compatibilists, only Dewey’s
reflection on democracy holds the potential to properly evaluate its epistemic
dimension. We see the meaning of Zamora’s interaction requirement in his
critique of Honneth. Honneth is indeed a compatibilist in the sense that the
“struggle for recognition” goes hand in hand with the epistemic dimension. It
means with learning processes as solutions to certain problems. But Honneth
does not consider the “transformative power of problem solving” (Zamora
2021, 39) specifically in relation to the value side of democracy. Thus, Zamora
criticizes Honneth precisely by pointing to the fact that he did not think out the
“epistemic” and “intrinsic” values of democracy. While these, according to
Zamora, interact with each other in Honneth’s work, the “epistemic” dimension
is underestimated (Zamora 2021, 39).
According to Zamora, this is certainly not true of Dewey. He interprets
Dewey in the standard way, especially through his thematization of demo-cracy
2 An example of mutual incompatibility can be the notion of a kind of “moderate
expertocracy,” the preference to limit inclusion to some extent to achieve the solution of certain
social problems. The opposite is the idea that solutions to these problems are legitimate only
if they are preceded by a deliberative decision-making procedure: as inclusive as possible (cf.
Zamora 2021, 3 – 12).
FILOZOFIA
79, 10
1189
in The Public and Its Problems. Zamora does not neglect the normative side of
Dewey’s reflections. That is, his conception of democratic practices as the
realization of the ideals of autonomy and self-realization. As already mentioned,
Dewey is interpreted by Zamora as an author who understands the political
potential of the epistemic. Together with Dewey, Zamora understands the
instrumentalization of participation as desirable not only in terms of means-ends
logic, but also normatively. The ideal of self-realization is supposed to be an
immanent part of the epistemic dynamics of problem solving. The point of
Dewey’s, and now Zamora’s, argument also lies in the fact that the
aforementioned ideals, including the notion of freedom behind it, stands outside
the individualistic framework, which is unacceptable for both of them.
III. Second Part: Social Movements and Democratization
In the second part, the social movements come into play. These are now a kind
of link between the epistemic dimension of democracy on the one hand and
the value-progressive dimension of participation on the other. With the notion
of social movement, Zamora gives more concrete contours to the general
statements concluded in the first part of the book.
That social movements contribute to democratisation is not a surprising
claim. Thus, Zamora first leans towards some of the conclusions of theorists
such as Young, Anderson, and Bohman, so as to use them for his own
argument (Zamora 2021, 83 – 109). This passage, too, is an erudite and lucid,
yet critical part of the book’s systematics. While Zamora agrees with Bohman
in the sense that social movements “disclose the world,” he does not limit
himself to making such a statement. This is because social movements,
according to Zamora, articulate, especially, injustice. This of course includes
Bohman’s disclosure and in this sense Zamora’s notion is broader.
This brings us to the key question that Zamora needs to clarify: What
exactly does the epistemic mean in the social movement and how does it relate
to the improvement of democracy (Zamora 2021, 106)? At the same time, we
are back at Dewey and Zamora’s own contributions and, all at once, at the core
of the book.
In fact, one can say that social movements in Zamora’s conception
represent this epistemic. He understands them firstly as problem solvers.
Within them, there is a normative assessment of the situation, the generation
of knowledge, the formulation of goals and the construction of identities. They
are thus not static “content providers” but dynamic structures that can be
understood as “inquirers” (Zamora 2021, 111 – 115).
1190
It is only from this that one can understand why Dewey’s experimentalism is the conceptual framework underpinning Zamora’s notion of
social movement. For experimentalism can be understood as a specific activity
of intelligence in a wider sense. The ability to solve certain problems through
a type of inquiry. Its notion of rationality is fallibilist, inclusivist, assumes a
certain fluidity between a given fact and the anticipation of a solution, and
emphasizes cooperativeness or the inter-subjective dimension in general (see,
e.g., Bogusz 2022). Therefore, Zamora can claim that it provides the cognitive
conditions (p. 130) for the growth of oppositional consciousness while
contributing to deepening the understanding of democracy by its actors.
It is in these key passages of the book that the development of Dewey
through the prism of critical philosophy suggested above is best revealed.
Significant is Zamora’s comparison of experimentalism with Adorno’s critique
of reified thinking (Zamora 2021, 136 – 139). Here we see the sense in which
experimentalism is an appropriate epistemic prop for a social movement.
Experimental thinking is open and non-dogmatic, there is a constant
incorporation and valuation of the experiences of those involved, alternatives
are projected alongside the proposed solution. However, reified thinking faces
ideological distortions of reality and Zamora wants to attribute something like
that to experimentalism as well. He interprets experimentalism as a critical
epistemology that can stimulate social change.3
IV. Third Part: Underpinning Democracy
The first chapter of the third part can be seen as just an elaboration of the above.
Thus, in the eighth chapter of the book, the question of the hermeneutical
dimension of social movements is opened up (Zamora 2021, esp. 167 – 170). It
is very desirable to combine the hermeneutic, pragmatic, and critical
dimensions of contemporary debates on democracy and to look for their
intersection (see Dunaj – Mertel 2022). And it is, in a way, original to propose
an experimentalist culture of inquiry as a solution to the hermeneutical
situation of “epistemic disadvantage” (Zamora 2021, 174) that Zamora argues
some social groups face. While references to the intersection between critical
philosophy and pragmatism may no longer sound entirely novel, the explicit
connection between critical hermeneutics and Dewey’s experimentalism
3 This does not mean, however, that it is only subversive. Zamora insists on the productivity
of experimentalism in the sense of creating content that articulates the interests of the
disadvantaged.
FILOZOFIA
79, 10
1191
is unusual.4 Yet this connection is by no means trivial. Zamora understands
experimentalism as a tool through which actors articulate their social world
and thereby “already” perform a distance in relation to it. Thus, we see vividly
how pragmatic elements converge with the hermeneutic-critical dimension.
Subsequently, Zamora adds a kind of ending consisting in situating the
whole argument on a more fundamental ground. He simultaneously develops
the hermeneutic dimension outlined above. Zamora also concludes the
interpretation of Dewey through his later texts, especially the notes published as
Lectures in Social and Political Philosophy, but he also returns to the theory of
experience already put forward in Art as Experience. By “an expressivist
interpretation of Dewey’s conception of social conflict” (Zamora 2021, 175 – 190),
Zamora means the mediation between the different phases of awareness of selfinterest and its articulation. Zamora wants to use Dewey to explain how it is
possible to move from the initial naturalization of a given social status quo to the
final stage of social struggle. That is, to the recognition of the interests of the
governed by the governors and, at the same time, to the sublimation of their
interests into a consciousness of social responsibility and not, for example, into
an individualistically conceived revolt against institutions.
Thus, as in the previous chapters, Zamora seeks an epistemic underpinning of the possibility of social change, but this time he abandons the
explicit thematization of social movements and is more general in outlook.
V. Deliberative Approaches Revisited
From a purely formal or methodological point of view, Zamora can hardly be
criticized. The book is very clear and represents a masterpiece of academic
work. Zamora carefully prepares the ground for the formulation of his own
theses, situates his reflections in the context of contemporary debates, and
works critically with authors who research in the same field. Nevertheless, the
number of references and various excursions is sometimes too tedious for the
reader, although the internal structure of the text and the partial concluding
summaries fortunately minimize this problem.
The attempt to bring the reader closer to the epistemic dimension of the
argument through the – again very systematic – choice of appropriate
examples is also very positive. I understand these examples in a specific way.
Zamora presumably wants to show that the experimentalist culture of inquiry
is something real though not properly realized in a democratic society, which
4
See, as one of the few, Busacchi, V. et al. (2022).
1192
in a sense we look back on through abstraction and support or improve and
thus improve democracy through theoretical reflection. The very first example
of the whole book, the PAH platform (Zamora 2021, IX – XI), nicely illustrates
that it is the social movements whose potential for democratization Zamora
wants to exploit. The example – like many others – facilitates the linking of the
epistemic and concrete levels, where we see vividly how social movements
“identify, define and solve social problems” (Zamora 2021, XVII) growing
precisely out of, for example, the economic crisis.
The fact that Zamora is working specifically with John Dewey’s political
and social philosophy allows him to situate his conclusions in a critical
relationship with both the liberal tradition as far as value issues of democracy
are concerned and various forms of republicanism, which often actually
underestimate the epistemic dimension of political processes. Moreover, Zamora
also considers Dewey’s original notes, which were published only recently in
European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy (see Dewey, 2015). In
this sense, Zamora is one of those who valorise Dewey’s still unexhausted
legacy for contemporary social-political thought.
This is also evident in what I consider the most valuable feature of the
study in general. Zamora works very systematically and at the same time critically
with deliberative theories, which today represent a strong alter-native precisely
to liberal, republican, or proceduralist approaches (see Bohman – Regh 1997) At
the same time, the use of experimentalism, as Zamora himself points out
(Zamora 2021, 160), makes it possible to understand the overemphasis on
deliberation as a kind of reductionism. Zamora’s Deweyan approach shares
with deliberative approaches an emphasis on the inclusivity of political
participation as a problem or commitment. However, he extends the possible
field of this inclusivity beyond the discursive framework in order to
subsequently delimit this field with the notion of social movements, because
the experimentalist culture operates, as it were, within social movements. Thus,
participation must be understood as a complex set of certain practices and not as
a discursive-procedural rationality. This is one of the most interesting and
relevant conclusions of the whole study.
It is interesting to note that although Zamora is theoretically and
methodologically critical, he shares with deliberative approaches precisely
what I think is valuable about them. Namely, the understanding of political
legitimacy within an overall inter-subjective framework, which in turn points
FILOZOFIA
79, 10
1193
to the pragmatic nature of Zamora’s study.5 The proper articulation of the
interest of the oppressed is ultimately a form of commitment into which their
former ignorance or revolt is transformed. Thus, real legitimacy is formed both
outside the given and outside the revolt (Zamora 2021, 174) only when we
really acknowledge the point of view of others and understand it in a certain
sense as epistemically primary.
On the other hand, Zamora’s theory also remains in some sense
intellectualist, even though it is more remote from such an objection than
precisely deliberative approaches. Admittedly, for Zamora it is no longer just
about presenting and justifying reasons as the basis of democratic legitimacy.
Yet his approach is primarily based on a theory of inquiry. Precisely because the
book approaches democracy from an epistemic perspective, an explicit
comparison of the deliberative and experimentalist rationality would be fitting.
I do not think it is entirely clear why someone could not be excluded from
participating in an experimentalist culture of social movements, just as
someone is at a significant disadvantage, for example, due to their cognitive
abilities, when it comes to deliberative discursive frameworks which Zamora
himself mentions. Thus, one can certainly agree with Zamora that experimentalism is a more inclusive theory in this regard, especially in connection
with the social movement. However, it does not follow that its inclusiveness is
sufficient or even complete.
I think that the deliberative frameworks, with their emphasis on the
procedure of justification, thematizes more thoroughly the epistemic criteria
that provide legitimacy to any social change even if partial. The question of the
complete inclusion is thus not posed with such urgency. Since in the case of
Habermas’s approach, for example, the regulative function of the ideal
communicative situation plays a significant role (see Habermas 1992, 2022).
It would therefore be useful to thematise in more detail the ability of
a social movement to reach out to, or to include, as many actors with a common
interest as possible. And at the same time to show in what sense their interest is
articulated in relation to the whole of society or, let me say, to the interest of
society as a whole. The goals and interests of particular social movements can
be quite diverse and the obligations as which, according to Zamora, they can if
successful articulate themselves can be mutually contradictory. While the
inclusiveness of social movements is perhaps at least partially thematized in
5 See Peirce’s consensus theory of truth, upon which some deliberative approaches build (see
Misak 2000).
1194
the most illustrative way in the examples chosen,6 the issue of the plurality of
social movements and their potentially divergent interests remains on the side
lines, which on the other hand is understandable for methodological reasons.
Zamora is primarily interested in the general contribution of social movements
to democracy.
VI. Conclusion
Let me conclude by saying that Zamora, inspired by critical philosophy, fills
one of the gaps in Dewey’s work, as he himself set out to do. Similarly, as I
argue on the basis of the above, he offers an original and critical insight into
contemporary discussions on democracy and, in an interesting way, confronts
mainly deliberative approaches.
I think that Zamora’s affiliation with pragmatic thinking is most evident
precisely through the fact that he approaches the whole issue from an epistemic
point of view. As a result, he builds a critical and hermeneutical dimension into
his reflections. Altogether, it creates an integral whole that convincingly deals
with the phenomenon of social movements and demonstrates why it could be
possible to think about them as a buttress of democracy.
Let me end again somewhat generally. As I stated in the introduction,
pragmatism cannot be considered a marginal and provincial philosophical
tradition today. On the contrary, its heritage is alive well precisely because it
allows us to grasp the most fundamental questions that lie at the origin of
philosophical thought in general. The question of justice is one of them. Thus,
in addition to all that has already been said, Zamora also encourages us to
consider whether the form of democracy we are living in at the moment is
sufficiently fair.
Bibliography
BERNSTEIN, R. (2010): The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge: Polity Press.
BOGUSZ, T. (2022): Experimentalism and Sociology: From Crisis to Experience. Heidelberg:
Springer International Publishing.
BOHMAN, J. – REGH, W. (eds.) (1997): Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
BOHMAN, J. (1998): Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity and Democracy. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: MIT Press.
6 In the sense that social movements include the organization of meetings, discussions,
workshops, etc., which clearly can have inclusive potential.
FILOZOFIA
79, 10
1195
BUSACCHI, V. – NIEDDU, A. – MICHEL, J. (eds.) (2022): Experience, Interpretation and
Meaning: A Dialogue between Hermeneutics and Pragmatism. European Journal of
Pragmatism and American Philosophy, 14 (1), 1 – 6. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.2688
DEWEY, J. (2015): Lectures in Social and Political Philosophy. European Journal of Pragmatism
and American Philosophy, 7 (2), 7 – 44. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.398
DEWEY, J. (2016): The Public and its Problems: An Essay in Political Inquiry. Athens, Ohio:
Swallow Press.
DUNAJ, L. – MERTEL, K. (eds.) (2022): Hans-Herbert Kögler’s Critical Hermeneutics. London:
Bloomsbury.
FREGA, R. (2014). Between Pragmatism and Critical Theory: Social Philosophy Today. Human
Studies, 37 (1), 57 – 82. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9290-0
HABERMAS, J. (1992): Faktizität und Geltung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
HABERMAS, J. (2022): Ein neuer Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit und die deliberative Politik.
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
MISAK, CH. (2000): Truth, Politics, Morality: Pragmatism and Deliberation. London: Routledge.
MOYN, S. (2023): Liberalism against Itself. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press.
SÄRKELÄ, A. (2021): American Pragmatism and Frankfurter School Critical Theory: A Family
Drama. In: Festl, M. (eds.): Pragmatism and Social Philosophy: Exploring a Stream of Ideas from
America to Europe. New York: Routledge, 145 – 162.
ZAMORA, J. (2021): Democratization and Struggles against Injustice: A Pragmatist Approach to the
Epistemic Practices of Social Movements. London and New York: Rowman & Littlefield.
This work was supported by the European Regional Development Fund project “Beyond Security: Role of Conflict in Resilience-Building” (reg. no.: CZ.02.01.01/00/22_008/0004595).
Štěpán Raška
Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies
Faculty of Arts, Charles University
nám. Jana Palacha 2
116 38 Prague 1
Czech Republic
e-mail:
[email protected]
ORCID ID: https://orcid.org/0009-0008-0083-7392
1196