Edinburgh Research Explorer
Punishment and democratic theory
Citation for published version:
Dzur, A, Loader, I & Sparks, R 2016, Punishment and democratic theory: Resources for a better penal
politics. in A Dzur, I Loader & R Sparks (eds), Democratic Theory and Mass Incarceration. Oxford University
Press, Oxford, pp. 1-17. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190243098.001.0001
Digital Object Identifier (DOI):
10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190243098.001.0001
Link:
Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer
Document Version:
Peer reviewed version
Published In:
Democratic Theory and Mass Incarceration
Publisher Rights Statement:
"This material was originally published in ' Democratic Theory and Mass Incarceration' edited by Albert Dzur, Ian
Loader, and Richard Sparks, and has been reproduced by permission of Oxford University Press
http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190243098.001.0001/acprof-9780190243098.
For permission to reuse this material, please visit http://global.oup.com/academic/rights."
General rights
Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s)
and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and
abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights.
Take down policy
The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer
content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please
contact
[email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and
investigate your claim.
Download date: 05. Dec. 2021
1
Punishment and Democratic Theory
Resources for a Better Penal Politics
Albert Dzur, Ian Loader, and Richard Sparks
Introduction
On July 16, 2015, President Barack Obama toured El Reno Federal Correctional
Institution near Oklahoma City and had a forty-five-minute roundtable discussion with
six nonviolent drug offenders, a conversation recorded by HBO for a documentary on
criminal justice. Mass incarceration, the president said during his visit, has become an
unquestioned part of American life: “We have a tendency sometimes to almost take it for
granted or think it’s normal. It’s not normal. It’s not what happens in other countries.
What is normal is teenagers doing stupid things. What is normal is young people making
mistakes.”1 The president’s El Reno trip was intended to build support for a significant
shift in federal policy: reduction or elimination of mandatory minimum sentences,
alternative sanctions for nonviolent offenders, restoration of voting rights to former
prisoners, and “ban the box” rules to discourage employers from asking job candidates
about their criminal records. The president’s visit and his proposed reforms illustrate a
departure from a dominant leadership paradigm in the United States, aptly characterized
by Jonathan Simon as “governing through crime.”2 For over a generation few political
costs were paid and many benefits reaped by elected officials for increasing sentences,
ignoring racial disparities, and indeed considering mass incarceration to be “normal.”
President Obama’s attempt to bring criminal justice into public view, to begin a dialogue
on how to punish better and more fairly, is in itself a significant change in the political
culture.3
The president’s prison visit is a further sign that over recent years, in the wake of
the crime drop and falling levels of public concern with and attention to crime, the
seemingly inexorable upsurge in US imprisonment is slowing down, or being sent into
reverse.4 The recent publication and discussion of high-profile reports on the problems of
mass incarceration and police racism and brutality are also indicators that the terms of
debate about crime and justice may be shifting.5 It is no doubt too early to tell to what
extent, or how durably, the penal climate is altering and to know whether recent reversals
signify a material change (in that climate), or simply a reversible fluctuation (in the penal
weather). It would certainly be naïve to rely on simple optimism that things are taking a
turn for the better, to assume that state austerity will alone be sufficient to produce
significant penal change, or to underestimate the reach and embeddedness of the
American carceral state.6 In this regard, we should recall something else that makes the
El Reno trip remarkable: Obama was the first sitting president to visit a federal prison,
the first leader of America’s democracy to visit the unfree world that has been
constructed in that democracy’s midst. What had been keeping these powerful men away
for so long from the disempowered and disenfranchised? What was so repellent about the
institutions over which the president has ultimate oversight? Why did it take the
intolerable financial burden of massive public spending on incarceration at a time of deep
economic recession to push criminal justice, slowly and hesitantly at first, on to state and
federal executives’ agendas?
These are important caveats: reminders of the invisibility of the prison within the
life of modern democracies. It may nonetheless be the case that room is opening up for
new forms of constructive thinking and strategic intervention in the penal field wherein
we can bring to bear new intellectual resources in addressing questions of punishment.7
But what concepts and arguments are available to us at this moment of possibility, after
more than a generation of “normal” mass incarceration, to speak to its abnormality and to
fix what is broken about a dysfunctional system that implicates all of us who have grown
accustomed to it and in whose name it was assembled? What social and institutional
resources exist for creating different futures for the penal arrangements of modern
capitalist democracies? How—if at all—can criminology and related forms of knowledge
make such futures more likely to be achieved? What are the best outcomes for which we
can reasonably hope in penal politics?
In this introductory chapter we want to outline and develop the core idea that
animates this volume: namely, that one underexploited resource for a better penal politics
lies in investigating the ideals and institutions of democracy and thinking about how
these ideals can be theorized and given practical effect in reshaping the criminal justice
and penal arrangements of advanced capitalist democracies today.
The Long Shadow of Mass Incarceration
Over the last thirty years mass incarceration (especially in the United States) came to
seem inexorable and unremitting. This was so not just in terms of chronically high levels
of imprisonment. It was also registered in terms of massive racial disproportion and the
demotic symbolic politics that made “the prison” appear a necessary, obvious,
commonsense solution to problems of crime and violence. But the more immovable mass
imprisonment came to seem, the more it imposed a block on our capacity to imagine
alternatives to it. The major and urgent task became that of tracing the contours of this
phenomenon and grasping its social, institutional, economic, and cultural impact.
The long shadow cast by mass incarceration over penal scholarship has generated
much original work on this phenomenon and its wider consequences. We consequently
now know a great deal about the structural causes of this phenomenon and about the
political dynamics that have fueled and shaped it.8 Of late, rather more sustained attention
has been devoted to examining the effects of mass incarceration, not only in terms of its
impact on crime,9 but also in respect of how it has reshaped other institutions of
American society from the economy, to families, to communities, to the political
process.10 This has been important work. But beneath the shadow cast by penal excess it
is also possible to discern certain temptations and attendant pathologies that have
informed both analyses of mass imprisonment and prescriptions for how best to respond
to it. Our judgment is that these pathologies have become an impediment to our capacity
to think not just about, but also beyond, mass incarceration.
Common among them, we suggest, has been nostalgia: a lament for a better and
lost world in which welfare liberal social policies were ascendant, where these coincided
with (or helped produce) imprisonment rates that were lower and more stable, and where
the climate of social and penal policymaking was much “cooler” and more rational. As
we have noted elsewhere, this lamentation for mid-twentieth-century welfare liberalism
(or in European terms, social democracy) is often accompanied by the miserabalist
premise that what gets bad is going to get worse.11 In terms of intervention, the heatingup of the penal climate over recent decades has given rise to a situation in which
countervoices of social science have tended to eschew spaces of public engagement for
fear of being trashed by a febrile media, as well as adopting a certain defensiveness in the
diagnosis of what is to be done. The result is that penal politics has come to be seen as a
rear-guard action where the principal objective is damage limitation or the protection of
the hard-won and fragile gains of the past.
Two points might usefully be made about these structuring orientations toward
mass incarceration. The first is to ask why lament and defensiveness has become so
prevalent in the social analysis of, and responses to, penal excess. One answer is that
mass imprisonment has played to criminology’s self-image (and, we should add, its
strengths) as a “dismal science.” Our most powerful and compelling stories of penal
change are narratives of decline and disaster. They have variously documented, warned,
alerted, and critiqued. In the process the field has spun or imported (and sometimes
loosely deployed or overextended) certain now-familiar concepts—risk, populism,
punitiveness, and neoliberalism being obvious cases in point. But the social analysis of
punishment has much less frequently speculated, reconstituted, or imagined alternatives
to the penal disasters that it describes or denounces.
The second is to bring more clearly into view one alternative world that is to be
found (sometimes expressly, often implicitly) in dominant accounts of mass
imprisonment. What holds these responses to mass incarceration together, we think, is an
outlook that one might call penal elitism. This is the worldview which holds that so long
as experts—government officials, justice professionals, lawyers, researchers, and so on—
are given the predominant say over the shape of penal policies, or else reinstated to a
position of dominance, better penal outcomes will follow—where “better” means
something along the lines of more moderate, milder, rights-respecting, liberal, or
principled. The flip-side of this warm embrace of expertise has been a certain “discomfort
with democracy”:12 a fear of permitting the demos too great an influence over penal
policy and a concern that too intimate a connection between the public and policymakers
will lead to immoderately punitive measures. This discomfort with democratic practice
(and the resultant tendency to neglect democratic theory) 13 has been one of the most
striking analytic effects generated by the three decade long penal upsurge. It has come
close to acquiring the status of orthodoxy among analysts and critics of mass
incarceration—one that has made a return to insulated professionalism and technocratic
governance seem an obvious antidote to “hot” issues such as criminal justice. Protecting
punishment from democracy has, in short, become the default answer to the question of
what we can reasonably hope for in penal politics. So much so that the problematic that
animates and organizes this book may (initially) strike readers as counterintuitive, even
decidedly odd.
Distrust of the public has first and foremost shaped thinking on how to explain the
rise of mass imprisonment—and the “exceptional” character of penal regimes in the
United States. Reflected in scholarship on so-called penal populism, but also in the dayto-day assumptions of politicians and sitting government officials, looms an image of the
punitive public demanding tough sentences and resistant to progressive reform. This, the
argument runs, has been coupled with “the radically extensive and extraordinarily
decentralized quality of US democracy”14—porous state and local political systems that
have given way to democratic pressures of uninformed electorates and frenzied media
responses to dramatic criminal events.15 The ability of penal bureaucrats to manage or
fend off these pressures is, conversely, posited as the principal explanation for the
relative mildness of punishment in Scandinavia and parts of Western Europe.16 By
extension, keeping the public at bay has become a central plank of several influential
accounts of how to temper punitive excesses. Here the claim is that the only way to scale
back imprisonment is to insulate criminal justice policy through more backroom
decisions, more expert interventions in sentencing commissions, and fewer grandstands
offered to politicians seeking office on the back of tough-on-crime promises. The
attendant ambition is to defend existing institutions of mediation between public demands
and penal outcomes (such as parole boards) or to create new expert authorities, operating
at one remove from direct political pressure, in and through which rational penal policy
can be formed.17
Such technocratic solutions have also loomed large in recent governmental
thinking about how to navigate a route away from mass incarceration. Even as the current
administration began to draw mass incarceration into focus as a policy problem, highranking officials continued to block broader critical thinking on the issue as a public
problem. In 2013, at the beginning of the policy shift, US Attorney General Eric Holder,
the nation’s most visible criminal justice professional, proclaimed that his colleagues
needed to be “smarter on crime,” meaning more sensible about sentencing for nonviolent
or low-level offenses and more conscious of the racial biases of current practice.18
Though Holder applauded the professionalism of his colleagues standing at the gateway
to prison—the police, attorneys, prosecutors, judges, wardens, probation officers—his
“smarter on crime” remarks implied that status-quo tough sentences and racial bias do not
lead to safer streets; they are “dumb.” At a time when leading scholars increasingly see
criminal justice as “the most dysfunctional of the major institutional accomplishments of
the Enlightenment,”19 Holder’s framework suggests that the way forward is a return to
Enlightenment rationality (rather than an immanent critique of it) to become more
sophisticated criminal justice experts and professionals. Being smart on crime, on this
view, means listening to the experts more and the electorate less.
Penal Politics and Democratic Hope
This volume takes issue with technocratic discourse and the attendant suspicion of the
public—and its participation in political life—that is at its root. It is not entirely correct to
say, as President Obama did, that “we,” meaning “the public,” think mass incarceration is
normal. It may be more precise to say that we the public have not been provided many
opportunities to think seriously about mass incarceration at all. Crime and punishment
saturate news and entertainment media, to be sure. But we actually don’t engage in much
concerted public discourse about the process or the practices our taxes support. Indeed,
institutions involved in policing, adjudicating, and punishing have successfully repelled
critical public awareness and involvement. Criminal justice work is often physically
removed from the lay public, as with prisons that tightly control communication and
interaction with those outside. Probation and other postincarceration administrative
decisions and programs too are normally conducted outside the public gaze, commonly
attracting attention only when something goes very wrong. Even the court process
leading to prison can hardly be called public, as backroom plea bargaining has drastically
replaced trials, leaving a scant 1 to 4 percent of state and federal criminal cases in the
United States for the courtroom.
The aim of this volume is to connect debate about the future of punishment to a
wider conversation about ideals and institutions of democracy. We want to encourage
research and reflection on the mutually corrosive relationship that occurs, but also on the
mutually supportive associations that may be fostered, between penal practices and
democracy. In so doing, our aim is to treat democratic values and commitments as an
underexploited “resource of hope” for building a better—by which we mean more
deliberative and inclusive—penal politics.20 Doing this, however, means making
connections between areas of scholarship that have long and puzzlingly been
disconnected: namely, between the social analysis of punishment and political theory in
general and democratic theory in particular.
The United States remains the “world champion” in incarceration, to borrow Nils
Christie’s words, and jurisdictions in the United Kingdom, though some distance behind,
are persistently among the European countries with the highest per capita rates of
imprisonment. Yet until recently Anglo-American political theory has hardly registered
mass incarceration and has done little to analyze any incongruity with mainstream
normative commitments.21 This disconnect is puzzling, first, because of the powerful
lines of argument present within progressive, liberal, and conservative traditions alike
which draw limits to state coercion and demand strict scrutiny over threats to individual
rights, human development, and civic dignity posed by institutionalized exclusion and
stigmatization. It is puzzling, second, because of the common ground occupied by
restorative justice advocates and political theorists concerned with deliberative
democratic institutional design. It is puzzling, third, because of the available links to
robust and sophisticated theoretical discussions within criminology by David Garland,
Jonathan Simon, and other scholars on the state, citizen action, and efficacy of
punishment.
But this general dissociation between punishment and political theory also holds
for the more particular domain of theorizing about democracy. The disconnection that
concerns us here is of a particular kind, and the allegation may at first sight appear
somewhat puzzling. Of course legal and political theorists have long concerned
themselves with problems about the relationship between systems of law and personal
and political liberty, and with questions about the justification of coercion in general and
the right to punish in particular. Our point is rather that it is just because these sorts of
problems are of such central and permanent interest that the slow and hesitant extent to
which scholars of those questions have taken note of a phenomenon of such scale and
consequence as that of contemporary mass incarceration is so puzzling. Against this
backdrop, this volume therefore also invites people whose primary focus is with the
concept of democracy and the development of democratic practices to consider how mass
incarceration bears upon their core concepts and fundamental arguments about how
institutions function and how they might improve, or be supplemented, or replaced, or
transformed. Contemporary democratic theorists have to date done considerably less to
address the subjects of crime, punishment, prison, and re-entry than we might have
expected, despite the massive social, political, economic, and moral reverberations of
mass incarceration. At a time often referred to as a renaissance in democratic theory, the
field has been eerily silent on punishment. We think this neglect—what Bernard Harcourt
has called the “invisibility of the prison in democratic theory”22—has emaciated
scholarship on power, social justice, political equality, citizenship, institutional
innovation, and related topics. By avoiding the real world of mass incarceration,
democratic theory has risked becoming less democratic, less relevant to political reform,
and less able to contribute productively to public discourse.
So just how should we go about better acquainting democratic theory with the
study of mass incarceration in particular and punishment in general? How might the
former alter the ways in which we think about, research, and evaluate the latter? Why
should the carceral state command the attention of democratic theorists? What questions
open up if we examine punishment though the lens of democratic theory and practice?
We want to suggest three main ways in which a productive interplay between punishment
and democratic theory is being developed.
A first line of analysis seeks to extend the critique of mass incarceration by
situating it within the frame of democratic ideals and practice, thereby extending and
recasting our analysis of what is at stake in penal policy and politics. Much of the
empirical research on American punishment in recent years has focused on the impact of
political systems on punishment—whether in terms of the advent of governing through
crime,23 the rise of symbolic and populist political forms,24 the incentive and opportunity
structures created (or blocked) by different political arrangements,25 or the mobilization
of social movements in the penal field.26 But thinking about punishment through the lens
of democracy also calls for analyses of the impact of mass incarceration upon democratic
politics.27
To think democratically—rather than simply in crime control terms—about
punishment is not just to revisit longstanding questions about the claims of retribution,
deterrence, or rehabilitation as penal aims, or about the grounding of the sovereign right
to punish in general. Rather, in our current contexts, it is also to seek to ask sharper
questions about the collateral effects of the transformations of the carceral state upon
political participation, the formation of civic identities and the associational life of
impacted communities. The recent body of work on felon disenfranchisement is most
obviously of importance here. But the very particular and locally variable phenomenon of
felon disenfranchisement is one that opens a much wider set of concerns. It has as such
provided a jumping-off point for the emergence of broader research agenda on what
Lerman and Weaver term the political consequences of the carceral state, for
investigating and theorizing the ways in which American punishment “violate(s) the
democratic imperatives of voice, responsiveness, and accountability.”28 The further
development of this agenda entails, among other matters: demonstrating that how
societies punish goes to the quality and reach of their democratic claims; problematizing
the relations between (excessive) punishment and democratic legitimacy; and identifying
the ways in which crime control institutions attend to, or breach, democratic principles.
A second—in some respects more established and well-trodden—path entails
finding within penal and political theory arguments for restraining the reach of the penal
state, whether via desert theory, penal communication, or republicanism. Democratic
theory has, arguably, been an underutilized resource in such normative thinking about
justifying and limiting the scope of state punishment. It is a field that might usefully be
mined further in order to make the numerous sage recommendations for penal moderation
or parsimony more compelling and better grounded—and we and others have recently
intimated that the concepts of legitimacy and citizenship might prove to be useful
meeting grounds for extending that conversation.29 In our view, such an extension of
penal theory offers grounds for questioning the democratic credentials of a society that
punishes its citizens in the way that the American polity currently does. Quite a few
criminologists in the United States and elsewhere have taken steps in these directions,32
sometimes in alliance with progressive administrators and practitioners, and those parties
need to be both supported and challenged by democratic theory.
A third point of connection is to be found in the use of democratic theory as a
resource for exploring strategies of penal reform and for more broadly reconstructing
how democratic societies might respond to crime. This has been a lively but still nascent
theme with a small body of literature on deliberative democracy and punishment. Work
here has largely developed as a response to, and critique of, the orthodoxy of insulating
criminal justice from political control. It has sought instead to explore the unfulfilled
promise of the ideal of greater democratic participation in crime control, and to bring to
notice and advance understanding of practical innovations that give effect to such public
involvement, in respect of restorative justice, justice reinvestment, and beyond.33 There
remains a great deal more theoretical work to be done along these lines, not least in
demonstrating that populism and technocracy are not the polarized ideologies they are
typically assumed to be within criminology, but can be theorized instead as twin
pathologies of our contemporary anti-political malaise,34 both of which “disfigure” the
ideal and practice of democratic government by neglecting the normative force of
democratic procedures.35 But there is also a rich agenda of research and theorizing
entailed in furthering practices of “democratic experimentalism” in crime control and
punishment36—that is to say, in fostering the development of, and learning lessons from,
deliberative practices whose aim is to promote civic reintegration, emphasize mutual
accountability for penal decisions, and foster proper recognition that those whom we
punish are co-citizens.37 In other words, we need greater reflection on what it would look
like to impose sanctions without magnifying existing inequalities and in ways that
maintain equality of concern and respect for all parties involved.
In our view, these points of intersection between democratic theory and penal
practice offer a theoretically rich and politically promising agenda for thinking about
punishment beyond mass incarceration. It is an agenda that focuses—via the three
moments of critique, restraint, and reconstruction we have described—on the aims and
practices of crime control institutions and asks from the standpoint of democratic theory
what one tasks police, probation, and prisons to do. From this standpoint, the overarching
question that emerges is how to produce criminal justice institutions that contribute to
democratic development and build up civic capabilities and participatory resources. Can
this democratic ambition for criminal justice be justified, and if so how? What might one
require of different criminal justice institutions if we conceived of their purposes at least
in part in these terms? How would such institutions have to be remade and reimagined if
they are to become agents of a deeper democracy?
Organization of this Volume
This collection of original chapters seeks to catalyze an engaged, multidisciplinary
discussion among philosophers, political theorists, and theoretically inclined
criminologists about how contemporary democratic theory might begin to think beyond
mass incarceration.38 Rather than viewing punishment as a natural reaction to crime and
imprisonment as a sensible outgrowth of this reaction, we frame these as institutions with
deep implications for contemporary civic identity and that present unmet demands for
public oversight and reflective democratic influence. What conceptual resources can be
deployed to support decarceration and alternatives to prison? How might democratic
theory strengthen recent efforts in restorative justice and other reform movements? How
can the normative complexity of criminal justice be grappled with by lay citizens rather
than experts or officials—from street-level policing decisions, to adjudication, to prison
and probation policy? How, in short, might modern publics forge a creative alternative to
an unreflective commitment to mass incarceration? In reflecting on these questions, the
authors investigate how to better situate the prison in the discourse of reform, offer
conceptual guideposts for thinking about incarceration, critically examine the methods
and uses of public opinion regarding punishment, and suggest ways of reconceiving
crime control institutions to enhance rather than thwart citizen capabilities.
One explanation for the doxa surrounding the normalcy of mass incarceration, and
a problem facing any attempt at a more critical public discourse for reform, is social
geography. As Rebecca Thorpe’s chapter forcefully points out, prisons are out of sight,
out of mind, and highly ambiguous for many people. The rapid growth of prisons since
the 1970s, especially in rural America, has provided jobs and revenues in impoverished
communities. This kind of public investment is an economic dead end, however. As
prison areas are rarely sites of further growth or development, it represents the
shortsighted triumph of penal policy over more constructive approaches to rebuilding the
poor, urban, and racially segregated neighborhoods disproportionately filling the rural
prison cells.
How to orient our normative thinking about reform is the subject of the next three
chapters. Reform efforts targeting contemporary penal institutions need to take their
bearings from some overarching understanding of the purposes served by criminal
justice. Antony Duff and Sandra Marshall draw attention to the ideal role of the criminal
law in a democratic republic, understood as a political society made up of free and equal
citizens. Criminal law in such a society would be recognized by citizens to be something
they shared and took part in as a common law. Focusing in particular on citizens
convicted of crimes, they discuss the civic roles related to punishment that emerge in a
democratic republic and how these roles, considered as a matter of ideal theory, reflect
just how far current punishment practices are from widely embraced political ideals.
Seeking a gravitational principle that can shed light on the core question of just
how much punishment is enough, Richard Dagger calls our attention to the importance of
fair play. When punishment is deployed justifiably it intends to pay back those who do
not play fair and it communicates disapproval of rule breaking, thus shoring up a
cooperative, law-abiding system. When used in excess, it is a symptom of dysfunction
calling into question the fairness of the laws and the status of the polity as a cooperative
enterprise. Honing in on the value of political equality, Peter Ramsay argues that taking
this value seriously results in strict limits on the use of imprisonment as a sanction. It is a
mistake, he argues, to see an incarcerated person as a full and equal citizen. Prison
inevitably takes away the exercise of free association and free assembly, and it severely
limits free speech. Prisoners are in no way able to take part on equal terms with their
fellow citizens in the regular political process. Political equality demands radical
decrementalism in penal reform and points the way toward the abolition of incarceration.
Chapters 6 and 7 consider what more widespread citizen participation might
contribute to criminal justice institutions. Focusing on adjudication and sentencing,
Christopher Bennett asks whether greater lay participation would help produce more
moderate decisions than the professionalized, official justice that has done little to block
the development of mass incarceration. Democratization efforts may prove less beneficial
in this respect than some scholars believe, he argues, but could be normatively significant
nonetheless if they held citizens responsible as co-owners for punishment enacted for the
public good. One approach already available for involving citizens as stakeholders in
criminal justice is the wide range of practices offered by restorative justice programs as
supplements to or substitutes for traditional sentencing procedures. Thom Brooks
discusses the advantages of restorative justice as an alternative to mainstream criminal
procedures for both victims and offenders. To serve as an effective institutional reform
movement, however, restorative justice needs to become a more routine part of the
criminal justice system and expand to handle a wider variety of cases, including serious
offenses. To do so, Brooks argues, it may need to include penalties like suspended
sentences and short prison stays for cooling off or rehabilitation.
Chapters 8 through 10 approach the complicated and controversial relationship
between public opinion—about criminal offenses, offenders, and proper punishment—
and the development of public policy that undergirds mass incarceration. In response to
what she sees as the limitations of mainstream academic discourse, Lynne Copson argues
that any satisfying theory of criminal justice reform must move some significant distance
from conventional assumptions about what the public wants from crime control measures
and what victims and offenders require. Reform must be grounded in utopian thought:
committed to posing large and general questions about the kind of society we wish to
have and the kind of citizens we hope to become.
Taking up the debate over so-called penal populism, David Green and Elizabeth
Turner reject the aforementioned elite-centered orthodoxy that points to the political
success of “tough on crime” campaign rhetoric and advocate expert dominated
sentencing commissions insulated from demotic electoral pressures as an antidote to
penal severity. Like Copson, Green and Turner favor more direct and robust public
involvement. Decremental strategies that rely on stealth, Green points out, have had some
modest success in the United States and United Kingdom, but they do nothing to build
lasting support among the citizenry. It is better for governments to expand real
opportunities for the public to contribute to criminal justice policy discussions,
policymaking, and adjudication. One possibility Turner explores is the use of deliberative
democratic techniques such as deliberative polls and citizens’ juries, which have
uncovered less public support for “get tough” measures than traditional public opinion
polling because they typically provide context and promote discussion of multiple
viewpoints. While it is a mistake to think that such methods disclose “real” public
opinion, they do ask people to foster defensible positions, alert them to issues they may
not have contemplated, and help participants see their connections to others’ lives.
Rebuilding crime control institutions that can both respect and enable the civic
capacity of regular citizens is an uphill struggle. Chapters 11 to 13 take aim at
exclusionary practices in the penal system, policymaking process, and in the legal
system. Amy Lerman and Vesla Weaver investigate the legal and institutional barriers to
democracy inside prisons. An early twentieth-century reform idea, inmate selfgovernance through advisory councils thrived in the 1960s and 1970s, reflecting reformminded idealism about creating more democratic prisons as well as pragmatic thinking
about how to respond to inmates’ demands for voice that had found violent expression in
disruptive riots. Despite early positive evidence about the effects of inmate associations,
courts have held that the state’s interest in prison safety supported a tight rein on
organizations such as unions. The prison was not a “public forum,” the Supreme Court
held in 1977, allowing administrators to override the associational rights of inmates and
block organizations if they had the potential for disruption. Drawing on survey data from
California prisons, Lerman and Weaver show that inmate participation in self-governance
correlates with a decrease in prison violence. They advocate further democratic
innovation inside one of our currently least democratic institutions.
Lisa Miller disputes the common view of the American political system as overly
sensitive to democracy in its openness to popular pressure. She shows how the
combination of federalism, separation of powers, multiple decision-making venues, and
judicial supremacy produce a labyrinthine obstacle course with many veto points for
those with the resources to block social policy. The public good of security from violence
has close connections to poverty reduction, employment, education, and other social
welfare measures, but the complexity of the American system—not to mention its
counterdemocratic fixtures such as the Senate and Supreme Court—makes it extremely
difficult for these to survive the policy gauntlet.
Drawing attention to relatively unexplored links between democratic theory and
the criminal law, Roberto Gargarella suggests that criminal trials, sentencing, and penal
decision-making can become both more democratic and more deliberative. Trials can
treat offenders as active contributors to a moral dialogue about harmful action and the
law, not as passive subjects of condemnation, while sentencing and justice policymaking
can become more open to civil society. Rejecting both penal elitism and pure populism, a
deliberative democratic approach to criminal justice seeks out ways of constructively
welcoming citizen participation and action on criminal justice issues. Openness to public
engagement, even when it takes the form of disruptive social protest, is needed to address
the serious legitimacy problems facing the law in many countries.
This collection comes at an opportune moment when the onward march of mass
incarceration has taken a pause, thus weakening the politically and intellectually
convenient alibi of inevitability. Against this backdrop, the chapters in this volume offer
an exciting agenda for theorization, empirical inquiry, and civic engagement. They
present a new political mode of judgment and critique of actually existing penal
practices, reminding us that criminal justice and punishment are always about more than
just the regulation of crime. As the arguments presented in the pages that follow
forcefully attest, issues of crime control are also inescapably entangled with the question
of how to foster and sustain better democratic governance; the task that confronts us is
not simply “downsizing the carceral state,” but “strengthening the democratic state.”39
1
New York Times, July 16, 2015.
2
Jonathan Simon, Governing through Crime (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
3
It is noteworthy that similar shifts in political leadership around prisons appear to be
underway in the United Kingdom where the new Conservative Justice Secretary,
Michael Gove, has publically signaled that he would like to see much less reliance
upon imprisonment and to make productive changes to what happens inside
prisons. See, for example, Gove’s speech to the Prisoners Learning Alliance on
July 17, 2015: www.gov.uk/government/speeches/the-treasure-in-the-heart-ofman-making-prisons-work.
4
David Green, “US Penal-Reform Catalysts, Drivers and Prospects,” Punishment &
Society 17, no. 3 (2015): 271–298.
5
We have in mind here the enquiry set up by the National Academy of Sciences into the
causes and consequences of high rates of incarceration: Jeremy Travis, Bruce
Western, and Steve Redburn (eds.), The Growth of Incarceration in the United
States: Exploring Causes and Consequences (Washington, DC: National
Academy of Sciences, 2014) and the President’s Task Force on 21st Century
Policing, whose final report was published in May 2015:
www.cops.usdoj.gov/pdf/taskforce/taskforce_finalreport.pdf.
6
Amy E. Lerman and Vesla M. Weaver, Arresting Citizenship: The Democratic
Consequences of American Crime Control (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2014) and Marie Gottschalk, Caught: The Prison State and the Lockdown of
American Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2015).
7
A point also made recently by Jonathan Simon, “Editorial: Mass Incarceration on
Trial,” Punishment & Society 13, no. 3 (2011): 251–255.
8
On the former, see inter alia David Garland, The Culture of Control (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2000); David. Garland (ed.), Mass Imprisonment: Social Causes
and Consequences (New York: Sage, 2001); Nicola Lacey, The Prisoners’
Dilemma (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); and Loïc Wacquant,
Punishing the Poor (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, It is Duke2009). On
the latter, key contributions have included Marie Gottschalk, The Prison and the
Gallows (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006); Simon, Governing
through Crime; and Naomi Murakawa, The First Civil Right: How Liberals Build
Prison America (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014).
9
Frank Zimring, The Great American Crime Decline (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2008, ch. 3).
10
On the economy, see Bruce Western, Punishment and Inequality in America (New
York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2007) and Devah Pager, Marked: Race, Crime
and Finding Work in an Era of Mass Incarceration (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2007); on the family, Megan Comfort, Doing Time Together
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007); on communities, Todd Clear,
Imprisoning Communities: How Mass Incarceration Makes Disadvantaged
Neighborhoods Worse (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008); on the
political process, Jeff Manza and Christopher Uggen, Locked Out: Felon
Disenfranchisement and American Democracy (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2006) and Lerman and Weaver, Arresting Citizenship.
11
Ian Loader and Richard Sparks, “Beyond Lamentation: Towards a Democratic
Egalitarian Politics of Crime and Justice,” in Tim Newburn and Jill Peay (eds.),
Policing: Politics, Culture and Control (Oxford: Hart, 2012) 11-41
12
We borrow this coinage from Roberto M. Unger, who originally claimed it was one of
the “dirty little secrets of contemporary jurisprudence.” Roberto M. Unger, What
Should Legal Analysis Become (London: Verso, 1996, 72). This terminology also
plays a role in earlier work by Ian Loader and Richard Sparks; see especially their
Public Criminology? (London: Routledge, 2010).
13
To take just one recent example: in a collection of chapters reflecting on the normative
significance of public opinion in shaping penal policy and outcomes, those
contributors who argue for limiting public involvement in such matters
consistently defend that position with little or no reference to the underlying
theory of democracy that is implicit in their argument. This results in a status-quo
bias that is complacent about the operation of existing expert-dominated criminal
justice while imposing stern tests of any proposal to extend public participation.
Jesper Ryberg and Julian Roberts (eds.), Popular Punishment: On the Normative
Significance of Public Opinion (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014). See
especially the chapters by Jan W. de Keijser and Roberts.
14
Nicola Lacey and David Soskice, “Crime, Punishment and Segregation in the United
States: The Paradox of Local Democracy,” Punishment & Society 17, no. 4
(2015): 461.
15
David Garland, Peculiar Institution: America’s Death Penalty in an Age of Abolition
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010); Lacey and Soskice, “Crime, Punishment
and Segregation in the United States.”
16
See, for example, Michael Tonry, “Determinants of Penal Policies,” in Michael Tonry
(ed.), Crime, Punishment and Politics in Comparative Perspective (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2007) and Sonja Snacken, “Resisting Punitiveness in
Europe?,” Theoretical Criminology 14, no. 3 (2010): 273–292.
17
See, for example, Phillip Pettit, “Is Criminal Justice Politically Feasible?” Buffalo
Criminal Law Review 5, no. 2 (2002): 427–450; Julian Roberts, Loretta Stalans,
David Indermaur, and Mike Hough, Penal Populism and Public Opinion: Lessons
from Five Countries (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003); Frank Zimring and
David Johnson, “Public Opinion and the Governance of Punishment in
Democratic Political Systems,” ANNALS of the American Academy of Social and
Political Science 605, no. 1 (2006): 265–280; and Lawrence Sherman, “Evidence
and Liberty: The Promise of Experimental Criminology,” Criminology &
Criminal Justice 9, no. 1 (2009): 5–28.
18
Eric Holder, “Remarks at the Annual Meeting of the American Bar Association’s
House of Delegates,” San Francisco, August 12, 2013,
www.justice.gov/opa/speech/attorney-general-eric-holder-delivers-remarksannual-meeting-american-bar-associations.
19
John Braithwaite, “Between Proportionality and Impunity: Confrontation - Truth Prevention.” Criminology 43, no. 2 (2005): 283.
20
Raymond Williams, Resources of Hope (London: Verso, 1989).
21
There are of course key exceptions, especially among those who address the meetings
points between penal theory and political theory. See, for example, John
Braithwaite and Phillip Pettit, Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal
Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990); Barbara Hudson, Justice in the
Risk Society (Maidenhead: Open University Press, 1993); and Matt Matravers
(ed.), Punishment and Political Theory (Oxford: Hart, 1999).
22
Bernard Harcourt, “The Invisibility of the Prison in Democratic Theory: A Problem of
‘Virtual Democracy,’” The Good Society 23, no. 1 (2014): 6–16. Harcourt’s point,
of course, is that the prison in not unseeable, just not seen.
23
Simon, Governing through Crime.
24
John Pratt, Penal Populism (New York: Routledge, 2007).
25
Lisa Miller, The Perils of Federalism: Race, Poverty and the Politics of Crime Control
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2008) and Vanessa Barker, The Politics of
Imprisonment (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).
26
Gottschalk, The Prison and the Gallows.
27
Vesla M. Weaver, Jacob S. Hacker, and Christopher Wildeman, “Detaining
Democracy? Criminal Justice and American Civic Life,” Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Sciences 651 (2014): 6–13.
28
Lerman and Weaver, Arresting Citizenship.
29
Ian Loader and Richard Sparks, “Unfinished Business: Legitimacy, Crime Control and
Democratic Politics,” in Justice Tankebe and Alison Liebling (eds.), Legitimacy
and Criminal Justice: An International Exploration (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2013) and Anthony Duff, “A Criminal Law for Citizens,” Theoretical
Criminology 14, no. 3 (2010): 293–309.
32
Elliott Currie, “Consciousness, Solidarity and Hope as Prevention and Rehabilitation,”
International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy 2, no. 2 (2013):
3–11; David Brown, “Mapping the Conditions of Penal Hope,” International
Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy 2, no. 3 (2013): 27–42.
33
For example, Archon Fung, Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004); Albert Dzur and Rekha
Mirchandani, “Punishment and Democracy: The Role of Public Deliberation,”
Punishment & Society 9, no. 2 (2007): 151–175; Albert Dzur, “Trench
Democracy: Participatory Innovation in Unlikely Places,” Boston Review,
October 11, 2013, www.bostonreview.net/blog/dzur-trench-democracy-1; David
Brown, Chris Cunneen, Melanie Schwartz, Julie Stubbs, and Courtney Young,
Justice Reinvestment: Winding Back Imprisonment (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2015).
34
Pierre Rosanvallon, Counter-Democracy: Politics in an Age of Distrust (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2008).
35
Nadia Urbinati, Democracy Disfigured: Opinion, Truth, and the People (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 2014).
36
Roberto M. Unger, Democracy Realized (London: Verso, 1998).
37
Albert W. Dzur, Punishment, Participatory Democracy, and the Jury (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2012).
38
Some of the chapters in the book originated as contributions to a special issue of the
Good Society journal on democratic theory and mass incarceration. Good Society
23, no. 1 (2014). Thanks to Joshua Miller for his early organizational work.
39
Lerman and Weaver, Arresting Citizenship, 237.