This art icle was downloaded by: [ Vidhu Verm a]
On: 03 August 2015, At : 11: 04
Publisher: Rout ledge
I nform a Lt d Regist ered in England and Wales Regist ered Num ber: 1072954 Regist ered
office: 5 Howick Place, London, SW1P 1WG
Global Discourse: An Interdisciplinary
Journal of Current Affairs and Applied
Contemporary Thought
Publicat ion det ails, including inst ruct ions f or aut hors and
subscript ion inf ormat ion:
ht t p: / / www. t andf online. com/ loi/ rgld20
Democracy and the politics of the
spectacle
Vidhu Verma
a
a
Cent re f or Polit ical St udies, School f or Social Sciences,
Jawaharlal Nehru Universit y
Published online: 30 Jul 2015.
Click for updates
To cite this article: Vidhu Verma (2015): Democracy and t he polit ics of t he spect acle, Global
Discourse: An Int erdisciplinary Journal of Current Af f airs and Applied Cont emporary Thought , DOI:
10. 1080/ 23269995. 2015. 1070512
To link to this article: ht t p: / / dx. doi. org/ 10. 1080/ 23269995. 2015. 1070512
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTI CLE
Taylor & Francis m akes every effort t o ensure t he accuracy of all t he inform at ion ( t he
“ Cont ent ” ) cont ained in t he publicat ions on our plat form . However, Taylor & Francis,
our agent s, and our licensors m ake no represent at ions or warrant ies what soever as t o
t he accuracy, com plet eness, or suit abilit y for any purpose of t he Cont ent . Any opinions
and views expressed in t his publicat ion are t he opinions and views of t he aut hors,
and are not t he views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of t he Cont ent
should not be relied upon and should be independent ly verified wit h prim ary sources
of inform at ion. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, act ions, claim s,
proceedings, dem ands, cost s, expenses, dam ages, and ot her liabilit ies what soever or
howsoever caused arising direct ly or indirect ly in connect ion wit h, in relat ion t o or arising
out of t he use of t he Cont ent .
This art icle m ay be used for research, t eaching, and privat e st udy purposes. Any
subst ant ial or syst em at ic reproduct ion, redist ribut ion, reselling, loan, sub- licensing,
syst em at ic supply, or dist ribut ion in any form t o anyone is expressly forbidden. Term s &
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
Condit ions of access and use can be found at ht t p: / / www.t andfonline.com / page/ t erm sand- condit ions
Global Discourse, 2015
BOOK REVIEW SYMPOSIUM: DEMOCRACY DISFIGURED:
OPINION, TRUTH AND PEOPLE, BY NADIA URBINATI
Democracy disfigured: opinion, truth and people, by Nadia Urbinati, Cambridge,
Harvard University Press, 2014, 307 pp., US$39.95 (hardback), ISBN 978-0-674-725133
Review
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
Vidhu Verma
Democracy and the politics of the spectacle
Given the immense variety in the democratic practices as well as the fact that ‘democracy’
is a term applied so widely that it has become vague, it is necessary to survey changes in
the conception of democracy. With Democracy Disfigured: Opinion, Truth and People,
Nadia Urbinati (2014) offers a major contribution in this direction by examining democracy across manifold debates in political theory and speaking to the ideal conditions under
which we practice it. The book stands out in its singular desire to explore a decline of
electoral and political participation to which corresponds the people’s longing for political
spectacle.
This article is a response to Nadia Urbinati’s compelling attempt to articulate three
forms of disfigurement of representative democracy due to epistemic, plebiscitary and
populist visions of democracy. She theorizes the intimate ties between these visions
arguing that they converge towards a view that denies the normative character of democratic procedures. The processes of change and redefinition are intense not only due to the
challenges posed but the speed of events that new systems of internet democracy facilitate. This metamorphosis is assisted by movement of protests, opinion formation and
technological innovation even though democracy’s fundamental norms are not subject to
change.
The normative core of representative democracy is the public sphere of opinion
formation, which Urbinati cautions, is also a domain where considerable challenges
await us. Whereas she conceives of a direct causal connection between the disfigurement of democracy and the undemocratic character of politics, I argue that such a
conception is flawed. I provide a series of arguments designed to highlight some of
the limitations in this position and conclude by questioning the general thesis that
underlie Urbinati’s account of democracy. The disfigurement of representative
democracy is acknowledged by her as coinciding with a series of economic and
political crisis as a result of which democratic institutions and decision-making
procedures are facing loss of legitimacy. At times, this pattern of politics is remote
from participation and distribution of political power. The series of formal conditions
she subsequently enumerates are not sufficient to justify the causal relationship
between public opinion and political results or decisions – a thing to be added is
the way political discourse displaces antagonism between classes to restore balance
and justice among groups in liberal democracy.
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
2
Book review symposium
Three compelling objections emerge from a reading of her account. The first step in
my argument that I propose to take is cutting the link between the disfiguration of
democracy and an opinion-based approach to politics. The latter should not be mistaken
as a necessary reflection or rectification of the former. Such a conflation of politics and
democratic theory distort Urbinati’s project. It disregards her theory that has not been
inspired by presenting representation as a second-rate device in the absence of direct
democracy; Urbinati turns the question around so that the three forms of disfigurement in
modern society are not an impediment to representation but on the contrary its essential
condition that must be overcome.
For Urbinati, the normative core of representative democracy is at risk from the
complex world of opinion formation where assertion of popular assertion both in the
form of ‘plebiscitarian identification of the masses with a publicized leader’ and of
‘populist claims seeking to represent the whole people as a homogenous unity of values
and history’ (Urbinati, 13) are increasingly also phenomena of political passivity and
docility of citizens. At first sight, such malfunctions appear only in the basic traits
composing the democratic figure, but as the book proceeds her approach to politics
seems to miss the critical point. To begin with, a close link between media and public
opinion has been part of the work done by political scientists like Harold Lasswell, who
wrote about the open interplay of opinion and policy as mark of popular rule (Lasswell
1941). His approach is now central in public opinion polls, conducted world-wide during
elections, where the causal link between the power of media and the autonomy of trends
in voting and attitudes of citizens is deeply probed and contested. Urbinati is forging
similar links in her work but with new theoretical tools. One must take into account that
Urbinati’s main thesis is that mutations in democracy must be understood through the
tradition of doxa (popular opinion). It turns Plato’s idea into an ontological notion of
solipsism that denies authenticity to the plural realm of doxa. By making use of Aristotle’s
reading of political deliberation, she argues that democracy is the government ‘most
friendly to public discourse’ (Urbinati, 33). The roles played by doxa are that of cognitive,
political and aesthetic (Urbinati, 229). These broadly include information requirement and
consensus, expression of ideas that sends inputs into the political system and exposure of
politicians and policies to public judgment (Urbinati, 36). The new policy spaces, however promising they may be, are not enough. What insights can a normative theory of
democratic politics offer us in an era when individuals are deeply embedded in their
biographical experience and social and cultural identity? Are we living in representative
democracies anymore if plebiscitarian democracy which degrades voters’ political
engagement to electoral battles is driving citizens by a feeling of general well-being?
Moreover, opinions even though a solitary business, turn into critical judgment only
where the standpoints of others are open to discussions and interrogation. The very
process of opinion formation and constructing consensus is determined in contemporary
politics through technological methods. Indeed, it has become a commodity that can be
increasingly bought and sold.
Second, I want to argue that Urbinati begins her study with reference to the ancient
Greeks or their language of politics which is not essentially ‘an instrumental or goaloriented activity undertaken for the sake of some end’ but is ‘the medium of moral
education of the citizenry’ (Urbinati, 81). Despite the recent constraints of this kind of an
attempt, she goes on to assume that a European identity and notion of democracy are
closely related to the foundations of ancient Greek culture. Urbinati declares Greece to
have initiated something peculiarly modern: that it conceived a polis ‘based on speech’, a
principle which the electoral transformation of modern democracy did not change
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
Global Discourse
3
(Urbinati, 20). In contemporary debates on democracy it is important to examine to what
extent Plato and Aristotle appear to have shared or rejected the values of direct democracy
in their own societies; or to what extent Greek attitudes in general to slaves, women,
aliens and even to democracy were justified philosophically and logically. If the vast
majority of Greeks were not entitled to participate in political life, citizens were regarded
as equals in the sense that each could claim the right of private free speech (parrhesia) and
equality of public speech (isegoria). This independence of citizens as free men typified the
polis even though it had a distinctive form of a slave mode of production. Hence, the
peculiar embrace of the ancient polis as an objective force of democracy is different from
thinking of inheriting ways of thinking about values and institutions from the Greece and
of forging an identity with the Greeks and their past.
There is something odd about the aspiration to establish a tradition of political theory
across the centuries to challenge conventional ideas for modern readers. An insight into
Greeks tells us only something about the way public speech was tied to democracy as a
unique kind of civic life, but it tells us nothing substantive about the factors for the decline
in political power of traditional parties or the increasing role of television in constructing
political consent or the increasing weight of the executive as a result of economic and
financial emergencies. Indeed, scholars have written about the central role of media and
opinion polls as ‘mediacracy’, ‘videocracy’ and ‘audience democracy’ to stigmatize the
transformations of representative democracy.
Therefore, I think the author could also consider public opinion as an immaterial
phenomenon which appears as a cognitive and symbolic process equipped with potential
agency for both legitimacy and affective ties; this public sphere is not the polis or agora as
in ancient Greece but as a domain which goes beyond the sharing of the same space and
the same time for doing politics. Nevertheless, it is one of the pillars of modern
democracy that invoke a space of liberation or even empowerment from the yoke of
tyranny. The media including the printing press, electronic press and social media create
conditions for the formation of a speaking public even though a rational confrontation
rarely takes place due to the speed in circulation of these opinions. It also creates a public,
though distant in time and place, through texts and verbalizations. For these reasons the
link between media and public opinion appears a founding and constitutive act that I
mentioned earlier.
The third part of this reconstruction of the role of doxa lies in detecting the disfigurements of the system of representative democracy in which elections are viewed as ‘means
to a government of opinion as a government responsive to, and responsible toward, the
public’ (Urbinati, 229). Against these disfigurements, Urbinati advocates democracy as
linked to procedures and not only about an ideal society with a specific goal to achieve;
neither does it improve our decision-making capacity (we do not learn how to vote by
voting) across different arenas of citizen engagement. If we accept a proceduralist theory
of democracy on Urbinati’s terms, how will we come to accept the problem of caste or
racial segregation as our problem? How is the agenda set for collective deliberation
through doxa as she defines ‘representative government is government by doxa’?
(Urbinati 229). Can we blame civil society for imposing exclusionary norms, for defending unruly fasts, demonstrations and acerbic modes of expression? How can doxa alone
bring to the fore a set of values – freedom, equality, justice – which engage the affective
bonds of familiarity that we nurse in our immediate circles? These are difficult questions
for most democratic theories and they continue to nag the critical tradition Urbinati has
located herself.
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
4
Book review symposium
Nevertheless, Urbinati raises a crucial question of jurisdiction; procedurally a public
forum that keeps state under scrutiny should be ruled, she argues, according to the same
egalitarian principle embodied in citizens’ right to be self-governing (Urbinati, 228).
Electoral representation is egalitarian due to the premise of universal franchise. In most
respects, I found myself agreeing with her approach here. But Urbinati might consider
how in respect of authorization citizens show unstable preferences that are neither formed
by the electoral process nor the right to vote but by proportional representative electoral
systems; preferences can lead to a strong party to form a minority government with a
small per cent of the vote if turnout of eligible voters is also very low. How is such a
group to remain accountable to the interests and perspectives of others in a meaningful
way? In the ideal model that Urbinati has imagined, public opinion is a discursive process
which must develop in the co-presence of citizens along with dialogicity in face-to-face
interaction characterized by self-direction and determination. In reality public opinion is a
much more ambiguous process!
My final critique is that despite the sort of normative view she takes on democracy, it
is surprising that she does not give attention to contestatory mechanisms of the kind that
would look into issues of domination and power between democratic citizens that emerge
in the literature on ‘democracy deficit’ in European Union and elsewhere. To ask questions in areas in which collective decisions can be made, a conceptualization of the public
spheres across countries in the light of the new scenario of representative democracies is
urgently needed. These are the questions where her approach has real strengths but
somehow they do not emerge here. The ways in which power, authority and leadership
of communities are negotiated in civil society lead to a progressive disembedding of the
public sphere. Hence, the publicity through Internet to various debates can be accessible
to all without limits but it might not be necessarily discursive; in short, the structural
transformation of the public sphere from elites to many subaltern groups seems in actual
fact only through media processes and not through social integration.
Many scholars have written about the way the access to the public sphere does not
only lose dialogicity but also produces differentiation among citizens in the way about
who is speaking, listening and consuming. Others have traced the development of modern
society in which social life has been replaced with representation. Subsequently the
spectacle is the inverted image of society in which relationship between people is
mediated by images. Thompson has written about the ‘mediatisation of public opinion’,
where the media take on process of formation of individual and collective opinions
(Thompson 1995); the symbolic environment is driven by information and technology
by institutional actors, which is up for grabs by the media system, institutions of state,
opinion pollsters, public relations firms, marking offices, lobbies, etc.; the public presentation of these ideas in a symbolic arena constructed by the media pose the question of
the formation of public opinion or doxa in societies like ours where economic inequalities
create new meritocracies. Grossi has written about the ‘demoscopic field’ to identify the
formation of public opinion or mediated ‘public debate’ in post-industrial societies (Grossi
2005, 9). This is a specialized ambit or domain in which dynamics of opinion are
activated, competed and constructed. Hence, public opinion cannot be spontaneously
generated but would require associations, groups and movements that frame and interpret
the symbolic and cognitive dynamics of the formation of that domain.
Finally, I am unsure about Urbinati’s optimistic long-term scenario that presupposes
democracy will remain the goal that countries are seeking. This goal is likely to depend on
its being viewed both as a standard of political legitimacy and as the best system for
achieving a certain kind of effective governance that all countries seek. What has changed
Downloaded by [Vidhu Verma] at 11:04 03 August 2015
Global Discourse
5
is that many presuppositions about democracy are increasingly being questioned specially
in advanced countries of USA and Europe. In the last decade alone democracy in states
with grounded traditions have been involved in major debates about enjoyment of rights.
In an era of identity politics, what seem for many to endanger democracy is the attitude
towards immigrants and minorities, both seen as sources of crime and as burdens on the
state for jobs and social security benefits.
Despite the problems I raise, I think Urbinati’s emphasis on opinion-formation and its
distortions definitely lead her to give greater attention than many theorists do to crisis that
put democracy in peril today. She uses conceptual tools to counterbalance the dangers of
political judgments against the autonomy of individuals and persuasively uses opinion
formation as a means for overcoming debates on identity and difference. This analysis
provides an illuminating interpretation of the ideological crisis of post-liberalism and
exposes the intellectual weakness of earlier efforts (republican, deliberative or competitive) to delineate new versions of democracy. I would recommend that to negatively
stigmatize the transformations of representative democracy from the role played by its
three versions actually indicate the author’s move towards a ‘post-democratic society’
position. Overall this book remains valuable because it should make us think more deeply
about important aspects of democracy. This book is not only a scholarly and analytical
discussion on democracy but a book dedicated to reworking our democratic imagination
and for reshaping liberal theories and ideologies.
References
Grossi, G. 2005. “Public Opinion and Public Sphere: From Modernity to Postdemocracy?” Paper
presented at VII AECPA Congreso, Madrid, September 21–23, 1–29.
Lasswell, H. D. 1941. Democracy through Public Opinion. Menasha, WI: George Banta.
Thompson, J. 1995. The Media and Modernity: A Social theory of the Media. Cambridge: Polity.
Vidhu Verma
Centre for Political Studies, School for Social Sciences, Jawaharlal Nehru University
[email protected]
© 2015, Vidhu Verma
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/23269995.2015.1070512