South African Journal on Human Rights
ISSN: 0258-7203 (Print) 1996-2126 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjhr20
Focus: The Constitutional Court's 1999 Term
Andrew J Burrow , Jeremy Sarkin , Esther Steyn , Dirk van Zyl Smit , Ron
Paschke , Ronald Louw , Mohamed Alli Chicktay , Penelope Andrews ,
Shireen Motara , Stuart Woolman , Allen Leuta , Kirsty Mclean , Mabatho
Nteleki , Jack Phalane , Andrew Smith & Jonathan Klaaren
To cite this article: Andrew J Burrow , Jeremy Sarkin , Esther Steyn , Dirk van Zyl Smit , Ron
Paschke , Ronald Louw , Mohamed Alli Chicktay , Penelope Andrews , Shireen Motara , Stuart
Woolman , Allen Leuta , Kirsty Mclean , Mabatho Nteleki , Jack Phalane , Andrew Smith &
Jonathan Klaaren (2000) Focus: The Constitutional Court's 1999 Term, South African Journal on
Human Rights, 16:2, 283-371, DOI: 10.1080/02587203.2000.11827597
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/02587203.2000.11827597
Published online: 02 Feb 2017.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 6
View related articles
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rjhr20
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL
COURT'S 1999 TERM
REGULATING THE NEW NATIONAL ECONOMY
Ex PARTE PRESIDENT OF THE REPUBLIC OF SOUTH AFRICA:
IN RE CONSTITUTIONALITY OF THE LIQUOR BILL
I INTRODUCTION
As one learns to expect in constitutional law, matters of the greatest
importance for a country's constitutional, political and economic life
often arrive at court dressed in the drabbest factual garments. Putting this
consideration aside and at the risk of exaggeration, the core issue in the
Liquor Bill case was nothing less than the continued economic unity of
South Africa. Against the backdrop of the creation in recent years of the
new economy (characterised by the advent of black-empowerment
initiatives, public-private partnerships and efforts at privatisation of
state-owned assets), the national government's much-needed powers
of regulation were about to be tested and defined.
What the Liquor Bill 131 of 1998 - introduced in the National
Assembly on 31 August 1998- sought to achieve was summarised for the
Court by Cameron AJ in the following terms:
(a) the prohibition on cross-holdings between the three tiers involved in the liquor trade,
namely producers, distributors and retailers; (b) the establishment of uniform
conditions, in a single system, for the national registration of liquor manufacturers
and distributors; and, in a further attempt at establishing national uniformity within the
liquor trade, (c) the prescription of detailed mechanisms to provincial legislatures for
the establishment of retail licensing mechanisms. 1
The Bill sought to achieve these objects by dividing the liquor trade in
South Africa into three components: production, distribution (or
wholesale) and retail sales, and by requiring that any market participant
be registered with the appropriate authority in one of the three categories.
Two singular features of the proposed regime were, first, that no
applicant could apply for registration in more than one of the three
industry components and, second, that while registration for production
and distribution would be the responsibility of a national entity, the
National Liquor Authority, whose members would be appointed by
the Minister, registration for retail sales would be the responsibility of
provincial liquor authorities. Even in this case, however, the Bill set out in
some detail the duties of the provincial authority when considering retail
I Ex parte President of the Republic of South Africa: In re Constitutionality of the Liquor Bi/12000
(I) SA 732 (CC) para 69 (Liquor Bill).
283
284
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
sale licence applications? The clear intention behind these measures, as
stated in the Minister of Trade and Industry's affidavit, was to allow new
entrants into the market, particularly from previously disadvantaged
communities, by preventing the excessive concentration of economic
power in the hands of the few. 3
When the Bill was sent to the President for his assent, he referred it back
to the National Assembly for reconsideration in accordance with s 79(1) of
the 1996 Constitution,4 citing reservations about the Bill's constitutionality. After having reconsidered the Bill, the National Assembly returned it
to the President, with no amendments having been made. For the first time
under the 1996 Constitution, the President then invoked his power under
s 84(2)(c) to send a Bill before the Constitutional Court for a decision on
its constitutionality. On the invitation of the President of the Court, the
Western Cape government stated that it wished to be represented and to
present affidavit evidence as to why it was not necessary that national
legislation regulate the liquor trade in pursuit of any of the goals ins 44(2)
of the 1996 Constitution. 5 The Minister of Trade and Industry, as
representative of the government of the Republic of South Africa, also
wished to be represented and to supply evidence of the necessity of such
legislation in light of the requirements of s 44(2).
This note will examine the Liquor Bill case in the context of the need
for economic transformation in South Africa and will suggest how its
outcome, with its broad reading of national regulatory powers, might
facilitate that transformation. Furthermore, anyone familiar with US
constitutional jurisprudence must be struck by the similarities in the
issues raised, in reasoning, and even in the occasional turn of phrase,
between the Court's judgment in this case and that of Chief Justice
Marshall in the early, and justly famous, case of Gibbons v Ogden 6 before
the US Supreme Court. With this in mind, a comparative review will be
undertaken to see whether the outcome in that case, albeit in a very
different constitutional context, can tell us anything about what to expect
from the outcome of the Liquor Bill case. 7
2
3
4
5
Ibid para 79.
Ibid para 34.
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 108 of 1996 (1996 Constitution).
This section provides:
(2) Parliament may intervene, by passing legislation in accordance with section 76( I), with
regard to a matter falling within a functional area listed in Schedule 5, when it is necessary(a) to maintain national security;
(b) to maintain economic unity;
(c) to maintain essential national standards;
(d) to establish minimum standards required for the rendering of services; or
(e) to prevent unreasonable action taken by a province which is prejudicial to the interests
of another province or to the country as a whole.
6 6 L Ed 23 ( 1824). All references to this case in this note are to the extracts of the opinion
reproduced in G Gunther Constitutional Law 12 ed (1991) 94.
7 Apart from the core issue of whether or not the Liquor Bill was constitutional, the decision also
had to grapple with novel problems concerning the scope and purpose of the referral procedure
itself. This note will not address those issues.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
285
The central issue before the Constitutional Court, simply put, was the
capacity of the national legislature (Parliament) to assert control over
certain aspects of the economy which are potentially also subject to
provincial control under Schedules 4 and 5 of the 1996 Constitution.
Specifically, the case pitted the national legislature's (concurrently held)
competence with regard to trade and industrial promotion (Schedule 4A
of the 1996 Constitution) against the exclusive legislative competence
held by provincial governments with regard to liquor licences
(Schedule 5A of the 1996 Constitution). 8 Setting aside, for purposes of
this note, the procedural challenge to the Bill, the essence of the
constitutional challenge was that the provincial legislatures were excluded
from having any say in the licensing of producers and distributors and
that too much national intervention in retail licensing was permitted
under the Bill. The Province contended that the Bill's chosen regime
intruded upon the Provinces' exclusive legislative domain in the
'functional area of "liquor licences" '. 9
The Constitutional Court, per Cameron AJ, held that in respect of the
production and distribution aspects of the liquor industry, the regime
established by the Bill was constitutional in that the object sought (the
prohibition on cross-holdings in the liquor trade) fell within the national
legislature's competence to regulate trade. The means chosen to effect this
(the registration or licensing system) was a 'necessary' measure to
'maintain economic unity' in terms of s 44(2) of the 1996 Constitution.
Regarding the Bill's measures pertaining to the retail sale aspect of the
trade, however, the Court held that, as this licensing competence clearly
fell within the exclusive ambit of the provincial legislatures, and as the
Minister had not persuaded the Court of the necessity of national
regulation in this sphere, they were unjustified. To this extent, the Bill was
held to be unconstitutional.
II THE COURT'S ANALYSIS OF NATIONAL REGULATORY POWERS
Before delving into the Court's substantive analysis of the various strands
of argument, it is important to note one highly satisfying aspect of
Cameron AJ's judgment in this case: the kind of historical and economic
analysis he endorsed. It is possible that a decision based on narrow legal
principles which ignored either the country's (and the liquor trade's)
racialised past or the need for an integrated economy in the future, might
have had disastrous consequences. Noting that 'liquor licensing has a
shameful history in this country's racial past', and that 'liquor acted as
a means of social control since it was an offence for a black person to be
8 'The question', stated Cameron AJ, 'is whether the substance of this legislation falls within
the excluded field of "liquor licences", in which case the justifications itemised in s 44(2) [of the
1996 Constitution] will have to be shown; or whether it falls within a permitted competence of
Parliament even without such justification.' Liquor Bill (note I above) para 68.
9 Ibid para 36.
286
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
in possession of liquor outside the designated areas', 10 the Court detailed
the various measures by which the production, distribution and sale of
liquor had been controlled along racial lines. 11 The Minister of Trade and
Industry asserted, no doubt with this background in mind, that the
objectives of the Bill included 'erasing the history of the use of liquor as
an instrument of control over most of the population as part of the policy
of apartheid', and 'making the liquor industry more accessible to
historically disadvantaged groups' . 12 It is easy enough to understand that
against the background mentioned above, the ownership interests in all
three areas of the liquor trade (production, distribution and sale) are
predominantly in the hands of white capital. At least as much as the need
for continued (and improved) economic unity in the country, it was the
need to ensure more equal participation in all spheres of the economy
that made the outcome of this case so vital. The need for equal
participation is also, in my view, the driving force behind the national
government's concern to have certain elements of the economy regulated
at the national, as opposed to the provincial, level.
Cameron AJ, invoking the first provision of the 1996 Constitution,
immediately began his substantive analysis with an affirmation of the fact
that South Africa is 'one, sovereign, democratic State'Y Then, in a move
reminiscent of the great Chief Justice of the United States, John
Marshall, whenever he was about to limit States' rights or condone an
exercise of federal power, Cameron AJ quickly placated the provinces by
pointing out that this 'unitarian emphasis' 14 is not absolute in that
governmental power in South Africa is distributed between the national,
provincial and local spheres of government, and that the provinces are
allocated specific legislative areas in which they have either concurrent
competence (shared with the national government) or exclusive
competence. Not even the later mention of the Court's statement in the
First Certification judgment to the effect that the inclusion in the 1996
Constitution of a category of exclusive powers gave the provinces more
powers than they had under the interim Constitution, 15 however, could
disguise the fact that, fundamentally, the provinces are in a relatively
10 Ibid para 31.
II The judgment of Cameron AJ begins its investigation with the coming into being of the Union
of South Africa in 1910. A brief review of South Africa's history before Union, however,
confirms that the use of liquor as a means of social control, had roots even before that date.
Frank Welsh, discussing the deteriorating political conditions for blacks in the Cape during the
late nineteenth century in A History of South Africa (1998) 294, says of a disenfranchisement
measure- the 1887 Registration Act- that it 'was the first act of a long-drawn-out destruction
of non-white political rights, continued in 1898 with the Liquor Act, which banned the sale of
alcohol to "Aboriginal Natives", while allowing it to Coloureds'.
12 Liquor Bill para 31.
13 Ibid para 40.
14 Ibid para 40.
15 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution). See Ex
parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the
Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) para 335, cited in Liquor Bill (note I
above) para 49.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
287
weak position, and that the division of governmental power in South
Africa is heavily weighted in favour of central government.
After setting out the various allocations of powers and functions to
national and provincial governments, Cameron AJ came to the
conclusion that the 'list of exclusive competences in Schedule 5 must
therefore be given meaning within the context of the constitutional
scheme that accords Parliament extensive power encompassing "any
matter" excluding only the provincial exclusive competences' . 16 With a
few more steps, the end result would almost be in sight: the 'new
philosophy' 17 of co-operative government notwithstanding, provinces
and their allocation of certain legislative competences would not be
allowed to stand in the way of the national government's important
function of ensuring a unitary and more distributive economy. How
would the Court reconcile the concurrent competences under
Schedule 4A with respect to trade and industrial promotion with the
exclusive provincial competence under Schedule 5A with regard to liquor
licences? And what would it make of the Bill's apparent recognition of
the national/provincial distribution of power in its division of the liquor
trade into three distinct categories regulated by either national or
provincial authorities?
Noting that the legislative competences in Schedules 4 and 5 of the
Constitution are designated 'functional areas', Cameron AJ made
the important jump to evaluating the constitutional legitimacy of the Bill
by the appropriateness of different kinds of action by either national or
provincial spheres of government. 18 This inevitably involved a valuebased adjudication which, although enabled or assisted by the detailed
provisions of s 146 of the 1996 Constitution regulating conflicts between
national and provincial legislation, was still a bold undertaking
considering that the objects of the evaluation are governmental
authority, on the one hand, and vital aspects of the national economy,
on the other. In giving meaning to the functional area of 'trade', included
in Schedule 4 to the 1996 Constitution, the Court thus adopted a broad
definition that recognised the original connotation of travel included in
the term and its tendency to cut across provincial boundaries. The Court
also accepted that the only limitations on the term (and thus on the
functional area) were those that were to be found in the 1996
Constitution itself; there were no inherent limitations which limited the
national legislative competence either geographically or to certain aspects
of the trade. The result of this line of reasoning was that, by their nature
as nationally based activities, the production and distribution of liquor
16 Liquor Bill para 47.
17 Ibid para 40.
18 'The Constitution-makers' allocation of powers to the national and provincial spheres appears
to have proceeded from a functional vision of what was appropriate to each sphere and,
accordingly, the competences itemised in Schedules 4 and 5 are referred to as being in respect
of "functional areas". The ambit of the provinces' exclusive powers must, in my view, be
determined in the light of that vision.' Ibid para 51.
288
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
were more amenable to national regulation (by Parliament) and were
thus held to fall within the concurrent competences of 'trade' and
'industrial promotion'. The 'necessity' element of s 44(2) was provided by
the Minister's ecooomic rationale that fragmentation of the industry, as
well as inter-provincial 'arbitrage' should be avoided. 19
The Court, however, recognising that 'the substance of a particular
piece of legislation may not be capable of a single characterization
only', 20 then ·determined that the Constitution made provision for
exclusive provincial legislative power only in regard to matters that did
not extend beyond the provincial boundaries. In this way, it could hold
that retail sales, which by and large were wholly internal matters, clearly
fell within the Schedule 5A exclusive competence of 'liquor licences'. To
the extent that the nascent legislation tried to regulate this aspect of the
trade, it was held to be unconstitutional. It is submitted that not only is
this finding consonant with the internal logic of the decision, but it is also
correct as a matter of broader constitutional interpretation and public
policy. It seems perfectly acceptable that provincial governments, which
are by and large more in touch with local cultural and religious
sensitivities and needs, have the ability to regulate the sale of liquor. By
the same reasoning that was used to hold that retail sales were an
exclusive provincial competence, production and distribution, precisely
because they have a national (and international) focus, could not be
conveniently encompassed by this functional area. 21
III COMPARATIVE AND HISTORICAL REFLECTIONS
This brings us to the comparative section of this note. Although it is
worth bearing in mind the admonition that foreign, and particularly
American, constitutional case law will frequently be irrelevant to the
development of South African constitutional jurisprudence, 22 it is
obviously worth examining such jurisprudence when its consequences
have been fully fleshed out after 175 years and the judgement of history
can be examined. In this context, this note will briefly examine the US
Supreme Court's decision in Gibbons v Ogden. 23 Under art 1 of the
19 Ibid para 77.
20 Ibid para 62.
2I Without keeping the social dimension of national regulation in mind (ie the need to ensure
diversification of market participants and encourage, in particular, black empowerment), it
could be claimed that Cameron AJ too readily grouped production and distribution together.
Whereas distribution almost invariably is a national undertaking, most liquor production, by
his own admission, is contained within a few provinces (ibid para 72). Why should the Western
Cape government, after all, not know its own wine producers (who are unlikely to be operative in
other provinces) best? It is submitted that in light of South Africa's specific history, the national
legislative body has been given the task of opening up the economy, and it is this body which can
'produce the goods', so to speak, more effectively than the government of the Western Cape or of
Gauteng for that matter. This would seem to be an implicit premise of the decision.
22 Richard Blake 'The Frequent Irrelevance of US Judicial Decisions in South Africa: National
Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice 1999 (I) SA 6 (CC)' (1999) 15
SAJHR 192.
23 Note 6 above.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
289
US Constitution, Congress has the power to 'regulate Commerce with
foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian
Tribes'. This explicit delegation of power to the federal government is
important because the US constitutional division of authority (between
the United States and the several States) is the opposite of that in South
Africa: the so-called 'commerce clause', the Tenth Amendment (1791),
clearly states that 'The powers not delegated to the United States by the
Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States
respectively, or to the people.' In other words, federal power was, at the
beginning in any event, rather more limited than that of the States.
Gibbons v Ogden was the first time the Supreme Court had had to
interpret this rather obscure clause. The respondent in the case operated a
ferry in New York and New Jersey under a monopoly granted by the
New York legislature. When the appellant began operating a rival ferry
service, licensed under a federal statute, in the same waters, a New York
court granted the respondent an injunction barring the appellant from
operating his ferries in New York. Against the background of
deteriorating relations between all the involved States (including the
passage of legislation authorising the seizure of vessels licensed in New
York), the case eventually found its way to the Supreme Court under the
Chief Justiceship of John Marshall. The essential questions to be
answered were as follows: what was interstate commerce and what
activities did it cover? To what extent could Congress regulate this
commerce, however defined, and what did this delegation of power do to
the States? 24
Marshall, in much the same way as Cameron AJ would do 175 years
later, began by looking to the object for which a specific power was given? 5
Once it was established that this object was 'commerce', for which Marshall
proceeded to give an expansive definition, covering all forms of trading and
'commercial intercourse' (and clearly including navigation), he was then
able to define the power to regulate it in a similarly broad manner. In his
eloquent prose, he asked and answered his own question thus:
[We] are now arrived at the inquiry- What is this power? It is the power to regulate; that
is, to prescribe the rule by which commerce is to be governed. This power, like all others
vested in congress, is complete in itself, may be exercised to its utmost extent, and
acknowledges no limitations, other than are prescribed in the constitution. 26
Congress could exercise this power wherever its object, in this case
commerce, was to be found. That commerce, and navigation in
24 For this summary of the case and the constitutional questions it raised, I am indebted to
Gunther (note 6 above) 94 and to RG McCloskey The American Supreme Court 2 ed (rev ed
S Levinson, 1994) 45.
25 Rejecting the notion that the commerce clause should be restrictively interpreted, Marshall held
that if, 'from the imperfection of human language, there should be serious doubts respecting the
extent of any given power, it is a well settled rule, that the objects for which it was given, especially
when those objects are expressed in the instrument itself, should have great influence in the
construction.' Gibbons v Ogden, as reproduced in Gunther (note 6 above) 95.
26 Ibid 96.
290
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
particular, often cut across State boundaries was obvious and the power
to regulate it could thus also be exercised across these boundaries and in
the interior of the States. The only exception, the Court reasoned, was
commerce that was entirely internal in a given State. That remained
beyond Congress's power to regulate. Once again, the similarity between
Marshall's reasoning and that of Cameron AJ is striking: the latter also
held that matters which were by nature provincial or non-national fell to
be regulated by the provincial legislatures. Included in this category were
micro-manufacturers and retailers 27 - just the sort of enterprises
Marshall might have concluded were subject to the States' reserved
powers. The result in Gibbons was that the New York law was held to be
invalid and the monopoly was ended.
Of course, the vast constitutional differences between the early United
States and modern South Africa must be considered. What is remarkable
in the comparison of the two cases is precisely that, despite the inverse
starting points regarding national regulatory power, they managed to
arrive at similar results, justifying exercises of federal/central power at the
expense of States' rights and provincial powers. How did this occur and
what can Gibbons tell us about what to expect in the wake of the Liquor
Bill case? The US Constitution had been adopted with the experience of
competing States fresh in the mind of the drafters. In fact, the need to end
inter-state feuding and tariff wars was recognised as vital to the
continuation of the Union. With Gibbons, the steamboat business
rapidly expanded and helped ensure the subsequent economic development of the United States. Had the Supreme Court decided that the
federal states were entitled to regulate such matters by giving the commerce clause an exceedingly narrow ambit, it is difficult to imagine
America today bearing any resemblance to what it is: a great economic
power. 28 Although the direct relevance of Gibbons may be difficult to
deduce at first glance, the following points should be considered. First,
South Africa's background is not one of inter-provincial strife, but it is
certainly one of huge economic inequalities and lack of access to
economic opportunity for the majority of people. Second, a monopoly,
such as was operative in the dispute underlying Gibbons, is itself a kind of
economic inequality which hampers future economic development and
which governments, even today, are loathe to tolerate. Third, with the
current provincial distribution of power, it is not inconceivable that in the
future, provinces may be tempted to interfere with the trade of neighbouring provinces in some measure. However, the comparison operates
at a deeper level than these similarities: both inter-state economic strife
and socio-economic disparities, are by their nature national issues
requiring national intervention and regulation. It is therefore welcome
27 Liquor Bill paras 80 and 83.
28 JE Smith John Marshall: Definer of a Nation (1996) 481, provides a comprehensive account of
how the decision rapidly helped fuel economic expansion and, eventually, political unity.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
291
that the Court has recognised 'that where a matter requires regulation
inter-provincially, as opposed to intra-provincially, the Constitution
ensures that national government has been accorded the necessary power,
whether exclusively or concurrently under Schedule 4, or through the
powers of intervention accorded by s 44(2)'. 29 Thus, the differing
constitutional contexts notwithstanding, both courts recognised the
over-arching political and economic imperatives involved and ensured
that, to the extent provided for in the respective constitutions, the central
governments were able to carry out their mandates. 30
IV
CONCLUSION
What then do we make of the Liquor Bill case? While this note may have
seemed to suggest at times that the validation of national power is a goal
to be pursued at all costs, and that this was what the Court held, this
notion should be corrected. The Court was clear that it would assign
meanings to exclusive provincial legislative competences every bit as full
and expansive as it did to (concurrent) national powers, within the
confines of the 1996 Constitution. Furthermore, it would apply the same
functional approach to determining what was appropriate to provincial
regulation. Cameron AJ also accepted the contention by the Western
Cape government that differences between provincial regulation in the
appropriate areas were in fact desirable. 31 However, it should be
recognised that the social and economic ills to be addressed by
government in South Africa are of such proportions that only regulation
at the national level will, in many instances, be sufficient. While the
government's ability single-handedly to create jobs and opportunity in
the liquor industry may be limited, by ensuring that the relevant market
participants, producers and distributors, are subject to a uniform,
national system of regulation, it will enable this industry to grow in a
relatively unencumbered manner. Furthermore, new market entrants on
a national level will not face the daunting prospect of multi-province
licensing ordeals. If Gibbons v Ogden was destined to become known as
'the emancipation proclamation of American commerce', 32 then the
29 Liquor Bill para 52.
30 Ibid para 82.
31 Of course, Gibbons is nowhere mentioned in the judgment of Cameron AJ and we might want
to speculate about this. Frankly, I find it hard to imagine he has not read the decision. If this is
so, why then not mention it? This would admittedly be a rather unusual use of foreign case
law, as is shown by the trouble the present author has had in justifying the comparative
exercise. There are at least two potential problems: first, the possibly grating idea of a South
African court 'following' American jurisprudence in such a sensitive area as socio-economic
policy; and, second, the narrow way in which we usually view the comparative enterprise. At
present I will not take these ideas any further, but I believe they are both fruitful avenues to
explore in the future. Of course, if I am wrong and Cameron AJ has never heard of Gibbons,
then my thesis, such as it is (ie, that two very different Courts, perceiving similarly broad
problems, will adopt similar approaches), is possibly strengthened.
32 C Warren History of the American Bar (1911) 396, quoted in Smith (note 28 above) 473.
292
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Liquor Bill case may in time become known in South African
constitutional jurisprudence as the new national economy's opportunity
charter of distributive justice.
ANDREW J BURROW*
Legal Assistant to Judge Gaetano Arangio-Ruiz
Iran-United States Claims Tribunal, The Hague
THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S BAIL DECISION: INDIVIDUAL LIBERTY
IN CRISIS?
S
V DLAMINI
I INTRODUCTION
Long, long ago, a Constitution to guarantee, for an interim period, rights
for all in the new South Africa was adopted by the last Parliament of the
old minority regime.' Many, even those who had been skeptical about
Utopian claims for constitutionalism, were impressed by the rights
guarantees contained in the interim Constitution. They were equally
pleased when most of these guarantees were repeated in the 1996
Constitution. 2 They literally and figuratively clutched breast-pocket
versions of the Constitution to their hearts and shared their newfound
belief in constitutionalism with their colleagues, their students and their
friends. Lovers of liberty, equality and human dignity were further
emboldened to hail the new dispensation by early decisions of the new
Constitutional Court to abolish the death penalty3 and corporal punishment,4 and to deny the constitutionality of reverse onus provisions in
statutes creating criminal offences. 5 Especially heartening about these
early decisions was the demonstration of a firm commitment not to be
swayed by contrary popular opinion, but to apply fearlessly the wide
range of rights that the Constitution manifestly guaranteed.
• Thanks to Felco Szabo and Tom Ginsburg for comments on an earlier version of this note. All
mistakes are, of course, my own.
I Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution).
2 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 108 of 1996 (1996 Constitution). On the
1996 Constitution and its drafting see, further, Jeremy Sarkin 'Innovations it) the Interim
and 1996 South African Constitutions' (June 1998) The Review 57; 'The Development of a
Human Rights Culture in South Africa' (1998) 20 Human Rights Q 628; 'The Drafting of the
Final South African Constitution from a Human Rights Perspective' (1999) 47 American J of
Comparative L 67 and 'The Effect of Constitutional Borrowings on the Drafting of South
Africa's Interim Bill of Rights and the Role Played by Comparative and International Law in
the Interpretation of Human Rights Provisions by the South African Constitutional Court'
(1998) I J of Constitutional L 176.
3 S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC).
4 S v Williams 1995 (3) SA 632 (CC).
5 SeeS v Zuma 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC), S v Bhulwana 1996 (I) SA 388 (CC), S v Mbatha 1996 (2)
SA 464 (CC), S v Julies 1996 (4) SA 313 (CC), Scagel/ v Attorney-General. Western Cape 1997
(2) SA 368 (CC), S v Coetzee 1997 (3) SA 527 (CC), S v Ntsele 1997 (II) BCLR 1543 (CC) and
S v Mello 1998 (3) SA 712 (CC).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
293
Many, even academic lawyers, overlooked the early indication by a
majority of the Constitutional Court in S v Mhlungu 6 that it would
readily depart from the literal meaning of the words of the Constitution if
it believed that there were compelling reasons for doing so. 7 Or, if the
judgment was noted disapprovingly, it was passed over as the product of
a new court that was still settling down and that had been carried away
by its enthusiasm for the wider values that the Constitution undoubtedly
appeared to guarantee. At issue in Mhlungu was the interpretation of an
unusual interim provision; many hoped that this sort of aberration would
not happen again under the 1996 Constitution. Moreover, the departure
from the text was, so it appeared, inspired by a deep commitment to the
value of individual liberty, an impression that allowed some scholars to
come to the defence of the majority decision in Mhlungu and the style of
constitutional interpretation it represented. 8
A scant four years after Mhlungu, the Constitutional Court has again
overlooked the clear meaning of words- not only in the Bill of Rights but
also in the legislation it was evaluating. It has done so not to protect
liberty but to allow the limitation of the most fundamental of liberty
rights. A unanimous Court judged as constitutionally valid, legislation
that allows- with qualifications, but nevertheless allows- the violation of
the right to bail and therefore the continued detention of persons who are
suspected but have not been convicted of any criminal offence. In doing
so, it appears to have succumbed to the panic and hysteria that exists
about crime in South Africa. 9
How did the Constitutional Court come to deal with current bail
legislation in the way that it did? We propose to address this question by
analysing the decision in S v Dlamini; S v Diad/a; S v Joubert; S v
Schietekat 10 (Dlamini) in some detail. The scene is set, first, by describing
the current social context of crime and fear of crime and, secondly, by
outlining South African bail law and the most recent legislative
amendments. We then describe the grounds of constitutional attack in
Dlamini and note some aspects of the judgment that seem to us to be
unproblematic. Detailed attention is then paid to the three provisions
that seem to us to be open to constitutional attack. They are the
allowance made by the legislation for community reaction to possible bail
decisions; the provision for denying bail in serious cases; and the
enactment on the admissibility at a subsequent trial of the evidence that
accused persons give at their own bail hearings. In this analysis, we
consider what appear to us to be the major difficulties of this judgment,
6 1995 (3) SA 857 (CC).
7 See Eduard Fagan 'The Longest Erratum Note in History' (1996) 12 SAJHR 79.
8 Dennis Davis 'The Twist of Language and the Two Fagans: Please Sir May I Have Some
More Literalism!' (1996) 12 SAJHR 504 and Jacques de Ville 'Eduard Fagan in Context'
(1997) 12 SAPL 491.
9 Jeremy Sarkin 'Panic Over Crime Could Poison South Africa' Democracy in Action (March
1996) 17.
10 1999 (4) SA 623 (CC).
294
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
namely the Court's deference to public perceptions about the crime
problem in South Africa and attitudes towards bail, and the mode of
interpretation applied to the legislation that it was required to examine.
We attempt to show how these two factors combined to produce the
result that they did and analyse the specific outcomes that we believe to
be problematic. Finally, we suggest that the conclusions reached by the
Court on the bail legislation are not only destructive of the fundamental
values of the Constitution that the Court has purported to uphold, but
are also not the solution to South Africa's crime problem. 11
II
CRIME AND THE FEAR OF CRIME
The issue of crime obviously played an influential role in the reasoning of
the Court in Dlamini. In the words of the Court:
over the last few years our society has experienced a deplorable level of violent crime,
particularly murder, armed robbery, assault and rape, including sexual assault on
children. Nor can there be any doubt that the effect of widespread violent crime is deeply
destructive of the fabric of our society and that accordingly all steps that can reasonably
be taken to curb violent crime must be taken ... it is against this background that we
should assess the ... [baillegislation]. 12
Steven Donzinger, commenting on the disproportionate role that fear of
crime plays in determining American criminal justice policy, states:
There is nothing more viscerally disturbing than the fear of being a victim of violent
crime. Much of that fear has a legitimate basis in fact, for violent street crime is a real
threat, particularly in the inner city. Yet fear of crime rather than crime itself drives much
criminal justice policy in the United States. Fear of crime and crime are not the same
thing. Policies based upon fear are not the same as policies based upon fact. 13
These comments are equally applicable in South Africa. One factor that
accounts for the difference between the fear of crime and its incidence is
the way in which crime is portrayed by the media. Newspaper headlines
and bloody front-page pictures present a distorted view by focusing on
particular violent incidents. People become scared when they personalise
these stories in their minds and fear that they may be next. Individuals
(including judges) thus tend to exaggerate the crime problem.
Crime in South Africa did increase dramatically in 1990, the year when
the transition to democracy began. 14 Levels of crime increased further
across the board between 1990 and 1994. From 1994 to 1998, however, the
per capita incidence of violent crimes reported by the police either remained
unchanged or decreased. 15 These statistics, it is true, may be under11 See also Esther Steyn Witnesses in South Africa. the Stepchildren of the Criminal Justice System
(unpublished LLM Dissertation, University of Cape Town, 1999) 56-74.
12 Dlamini para 67.
13 S Donzinger (ed) The Real War on Crime - The Report of the National Criminal Justice
Commission (1996) 97.
14 M Shaw Crime and Policy in Post-Apartheid South Africa (1998) 24.
15 The Incidence of Serious Crime January to December 1998 Semester Report I /99 South African
Police Services (SAPS), Crime and Information Analysis Centre (CIAC) 3.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
295
reporting the actual amount of crime, but as the primary 'hard facts'
available they need to be taken seriously. Certainly, both the question of
what these figures mean and the wider issue of what weight the
Constitutional Court should attach to crime trends require careful
attention before any conclusions can be drawn from them. This is not to
deny that current crime rates are alarming and that victims, particularly
of violent crime, are not receiving the support and protection that are
needed.
III
SOUTH AFRICAN BAIL LAw
South African law has long recognised the procedural device of bail as a
means of striking a balance between the liberty interest of a person
detained on the suspicion of having committed an offence and the interest
of society that requires that such a person should stand trial. 16
Underlying the need for bail is the presumption of innocence, which
requires that an innocent person should not be deprived of his or her
liberty. 17 Internationally, bail has long been recognised as an expression
of the fundamental principle of presumption of innocence. 18 This
principle has been recognised historically in South African common
law, in the law of other major jurisdictions 19 and in internationallaw?0
As a result of this presumption, courts have traditionally granted bail
whenever possible and tried to lean in favour of the liberty of the accused,
provided that it is in the 'interests of justice' to do so. 21 This approach
was robustly expressed by Van Zijl AJP inS v Budlender: 22
16 SeeS v Budlender 1973 (I) SA 264 (C), 269.
17 See J Vander Berg Bail~
a Practitioner's Guide (1986) 1:
Pre-trial incarceration presents a special problem. An accused is being deprived of his liberty
in circumstances where no court of law has pronounced him guilty and the presumption of
innocence operates in favour of the accused. But at the same time there is a possible risk ~
and in many instances a very real risk~
that an accused who is released pending trial might
abscond. The procedural device known as 'bail' attempts to strike a balance between these
competing criminal justice interests.
18 This presumption has been recognised since at least 1789. For example, art 9 of the French
Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen began with the words: 'Every man being
counted innocent until he has been pronounced guilty, if it is thought indispensable to arrest
him, all severity that may not be necessary to secure his person ought to be strictly suppressed
by law.' Scholars such like HJ Berman maintain that this French doctrine was originally
intended to operate, primarily, at the stage of investigation: 'The Presumption of Innocence:
Another Reply' (1980) 28 American J of Comparative L 615 at 622.
19 See Stack v Boyle 342 US I (1951) 6, where Vinson CJ stated with reference to the right of bail,
'this traditional right to freedom before conviction permits the unhampered preparation of a
defence, and serves to prevent the infliction of punishment prior to conviction. Unless this
right to bail before the trial is preserved, the presumption of innocence, secured only after
centuries of struggle, would lose its meaning.'
20 In Krause v Switzerland (7986/77) DR 13, 73 the European Commission of Human Rights
stated in a similar vein that the principle of the presumption of innocence is in the first instance
a procedural guarantee applying to all aspects of criminal procedure. Its application therefore
reaches much further than just the trial.
21 S v Smith 1969 (4) SA 175 (N) 17E~F.
22 Note 16 above, 269E~F.
296
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
The Courts do not like ever to deprive a man of his freedom while awaiting trial. He may
be innocent, and then it would be very wrong. Also, even if he is guilty, we try not to
deprive him of his freedom until he has been convicted. After all, even if you are sitting in
gaol awaiting trial under the most favourable conditions in the gaol you are nevertheless
deprived of your freedom.
Herbert Packer's crime control and due process models of how crime is
dealt with provide a useful theoretical basis for understanding the fundamentally different attitudes to bail that exist in society. 23 In the crime
control model, liberty is and should be kept to a minimum and pre-trial
liberty should not become the norm. In the due process model, however,
the basic point of departure is that there is a right to pre-trial liberty. A
clear distinction must be maintained between the status of an accused
who is awaiting trial and one who has been formally found guilty by a
court of law. Constitutional law emphasises the importance of due
process and is therefore designed to keep in check excesses that may
result in too great an emphasis on crime control.
Under South African common law, bail applications were regarded as
sui generis and the onus was on accused persons to show on a balance of
probabilities that they should be released?4 The interim Constitution
spelt out detainees' rights more specifically. In terms of s 25(2)(d) of the
interim Constitution, every person arrested for the alleged commission of
an offence had the right 'to be released from detention with or without
bail, unless the interests of justice require otherwise'.
The interpretation and application of these rights initially caused some
confusion amongst members of the judiciary. This was particularly so in
relation to the interpretation of the 'interests of justice' and the incidence
of the onus in a bail application. 25
(a) The 1995 amendment
Fortunately, much of the initial confusion was clarified in 1995 when the
legislature amended s 60 of the Criminal Procedure Act 55 of 1977 to fit
the constitutional norm in s 25(2)(d) of the interim Constitution?6 The
legislature did not set out a closed list of instances defining 'interests of
justice' but left the list open-ended to leave room for judicial
interpretation. 27 The 1995 amendment emphasised that presiding
23 H Packer The Limits of the Criminal Sanction (I 968) 149-173.
24 SeeS v Hlongwa 1979 (4) SA 112 (D). Even the common law, however, was criticised on this
ground.
25 On the onus, see Ellish v Prokureur-Generaal, Witwatersrandse Plaaslike Afdeling 1994 (2)
SACR 579 (W); Magana v District Magistrate, Johannesburg ( 1) 1994 (2) SACR 304 (W);
S v Mbe/e 1996 (I) SACR 212 (W); Prokureur-Generaal van die Witwatersrandse Plaaslike
Afdeling v Van Heerden 1994 (2) SACR 469 (W); Prokureur-Generaal, Vrystaat v Ramokhosi
1997 (I) SACR 127 (0); S v Vermaas 1996 (I) SACR 528 (T). On 'interests of justice', seeS v
De Kock 1995 (1) SACR 299 (T); S v Dhlamini 1997 (1) SACR 54 (W); S v Tshabalala 1998 (2)
SACR 259 (C).
26 Criminal Procedure Second Amendment Act 75 of 1995.
27 See P M Bekker 'Interpretation of the Right to Bail and the Limitation Clause of the
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa' (1994) 57 THRHR 490; L C Kotze 'Wat is die
huidige posisie by 'n aansoek om borgtog deur 'n gearresteerde in die lig van die nuwe
(2000) 16 SAJHR
297
officers should acknowledge their new roles and functions in dealing with
bail applications, 28 and that every presiding officer should consider what
effect the release of the detainee would have on the 'interests of justice'.
Important from the perspective of crime control was that it was no longer
required of judicial officers to act as neutral umpires in bail hearings.
Instead they were obliged to act inquisitorially and investigate each
matter. 29 A further desirable innovation was that the 1995 amendments
provided guidance for judicial officers where previously little was
available.
The 1995 amendment introduced a new subsection, s 60(11), which
caused some controversy because it created a reverse onus. In cases where
the accused had allegedly committed a Schedule 5 offence, or had
allegedly re-committed a Schedule 1 offence while out on bail, the
accused was required to satisfy the court that the 'interests of justice'
did not require their detention in custody. From the wording of the
legislation it was clear that, in all other instances, the state bore the onus
of proving that the accused should not be released from detention. By
international standards, the 1995 amendments were strict measures. They
provided, for example, for the continued detention of someone who
might commit further crime rather than limiting pre-trial detention only
to those who might not stand trail or who might interfere with witnesses
or other preparations for the trial. Nevertheless, the provisions were
widely regarded as fair and as a constitutionally sound crime-control
measure. 30 In a positive sense the law offered the protection to all,
including victims and witnesses, that had been lacking after the inception
of the interim Constitution. One could have been forgiven for thinking
that the question of bail law had been settled.
(b) Bail and the 1996 Constitution
The 1996 Constitution, like the interim Constitution, also dealt with pretrial release. It made a subtle change, however. Where the 1993
Constitution recognised a right to be released unless the interest of
justice required otherwise, s 35(l)(f) referred to the right to be released
from detention if the interests of justice permit. In the context of a Bill of
Rights that was still replete with other references to individual freedom,
this subtle change may have seemed an insignificant product of the plain
English in which the 1996 Constitution was cast. It was, however, to
prove to be of considerable significance.
grondwet?' (1995) 30 The Magistrate 36; K Malan 'Die Grondwet en borgaansoeke' 1995
De Rebus 49; D J L Kotze 'Borgtog- artikel25(2)(d) van Wet 200 van 1993' 1994 De Jure 407;
M Cowling 'Criminal Procedure' (1995) 8 SACJ 239; M Cowling 'A Constitutional Right to
Bail' Human Rights & Constitutional LJ of Southern Africa 36.
28 See £//ish (note 25 above). This approach is confirmed by s 60(3) of the Criminal Procedure
Act, as introduced by Act 75 of 1995.
29 See s 60(3) of the Criminal Procedure Act, as introduced by Act 75 of 1995.
30 SeeM Schonteich A Case of a Good Law, its Bad Application and its Ugly Results (Institute of
Race Relations, 1997).
298
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURTS 1999 TERM
(c) The 1997 amendments
Despite the fact that adequate legislation was in place to protect the
rights of the community and that the wording of the Constitution had
been tightened, members of the South African public remained convinced
that the right to bail was to blame for the perceived increase in crime.
This belief was strengthened by one incident in particular, the 1997 rape
and murder of six-year old Mamokgethi Malebane. 31 The Mamokgethi
case sparked an outcry from the community that courts failed to protect
innocent victims, by granting bail to hardened criminals too readily. 32
Suggestions were made that the bail law should be tightened.
Government's response to these calls for vengeance was to amend the
bail law again by enacting the Criminal Procedure Second Amendment
Act 85 of 1997. It was these amendments that were to be the subject of the
Dlamini case.
IV
GROUNDS FOR CONSTITUTIONAL CHALLENGES
In Dlamini, the bail provisions of the Criminal Procedure Act (as
amended in 1997) were challenged on six grounds:
l. The constitutional right to bail was frustrated by the provision that
bail may be refused 'where in exceptional circumstances there is a
likelihood that the release of the accused will disturb the public order
or undermine the public peace.J 3 (the 'community reaction' ground).
2. Section 60(1l)(a) effectively denied bail to persons charged with
certain very serious offences by requiring them to adduce evidence
that 'exceptional circumstances' exist which in the 'interests of justice'
permit their release 34 (the 'very serious offence' ground).
3. Section 60(11 B)(c) unfairly made the bail record part of the trial
record 35 (the 'admissibility of the bail record' ground).
4. The bail amendments generally offended the separation of powers
doctrine and adversely affected judicial independence. 36
5. Access by the accused to the police docket was unreasonably
restricted. 37
6. Sections 60(4)(a) and 60(5) listed factors unrelated to trial. 38
31 Mamokgethi Malebane was abducted, raped and killed by Dan Mahote. shortly before she
had to testify against him in a rape trial. Mabotc had been released by the court on bail of
R2 000 despite the fact that the police were investigating two other charges of rape against him
and that the police had opposed the bail application. Sec 'Mamokgcthi: and justice for all?'
Weekly Mail & Guardian 31 July 1998.
32 Sec 'Justice betrayal of innocence' Weekly Mail and Guardian 9 May 1997 9: 'Selmaats slaan
man na moord op kind' Burga 2 August 1997 4.
33 Sections 60(4)(e) and 60(8A) of the Criminal Procedure Act, dealt with at paras 54- 57 of
Dlamini.
34 Section 60( II )(a). dealt with at paras 58-80.
35 Section 60( II B)(c). dealt with at paras 86 100.
36 Section 60(4)-(9). dealt with at paras 37-44.
37 Section 60(14). dealt with at paras 81 85.
38 Sections 60(4)(a) and 60(5). dealt with at paras 51-53.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
299
The manner in which the Constitutional Court dealt with the last three of
these grounds is unproblematic. However, we take issue with the way in
which the Court dealt with the first three grounds, namely the grounds of
constitutional attack relating to community reaction, very serious
offences and the admissibility of the bail record. Before analysing these
grounds, we need to consider briefly one preliminary matter that coloured
the approach of the Constitutional Court. As we have seen, the provision
in the 1996 Constitution dealing with release from pre-trial detention was
worded differently from its 1993 predecessor. The Constitutional Court
seized on this subtle shift. The use of 'if' rather than 'unless' was the basis
for a finding that the 1996 Constitution did not favour the liberty of the
accused to the extent that the interim Constitution had done. 39 This is a
very narrow interpretation that largely ignores both the common Jaw
presumption in favour of liberty and the wider constitutional protections
of individual liberty contained in s 12 of the 1996 Constitution. It reveals
a restrictive approach to liberty rights that also shapes the Court's
analysis of the challenges to the specific restrictions introduced by the
1997 amendments. It is to the most controversial of these amendments
that we now turn.
(a) Community Reaction
There can be little argument that community reaction should not decide
when a person should be detained or not. How then could a provision
that bail could be denied where 'in exceptional circumstances there is a
likelihood that the release of the accused will disturb the public order or
undermine the public peace' pass constitutional muster?
In Dlamini, the Court recognised the draconian and prima facie
unconstitutional nature of the Jaw but nevertheless upheld it. The Court
summarised the grounds for opposition to the provision as follows:
Looking at public opinion and taking into account the likely behaviour of persons other
than the detainee, so counsel suggested, smack of preventive detention and infringe a
detainee's liberty interest protected by s 35(1)(f) of the (1996) Constitution. Elevating the
sentiments of the community above the interests of the detainee is constitutionally
impermissible. There is force in the argument. Ordinarily, the factors identified in
s 60(4)(e) and (8A) would not be relevant in establishing whether the interests of justice
permit the release of the accused. It would be disturbing that an individual's legitimate
interests should so invasively be subjected to societal interests. It is indeed even more
disturbing where the two provisions do not postulate that the likelihood of public
disorder should in any way be laid at the door of the accused. The mere likelihood of such
disorder independently of any influence on the part of the accused would suffice. 40
39 Sec Dlamini paras 37-38. where Kriegler J holds that s 60(l)(a) of the Act was introduced
by the 1995 amendment to acknowledge the demands of s 25(1) of the interim Constitution.
As it was left unchanged by the 1997 amendment which was introduced after the 1996
Constitution was enacted. it "favours liberty more than the minimum required by the
[1996] Constitution·.
40 Paras 54-55.
300
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
The way the Court dealt with the matter was to find that although
ss 60(4)(e) and 60(8A) infringed a fundamental constitutional right, they
were, in terms of s 36 of the 1996 Constitution, a permissible limitation of
the right. The primary question is how the Court managed to convince
itself that this possibility could ever be acceptable in an open and
democratic society based on human dignity, freedom and equality. 41 The
answer is twofold. First, the Court made much of the crime rate and
the public's violent reaction to the perception that bail was being granted
too freely. Secondly, it noted that the courts had a discretion to apply this
provision, but that this discretion was shaped and indeed restricted by the
requirement that it was only to be exercised if there was a 'likelihood' of
such public reaction, and then only in 'exceptional circumstances'.
The first of these answers is highly suspect. The threat of a violent
public reaction should not be enough to justify an action that is otherwise
unconstitutional any more than public opinion may be used as such a
justification. In Makwanyane, Chaskalson P, considering the constitutionality of the death penalty, commented that public opinion was 'no
substitute for the duty vested in the Courts to interpret the Constitution
and to uphold its provisions without fear or favour'. 42 In the same way
that the threat of public lynchings was not enough to persuade the Court
to uphold the death sentence, it should not have had any persuasive
power in the case of bail. It is simply not an acceptable response in a
democratic society of any stripe.
Jonny Steinberg has argued that the justification 'remains striking for
its glibness and its rather clumsy forays into pop criminology':
in essence, Kriegler is telling us that the accused should remain in jail because lawless,
vigilante action is rife, because people have little respect for the criminal justice system
and take justice into their own hands. It is doubtful whether a constitutional court the
world over has ever before denied an accused person his freedom with a glib reference to
the force of mass lawlessness. 43
Kriegler J's second explanation was that '[e]xperience has shown that
organised community violence ... does subside while ringleaders are in
custody.' However, a criminologist, Eirena van der Spuy, has questioned
the basis for this assertion. Van der Spuy asks:
Experience? What experience? Sometimes taking gang leaders off the streets opens the
space for a new and wilder generation of leadership. There are no axioms here. Each case
has its own logic. Using that axiom as a basis for denying an accused bail strikes me as a
little crazy. 44
41 See the statement by Kentridge AJ in Makwanyane (note 3 above) para 204: 'In conclusion I
would endorse what Didcott J has cogently stated; the striking down of the death penalty
entails no sympathy whatsoever for the murderer, nor any condonation of his crime. What our
decision does entail is a recognition that even the worst and most vicious criminals are not
excluded from the protections of the Constitution.'
42 Note 3 above, para 88.
43 Jonny Steinberg 'Clumsy Foray into Pop Criminology' Business Day 14 June 1999.
44 Quoted by Steinberg (note 43 above).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
301
Once the conclusion is reached that the community reaction is an
illegitimate ground for limiting the fundamental right to liberty that is at
stake here, the second answer is largely irrelevant because merely restricting
the scope of the disputed provision cannot save it. However, the attempt to
develop these restrictions is of interest because it reveals another
fundamental weakness of the judgment. In the course of trying to extend
these restrictions as far as possible (in itself a laudable enterprise from the
point of view of liberty), Kriegler J turned, inter alia, to the meaning of
the words, 'exceptional circumstances'. These, he explained, were a 'clear
pointer' to the fact that the sentiments of the community should only be
acceded to - 'pandered to' would perhaps be an unfair paraphrase- in
'those rare cases where it is really justified'. 45 Although no further
explanation was given of what was meant by 'really justified', other than
the 'likelihood' of disturbance or undermining of the public peace (which
is really a separate restriction), the intention was that 'exceptional
circumstances' was to be interpreted narrowly as a strong limitation on
what was, by the Court's own admission, a fundamentally illiberal
provision. Strict constructionism in the interest of individual liberty is of
course a hallowed technique of constitutional interpretation. What the
judge seems to have overlooked is the use made of the same words in
the provision dealing with very serious offences, to which we now turn.
(b) Very serious offences
In his classic dissent in Liversidge v Anderson,46 Lord Atkins said:
I view with apprehension the attitude of Judges who, on a mere question of construction,
when face to face with claims involving the liberty of the subject, show themselves more
executive minded than the executive .... It has always been one of the pillars of freedom,
one of the principles of liberty for which, on recent authority, we are now fighting, that
Judges are no respecters of persons and stand between the subject and any attempted
encroachments of his liberty by the executive, alert to see that any coercive action is
justified by law. 47
The complaint against s 60(1l)(a) was that it made it almost impossible
for persons charged with certain very serious offences to obtain bail
because it required them to adduce evidence that 'exceptional
circumstances' exist which, in the 'interests of justice', permit their
release. In our view, according to the ordinary interpretation of the words
in s 60(1l)(a), it is more onerous than the bail laws under apartheid
applicable to the same (non-political) crimes. The only provisions that
were more draconian were those relating to detention without trial of
people accused of political offences. 48
45
46
47
48
Dlamini para 57.
[1941] 3 AllER 338.
Ibid 361.
For an overview of a number of these offences see Anthony Mathews Freedom, State Security
and the Rule of Law- Dilemmas of the Apartheid Society (1989). See further Jeremy Sarkin
'Preventive Detention in South Africa' in Andrew Harding and John Hatchard (eds)
Preventive Detention and Security Law: A Comparative Survey (1993) 130.
302
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Given the requirements of the subsection, the Constitutional Court
correctly concluded as follows: 'To the extent, therefore, that the test for
bail established by s 60(ll)(a) is more rigorous than that contemplated by
s 35(l)(f) of the Constitution, it limits the constitutional right.' 49 As in
the case of the provision dealing with community reaction, the court then
moved to the second stage of the constitutional enquiry to assess whether
'that limitation may be justified in terms of s 36 of the Constitution'. 5°
The main justification found by the Court was that of crime. The court
was presumably also referring to the crime rate when it concluded that
the requirement of "exceptional circumstances" ... is a limitation which
is reasonable and justifiable in terms of s 36 of the Constitution in our
current circumstances.' 51
The Court referred, rather melodramatically, to the submissions made
in this regard by counsel on behalf of the State:
He pointed to the grim statistics which show that our society is racked by a surge in
violent criminal activity which has made all ordinary law-abiding citizens fearful for their
safety and that of their family and friends. 52
Here the court makes the common mistake of equating fear of crime with
the actual incidence of crime. It thereby takes judicial notice of something
that is not quite correct. With respect, not 'all law-abiding citizens are
fearful for their safety and that of their family and friends'. Although
the fear of crime is certainly very real in our society, there is considerable
evidence that people's fear of being a victim of crime outstrips the actual
risk to which they are subjected. While it may be a common mistake not
to distinguish fear of crime from crime itself, it is inexcusable for a
court to make this mistake when allowing the supposed 'surge in violent
crime' as a justification for curbing a fundamental constitutional right.
The Court recognised that the level of criminal activity was not
the only factor relevant to the limitation enquiry. In considering the
balancing exercise required in s 36, the Court described the one side of
the balance as comprising 'the purpose, effects and importance of the
infringing legislation'. 53 In this regard it found the following: 'Parliament
enacted s 60(11)(a) with the clear purpose of deterring and controlling
serious crime, an indubitably important goal.' 54 However, the Court
seems to have taken judicial notice that s 60(ll)(a) will indeed 'deter and
control serious crime'. This is in sharp contrast to the considerable
attention given to the same issue inS v Makwanyane. 55 All eleven Justices
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
Dlamini para 65.
Ibid.
Ibid para 77, emphasis added.
Ibid para 66.
Ibid para 68.
Ibid.
Note 3 above. See Jeremy Sarkin 'Problems and Challenges Facing South Africa's
Constitutional Court: An Evaluation of its Decisions on Capital and Corporal Punishment'
(1996) 113 SALJ 71.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
303
in their separate judgments discussed whether the death penalty was in
fact a deterrent to serious violent crime. Chaskalson P stated:
It has not been shown that the death sentence would be materially more effective to deter
or prevent murder than the alternative sentence of life imprisonment would be. 56
Mahomed J came to the same conclusion:
Bringing to bear upon the issue, therefore, a rational and judicial judgment, I have not
been persuaded that the fear of the death penalty rationally or practically operates as a
demonstrable deterrent for offenders seeking to perpetrate serious crimes. 57
While somewhat more equivocal about the ineffectiveness of the death
penalty as a deterrent, and although clearly attracted by the argument,
Kriegler J in M akwanyane also rejected this justification advanced by the
State. In an interesting parallel with many of the issues in Dlamini, he
stated in his concurring judgment in Makwanyane:
We were favoured with literally thousands of pages of material in support of and opposed
to the death penalty, ranging from the religious, ethical, philosophical and ideological to
the mathematical and statistical. Mr Von Lieres SC, who argued the retentionist cause
with great skill, in essence sought to bring the death sentence within the protection of
s 33(1) on the strength of its deterrent and retributive value .... But when all is said and
done the answer is still what it was to Marshall J in Furman's case: the death penalty has
no demonstrable penological value over and above that of long-term imprisonment. No
empirical study, no statistical exercise and no theoretical analysis has been able to
demonstrate that capital punishment has any deterrent force greater than that of a really
heavy sentence of imprisonment. That is the ineluctable conclusion to be drawn from the
mass of data so thoroughly canvassed in the written and oral arguments presented to
us. 58
All the Justices specifically considered and rejected the proposition
offered by the state in Makwanyane that the death penalty was an
effective deterrent against violent crime. This 'governmental purpose' for
the measure was thus discounted as a justification for the infringement of
a fundamental right.
In contrast to the critical evaluation made of the deterrence
justification in Makwanyane, the Court apparently glossed over this justification in Dlamini. This difference in approach is baffling. Most, if not
all, South Africans are aware that the death penalty has been abolished.
And yet, despite the Constitutional Court's ruling, the death penalty
remains the subject of fierce public debate. People contemplating
committing a capital crime are therefore likely to know whether or not
the death penalty applies to that crime. By contrast, the provisions of
s 60(ll)(a) read with Schedule 6 of the Criminal Procedure Act are highly
technical and their details are probably familiar only to the few legal
practitioners who deal with these provisions on a day to day basis. People
contemplating committing a Schedule 6 crime are highly unlikely to know
56 Makwanyane (note 3 above) para 146.
57 Ibid para 293.
58 Ibid paras 211-12.
304
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
that it is a Schedule 6 crime and are likewise unlikely to know that at their
bail hearing they will have to prove 'exceptional circumstances' justifying
their release. Obviously, the death penalty can hardly be compared in its
severity and brutality to pre-trial detention. For these reasons, if the
death penalty cannot be considered an effective deterrent against violent
crime (and we agree that this is so), then the provisions of s 60(ll)(a)
certainly cannot.
If deterrence is not the purpose of s 60(ll)(a), then what is? We believe
that the real purpose was revealed earlier in the judgment:
Mr D'Oliveira, on behalf of the prosecution in Diad/a, vigorously defended subsection
I I, saying that its wording had been well chosen with a view to the pressing social need to
strengthen confidence in the criminal justice system. 59
One thing that everybody in this country will be able to agree on is that
there is a need to strengthen confidence in the criminal justice system.
However, the abrogation of fundamental rights is no way to strengthen
such confidence, particularly when it is by no means clear that the
exercise of that right is responsible for the lack of confidence in the first
place.
Let us return to the balancing exercise in which Kriegler J was
supposedly engaged. He put it like this:
It is well established that s 36 requires a court to counterpoise the purpose, effects
and importance of the infringing legislation on the one hand against the nature and
importance of the right limited on the other. 60
The Court did indeed make reference to the purpose of the infringing
legislation; this is discussed in detail above. However, it appears to have
failed to consider the 'other hand', namely 'the nature and importance of
the right limited'. It did not refer again to the most fundamental of rights,
that of freedom. Perhaps that is why it came to the conclusion that it
did.
The judgment proceeded to list the bail laws in other countries. Briefly
stated, the United Kingdom is said to allow denial of bail if there are
'substantial grounds'. 61 The United States of America requires detention
if "no conditions or combination of conditions will reasonably assure the
appearance of the [defendant] as required and the safety of any other
person ... before trial". 62 In Canada, pre-trial detention is only justified
'where necessary'. 63 And in Australia, the onus is reversed for serious
offences. 64
None of these bail laws from other countries described in the judgment
contain a provision as draconian as requiring the accused to show that
59
60
61
62
63
Dlamini para 62, emphasis added.
Ibid para 68.
Ibid para 70.
Ibid para 71.
Ibid para 72.
64 Ibid para 73.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
305
there are 'exceptional circumstances' which justify their release. The
Court was thus correct in finding that:
It is clear from the above discussion that bail is limited in open and democratic societies,
although it is also clear that the limitation imposed by s 60(ll)(a) is an unusual one
which may well be more invasive than those described above. 65
Other than making the seemingly reluctant finding that s 60(ll)(a) might
be more severe than bail laws found in other democracies, the Court did
not refer to these laws again. We are not sure why the Court refers to
these decisions at all. Kriegler J concludes:
therefore, I am of the view that, although the inclusion of the requirement of 'exceptional
circumstances' in s 60(11)(a) limits the right enshrined in s 35(l)(f), it is a limitation
which is reasonable and justifiable in terms of s 36 of the Constitution in our current
circumstances 66
When called upon to adjudicate the constitutionality of s 60(ll)(a) the
Court again had to interpret the words 'exceptional circumstances'. It is
interesting to contrast the interpretation of these words in this context
with the interpretation of the same words used in the first instance,
namely the community reaction ground discussed above. In both cases
the Court holds the provisions to be in contravention of s 35(3)(f) but to
be saved by the limitations clause.
Here the provision is in some ways not so obviously in contravention
of the primary constitutional right. Many legal systems recognise that the
'interests of justice', loosely defined, require that bail applications in
especially serious cases be treated with particular circumspection; for
example, the failure of a person accused of murder to stand trial may
have wide ramifications. The difficulty is that these factors are covered
fully in the earlier subsections ofs 60. Section 60(11)(a) imposes a further
restriction that requires its own justification to pass muster in terms of the
limitations clause. Here, too, the Court used public opinion as a crutch,
for it argued that the prima facie unjustifiable restrictions on bail were
acceptable in a democratic society at least in part because of public
misconceptions of the bail process. To these it coupled a claim that many
judicial officers have fundamental misconceptions of what bail is all
about- a gratuitous insult for which no evidence was presented. Nor was
evidence presented that 'grim crime statistics' will be improved by tighter
bail laws. This is not surprising: it is unlikely that more convincing
evidence could have been found to support such a claim than that which
was offered about the efficacy of the death penalty as a deterrent, a
proposition that the same Court rejected with scorn in Makwanyane.
The main reason for the Court concluding that s 60(ll)(a) was
constitutionally acceptable, however, was that the restriction it contains
on bail being granted to serious offenders was not as drastic as it appears.
65 Ibid para 73.
66 Ibid para 77.
306
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
In deciding this, the Court made much of the fact that persons accused of
Schedule 6 offences were not denied bail automatically. Thus the Court
ruled that, because bail could still be granted to persons accused of even
the most serious offences in 'exceptional circumstances', judicial officers
still make the ultimate decision on whether bail should be granted. This is
of course true, but the extent of the judicial officer's discretion depends
on what is meant by 'exceptional circumstances'. For the discretion to be
meaningful it should be wide enough to allow the court to grant bail
whenever the accused in fact deserves it.
Unfortunately for the Court, the ordinary meaning of 'exceptional
circumstances' is in fact relatively narrow. Lord Chief Justice Bingham
recently explained in the Criminal Division of the English Court of
Appeal that the ordinary meaning is
a circumstance such as to form an exception, which is out of the ordinary course or
unusual or special or uncommon. To be exceptional a circumstance need not be unique
or unprecedented or very rare, but it cannot be one that is regularly, or routinely, or
normally encountered. 67
The Constitutional Court's difficulty is compounded by the fact that this
restrictive exposition of 'exceptional circumstances' fits closely with the
approach it adopted to the same words in s 60(4)(e) where it refers to
'rare cases' in which the invocation of that restriction would be justified.
Confronted by its own precedent of a few pages earlier the Court
simply obfuscated. It denied the obvious, literal reading of s 60 as a
whole, by ignoring its earlier restrictive interpretation of 'exceptional
circumstances'. The section itself lists over thirty circumstances where
bail may ordinarily be refused. The Court denied the fact that for circumstances to be 'exceptional' this must mean that there are other
circumstances than those listed. Its reasoning for the latter conclusion is
entirely unconvincing. It studiously avoided a definition of the term
exceptional but attempted instead to illustrate how the words should be
interpreted. The specific example that it gave, derived from the Joubert
case, 68 was of 'an otherwise dependable man charged with consensual
sexual intercourse with a 15 year old girl, and who has minor previous
convictions'. Such a man would fall within the ambit of s 60(11)(a) and
yet, according to the Court, a prudent judicial officer exercising the
discretion that the words 'exceptional circumstances' allow, should grant
him bail. On the equities of the matter the outcome may be correct. Yet,
contrary to what the Court suggested, there is nothing 'exceptional'
about these facts at all. It is unfortunately not rare for 'dependable' men
with limited or no previous records to be charged with Schedule 6 crimes
that are not necessarily particularly heinous (indeed it may happen
'regularly'). What the Court has done is to deny the ordinary meaning of
67 R v Kelly [1999]2 AllER 13, 17.
68 S v Joubert 1998 (2) SACR 718 (C). An appeal by the state in Joubert's case was considered by
the Constitutional Court in Dlamini.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
307
the words 'exceptional circumstances' in order to develops 60(ll)(a) in a
way that allows it to pass constitutional muster.
It is worth emphasising why this interpretation is problematic. The
debate about constitutional interpretation in South Africa thus far has
concerned primarily the question of how the Constitution itself and
particularly the Bill of Rights should be interpreted. Literalists have
argued that the Constitution protects a wide spectrum of rights and that
it should simply be applied as strictly as possible to achieve the protection
of liberty, dignity and equality that for them the actual wording so
manifestly encompasses. Their opponents have argued for a wider
interpretation, which would allow the underlying principles of the
Constitution to be applied even where they are not spelled out literally. In
practice the results will not often differ, although the latter approach is
perhaps more open to distortion by a misapplication of public opinion as
a form of contextualisation.
What we have here though, is a determinedly non-literalist interpretation of an ordinary statutory provision, the constitutionality of which is
being tested. It is, of course, acceptable, where words are inherently
ambiguous, to give them a meaning that is compatible with the
Constitution, but in this instance, as we have illustrated, there is no
ambiguity about the term 'exceptional circumstances'. The problem is
that the Court did not attempt seriously to grapple with its meaning but
simply gave it two different slants when applying it in two subsections of
the same statutory provision. This is a true sleight of hand, for unlike its
interpretation of 'interests of justice' where it pointed out the two
meanings of the words in the same provision, 69 the Court simply glossed
over what it was doing. What it should have done, is simply to have given
'exceptional circumstances' its ordinary, restricted meaning. The outcome
would then have been that subsection ll(a) could not possibly have
passed constitutional muster in terms of the limitations clause as
'justifiable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,
equality and freedom'.
In the present circumstances, the only rule of construction that
explains the approach adopted by the Court is from Lewis Carroll's
masterpiece Alice in Wonderland (1865):
'When I use a word', Humpty Dumpty said in rather a scornful tone, 'it means what I
choose it to mean, neither more nor less.' 'The question is', said Alice, 'whether you can
make words mean different things.' 70
One further point needs to be made in this regard. One of the strengths of
s 60 in its current form, as the Court recognised, is that it provides
guidance for judicial officers in structuring their bail decisions. Section
60(11 )(a) as interpreted does not do so. In this instance the judicial officer
is being asked to interpret the words 'exceptional circumstances' widely
69 Dlamini paras 45-50.
70 Quoted by Lord Atkin in Liversidge v Anderson (note 46 above) 361.
308
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
and not literally, while in s 60(4)(e) they must be interpreted narrowly
and literally. 71 It is often argued that one of the strengths of literal
interpretation is that it supports the rule of law in the traditional sense of
making it clear and easy to apply. This may, or may not, be a clinching
argument in a jurisprudential debate. In the context of this bail legislation
though, we can see an example of it being applied, at least in part, for the
flexibility of interpretation that the Court requires here is both confusing
and fundamentally undermining of the important guarantee of individual
liberty that is at stake.
(c) Admissibility of bail proceedings
One of the very first cases that decided upon the constitutionality of
subsequently admitting the record of a bail proceeding was S v Botha. 72
Myburgh 1 stated the dilemma facing an accused in applying for bail in
the following terms:
[I]f he fails to give evidence or refuses to answer incriminating questions, he may be
refused bail, yet, if he does give evidence and answers incriminating questions in order to
get bail, he foregoes his right to remain silent and the privilege against self-incrimination.
In the interests of a fair trial, the accused should not have to choose. 73
In Botha, it was decided that the proceedings of a bail application should
be excluded on the following grounds: first, that it infringes upon an
accused's right against self-incrimination, and secondly, that it is in
violation of an accused's fair trial rights in terms of s 25 of the interim
Constitution. 74
It was held by the court in Botha that the evidence of a bail hearing be
held distinct from the trial in the same way that evidence adduced in a
trial-within-a-trial be excluded as testimony. Shortly after the decision in
Botha, the legislature intervened by adopting s 60(11B)(c) of the Criminal
Procedure Act in 1997, 75 making bail proceedings admissible as evidence
at the trial. This provision was criticised by human rights lawyers, as well as
the Cape High Court, in S v Schietekat. 76 In that case, Slomowitz AJ held
that subsection (llB)(c) was unconstitutional. He reasoned as follows:
A bail proceeding is not a Star Chamber.
Whatever the purpose of Parliament may have been in enacting it, its effect is
malevolent. An accused may only elect to exercise his right to apply for bail on pain of
71
72
73
74
75
As argued above, ss 60(4)(e) should have been struck down but for other reasons.
1995 (2) SACR 605 (W).
Ibid 611i-j.
More specifically s 25(3)(c) and (d) of the interim Constitution.
Section 60(11B)(c) now provides as follows:
The record of the bail proceedings, excluding the information in paragraph (a), shall form
part of the record of the trial of the accused following upon such bail proceedings: Provided
that if the accused elects to testify during the course of the bail proceedings the court must
inform him or her of the fact that anything he or she says, may be used against him or her at
his or her trial and such evidence becomes admissible in any subsequent proceedings.
76 1998 (2) SACR 707 (C). See also S v C 1998 (2) SACR 71 (C). An appeal by the state in
Schietekat's case was one of the matters dealt with by the Constitutional Court in Dlamini.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
309
being interrogated on the merits of the case against him, thus to have his own testimony
used against him as part of the State's case when he eventually comes to be tried. It is by
fashioning this weapon that those who would seek their liberty are to be discouraged
from asking for it ... ?
Upon testifying an accused might well incriminate himself, whether of the crime
charged or, what is more serious, of other offences unknown and uncharged. I am bound
to hold, as I do, that the subsection violates the Constitution .... 77
It is against this background that we turn to the Constitutional Court's
interpretation of the provision and of its constitutionality. In Dlamini,
Kriegler J made it clear that the facts of the two cases should be
distinguished. In Botha it had been held that the accused testified without
being informed of his right against self-incrimination, whereas in Dlamini
the accused had been properly informed of his right to remain silent
and the right not to incriminate himself. Kriegler J reflected on the
tension that exists between the right of an accused to make out an
effective application for bail by adducing evidence and the list of rights
under s 35(1) and (3) of the Constitution. He did not, however, consider
the tension as exceptional, or unusual, or uniquely applicable to bail
applicants. Rather, he observed, that what was required of an accused
under the circumstances was to exercise an informed choice. 78
The Court went further and criticised the Botha judgment on the basis
that effectively it had given the accused the right to lie in a bail application
and not to be confronted with the lies in the later trial. Kriegler J in Dlamini
interpreted the right of an accused not to incriminate himself as meaning
that he may not be compelled to testify. Based on the Court's
interpretation, an accused had to exercise his discretion as to whether to
testify in the bail application and if the person did so, it could be claimed
that the proceedings should not be quoted in the trial. 79 It is submitted that
in its intepretation of the right not to incriminate oneself and the right to
remain silent, the Court lost sight of the fact that an accused is not merely
exercising a choice when deciding to testify in his own bail application. He
has no choice. Without his testimony to support his application he will
be denied his freedom. Section s 60(ll)(a) creates an onus, which has
77 Schietekat (note 76 above) 714g-i.
78 Dlamini para 93.
79 See Dlamini para 95:
In effect the reasoning in Botha wishes to give the accused the best of both alternatives or, as it
was put bluntly in Dlamini, the right to lie: one can advance any version of the facts without
any risk of a come-back at the trial; and there one can choose another version with impunity.
However, the protection of an arrestee provided under the right to remain silent in the
Constitution - or the right not to be compelled to confess or make admissions - offers no
blanket protection against having to make a choice. It is true, the principal objective of the Bill
of Rights is to protect the individual against abuse of state power; and it does so, among
others, by shielding the individual faced with a criminal charge against having to help prove
that cl:targe. That shield against compulsion does not mean, however, that an applicant for
bail can choose to speak but not to be quoted. As a matter of policy the prosecution must
prove its case without the accused being compelled to furnish supporting evidence. But if the
accused, acting freely and in the exercise of an informed choice, elects to testify in support of a
bail application, the right to silence is in no way impaired. Nor is it impaired, retrospectively
as it were, if the testimony voluntarily given is subsequently held against the accused.
310
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
to be discharged and the only way it can be discharged is to testify. There
is no real choice under such circumstances. Kriegler J justified the
infringement upon the right to remain silent by using other comparisons
on the trial process. We are not convinced that the choice exercised by an
accused whether to volunteer to give a statement to the police, or to
respond to their questions, is analogous to the choice of applying for bail.
Should an accused exercise his right to remain silent and not give a
statement to the police he will not be 'punished' by being detained, but
should he wish to exercise this right when applying for bail it is more than
likely that he will be detained. The other examples used by Kriegler J are
by no means more persuasive. 80
The Constitutional Court relied on an earlier judgment of the Supreme
Court of Appeal in S v Nomzaza 81 to demonstrate that an accused could
never, not even under the common law, succeed in a claim that incriminating evidential material given by the accused could be excluded. 82 What
the Court failed to recognise is the element of implied compulsion to
testify under the 1997 bail legislation as distinguished from incriminating
statements made freely and voluntarily by an accused in the course of an
ordinary criminal trial under common law. It is submitted that the
decision of Nomzaza deals with a different situation from that which
s 60(B)(c) is regulating and cannot be used to justify saving the provision.
V CONCLUSION
The Constitutional Court has judged the current bail law to be
constitutional by interpreting narrowly the protection of liberty
contained in the Constitution and, more particularly, by limiting the
right in s 35(l)(f) that '[e]veryone who is arrested for allegedly
committing an offence has the right ... to be released from detention
if the interests of justice permit, subject to reasonable conditions'. It has
failed to live up to the importance of freedom as a constitutional value as
acknowledged in Ferreira v Levin N0. 83 In that case, Ackermann J
interpreted s 11(1) of the interim Constitution in the following words:
Although freedom is indispensable for the protection of dignity, it has an intrinsic
constitutional value of its own. It is likewise the foundation of many other rights that are
specifically entrenched. Viewed from this perspective, the starting point must be that an
individual's right to freedom must be defined as widely as possible, consonant with a
similar breadth of freedom of others. 84
80
81
82
83
84
Dlamini supra par 94.
1996 (2) SACR 14 (A).
Dlamini para 96.
1996 (I) SA 984 (CC).
Ibid para 49. In Bernstein v Bester NO 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC) para 145, 0' Regan J interpreted
freedom as having 'two interrelated constitutional aspects: the first is a procedural aspect
which requires that no one be deprived of physical freedom unless fair and lawful procedures
have been followed. Requiring deprivation of freedom to be in accordance with procedural
fairness is a substantive commitment in the Constitution. The other constitutional aspect of
freedom lies in a recognition that, in certain circumstances, even when fair and lawful
procedures have been followed, the deprivation of freedom will not be constitutional, because
the grounds upon which freedom has been curtailed are unacceptable.' (Emphasis added)
(2000) 16 SAJHR
311
In Dlamini, by contrast, the Court restricted this right for persons
detained while awaiting trial. Where it could not restrict it any further the
Court ruled that circumstances in South Africa justify the legislator in
infringing even the limited guarantee that the Court recognised these
detainees as having. This it did by invoking the general clause that allows
the rights in the Bill of Rights to be limited if specific conditions apply.
Draconian bail laws are not the solution to South Africa's crime
problem. An effective criminal justice system is the key. The Court
recognised this when it declared the death penalty unconstitutional. In
Makwanyane, Chaskalson P correctly stated that
[t]he greatest deterrent to crime is the likelihood that offenders will be apprehended,
convicted and punished. It is that which is presently lacking in our criminal justice
system; and it is at this level and through addressing the causes of crime that the State
must seek to combat lawlessness. 85
In the same case, Mahomed J provided a useful and concise list of the
most critical problems confronting the criminal justice system and
perceptively described what needs to be done to deter serious crime. 86
The reason that four years later the criminal justice system remains in
crisis is in part because of the scale and complexity of the problems that
need to be overcome by the State.
Solving the real problems of the criminal justice system is complex and
will take a long time and a great deal of effort. It is politically difficult for
government to concede this to a public hysterical about crime. By contrast,
tough-on-crime legislation is a 'quick-fix', a rapid and cheap way for
government to be seen to be doing something. Democratic governments
make decisions according to political demands. In the current South
African context, it is therefore understandable that the government will be
tempted to pass constitutionally dubious laws in an effort to present itself as
'strong on crime'. In fact, in a society that has yet to build a strong
85 Makwanyane (note 3 above) para 122.
86 'It appears to me to be an inherent probability that the more successful the police are in solving
serious crimes and the more successful they are in apprehending the criminals concerned and
securing their convictions, the greater will be the perception of risk for those contemplating such
offences. That increase in the perception of risk, contemplated by the offender, would bear a
relationship to the rate at which serious offences are committed. Successful arrest and conviction
must operate as a deterrent and the State should, within the limits of its undoubtedly constrained
resources, seek to deter serious crime by adequate remuneration for the police force; by incentives
to improve their training and skill; by augmenting their numbers in key areas; and by facilitating
their legitimacy in the perception of the communities in which they work ....
Successful deterrence of serious crime also involves the need for substantial redress in the
socio-economic conditions of those ravaged by poverty, debilitated by disease and malnutrition
and disempowered by illiteracy. Rapid amelioration in these areas must have some concomitant
effect on the levels of crime. There has to be a corresponding campaign among the communities
affected by serious crime to harness their own legitimacy and their own infrastructures in
interaction with the security agencies of the State. The power and influence of agencies of moral
authority such as teachers, school principals and religious leaders must rapidly be restored.
Crime is a multi-faceted phenomenon. It has to be assaulted on a multi-dimensional level to
facilitate effective deterrence.' Makwanyane (note 3 above) paras 290-91.
312
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
human rights culture, 87 government is under considerable pressure to do
so. In the short term, it is politically irrelevant that such laws will not
solve the real problems in the criminal justice system.
The Constitutional Court is the final guardian of the Constitution. It
has the task of counterbalancing the majoritarian political pressures
faced by government when it concerns fundamental rights. In this
instance the Court has failed, comprehensively and unanimously, in
its fundamental duty to protect the liberty of a reviled group, those
accused - note, not convicted - of serious crimes. The decision in Dlamini
parallels that in Liversidge v Anderson. 88 We all recognise now that
Liversidge v Anderson was wrongly decided; 89 but at least it was decided
during wartime when an infringement of the right to liberty by the
executive was countenanced by the majority. In his famous dissenting
speech in Liversidge's case, Lord Atkin said:
In England amidst the clash of arms the laws are not silent. They may be changed, but
they speak the same language in war as in peace. It has always been one of the pillars of
freedom, one of the principles of liberty for which, on recent authority, we are now
fighting, that the Judges are no respecters of persons, and stand between the subject and
any attempted encroachment on his liberty by the Executive, alert to see that any coercive
action is justified in law. 90
Dlamini was decided in the misunderstood war against crime. It follows that
the case may be the Constitutional Court's contribution to the national war
against crime and could therefore be dismissed as an aberration in the
struggle for the protection of liberty. Although not excusing the illiberal
elements of the decision, that might he the best course to adopt, for it would
be deeply ironic if, although the guns of war could not permanently silence
the common law, the guns of a few gangsters undermine the much-vaunted
new Constitution. Dlamini cannot be allowed to set the standard for the
future protection of individual liberty in South Africa.
JEREMY SARKIN
Professor of Law and Deputy Dean
Law Faculty, University of the Western Cape
ESTHER STEYN
Lecturer in Law, University of Cape Town
DIRK vAN ZYL SMIT
Professor of Law, University of Cape Town
RON PASCHKE
Advocate, Cape Bar
87 On the creation of a human rights culture, see Jeremy Sarkin 'The Development of a Human
Rights Culture in South Africa' (note 2 above) 628.
88 Note 46 above.
89 Lord Atkin's dissent in Liversidge was finally vindicated in Inland Revenue Commissioners v
I Rossminster Ltd 1980 AC 952 (HL), 1011, where Lord Diplock said: 'For my part I think the
time has come to acknowledge openly that the majority of this House in Liversidge v Anderson
were expediently and, at that time, perhaps, excusably, wrong, and the dissenting speech of
Lord Atkin was right.'
90 Liversidge (note 46 above) 361.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
313
GAY AND LESBIAN PARTNER IMMIGRATION AND THE REDEFINING
OF FAMILY
NATIONAL COALITION FOR GAY AND LESBIAN EQUALITY V MINISTER OF
HOME AFFAIRS
I INTRODUCTION
In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of
Home Affairs 1 (National Coalition 2), the Constitutional Court dealt
with the constitutionality of s 25(5) of the Aliens Control Act 96 of
1991 (the Act). The provision allows the Department of Home Affairs
to issue an immigration permit to a foreign national applicant 3 who is a
spouse or a dependent child of a permanent South African resident. It
facilitates the immigration of spouses to enable them to live with their
South African counterparts. The provision is a reasonable one as it
enables married couples to live together irrespective of the nationality
or permanent residence of one of the spouses. Until this case, however,
its benefits were not available to gay and lesbian partners in an
otherwise similar situation, as South African law does not permit them
to marry. 4
The central issue canvassed in this note is the relationship between
family and marriage, and particularly the extent to which gay and lesbian
couples can be considered as constituting family. 5 In several jurisdictions,
including South Africa, the traditional legal definition of family has
recently been subject to scrutiny and reappraisal for its exclusion of
lesbians and gays. In National Coalition, the Constitutional Court
unanimously acknowledged that gays and lesbians do indeed constitute
family; but it appears that, at least for the time being, such acceptance
does not extend to marriage. That institution remains an exclusively
heterosexual preserve. Given international trends and the possible
implications of this judgment (examined below), gay and lesbian
activists may find that, without strategic activism on their part and
principled constitutional interpretation, the -equal right to marry will be
denied to them.
Internationally, the trend is to retain marriage as a heterosexual
institution and in certain instances create some other parallel institution
I 2000 (2) SA I (CC). The decision of the court a quo, per Davis J, with Conradie J and Knoll AJ
concurring, was reported as National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home
Affairs 1999 (3) BCLR 280 (C).
2 An earlier case brought by the same applicants is cited as National Coalition for Gay and
Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice !999 (!) SA 6 (CC), and generally referred to as the
Sodomy judgment. See National Coalition para 31.
3 For a comment on terminology, see National Coalition para 15 fn II.
4 See B Silver' 'Til Deportation Do Us Part: the Extension of Spousal Recognition to Same-sex
Relationships' (1996) 12 SAJHR 575.
5 The judgment deals with other important jurisprudential issues such as 'reading in' and the
'intersectionality of rights' which will not be dealt with in this note.
314
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
to recognise gay and lesbian unions. In Quilter v Attorney-Genera/, 6
the New Zealand Court of Appeal held that the common law and the
statutory definition at issue in this case confined marriage to a union
between a man and a woman. In Fitzpatrick ( AP) v Sterling Housing
Association Ltd, 7 the House of Lords refused to interpret the word
'spouse' as including two persons of the same sex, but did hold that samesex partners could constitute a family. In M v H, 8 the Supreme Court of
Canada affirmed a law that marriage was exclusive to opposite-sex
couples. The only contrary trend has been that of the Hawaii Supreme
Court. 9
II
THE DEVELOPMENT OF FAMILY LAW
The development of a progressive body of family law in South Africa has
been slow. 10 This is the result of a very conservative foundation laid by
our academic writers and the courts. Family law in South Africa has been
traditionally defined as constituting that part of law that deals with
married persons and their children. 11 In W v W, 12 the court refused to
recognise that a sex-change operation could legally change the sex of a
6 1998 I NZLR 523 (CA). The appellants were three lesbian couples who argued that the
Marriage Act 1995 should be re-interpreted to allow same-sex couples to marry (526). It was
argued that such an interpretation would be appropriate in light of the New Zealand Bill of
Rights Act 1990 (571). Section 19 of the Bill of Rights deals with freedom from discrimination
and s 21(1) specifically refers to sexual orientation (556). The court held, however, that if the
Marriage Act constituted discrimination, Parliament had sanctioned it (582).
7 House of Lords 28 October 1999, unreported.
8 (1999) 171 DLR 4th 577. This case dealt with the definition of spouse ins 29 of the Family
Law Act 1990 and particularly with whether the term included same-sex couples. The
provision allows for 'persons who become financially dependent in the course of an intimate
relationship some relief from financial hardship resulting from the breakdown of that
relationship' (579). The provision is specifically made applicable to unmarried opposite-sex
couples as well as married couples.
9 In Baehr v Lewin 74 Haw 530 (1993), the Hawaii Supreme Court found that the stipulation
that marriage be between a man and a woman required 'strict scrutiny', a standard seldom met
by the state. See also Baehr v Mike 23 FLR 2001 (1996) (Hawaii) for a particularly good and
inclusive discussion of gay and lesbian parenting.
10 See generally C Lind 'Sexual Orientation, Family Law and the Transitional Constitution'
(1995) 112 SALJ 481, TL Mosikatsana 'The Definitional Exclusion of Gays and Lesbians
from Family Status' (1996) 12 SAJHR 549, and A Pantazis 'An Argument for the Legal
Recognition of Gay and Lesbian Marriages' (1997) 114 SALJ 556.
II See, for example PJ Visser & JM Potgieter Introduction to Family Law 2 ed (1998) I. These
authors not only define family law narrowly but display a hostile attitude to homosexuality:
It should be remembered that the prohibition on unfair discrimination against persons on
account of their sexual orientation does not override the constitutional principle that the
'best interests of the child' are of paramount importance in every matter that concerns
the child. And for as long as society does not see homosexuality and lesbianism as normal, it
will frown upon any attempt to treat homosexual and lesbian parents as 'normal' for the
purpose of access to young children. Moreover, the Constitution does not require that
homosexualism must be actively promoted (170 fn 108).
12 1976 (2) SA 308 (W). For a fuller discussion, see B Van Heerden, A Cockrell & R Keightley
Boberg's Law of Persons and the Family 2 ed (1999) 209-61.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
315
person. In Van Rooyen v Van Rooyen, 13 not only were stringent
conditions placed on a lesbian mother who sought access to her
children, but the court treated homosexuality particularly negatively.
Since the enactment of the interim Constitution, 14 the legal definition of
family has begun to widen. The most significant judicial break with the
past has been that of Langemaat v Minister of Safety and Security. 15 In
this case a lesbian police captain sought to have her partner included
in her medical aid scheme. In finding in her favour, Roux J dramatically
changed traditional conceptions of family law when he held that:
The stability of their [same-sex] relationship is no different from the many married couples I
know. Both unions are deserving of respect and protection. If our law does not accord
protection to the type of union I am dealing with, then I suggest that it is time it does so. 16
With regard to custody of children by lesbian mothers, there have
been significant shifts away from Van Rooyen in the past couple of
years. In V v V, 17 the court found that the homosexuality of the mother
was not necessarily a bar to joint custody. 18 In addition, there have
been at least two unreported judgments where the court has found in
favour of a lesbian mother in a custody matter. 19 In Farr v Mutual &
13 I 994 (2) SA 325 (W). See generally P De Vos 'The Right of a Lesbian Mother to Have Access
to Her Children: Some Constitutional Issues' (1994) I I I SALJ 687, E Bonthuys 'Awarding
Access and Custody to Homosexual Parents of Minor Children: A Discussion of Van Rooyen v
Van Rooyen 1994 2 SA 325 (W)' (1994) 3 Stellenbosch LR 298; D Singh 'Discrimination
Against Lesbians in Family Law' (1995) II SAJHR 571.
14 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution).
15 1998 (3) SA 312 (T). SeeR Louw 'Langemaat v Minister of Safety and Security: A Gay and
Lesbian Victory but a Constitutional Travesty' (1999) 15 SAJHR 393.
16 Langemaat (note 5 above) 314B-C.
17 1998 (4) SA 169 (C).
18 The court had to decide whether an order for joint custody was appropriate. Although the
parents had in practice been exercising joint custody for the two years prior to the divorce,
the plaintiff husband objected to such an order on two grounds and sought an order for sole
custody. The grounds were that the mother was suffering from borderline personality disorder
and that she was lesbian. However, the evidence of the psychiatrist and psychologists for both
parents did not consider the mother's sexual orientation to be a factor. Significantly, the court
quoted from one of the psychologists' reports that stated generally that the homosexual
orientation and lifestyle per se of a parent do not constitute a moral or psychological threat to
the wellbeing of children. The report continued that inappropriate sexual behaviour that
impinges on children of whatever sexual orientation might be harmful. See also EP Critchfield
and Critchfield (WLD 30 October 1998, unreported) where the court viewed the homosexual
encounters of the first applicant during the marriage in 'no more serious a light than
conventional adultery'.
19 In Mohapi v Mohapi (WLD 1998, unreported) the applicant mother obtained an order of court
for the father to return their minor daughter to her. In her papers, the mother acknowledged
that she was lesbian and living with another woman. She alleged that her daughter had 'an
extremely good relationship' with her partner as well as her partner's daughter. The father had
often vilified the mother in public regarding her sexual orientation and threatened to have her
custody of their daughter removed by the court. Although the mother already had custody of
her child and only sought an order for the return of her child, the court drew no adverse
inference regarding her sexual orientation. In Greyling v Minister of Welfare and Population
Development (WLD case no 98/8297, unreported) the applicant had been divorced three years
prior to the matter and was granted custody of her daughter. After moving out of her
parents' home a year later she formed a lesbian relationship with a co-worker. The applicants'
316
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
FederaP0 the court held that two gay men living together in a domestic
relationship constituted a family:
I think that while society might not necessarily approve of homosexual relations, it does
recognise that where such a relationship has a degree of permanency and the manner in
which the partners live together resembles for all intents and purposes (save that their
sexual relations are homosexual and not heterosexual) a marriage between a husband and
wife, they could be considered members of a family as would a husband and a wife.
The most far-reaching understanding of family was recently articulated
by O'Regan J in the unanimous Constitutional Court judgment m
Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs, 21 where she stated that
families come in many shapes and sizes. The definition of family also changes as social
practices change. In recognising the importance of the family, we must take care not to
entrench particular forms of family at the expense of other forms. 22
While there have been considerable developments in broadening our
conception offamily law, 23 the most significant remaining issue is that of
gay and lesbian marriage. This question arose in the National Coalition
case but was avoided. Ironically, it was raised by the Department of
Home Affairs, the respondent, who argued, in both the court a quo and
the Constitutional Court, that the matter brought by the applicants was
not ripe for constitutional determination. 24 It was argued that a regional
committee of the Department could interpret 'spouse', as contained in the
relevant provision, to include a same-sex life partner. It was, therefore,
unnecessary to consider the constitutional validity of this provision. In
dismissing this argument, the Court relied in the first instance on the
definition of 'spouse' in the New Shorter Oxford Dictionary as connoting
a 'married person; a wife, a husband'. 25 Nothing in the Act suggested a
wider meaning. Secondly, the use of the term 'marriage' in the Act also
20
21
22
23
24
25
parents objected to the relationship and obtained an order removing the daughter from her
mother on the rather spurious grounds that the daughter did not wish to reside with
her mother, that the mother and her partner 'do things which the minor child cannot or is
afraid to speak of' and that the daughter was suffering psychological damage. After
protracted delays largely at the hands of government officials, the applicant approached the
High Court requesting that the order of removal be set aside. Once again, without detriment to
her application, the applicant disclosed her sexual orientation in her court papers. The court
ordered the return of the child and awarded punitive costs against the respondents on an
attorney and client scale. See LA Minot Conceiving Parenthood: Parenting and the Rights of
Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual and Transgender People and their Children (International Gay
and Lesbian Human Rights Commission, 2000) 96-98.
CPO II October 1999, unreported. In this case the applicant was involved in a motor vehicle
accident. His passenger was his partner with a limited claim on the Multilateral Motor Vehicle
Fund. This made the applicant liable for the remainder of his partner's claim and accordingly
the applicant relied on his own insurer, the respondent. The respondent repudiated the claim,
alleging it was not liable for claims in respect of family members. The court upheld the
repudiation in finding that the applicant's partner was a member of his family.
2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) (dealing with immigration permits for foreign spouses).
Ibid para 31 (internal footnotes omitted).
There have been a number of statutory changes as well; see National Coalition para 37 fn 41.
For a fuller explanation of ripeness, see National Coalition para 22.
Ibid para 25.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
317
indicated that the term 'spouse' was used for a partner in a marriage and
that the term marriage extended no 'further than those marriages that are
ordinarily recognised in our law'?6 Finally, if the term 'spouse' could
have been given a more extensive meaning, the Court reasoned that it
would have been unnecessary to have provided in the definition section of
the Act that 'marriage' includes a customary union where the definition
of customary union was based on an opposite-sex relationship. 27
By relying first of all on a dictionary definition, secondly on the
meaning of a word 'ordinarily recognised in our law' and, thirdly, by
applying a narrow legislative interpretation, the Court could not by its
own restrictive parameters have come to a conclusion any different to
that of the current law. Such avoidance of constitutional interpretation
may prove to be an obstacle for future litigation concerning the definition
of gay and lesbian marriage. It is not that we are bound by this narrow
definition (in fact the Court's avoidance of the issue might be a reason
why it will require future constitutional analysis), but there are dicta in
the judgment which, if followed, could lead to an institution alternative
to marriage being used to recognise gay and lesbian relationships.
Having come to the conclusion that it was not possible to construe the
term 'spouse' to include same-sex partners, the Court nevertheless
proceeded to affirm gay and lesbian relationships in the most positive
way. The Court commenced its discrimination analysis by building on the
jurisprudence it had established in its Sodomy decision:
The denial of equal dignity and worth all too quickly and insidiously degenerates into a
denial of humanity and leads to inhuman treatment by the rest of society in many ways.
This is deeply demeaning and frequently has the cruel effect of undermining the
confidence and sense of self-worth and self-respect of lesbians and gays. 28
The Court went on to dismiss certain stereotypes discriminatory of gays
and lesbians, most notably in respect of children. Although a gay and
lesbian couple could not jointly adopt a child, an adopted child by one of
the partners could be loved, cared and provided for jointly by both
partners?9 Most significantly, the Court held that in all respects a samesex partnership resembled a marriage and that gay and lesbian families'
lives are indistinguishable from that of spouses:
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
.. .
.. .
.. .
gays and lesbians in same-sex life partnerships are as capable as heterosexual
spouses of expressing and sharing love in its manifold forms, including affection,
friendship, eros and charity;
(v) they are likewise as capable of forming intimate, permanent, committed,
monogamous, loyal and enduring relationships; of furnishing emotional and
26
27
28
29
Ibid.
Ibid para 26.
Ibid para 42.
Ibid para 50.
318
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
spiritual support; and of providing physical care, financial support and assistance
in running the common household;
(vi) they are individually able to adopt children and in the case of lesbians to bear them;
(vii) in short, they have the same ability to establish a consortium omnis vitae;
(viii) finally, and of particular importance for purposes of this case, they are capable of
constituting a family, whether nuclear or extended, and of establishing, enjoying
and benefiting from family life which is not distinguishable in any significant
respect from that of heterosexual spouses. 30
Having established the extent of the discrimination against gays and
lesbians, the Court had no difficulty in concluding that s 25( 5) of the Act
constituted unfair discrimination and a limitation of the 'right of gays
and lesbians who are permanent residents in the Republic and who are in
permanent same-sex life partnerships with foreign nationals.3 1 to
equality. The court also concluded that the subsection constituted a
'severe limitation of the s 10 right to dignity enjoyed by such gays and
lesbians'. 32 The Court found there to be no justification in the
discrimination 33 and took the unusual and creative step of reading into
the section, 'after the word "spouse", the following words: "or partner, in
a permanent same-sex life partnership" '? 4
Ill JURISPRUDENTIAL DEVELOPMENTS
The National Coalition judgment constitutes another milestone for gay
and lesbian legal equality in South Africa. A unanimous Constitutional
Court acknowledged widespread discrimination against gays and
lesbians. The positive and affirming tone of the judgment justify its
placement among leading decisions in the world in advancing gay and
lesbian equality jurisprudence. The strategic question facing proponents
of gay and lesbian equality within the National Coalition for Gay and
Lesbian Equality and elsewhere is how to build on the gains made thus
far and specifically how to advance partnership rights. 35 The critical
question to ask is to what extent have changes in the law in respect of
gays and lesbians made an impact? Here it is useful to distinguish
between jurisprudential developments, impacts on social attitudes, and
direct impacts on the lives of individual gay and lesbian litigants and on
the affected class. This note is concerned principally with jurisprudential
developments with regard to gay and lesbian equality and dignity. Not
only has constitutional protection in the equality clause been the
30
31
32
33
34
35
Ibid para 53.
Ibid para 57.
Ibid para 57.
Ibid paras 58-60.
Ibid para 86.
Thus far the most significant gains have largely been at the instance of the National Coalition
for Gay and Lesbian Equality, which has either lobbied or litigated (or assisted in litigation) to
change the law. See P Gerber 'Case Comment: South Africa: Constitutional Protection for
Homosexuals- A Brave Initiative, But is it Working?' (2000) 9 Australasian Gay & Lesbian LJ
37. More specifically, the NCGLE's work has centred around the organisation's Recognise our
Relationships campaign as set out in its various annual reports.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
319
foundation upon which all gay and lesbian law has developed, but
without doubt constitutional protection constituted a significant
affirmation of all gays and lesbians. Constitutional protection was
arguably the most significant reason behind changed public attitudes
toward gays and lesbians. The direct impact that legal and social
acceptance has had on the lives of gays and lesbians should not be
underestimated. The Sodomy judgment, which decriminalised gay sex,
confirmed that affirmation. Although it probably had significantly less
direct impact on gays and lesbians, 36 it laid a solid foundation, relying
principally on the right to equality, but also on dignity and privacy, on
which further developments in gay and lesbian rights have been and can
be based.
Significant changes have also taken place in the area of employment
law which prohibit discrimination against gays and lesbians. These
changes have been brought about statutorily and affect a wide range
of issues from non-discrimination in hiring practices to the extension of
medical aid and pension benefits. 37 The National Coalition case has added
significantly to the growing body of gay and lesbian jurisprudence.
Together with the custody judgments discussed above, gay and lesbian
family membership is now affirmed and legally recognised. These decisions
have largely dispelled fears about gay and lesbian parenting, and
accordingly law relating to custody and adoption will be easier to develop.
At this point, it is arguable that the most important legal and
jurisprudential development that gays and lesbians could achieve is that
of the right to marry. 38 It is an important right for a number of reasons.
36 This argument is not at odds with Cameron's assertion:
The criminal prohibitions on sex between men as well as the differential age of consent for
gay men and women have a severely negative impact on the lives of these people. Even when
these provisions are not enforced, they reduce men and women to what one author has
referred to as 'unapprehended felons', thus entrenching stigma and encouraging
discrimination in employment and insurance and in judicial decisions about custody and
other matters bearing on orientation. E Cameron 'Sexual Orientation and the Constitution:
A Test Case for Human Rights' (1993) 110 SALJ 450, 455 (internal footnotes omitted.)
I am arguing that negative social attitudes diminished significantly as a result of the enactment
of the equality provision in the interim Constitution. In other words, changes in the law,
whether legislative or judicial, impact on society. By the time of the Sodomy judgment (note 2
above), gay and lesbian stereotyping was on the decrease. Most obviously, constitutional
protection opened the route to eliminating discrimination in employment, insurance, custody
and other sexual orientation issues.
37 See specifically the Labour Relations Act 66 of 1995 (which prohibits dismissal on the ground
of sexual orientation), the Basic Conditions of Employment Act 75 of 1999 (s 27 deals with
'family responsibility leave'), the Employment Equity Act 55 of 1998 (which prohibits unfair
discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation in any employment policy or practice),
and the Medical Schemes Act 131 of 1998. See also the decision of the Pension Funds
Adjudicator in TWC v Rentokil Pension Fund Pension Funds Adjudicator Case PFA/KZN/
129/98 (26 October 1998). And see also M Jara 'Workplace Rights: A Gay and Lesbian Issue'
(1996) 20(6) South African Labour Bulletin 21 and M Jara 'Gay and Lesbian Rights' (1997)
21 ( 6) South African Labour Bulletin 31.
38 This is contrary to the argument by Cameron (note 36 above) 471:
[G]enuine recognition of non-discrimination on the ground of sexual orientation would
entail granting some recognition to permanent domestic partnerships. This need not take the
320
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
First, It IS a right that will be immediately accessible to all gays and
lesbians. Secondly, it is important in as much as marriage constitutes the
symbolic foundation upon which heterosexual society is built. Admission
to the institution of marriage may thus constitute the most important test
for determining the extent to which gays and lesbians will be treated
equally. Thirdly, it will be a logical culmination of the Court's developing
sexual orientation jurisprudence.
Marriage is much more than a union between two people: it constitutes
a social endorsement of a relationship that if extended to gays and
lesbians will enhance their social acceptance. Significant consequences
flow from marriage, including not only social but also economic stability.
Marriage is thus much more than a legal entity and the extension of
marriage to gays and lesbians will have ramifications far wider than the
legal consequences of marriage. Marriage has a uniquely privileged status
in society - to withhold that privilege from gays and lesbians will be
to deny them equality, dignity and the freedom to choose with whom to
associate and also autonomy in making significant decisions about their
personal lives. It is therefore a pity that the definition of marriage was
raised in such an oblique manner and dealt with perfunctorily at the
beginning of the National Coalition judgment. This approach could have
significant legal and social consequences for gays and lesbians. It is
inevitable that the issue of gay and lesbian marriage will come before the
Court some time in the future. It is regrettable that the Court has already
expressed itself, albeit indirectly, in this regard. Although National
Coalition is relevant specifically to the Aliens Control Act, 39 and dealt
with the definition of 'spouse' rather than 'marriage', it will need to be
addressed in future decisions and so constitutes an obstacle to the
achievement of gay and lesbian equality activism. But far more
importantly, and possibly constituting a more significant obstacle, is
the creation of a new legal institution by the Court, namely, that of a
'permanent same-sex life partnership'.
Although the Court specifically declined to comment on to what
extent, if at all, 'the law ought to give formal institutional recognition to
same-sex life partners', 40 the judgment does create a legal space for the
form of extending heterosexual marriage, which both by name and tradition may well be
unnecessary and inappropriate. (internal footnotes omitted)
It should be noted that these words were written in 1992, prior to any certainty that nondiscrimination on the ground of sexual orientation would be constitutionally protected.
Furthermore, the issue of same-sex marriage had not yet been debated in South Africa as the
right seemed to be unattainable at that time. Since the enactment of both the interim and 1996
Constitutions, gay and lesbian jurisprudence has changed to such an extent that Cameron's
comments are of historical rather than contemporary importance.
39 It is important to note that in coming to the conclusion that the term 'spouse' did not include
gay and lesbian couples, the Court explicitly confined itself to the Act: 'Under all these
circumstances it is not possible to construe the word "spouse" in s 25(5) as including the
foreign same-sex partner of a permanent and lawful resident of the Republic' (National
Coalition para 26).
40 Ibid para 60.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
321
statutory recogmtwn for what have been variously termed domestic
partnerships or civil unions. This is an option that has been followed in a
number of north European jurisdictions and most recently in the
American State of Vermont. The civil unions of the European
jurisdictions are not equivalent to marriage as they typically restrict the
right to adoption and other consequences of marriage such as donor
insemination and adoption of a spouse's surname. 41 But the Vermont
legislation is different. In April 2000, the State of Vermont enacted the
most far-reaching legislation in respect of civil unions (the Vermont
Act). 42 Section l of the Vermont Act, dealing with Findings of the
General Assembly, states that '[t]he state has a strong interest in
promoting stable and lasting families, including families based upon a
same-sex couple' 43 and '[w]ithout the legal protections, benefits and
responsibilities associated with civil marriage, same-sex couples suffer
numerous obstacles and hardships'. 44 The Vermont Act proceeds to set
out in detail the content of a civil union giving it the same content as
marriage: 'Parties to a civil union shall have all the benefits, protections
and responsibilities under law, whether they derive from statute,
administrative or court rule, policy, common law or any other source
of civil law, as are granted to spouses in a marriage.' 45
While the Vermont Act must be acknowledged as a remarkable piece
of legislation, it not only perpetuates but entrenches inequality between
gay and lesbian couples and heterosexual couples. The Vermont Act is
explicit that marriage is a 'union between a man and a woman' 46 and a
civil union is restricted to persons 'of the same sex and therefore excluded
from the marriage laws of this state'. 47 The Act therefore recreates
the discredited 'separate but equal' doctrine of racial legislation in the
context of same-sex relations. By granting gay and lesbian unions all
the rights and obligations of marriages it would appear to be granting
substantive equality- denial of the name of marriage would appear to be
a denial of formal equality only. However, as argued above, the denial
of the name of marriage to gays and lesbians denies them more than
the name and thus denies them substantive equality. Marriage remains
a privileged social institution for heterosexual couples, but most
41 See MP Boberg 'The Registered Partnership for Same-sex couples in Denmark' (1996) 8 Child
& Family LQ 147 and M Roth 'The Norwegian Act on Registered Partnership for
Homosexual Couples' (1996-97) 35 University of Louisville J of Family L 467.
42 Act 91: Act Relating to Civil Unions (which came into effect on I July 2000). The statute was a
43
44
45
46
47
direct result of Vermont's Supreme Court's decision in Baker v State which held that the state
had a 'constitutional obligation to extend to plaintiffs the common benefit, protection, and
security that Vermont law provides opposite-sex married couples' (www.lambdalegal.org/
sections/library/decisions/vermont December 1999).
Act Relating to Civil Unions (note 42 above) s 1(7).
Ibid s I (8).
Ibid s 3.
Ibid s 1(1).
Ibid s 3.
322
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
importantly retains the exclusivist traditional and religious content and
the less tangible connotations of marriage. The Vermont Act states:
Extending the benefits and protections of marriage to same-sex couples through a system
of civil unions preserves the fundamental constitutional right of each of the multitude of
religious faiths in Vermont to choose freely and without state interference to grant the
religious status, sacrament or blessing of marriage under the rules, practices or traditions
of such faiths. 48
It is in this formulation that we see that the denial of the name of
marriage amounts to a denial of substantive equality. The denial of the
name was of course achieved through a complex statutory process that,
while retaining the appearance of marriage, simultaneously denied gays
and lesbians spiritual and religious equality. 49 It is significantly the
spiritual and religious content of marriage that accords marriage
the socially privileged status that it has. When gays and lesbians wish to
marry it is not only legal equality that they desire but also the socially
accepted status of being married. The Vermont Act's bracketing off of the
religious, spiritual and less tangible content of marriage from civil unions
seems to be paying undue deference to religious orthodoxy in the guise of
religious freedom. This is done at the expense of gays and lesbians whose
freedom of religion is instead violated. The Vermont Act fails to create an
institution that upholds the equality of gays and lesbians as well as the
freedom of religion of both heterosexuals and gay and lesbian couples.
IV
POSSIBLE FUTURE DEVELOPMENTS
There are many routes that South Africa could go in seeking to create
equality for gay and lesbian relationships. The retention of marriage as
an exclusivist institution and the creation of a separate institution for
gays and lesbians (even if it were an institution available to heterosexuals
as well) would be by definition a violation of equality. Neither the
Vermont Act nor the north European models are satisfactory. However,
the National Coalition case, in its recognition of 'permanent same-sex life
partnership' alongside 'spouse', has already laid the legal foundation for
separate institutions. Furthermore, the South African Law Commission is
currently researching the legislative recognition of domestic partnerships.
It is possible, therefore, that Parliament will pre-empt any Constitutional
Court decision in this regard and establish a civil union not unlike the
Vermont model.
Another option would be to strip ministers of religion of their state
authority and grant no legal recognition to religious marriages. Although
this would result in equality for all who wish to get married, it would
simultaneously, and unnecessarily, infringe the freedom of religion of
48 Ibid s 1(11).
49 If substantive equality was what was being sought it would have been much easier to have
admitted gays and lesbians to the institution of marriage rather than creating a look-alike
institution.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
323
those persons whose religious marriages are recognised. If religious
marriages continue to receive state sanction, then would an extension
of marriage to gays and lesbians infringe on the religious freedom of
others? No religious group can claim an absolute right to define marriage.
South Africa has an unfortunate history in this regard in that only
Christian marriages once received state recognition. 50 The extension of
marriage to other religions and customary unions has not impinged on
the right of Christians to marry. All it has removed is their absolute claim
on marriage, which was not constitutionally acceptable.
The only constitutionally acceptable solution is to extend to gays and
lesbians the right to marry. They may then do so with the full religious
blessing of whatever faith wishes to marry them. This extension could be
achieved by legislation. Such a controversial step is, however, unlikely.
Extension will in all probability only be achieved by the Constitutional
Court. But will the Court uphold such a claim? Its jurisprudence in this
regard is somewhat ambivalent. There are numerous grounds on which
such a claim could be made, notably the right to equality, the right to
privacy and the right to dignity. 51 The first indication of possible judicial
acceptance of gay and lesbian marriage can be found in the Sodomy
judgment where Ackermann J stated:
The issues in this case touch on deep convictions and evoke strong emotions. It must not
be thought that the view which holds that sexual expression should be limited to marriage
between men and women with procreation as its dominant or sole purpose, is held by
crude bigots only. On the contrary, it is also sincerely held, for considered and nuanced
religious and other reasons, by persons who would not wish to have the physical
expression of sexual orientation differing from their own proscribed by the law.
It is nevertheless equally important to point out, that such views, however honestly and
sincerely held, cannot irifluence what the Constitution dictates in regard to discrimination on
the grounds of sexual orientation. 52 (emphasis added)
Yet in the National Coalition case Ackermann J seems to retreat from this
position. Admittedly the issue of marriage was not directly before the
Court, but only the definition of spouse. Even this issue, however, was
not thoroughly canvassed. Secondly, the Court's creation of a legal
construct, 'permanent same-sex life partnership', suggests that the Court
may already be considering an institution other than marriage through
which to recognise gay and lesbian relationships. This position may be
contrasted with the recent judgment of O'Regan J in Dawood: 53
The decision to enter into a marriage relationship and to sustain such a relationship is a
matter of defining significance for many if not most people and to prohibit the
50 See Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund (Commissioner for Gender Equality
Intervening) 1999 (4) SA 1319 (SCA) and Naude v Fraser 1998 (4) SA 539 (SCA).
51 Other writers have extensively commented on the cogency of these claims and it is not my
intention here to reconsider these arguments. See generally B Grant 'Comments and Cases on
Same-sex Marriage' (1996) 12 SAJHR 568.
52 Note 2 above, para 38 (internal footnotes omitted).
53 Note 21 above.
324
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
establishment of such a relationship impairs the ability of the individual to achieve
personal fulfilment in an aspect of life that is of central significance. In my view, such
legislation would clearly constitute an infringement of the right of dignity. 54
The right to dignity is here given extensive content. Coupled with equality
protection for gays and lesbians, it would now be difficult for the
Constitutional Court to refuse gays and lesbians the right to marry. Such
a decision would undermine the Court's own equality and dignity
jurisprudence that has been built not least upon the grounds of sexual
orientation and marital status:
South African families are diverse in character and marriages can be contracted under
several different legal regimes including African customary law, Islamic personal law and
the civil or common law. However, full legal recognition has historically been afforded
only to civil or common-law marriages. Even if the legal implications of the marriage
differ depending on the legal regime that governs it, the personal significance of the
relationship for those entering it and the public character of the institution, remain
profound. In addition, many of the core elements of the marriage relationship are
common between different legal regimes. 5 5
In light of the extension of marriage to different faiths and customs and
the developing jurisprudence in Dawood, gay and lesbian activists should
not narrowly call for their right to marry but instead for the equal right of
all to marry.
RONALD LOUW
*
Senior Lecturer in Law, University of Natal, Durban
Co-chairperson, National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality
MISSION IMPOSSIBLE: TRADE UNION AND PROTEST ACTION RIGHTS
IN THE MILITARY
SOUTH AFRICAN NATIONAL DEFENCE UNION V MINISTER OF DEFENCE
I INTRODUCTION
A class of men set apart from the general mass of the community, trained to particular
uses, formed to peculiar notions, governed by peculiar laws, marked by peculiar
distinctions. 1
27 Aprill994 marked a turning point in South African history. A system
of atrocious racist policies was replaced by one of democratic values.
54 Ibid para 37.
55 Ibid para 32.
* This article was written in my academic capacity. I wish to express my thanks to Zackie
Achmat for helpful comments on earlier drafts.
I M Howard Soldiers and Government (1957) II.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
325
Recognition of equality and human dignity emerged with the adoption of
the interim Constitution 2 and the first democratic elections. This newfound freedom needs to be protected from both internal and external
aggression. The responsibility for doing so lies primarily with the South
African National Defence Force (SANDF). Once the instrument of
government aggression, the Defence Force has now become the protector
of our new democracy. To fulfill this role effectively, the SANDF needs
to be disciplined and loyal to the state. In South African National Defence
Union v Minister of Defence 3 (SANDU) the Court had to determine
whether members of the SANDF should be entitled to participate in
protest action and whether members should be entitled to form and join
trade unions. The issue was whether or not such rights would challenge
the discipline of the military. Should these democratic rights be denied
to the protectors of democracy in order to maintain it?
II
PRE-CONSTITUTIONAL COURT SKIRMISHING
Before the 1994 elections, protest action in the form of stayaways was a
common occurrence in South Africa, 4 despite its illegality. When the
Labour Relations Act 66 of 1995 was drafted, special provision was made
for protest action. The 1995 Act, following the advice of the International
Labour Organisation (IL0), 5 allows workers to participate in protest
action provided that the aim of the action is to promote the workers'
socio-economic interests and that it is not purely political in character. 6
Workers participating in protest action are also required to follow a
stringent procedure before undertaking such action. 7 The 1995 Labour
Relations Act, however, did not apply to members of the SANDF. 8
SANDF members were still governed by the Defence Act 44 of 1957 (the
2 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution).
3 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC).
4 D du Toit eta! The Labour Relations Act of 1995 2 ed (1998) 243. Employees often protested
against the previous government's political and socio-economic policies. Such actions were
illegal in terms of the Labour Relations Act 28 of 1956 and many employees were dismissed for
participating. See A Basson et al Essential Labour Law Volume 2: Collective Labour Law I ed
(1998) 154.
5 In 1992, the International Labour Organisation's Fact-Finding and Conciliation Commission
on Freedom of Association investigated the validity of certain provisions of the 1956 Labour
Relations Act. They were critical of the narrow definition of strikes in the Act arguing that
employees should be allowed to partake in protest strikes aimed at criticising the government's
economic and social policies provided that they were not purely political in character. See the
ILO Report of the Fact Finding and Conciliation Commission on Freedom of Association
concerning the Republic of South Africa (May-June 1992).
6 Section 213 of the Labour Relations Act 66 of 1995 (the LRA) defines protest action as 'the
partial or complete concerted refusal to work, or the retardation or obstruction of work, for
the purpose of promoting or defending the socio-economic interest of workers, but not for a
purpose referred to in the definition of a strike'.
7 See s 77 of the LRA.
8 In terms ofs 2 of the LRA, the Act does not apply to members of the National Defence Force,
the National Intelligence Agency and the South African Secret Service.
326
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Act). Participation in protest action was prohibited in terms of
ss 126B(2)9 and 126B(4) 10 of that Act.
Likewise, SANDF members could not be members of trade unions in
the immediate post-apartheid era. Trade union movements emerged as a
response to exploitation by employers. The employment relationship is
contractual in nature. The parties are, however, rarely on an equal
footing. Employers have generally far greater bargaining power than
employees, who are usually in abundance. This often led to the
exploitation of employees. To cater for this problem, most states have
adopted legislation setting minimum standards of employment for
employees. 11
Another response to exploitation is the creation of trade unions.
Instead of acting individually, employees act collectively. With the aid of
trade unions, the bargaining power of employees improves and they are
able to negotiate better conditions of employment. 12 'It is only through
unity of purpose and control of the supply of labour that workers can
counter managerial power.' 13 This response is however often denied to
9 Section 126B(2) read:
Without derogating from the provisions of sections 4(h) and 10 of the Military Discipline
Code, a member of the South African Defence Force who is subject to the said Military
Discipline Code, shall not strike or perform any act of public protest or participate in any
strike or act of public protest or conspire with or incite or encourage, instigate or command
any other person (whether or not such person is a member of the South African Defence
Force or an officer or employee referred to in section 83A(2) serving in the South African
Defence Force or a member of any auxiliary or nursing service established under this Act) to
strike or to perform such an act or to participate in a strike or such an act.
10 Section 126B(4) read:
For the purpose of subsection (2) 'act of public protest' means any act, conduct or
behaviour which, without derogating from the generality of the aforegoing, includes the
holding or attendance of any meeting, assembly, rally, demonstration, procession,
concourse or other gathering and which is calculated, destined or intended to influence,
support, promote or oppose any proposed or actual policy, action, conduct or decision of
the Government of the Republic of South Africa or another country or territory or any
proposed or actual policy, action, conduct or decision of any public or parastatal authority
of the Republic or another country or territory or to support, promote, further, oppose or
publicize any real or supposed private or public interest, object, principle, cause, concern,
demand or claim, grievance, objection or outrage or to indicate, demonstrate or display real
or supposed private or public support for, opposition or objection to, dissatisfaction,
sympathy, association or solidarity with, or concern or outrage regarding any such policy,
action, conduct, decision, interest, object, principle, cause, concern, demand or claim,
grievance, objection or outrage, or to do so in relation to any event or occurrence of
national or public concern or importance or significance, or eliciting national or public
concern or interest, in such manner as to attract or direct thereto, or be calculated, destined
or intended to attract or direct thereto, the attention of:
(i) any such Government or authority;
(ii) any other country, territory or international or multinational organization, association
or body; or
(iii) the public or any member or sector of the public, whether within or outside the
Republic;
'strike' means any strike as defined in section I of the Labour Relations Act, 1956.
II The South African variant is the Basic Conditions of Employment Act 75 of 1997.
12 Basson (note 4 above) 2.
13 M Finnemore Introduction to Labour Relations in South Africa (1999) 4.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
327
persons within the armed forces of a state. In deciding whether or not to
grant Defence Force members trade union rights, states are faced with
two conflicting values: maintaining a disciplined defence force necessary
for state security versus the granting of trade union rights essential for
effective collective bargaining. South Africa opted for the former value.
As noted above, members of the permanent force were denied trade
union rights by ss 126B(l) 14 and 126B(3) 15 of the Defence Act.
The SANDF case began when the constitutional validity of these
restrictions was challenged in the Transvaal Provincial Division. 16
Hartzenburg J struck down s 126B(4) of the Act as unconstitutional in
its entirety. He also declared subsection (2) unconstitutional, but only
where it made reference to public protest. On the trade union issue, the
court struck down subsections (1) and (3). The orders were all suspended
until 31 December 1999.
The orders were referred to the Constitutional Court for confirmation
in terms of s 172(2) of the 1996 Constitution. 17 The South African
National Defence Union requested that the orders made by Hartzenburg J be confirmed. The Minister of Defence and the Chief of the
Defence Force did not oppose the confirmation of invalidity of
subsection (4) and parts of subsection (2), which prohibited members
of the SANDF from participating in protest action. They did, however,
oppose the confirmation of the order of invalidity in respect of s 126B(l),
which denied members of the Defence Force trade union membership. In
any event, the Constitutional Court still had to confirm the orders.
III
THE JuDGMENT oF THE CoNSTITUTIONAL CouRT
(a) Participation in Protest Action
The Court first considered the constitutional validity of the prohibition
on members of the SANDF from participating in protest action as
mentioned in s 126B(2) and defined in s 126B(4). In particular, it
considered whether this prohibition violated the right to freedom of
expression entrenched in s 16 of the 1996 Constitution. The Court held
that freedom of expression is of fundamental importance. It lies at that
heart of democracy and is important to the search for the truth. Against
this background, the definition of protest action in s 126B(4) was overly
broad and unclear. The definition was very lengthy. Its grammatical
14 Section 126B( I) read:
A member of the Permanent Force shall not be or become a member of any trade union as
defined in section I of the Labour Relations Act, 1956 (Act 28 of 1956): Provided that this
provision shall not preclude any member of such Force from being or becoming a member
of any professional or vocational institute, society, association or like body approved by the
Minister.
15 Section 126B(3) read: 'A member of the South African Defence Force who contravenes
subsection (I) or (2), shall be guilty of an offence.'
16 SA Defence Union v Minister of Defence 1999 (3) BCLR 32 (T).
17 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 108 of 1996 (1996 Constitution).
328
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
structure was clumsy and its overall meaning elusive. The broad
definition criminalised a wide range of conduct. It also did not
distinguish between on- and off-duty Defence Force members. Nor was
any distinction drawn between a public meeting and a private meeting in
one's own home. The Court concluded that s l26B(2) read with s 126B(4)
clearly infringed a Defence Force member's right to freedom of
expression. 18
For the majority, O'Regan J then went on to consider whether the
prohibition justifiably limited the right to freedom of expression as
contemplated in s 36 of the 1996 Constitution. One of the reasons for
prohibiting members of the Defence Force from participating in protest
action is because it is important that they act in a manner that encourages
confidence and trust in their dispassionate observation of their duties. To
do so they must not act in a partisan political fashion, as recognised
by s 199(7) of the 1996 Constitution. The Court, however, found that
s 126B(2) read with s 126B(4) went further than necessary. It seemed to
require that members of the SANDF detach themselves from society. It
prohibited members from forming, airing and hearing opinions on
matters of public interest even when they are off duty. Thus the court
held that s 126B(2) read with s 126B(4) was not saved by the limitations
clause. 19
O'Regan J next looked at whether or not it was possible to sever the
overly broad parts of the definition of public protest from s 126B(4) of
the Act. In this way only certain forms of public protest would be
prohibited and therefore s l26B(2) saved. O'Regan felt that it was not
possible to sever parts of the definition since the definition was too
clumsily worded and opaque. A remodelled definition by the Court
would also have the danger of not bearing any resemblance to what the
legislature may have originally intended. The whole of the definition in
s 126B(4) was therefore severed from the Act. With regard to s 126B(2),
only references to public protest were severed. The remainder of
s 126B(2) relating to the prohibition of strike action and the prohibition
of the incitement to strike action were left intact. 20
Another issue that the Court had to determine was whether or not its
order should be suspended. The Constitutional Court disagreed with the
High Court's order of suspension and declared that its order should take
immediate effect. Any lacuna arising from the invalidity of the provision,
the Court held, could be filled by the prohibition contained ins 146 of the
Military Discipline Code, which provides that any person who 'causes
actual or potential prejudice to good order and military discipline' shall
be guilty of an offence? 1
18
19
20
21
SANDU paras 6-9.
Ibid paras 10-13.
Ibid paras 14-15.
Ibid paras 37-39.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
329
(b) Membership in Trade Unions
In this part of its judgment, the Court had to determine whether
ss 126B(l) and 126B(3) of the Defence Act violated s 23(2) of the 1996
Constitution. Section 23(2) provides that '[e]very worker has the right(a) to form and join a trade union; (b) to participate in the activities and
programmes of a trade union; and (c) to strike.' The Court first had to
determine whether members of the permanent force constitute workers as
contemplated in s 23. Looking at the whole of s 23, the Court held that it
applies to a situation where a contract of employment is entered into
between two parties. Members of the permanent force do not enter into a
contract of employment; instead they enroll in the permanent force.
Despite this, the Court felt that the relationship between members of the
permanent force and the Defence Force is, with the exception of the way
in which members are disciplined, largely akin to an employment
relationship. Members of the permanent force receive salaries and
allowances. They are also entitled to certain benefits often found in
employment relationships such as leave, medical aid insurance and
transport expenses. 22
In determining whether the words 'every worker' in s 23 applied to
members of the Defence Force, the Court also looked to international
law for guidance. In particular, it looked at arts 2 and 9(1) of the
Freedom of Association and Protection of the Right to Organize
Convention 87 of 1948. 23 Article 2 recognises the right of workers to form
and join organisations of their own choosing. Article 9 on the other hand
leaves it open to the discretion of member states to determine the extent
to which these provisions should apply to members of the armed forces.
The court felt that this meant that the words 'every worker' in s 23 should
be interpreted to include members of the permanent force. 24
Since s 23(2) was interpreted to include members of the permanent
force, s 126B(l) was held to infringe their right to form and join trade
unions. The Court now had to determine whether or not this limitation
was justified in terms of s 36 of the Constitution. Section 200(1) of the
Constitution requires that the Defence Force be structured and managed
as a disciplined military force. The respondents argued that if members of
the permanent force were allowed to exercise their labour rights in terms
of s 23 the disciplinary character of the Defence Force would be
undermined, with grave consequences for the security of the state.
O'Regan J disagreed. It was possible, she held, for members of
the permanent Defence Force to be given limited and structured trade
union rights without challenging the discipline of the military. Section
126B(l) prohibited more than was necessary to maintain discipline in the
military. In providing for a total ban on trade unions in the Defence
22 Ibid paras 19-24.
23 Ibid paras 25-28.
24 Ibid paras 25-29.
330
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Force it clearly went beyond what is reasonable and justifiable in
achieving the legitimate state objective of a disciplined military force.
Section 126B(l) was therefore declared unconstitutional and invalid. 25
O'Regan J then went on to consider whether or not the Court's
declaration of invalidity should take immediate effect or be suspended.
The respondent requested that the order be suspended because time
would be needed to establish procedures regulating trade unions in the
Defence Force. Invalidating s 126B(l) without any regulations might be
potentially harmful. Regulations would be needed to avoid disruption to
discipline and to ensure that labour relations developed in a constructive
and orderly manner. The applicant on the other hand requested that the
order take immediate effect since there had already been a long delay.
The Court balanced the two interests in ordering that the declaration of
invalidity of s 126B(l) be suspended, but only for a period of three
months. This, the Court felt, would give the Minister of Defence
sufficient time to make regulations concerning trade union rights. The
Court further held that if the three-month suspension caused either
party substantial prejudice they could approach the Court for a variation
of its order. Finally, all references to s 126B(l) were severed from
s 126B(3). 26
IV
REGULATIONS: SUCCESSFUL REARGUARD ACTION
The Court's decision to suspend its order of invalidity for a period of
three months forced the Minister of Defence to make regulations with
some haste. On 20 August 1999, just before the end of the three-month
period, regulations under s 87(1)(rB) read with s 126C of the Defence Act
granting labour rights to members of the SANDF were made? 7 With
respect to participation in protest action, reg 8 provides that:
Members have the right to peaceful and unarmed assembly, demonstration, picket and
petition, and to present petitions in their private capacity: Provided that such right shall
not be exercised:
(a) while in uniform or wearing any part of a uniform or display any insignia linked to
the Defence Force, in a manner which indicates in any other way employment in the
Defence Force or the Department of Defence; or
(b) in respect of any matter concerning either the employment relationship with the
Department of Defence or any matter related to the Department of Defence.Z 8
These regulations give effect to the Constitutional Court judgment. They
allow SANDF members to participate in protest action. Members are
not, however, given a general right to participate in protest action. They
are only allowed to participate in protest action in their private capacity
25
26
27
28
Ibid paras 30-36.
Ibid paras 40-42.
See GN 410 in GG 20376 of 20 August 1999.
Regulation 7 provides further that: 'Subject to regulation 8, no member may participate in
peaceful and unarmed assembly, demonstration, picket and petition in support of a strike or
secondary strike if this relates to any defence matter.'
(2000) 16 SAJHR
331
and provided such action does not concern matters relating to their
employment relationship with the Department of Defence or any matter
related to the Department.
Generally, the regulations try to strike a balance between the right to
form trade unions and maintaining the disciplined character of the
military. Regulation 4 enables members of the SANDF to form military
trade unions? 9 A member's right to form a trade union is, however,
restricted. Regulation 24 indicates clearly that military professionalism
and military discipline should be adhered to at all times by members of
military trade unions. Members are also prohibited from participating in
strikes 30 and from entering into closed shop or agency shop agreements. 31
They are also prohibited from associating with any other labour
organisation, association, trade union or federation that is not
recognised or registered. Neither may members affiliate with any
political party or organisation. 32
The regulations also try to maintain discipline by ensuring that trade
unions do not play a role during certain essential military activities. Thus,
members of a military trade union are prohibited from participating
in trade union activities while involved in military operations or
military exercises or undergoing training as an integral part of a military
operation or during military training. 33 Neither may a military trade
union liase with its members during such activities. 34 From the date that a
state of emergency is declared or when the President has deployed the
Defence Force in terms of s 201(2)(b) of the 1996 Constitution, all trade
union activities other than administrative and financial functions of the
trade union shall be suspended until termination of such declaration or
employment. 35 A military trade union is also prohibited from undertaking or supporting any activity, which may impede military operations,
military exercises, training during military operations or exercises or the
preparation for military operations or exercises or during military
training. 36 Military trade unions may also not engage in collective
bargaining on matters relating to military operations, military exercises,
29 The regulations grant trade unions limited organisational rights (regs 9-20). Trade unions are
allowed representatives who are entitled to assist fellow members (regs 23-27). The regulations
also give the unions access to the Department of Defence (regs 33-35) and entitle them to
certain collective bargaining rights (reg 36). They are also entitled to access to information that
would enable them to perform their function as a trade union (reg 21 ). The regulations
establish a Military Arbitration Board (regs 72-80) and allow members to have recourse to the
High Court (regs 81-84). The regulations also enable members to form military bargaining
councils (regs 62-71). The registration of trade unions is dealt with in regs 41 to 54 and
accounting and auditing requirements in regs 55 to 61.
30 Regulation 6.
31 Regulation 19.
32 Regulation 13.
33 Regulation 37(1).
34 Regulation 37(2).
35 Regulation 38.
36 Regulation 39.
332
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
training during military operations or exercises or the preparation for
military operations or exercises or during military training. 37
V
ANALYSIS
(a) Participation in Protest Action
As noted above, the Constitutional Court declared the definition of
protest action in s 126B(4) of the Act unconstitutional. It also removed
any reference made to protest action from s 126B(2). At first glance this
may seem to indicate that members of the Defence Force are allowed to
participate in any protest action. However, this indication is quickly
shattered by O'Regan J's holding that members of the SANDF, when
participating in protest action, must still comply with the Military
Disciplinary Code, and in particular s 46 thereof. This section 'provides
that any person who "causes actual or potential prejudice to good order
and military discipline shall" be guilty of an offence'. 38
Section 146 itself is very broad and could prohibit a wide range of
protest action. Thus, it not only prohibits conduct that causes actual
prejudice to good order and discipline, but also conduct that may cause
potential prejudice. Terms such as 'good order' and 'military discipline'
are very broad and may cover a wide range of conduct. In the end,
therefore, although the Court declared s 126B(4) and parts of s 126B(2)
unconstitutional, it does not seem to have given members of the military
any real meaningful right to protest action.
This does not mean, of course, that soldiers should be blindly obedient.
As Sachs J correctly indicated in his minority judgment, 'a blindly
obedient soldier represents a greater threat to the Constitutional order
than one who [is] ... sensitive to his or her rights and responsibilities under
the Constitution.' 39 A soldier could thus refuse to follow unconstitutional
and illegal orders. This is manifested ins 199(5) of the Constitution, which
provides that 'the security services must act, and must teach and require
their members to act, in accordance with the Constitution and the law'.
Section 199(6) provides further, that 'no member of any security service
may obey a manifestly illegal order'. 40 The Court also indicated that
37 Regulation 40. In terms of reg 36, military trade unions may engage in collective bargaining,
and may negotiate on behalf of their members, only in respect of:
(a) the pay, salaries and allowances of members, including the pay structure;
(b) general service benefits;
(c) general conditions of service;
(d) labour practices; and
(e) procedures for engaging in union activities within units and bases of the Defence Force.
38 SANDU para 38.
39 Ibid para 47.
40 See also s 200(2) of the Constitution, which provides that '[t)he primary object of the defence
force is to defend and protect the Republic, its territorial integrity and its people in accordance
with the Constitution and the principles of international law regulating the use of force.'
(2000) 16 SAJHR
333
members should be allowed to participate in protest action in their
private capacity. 41 The effect of the judgment on protest action is
therefore that members of the Defence Force are still not given any
meaningful right to protest action and are still bound by further obstacles
found in the military disciplinary code. They can, however, refuse to
follow orders that are unlawful and/or unconstitutional and, as the Court
indicates, participate in protest action when not on duty.
The Court and the regulations' refusal to grant members of the
SANDF a general right to protest action is to be welcomed, since
the nature of the military requires discipline, loyalty and order. Protest
action has the potential to undermine these fundamental values. The
Constitutional Court's judgment and the regulations allowing members
to participate in protest action in their private capacity are, however,
disturbing. Allowing members to participate in protest action in their
private capacity could result in one of two situations, depending on one's
interpretation of regs 8(a) and 8(b). If these regulations are interpreted
broadly, they would prohibit a wide range of protest action in members'
private capacity, thereby depriving them of any meaningful right to
protest. For instance, reg 8(b) allows members to participate in protest
action in their private capacity except in matters relating to the
Department of Defence. Most matters in which members of the SANDF
are involved could be interpreted to relate directly or indirectly to
the Department of Defence. Since the protection of state security lies
primarily with the Department of Defence, any threat to the security
of the state, no matter how slight, could be seen as a matter relating to
the Department of Defence and therefore prohibited. Members of the
SANDF who believe that they have acquired the right to protest will
become frustrated once they realise that this right is essentially meaningless. This could lead to indiscipline and, in tum, threaten state security.
If the words 'matters relating to the Department of Defence' in reg 8(b)
are interpreted narrowly, on the other hand, members would be granted a
meaningful right to protest. But a narrow interpretation of reg 8(b) is
itself problematic for other reasons. Even if they are unrelated to
Department of Defence activities in the narrow sense, protests by
members of the SANDF, whether on or off duty, may still pose a danger
to the security of the country. For instance, suppose members of the
Defence Force, in their private capacity, protest against the foreign policy
of a particular country. It is unlikely that they will be prepared to assist
South Africa if later called upon to do so by the Department of Defence,
thus challenging military discipline and state security.
(b) Membership of Trade Unions
The effect of the Court's judgment in the SANDF case is that a total
prohibition on members of the Defence Force from forming trade unions
41 SANDU paras 9 and 12.
334
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
is unconstitutional and they should be allowed to form trade unions in
circumstances where there is no threat to the disciplinary nature of the
military. Despite the benefits of trade unionism to employees, it is often
unclear whether Defence Force members should be granted these rights. 42
The Defence Force is primarily responsible for maintaining state security.
The employment of members' expertise for their own advantage would
wreck the fabric of society. 43 Trade unions are often in conflict with
management. If members of the Defence Force are allowed to form trade
unions this may affect the loyalty and order required for a disciplined
military force, which may ultimately challenge the security of the state.
In order to avoid the indiscipline that could be created by granting
members of the SANDF absolute trade union rights, the Constitutional
Court and the subsequent regulations have provided them with only
limited rights. This is potentially dangerous and may actually lead to the
opposite of what is intended. The Constitutional Court judgment may
give members of the SANDF the impression that they have acquired
extensive trade union rights. In reality, however, the rights they have
acquired are worthless since military trade unions are prohibited from
partaking in most activities normally undertaken by trade unions. As
noted above, they are prohibited from striking and entering into closed
shop agreements. On discovering this, members of the SANDF may
become frustrated. This could encourage members to partake in unlawful
conduct in pursuit of fuller trade union rights, once again undermining
the military discipline and ultimately national security.
This problem could have been avoided had the Constitutional Court
denied members of the Defence Force trade union rights altogether. This
would have been possible had the Court taken a more cautious approach
to the interpretation of s 23(2)(a), which granted every worker the right
to form and join a trade union. O'Regan J indicates that members of the
Defence Force are 'workers' as contemplated in the section. One of her
reasons for doing so is the alleged support found for this proposition in
international law. The conclusion that international law recognises the
term 'workers' as including members of the Defence Force is, however,
dubious. Article 2 of the Freedom of Association and Protection of the
Right to Organize Convention does recognise the right of workers to
form and join organisations of their own choosing. But art 9 of the
Convention leaves it open to the discretion of member states to determine
42 A number of states have found it difficult to decide whether or not to grant Defence Force
members trade union rights. According to L Heinecken ('Court Rules in Favour of
Democracy' (I 999) July Salut I 0-11 ), a number of countries have given the military the right
to form collective associations. The majority of them have taken the form of professional
associations, with very few countries allowing members of the military to form fully-fledged
civilian-type trade unions. In most of these countries the power of the trade unions and
professional associations is limited.
43 SP Huntington The Soldier and the State: The Theory and Politics of Civil-Military Relations
(1998) 14.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
335
the extent to which these provisions should apply to members of the
armed forces. 44 Therefore, the term 'worker' does not automatically
apply to members of the Defence Force, as suggested by O'Regan J. In
fact it is left to the discretion of member states to determine whether or
not to grant members of the Defence Force these rights. 45
It is submitted that the term 'worker' found in s 23(2) of the 1996
Constitution should not have been interpreted to include members of the
Defence Force. Members of the SANDF are not merely employees of
the Defence Force as suggested by O'Regan J, but part and parcel of the
institution. There is a difference between an institution, to which
members of the Defence Force belong, and an occupation consisting of
workers. An institution is legitimated in terms of values and norms. An
occupation, on the other hand, is legitimated in terms of the marketplace.
Members of an institution follow a calling captured in words such as
duty, honour and country. They regard themselves as different and
separate from society. In an institution, members are expected to perform
tasks not limited to their military specialties. They are under the purview
of the military organisation, whether on- or off-duty and whether on or
off the base.
By contrast, workers in an occupation operate within a market. They
should enjoy a voice in the determination of their salary and working
conditions. The occupational model implies the priority of self-interest
rather than that of the organisation. 46
Charles Moskos and Frank Wood give three good reasons why one
should opt for a military of the institutional rather than the occupational
type. First, for the benefit of mission performance, there is an assumption
that institutional identification fosters greater organisational commitment
and performance than does occupational identification. The armed forces
require certain behaviour from their members that can never be made to
serve individual interests, certainly not in the narrow economic sense.
Institutional values require an unbounded definition of tasks. Occupationalism, however, defines task boundaries and sets standards of
accomplishment that, if met, signify adequate performance. In an occupation the employee need only do the job and no more, whereas in an
institution members are motivated to do more than they are supposed to. 47
44 Article 9(1): '[t]he extent to which the guarantees provided for in this convention shall apply to
the armed forces and the police shall be determined by national laws and regulations.'
45 Doubts regarding the status of members of the Defence Force as workers also seem to be
reflected in Sachs J's judgment. He indicates that instead of relying on s 23(2), which only
applies to 'workers', the Court should have relied on the right to freedom of association (s 18
of the Constitution) and the right to fair labour practices (s 23(1)), both of which apply to
'everyone' (SANDU para 48). It is submitted that reliance on these rights would not have made
much difference since they would still have been subject to reasonable and justifiable
limitations.
46 C Moskos & F Wood (eds) The Military: More Than Just a Job? (1998) 16-17.
47 Ibid 5.
336
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Secondly, occupationalism carries with it the danger of replacing the
intrinsic motivation of an institution with the extrinsic motivation of an
occupation. Instead of being motivated by the values and principles of
the institution the member is instead influenced by extrinsic factors such
as salary. This is potentially harmful since the reliance on extrinsic
rewards may weaken intrinsic motivation. Assume that the military
decides to motivate its members in an important skill by paying them
extra for that skill. In this situation we might expect that increasing
the extrinsic reward would increase the effort expanded. However, the
military person's motivation will possibly decrease if the extrinsic reward
is no longer forthcoming. 48
Thirdly, occupationalism may undermine military professionalism. If
military functions can be reduced to money then decisions on military
organisation and personnel become subject to cost-benefit analysis. An
institutional approach, by contrast, never loses sight of the uniqueness of
the military organisation in a democratic society. The nation has
entrusted its armed forces with the important task of defending the
national interest for which members could possibly risk life and limb. 49
One can sympathise with the Constitutional Court's desire to grant
trade union rights to the military by interpreting the right generously. In
an ideal democracy, it may be important to grant the greatest number of
rights to the greatest number of people. The Court should, however, have
been more cautious when dealing with the military. Members of the
SANDF play a unique role in society. Treating them as workers is a
denial of their institutional character and value, which are essential for
the protection of our democracy and state security. Trade union rights
should have been denied to the SANDF. Such a denial would not have
amounted to inferior treatment, but rather a recognition of the SANDF's
special role and place in society.
VI
CONCLUSION
The granting of labour rights to the military is dangerous, even more so
in the South African context. The SANDF is very volatile. It is made up
of a combination of opposing parties. Members of the pre-1994 Defence
Force, who were ordered to uphold the principles of apartheid and who
saw the liberation movement armies as the enemy, are now forced to
work together with them. 50 In attempting to unite these opposing groups,
the SANDF should not be given any further obstacles that could possibly
48 Ibid.
49 Ibid.
50 W Gutteridge (ed) South Africa's Defence and Security into the 21st Century (1996) 2. The
integration of these forces is not an easy task. It involves a number of issues, which if not done
carefully could disrupt the process. According to G Thiart ('The SA Army Post-war and Real
Democracy' (1999) August Salut 16), 'a definite effort towards gender equality and
determining measures to ensure representativity became a reality ... when seven forces
were integrated into the SANDF.'
337
(2000) 16 SAJHR
rupture an already unstable organisation. This is especially so in light of
the important role that the SANDF is likely to play in our fledgling
democracy. Not only is the SANDF responsible for national security, but
the order and discipline of the Defence Force may also be relied upon to
promote the socio-economic needs of the population. 5 1 In addition to this
the SANDF has important obligations internationally and regionally. 52
Whether or not the granting of trade union and protest action rights to
the SANDF will pose a threat to the security of the state will ultimately
depend on the support such action and organisation gets from members
of the SANDF. 53 The question we need to be asking ourselves, however,
is whether this is a risk worth taking.
MOHAMED ALLI CHICKTAY
Lecturer in Law, University of the Witwatersrand
THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT PROVIDES SUCCOUR FOR VICTIMS
OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE
S V BALOYI
I INTRODUCTION
In S v Baloyi 1 the Constitutional Court had occasion to consider the
constitutionality of s 3(5) of the Prevention of Family Violence Act 133
of 1993 (the Act). The subsection had been declared invalid by the
Transvaal High Court which had referred its finding to the Constitutional
51 J Cock & P Mackenzie From Defence to Development: Redirecting Military Resources in South
Africa (1998) 19. According to the authors, the SANDF has resources, equipment, skills and
infrastructure that could be used for reconstruction and development. They indicate that the
South African navy facilities could be used for training in diving, signals, catering and
computers. The SANDF could also be involved in adult education and literacy, in providing
health facilities through the South African Medical Services, and in loaning earth-moving and
other construction equipment.
52 Gutteridge (note 49 above) 157. The SANDF is to play a key role in a number of ways, eg
maintaining regional security, training missions, joint peacekeeping operations, and providing
international and regional disaster relief. South Africa, with one of the more powerful armies in
Africa, has a potentially important role to play in the Organisation of African Unity.
53 It is uncertain whether members of the SANDF support trade union and protest action rights
being given to them. In letters to the editor of the Defence Force journal ((1999) October Sa/ut
9), there were opposing views on whether members should be given these rights. One member
rejected these rights, arguing that: '[s]ou unies in die SANW toegelaat word, al is dit net as 'n
medium om sekere aangeleenthede te hanteer, sou dit katastrofiese gevolge vir die SANW
inhou' [there would be catastrophic consequences for the SANDF if trade unions were
allowed, even if just as a mechanism to deal with certain issues]. On the other hand, other
members accepted these rights, arguing that 'if you allow soldiers to join a union you make the
system more democratic and you reduce exploitation'.
2000 (I) BCLR 86 (CC) ( Baloyi).
338
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Court for confirmation? The High Court's declaration of invalidity was
based on three findings: that the subsection under review 'places a reverse
onus of proving absence of guilt on a person charged with breach of a
family violence interdict', 3 conflicting with the constitutionally protected
presumption of innocence, without compelling constitutional justification. The case presented the opportunity for the Constitutional Court to
confront the vexed issue of domestic violence, and to balance the need
to eradicate domestic violence with the constitutional rights of accused
persons to a fair trial.
Section 3(5) of the Act reads as follows:
The provisions of the Criminal Procedure Act ... 51 of 1977, relating to the procedure
which shall be followed in respect of an enquiry referred to in s 170 of that Act, shall
apply mutatis mutandis in respect of an enquiry under subsection 4.
Section 170 of the Criminal Procedure Act reads:
(!) An accused at criminal proceedings who is not in custody and who has not been
released on bail, and who fails to appear at the place and on the date and at the time to
which such proceedings may be adjourned or who fails to remain in attendance at such
proceedings as so adjourned, shall be guilty of an offence and liable to the punishment
prescribed under subsection (2).
(2) The court may, if satisfied that an accused referred to in subsection (1) has failed to
appear at the place and on the date and at the time to which the proceedings in question
were adjourned or has failed to remain in attendance at such proceedings as so
adjourned, issue a warrant for his arrest and, when he is brought before the court, in a
summary manner enquire into his failure so to appear or so to remain in a attendance
and, unless the accused satisfies the court that his failure was not due to fault on his part,
convict him of the offence referred to in subsection (I) and sentence him to a fine not
exceeding R300 or to imprisonment for a period not exceeding three months. 4
Section 3(5) becomes operative after an interdict has been obtained against
a person (almost always a male) in terms of the Act, the interdict has been
violated and the violator arrested. Section 3(2) of the Act provides for the
alleged violator to be brought before a judge or magistrate as soon as
possible. Section 3(4) allows the judge or magistrate, after an enquiry into
the alleged violation, either to order the release of the respondent from
custody or to convict the respondent as outlined in s 6. 5
2 Although the Prevention of Family Violence Act had been replaced by the Domestic Violence
Act 116 of 1998, the Constitutional Court believed it appropriate to deal with the sections under
review, since the appellant and others similarly situated would be affected by them.
3 Baloyi para I.
4 Emphasis added. Whether a reverse onus was placed on the appellant was the essence of the
enquiry in Baloyi.
5 Section 6 provides as follows:
A person who (a) contravenes an interdict or other order granted by a judge or magistrate under section
2(1) or (2); or
(b) fails to comply with the provisions of section 4, shall be guilty of an offence and liable
on conviction in the case of an offence referred to in paragraph (a) to a fine or imprisonment for a period not exceeding 12 months or to both such fine and such imprisonment
and in the case of an offence referred to in paragraph (b) to a fine or imprisonment for
a period not exceeding three months or to both such fine and such imprisonment.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
339
The Minister of Justice and the Commission for Gender Equality
intervened in the action challenging the High Court's decision on three
grounds. The first was that the 'alleged violators should not be considered
"accused persons" entitled to the presumption of innocence'. 6 Second,
even if they are to be treated as such, the sections of the Criminal
Procedure Act under review should not be interpreted as imposing a
reverse onus. Their third contention was that if the proper interpretation of those sections involved the imposition of a reverse onus, 'then
the limitation of the presumption of innocence involved could be
justified'. 7
II FACTS
The complainant, the wife of an army officer, had been granted an
interdict against her husband by a magistrate in Pretoria. The appellant
was ordered not to assault the complainant and their child, and not to
prevent them from entering or leaving the marital home. The appellant
ignored the interdict and subsequently assaulted and threatened to kill
the complainant. She complained to the police and, after she signed an
affidavit, the police arrested the appellant and brought him before a
magistrate to enquire into the alleged breach of the interdict.
III THE IssuE oF DoMESTIC VIOLENCE
The Court commenced its discussion by addressing the Constitution's
requirement that the problem of domestic violence be effectively dealt
with. Sachs J embarked on a thoughtful analysis of the need to deal comprehensively and effectively with the problem of domestic violence. Sachs J
described the unique 'hidden and repetitive character' 8 of domestic
violence, its ubiquity in cutting across class, race, cultural and geographical
boundaries and the deleterious consequences for society of its persistence.
Moreover, because domestic violence is so gender specific, it mirrors and
mimics patriarchal domination in a particularly abhorrent manner. 9
With intellectual precision Sachs J excavated the banality and
perceived inevitability of domestic violence, and the imperatives on the
government to stem it. He adroitly contextualised the problem as
embedded in partriarchy and the continued subordination of women. In
their research, women's organisations have uncovered the high levels of
6 Baloyi para 10.
7 Ibid.
8 Ibid para II. It has been estimated that one in every four adult women is regularly assaulted by
her partner. Jeni Irish 'Women and Political Violence' (1993) 16 Agenda 7.
9 Ibid para 12. Sachs J's identification of the intransigence of patriarchy in South Africa is not
new. Before he was appointed to the Constitutional Court, he wrote a frequently quoted article
on the pervasiveness of patriarchy, which he termed the only 'truly non-racial institution in
South Africa'. See Albie Sachs 'Judges and Gender: The Constitutional Rights of Women in a
Post-Apartheid South Africa' (1990) 7 Agenda I.
340
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
domestic abuse across all sectors of South African society. 10 These
disturbing numbers confirm the Court's assessment of the certain normalcy
or banality of domestic violence. 11 This analysis is purposely victimcentered, that is, Sachs J detailed the effects of domestic violence on the
victims. Moreover, he outlined how the collusion of the state in not rooting
out domestic violence undermines its promise of gender equality and nondiscrimination so clearly articulated in the Constitution. 12 Such inaction on
the part of the government also contradicts South Africa's international
and regional obligations; for example, those under the General Assembly
Declaration on the Elimination of Violence Against Women/ 3 the
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women 14 and the African Charter on Human and People's Rights. 15
Dealing with the constitutional presumption of innocence, 16 Sachs J
cited a list of Constitutional Court decisions that have reiterated this
right. 17 He then elaborated on the hybrid (public/private) nature of the
Act and analysed the complications that surface when the private (family)
domain intersects with the public through the interdict provisions. The
interdict proceedings in the Act are situated somewhere between family
and criminal law remedies, their purpose being to supplement and
enforce those remedies.
Citing feminist scholarship on this issue, Sachs J stressed the unique
character of domestic violence as a legal problem, because of the 'strange
alchemy of violence within intimacy'. 18 Innovative legal skills and
methods are therefore essential in combating the problem; and to some
10 For example, a survey conducted by the Human Sciences Research Council found that 43 per
cent of women in their survey sample in a Cape Town community had experienced marital
rape and assault. '43% of Women Claimed Marital Rape, Assault' The Citizen 18 August
1994, cited in Human Rights Watch/Africa Violence Against Women in South Africa (1995) 45.
II Human Rights Watch/Africa (note 10 above) 46-7 reported the following findings in their
surveys: 'A man is seen as necessary, especially in the rural areas, to have any hope of economic
security, and a degree of violence in a male-female relationship is frequently accepted as normal
and inevitable'. See also Catherine Campbell 'Learning to Kill? Masculinity, the Family and
Violence in Natal' (1992) 18 J of Southern African Studies 614. Campbell recounts (626) the
findings of a survey to probe violence in the family: 'Violence was a common theme in the young
respondents' accounts of their sexual relationships. Several respondents referred to the use of
violence in what they called the "common practice of forced sex" amongst young people.
Violence also played an important role in the territorial control of women'.
12 Of particular relevance to domestic violence is the right ins 12(1) of the 1996 Constitution:
'Everyone has the right to freedom and security of the person, which includes the right- ... (c) to
be free from all forms of violence from either public or private sources'. (Emphasis added)
13 GA Res 104 of 1993.
14 {1980) 19 ILM 33.
15 {1982) 21 ILM 58. The Charter was signed by South Africa in 1995 and ratified in 1996.
16 Section 35(3) of the 1996 Constitution provides: 'Every accused person has the right to a fair
trial, which includes the right - ... (h) to be presumed innocent, to remain silent, and not to
testify during the proceedings.'
17 The Court cites Osman v Attorney-General, Transvaall998 (4) SA 1224 (CC), Parbhoo v Getz
NO 1997 (4) SA 1095 (CC), S v Coetzee 1997 (3) SA 527 (CC), S v Mbatha 1996 (2) SA 464
(CC) and S v Bhulwana 1996 {I) SA 388 (CC).
18 Baloyi para 16, citing Joanne Fedler 'Lawyering Domestic Violence Through the Prevention of
Family Violence Act 1993- An Evaluation After a Year in Operation' (1995) 12 SAJHR 231.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
341
extent the interdict provisions of the Act create the legal space for such a
possibility. These provisions require that police officers and other actors
in the legal system temporarily jettison attitudes (often negative) about
the appropriateness or otherwise of interfering in private family matters.
In a country where victims of domestic violence have largely experienced
the policy as indifferent to their predicament, these provisions are
imperative if the attitudinal shift in policing domestic violence is to occur.
The interdict provisions are intended as an 'accessible, speedy, simple and
effective process' . 19 It is a proactive mechanism aimed at preventing
further violence without being punitive. In the words of Sachs J, 'it seeks
preventive rather than retributive justice'. 20
IV Is THE ALLEGED VIOLATOR AN 'ACCUSED PERSON'?
Sachs J then went on to deal with the three grounds on which the Act was
challenged. The first was whether the alleged violator is 'an accused
person' and therefore entitled to the presumption of innocence. Counsel
had argued on the basis of Nel v Le Roux 21 that the proceedings under
the Act were 'essentially civil in character' 22 and that the arrested person
was not an 'accused person' entitled to the right in s 35(3)(h). Nel had
dealt with the procedural consequences of the failure to testify when a
legal duty to do so has been established. Ackermann J had held that 'the
recalcitrant examinee who, on refusing or failing to answer a question,
triggers the possible operation of the imprisonment provisions ofs 189(1)
[of the Criminal Procedure Act] is not, in my view, an "accused person" '. 23
Ackermann J described the imprisonment provisions of s 189 as 'nothing
more than process in aid'. 24
Sachs J however distinguished the Baloyi situation from that which
pertained in Nel v Le Raux by pointing out the punitive nature of s 6 of
the Prevention of Family Violence Act, which provides for the conviction
to a fine or imprisonment for breach of the interdict provisions. Whereas
the examinees in Net carried 'the keys of their prison in their own
pockets', 25 no such situation existed with violators of the interdict
provisions of the Act. Once the enquiry into the alleged violation of the
Batoyi para 17.
Ibid.
1996 (3) SA 562 (CC).
Batoyi para 20.
23 Net (note 21 above) para 11.
24 Ibid. Section 189 of the Criminal Procedure Act provides that: 'If any person present at
criminal proceedings is required to give evidence at such proceedings and refuses to be sworn
or to make an affirmation as a witness, or, having been sworn or having made an affirmation
as a witness, refuses to answer any question put to him or refuses or fails to produce any book,
paper, document required to be produced by him, the court may in a summary manner enquire
into such refusal or failure and, unless the person so refusing or failing has a just excuses for
his refusal or failure, sentence him to imprisonment for a period not exceeding two years or,
where the criminal proceedings in question relate to an offence [referred to in Part III of
Schedule 2], to imprisonment for a period not exceeding five years.'
25 Net (note 14 above) para 11.
19
20
21
22
342
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
Act commences, the complainant essentially had abdicated control of the
proceedings to the state. In Sachs J's summary:
the objective is not to coerce the will to desist from on-going defiance, but to punish the
body for completed violation; and the convicted person carried no keys in his pocket indeed there is nothing in the Act to suggest that he can be released early if either the
complainant so wishes, or the judicial officer so decides.2 6
The Court concluded that the alleged violator of the interdict is an
'accused person' and therefore entitled to the presumption of innocence.
The Court then went on to discuss whether s 3(5) imposes a reverse
onus. Commenting on the 'obscure' 27 nature of the words utilised in s 3 of
the Family Violence Act and s 170 of the Criminal Procedure Act, Sachs J
examined three possible interpretations of the sections under review. They
are summarised in the judgment as interpretations A, B and C.
Interpretation A, emphasising the word 'procedure', allows only the
importation of the summary procedure, and not a reverse onus. In other
words, the protections guaranteed in the Criminal Procedure Act are not
suspended; there is therefore no reverse onus interfering with the
presumption of innocence. As the Court pointed out, this interpretation
lends itself to the approach mandated in s 39(2) of the Constitution:
'[w]hen interpreting any legislation ... every court ... must promote the
spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.'
Interpretation B embodies the High Court position, namely that s 170
'provides for a procedure which incorporates a reverse onus as a central
element'. 28
Interpretation C provides for a reverse onus, but only once the
'accused person' has proved lack of wilfulness on his part. As the Court
articulates this interpretation:
It presupposes that the judicial officer must first be satisfied beyond reasonable doubt
that the interdict has in fact been breached and that only then if the onus placed on the
alleged violator to prove on a balance of probabilities a lack of wilfulness on his part.
There is a reverse onus, but its reach would be restricted because it would be triggered
only after a breach of the interdict has been proved beyond a reasonable doubt. 29
Finding that interpretation C was too 'strained', 30 and not persuaded by
the High Court's position (interpretation B), the Court adopted
interpretation A as stating the correct legal position. Distinguishing the
substantive law question (what must be proved) and the procedural law
question (how to prove it), Sachs J pointed out that s 170(2) of the
Criminal Procedure Act provides for conviction for failure to attend
court proceedings 'unless the accused satisfies the court that his failure
was not due to fault on his part'? 1 This shifting of the burden to the
Baloyi para 22 (citations omitted).
Ibid para 24.
Ibid para 27.
Ibid para 28.
30 Ibid.
31 Ibid para 29.
26
27
28
29
(2000) 16 SAJHR
343
accused renders the issue one of substantive law, and therefore the
procedures of the Criminal Procedure Act are no longer apposite. In
short, the presumption of innocence is left undisturbed.
Sachs J referred to the need to provide the legislature with latitude in
dealing with intransigent social problems that find their way to the
courts. He does of course recognise that such latitude exists within
constitutionally appropriate limits; however, fairness to the complainant
is pre-eminent. This requires that the proceedings are 'speedy and
dispense with the normal process of charge and plea', 32 something akin to
a bail hearing.
Although the case was not mentioned in the Constitutional Court's
discussion, the question of the nature of the interdict proceedings under
the Act was dealt with by the Cape Provincial Division in 1997. In
Rutenberg v Magistrate, Wynberl 3 the applicant applied for review and
setting aside of the magistrate's decision on two bases. First, that the
magistrate had declined the applicant's request to conduct the hearing (to
have the interdict and order for his arrest set aside) in chambers and not
in open court. The applicant had argued that the hearings were
administrative or quasi-administrative in nature. The second basis was
that the magistrate had erred in allowing oral evidence to resolve the
disputes of fact on the papers. The Court held that the review had to fail,
specifying that the nature of the hearing was judicial. Secondly, the
decision of the magistrate 'to receive evidence viva voce and to try
the issue in dispute in a summary manner could not be faulted'. 34 The
Court suggested that a certain degree of latitude was to be accorded to
judicial officers in dealing with the interdict provision ins 2(1) of the Act.
Similar sentiments were expressed by Sachs J in Baloyi.
V
CONCLUSION
This judgment is another in a line of cases emanating from the
Constitutional Court which is carving out an impressive jurisprudence
with respect to women's rights and equality. 35 There is widespread
recognition that private violence against women is a cause for great
concern. Some would argue that it constitutes a continual violation of
women's human rights. The Court places its imprimatur on the need to
eradicate such violence, without constraining the constitutional rights of
the perpetrators.
32 Ibid para 31.
33 1997 (4) SA 735 (C).
34 Ibid 755F.
35 See, for example, President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo 1997 (4) SA I (CC), where
the court articulated a comprehensive definition of equality to incorporate not just formal
equality, but also substantive equality. Similarly, other courts have contributed to this new
dispensation of furthering women's rights. See, for example, Christian Lawyers Association of
SA v Minister of Health 1998 (II) BCLR 1434 (T) where the High Court confirmed a woman's
right to make decisions about her reproductive capacity and the right to exercise control of
her body, as articulated in the Constitution.
344
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
The Court's decision is incontrovertible: there is general societal
consensus that private violence, indeed any violence, against women is
odious and the state ought to deal with this problem aggressively. 36
However, there is still a large gap between ubiquitous cultural attitudes
about women, fuelled by a particular brand of South African
masculinity37 which gives rise to such violence, and the laudable
statements of the Court. Closing this gap will require a recognition that
the structural and attitudinal impediments to the 'right to be free from
private violence' as articulated in the 1996 Constitution, can only be
eradicated by a combination of governmental assaults which include
education, access to resources and continued vigilance about the extent
and persistence of violence. The Constitutional Court at least is doing its
part, but it needs to be bolstered by other institutional arrangements,
which will include both legal and extra-legal measures.
PENELOPE ANDREWS
Professor of Law, City University of New York
MAKING THE BILL OF RIGHTS A REALITY FOR GAY AND
LESBIAN COUPLES
NATIONAL COALITION FOR GAY AND LESBIAN EQUALITY V MINISTER
OF HOME AFFAJRS
I INTRODUCTION
According to Ackermann J, who delivered the judgment on behalf of a
unanimous Constitutional Court in this case, 1 there were two questions
for decision:
1. Whether it is unconstitutional for immigration law to facilitate the
immigration into South Africa of the spouses of permanent South
36 The Domestic Violence Act 116 of 1998, which replaced the Family Violence Act reflects the
government's commitment to eradicating domestic violence. For example, the new Act's
expansive definition of 'domestic violence' to incorporate physical as well as emotional and
economic abuse (and other forms of abuse) recognises the range of suffering perpetrated by
abusive spouses. Similarly, the Act's definition of 'domestic relationship' provides protection
for spouses who may not be formally married, for example those married according to
customary law, or same-sex couples, as well as for a host of family members beyond the
spouse, for example, children. Section 2 of the Act imposes a duty on police officers to assist
and inform complainants of their rights under the Act. Section 4 of the Act also provides fairly
comprehensive provisions to ensure that victims of domestic abuse are able to obtain
protection orders against abusive spouses, with the assistance of parties who may have an
interest in the complainant's welfare. Section 5-8 allow for streamlined set of procedures to
interdict the abuser.
37 Sachs (note 9 above).
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (2) SA I (CC)
(National Coalition).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
345
African residents but not to afford the same benefits to gays and
lesbians in permanent same-sex life partnerships with permanent
residents of South Africa.
2. Whether, when a court concludes that provisions in a statute
are unconstitutional, it may read words into the statute to remedy the
unconstitutionality.
II
FACTS
The facts of the case were as follows. After the 1994 elections the
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality (NCGLE) initiated
discussions with the Director-General of Home Affairs on a number of
issues, including the failure to recognise same-sex relationships for
purposes of granting immigration permits under s 25(4), (5) and (6) of the
Aliens Control Act 96 of 1991 (the Act). A 'cordial' working relationship
developed between the parties, and the Director-General confirmed that
exemptions in terms of s 23(b) of the Act would be considered on merit.
As a result of the continued requests for express statutory recognition of
same-sex relationships for purposes of s 25(4), (5), and (6), at least
thirteen temporary exemptions were granted between April and
November 1997 under s 28(2) of the Act to foreign same-sex partners
of lesbian and gay South Africans.
Section 25(4) of the Aliens Control Act sets out the conditions under
which an immigration permit may be issued, while s 25(5) makes
provision for the issuing of an immigration permit even where the
conditions in s 25(4) are not met. Section 25(6) states that the regional
committee may refuse to issue a permit where it is not satisfied that a
marriage entered into two years before application for such a permit was
not contracted for the purpose of evading a provision of the Act. In terms
of s 28(2) the Minister of Home Affairs may exempt any person or
categories of persons from the provisions ofs 23 (which outlaws entry into
the country without a permanent or temporary residence permit), if he
is satisfied that there are special circumstances which justify his decision.
During 1997 the department changed its attitude and this resulted in a
blanket refusal of such exemptions to foreign same-sex partners of South
African permanent residents. According to a letter from the DirectorGeneral of Home Affairs to the NCGLE, exemptions could only be
granted in 'special circumstances' and the fact that the Act did not cater
for same-sex relationships could not be considered as special circumstances.
Various steps were taken by the NCGLE to address this situation but
to no avail, and an application to declares 25(5) invalid was launched in
the High Court. 2 The matter was decided in favour of the applicants and
an appeal was lodged by the Minister against this decision.
2 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 1999 (3) SA 173 (C).
346
III
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
RIPENESS OF THE MATTER FOR HEARING
The respondents argued that the matter was not ripe for hearing
because the applicants had failed to pursue a non-constitutional remedy,
which if successful, might have rendered it unnecessary to consider the
constitutional validity of s 25(5). This contention had been dismissed by
the High Court. Ackermann J agreed with the High Court that the word
'spouse' as used in subsection (5) was not 'reasonably capable of the
construction as contended by the respondents'. The respondents had
argued that a regional committee may under s 39(2) of the Constitution
interpret 'spouse' as including a same-sex life partner.
Ackermann J further stated that the ordinary meaning of the word
spouse and the use of the word in s 25 of the Act did not recognise it
beyond its ordinary meaning of a 'married person, a wife, a husband'.
The Justice concluded that under these circumstances it was not possible
to construe the word 'spouse' ins 25(5) as including the foreign same-sex
partners of a permanent or lawful South African resident. The applicants
were therefore not able in law to successfully pursue a non-constitutional
remedy, based on such an interpretation of 'spouse'. Ackermann J held
that the respondents' contention that the constitutional issue was not ripe
for hearing was rightly dismissed by the High Court.
IV
CONSTITUTIONALITY OF SECTION
25(5)
OF THE ALIENS CONTROL ACT
Ackermann J held that the respondents could not rely on the contention
that South Africa as a sovereign independent state was lawfully entitled
to exclude any foreign nationals and that it had absolute discretion to do
so. According to Ackermann J, the present case did not involve 'such a
category of foreign nationals', but persons who are in intimate life
partnerships with people who were permanently or lawfully resident in
South Africa. Failure of the Act to give recognition to same-sex life
partnerships impacts in the same way on the South African partners as it
does on the foreign national partners. Consequently, this case had to be
decided on the basis of whether s 25(5) unconstitutionally limited the
rights of the South African partners.
The Court relied on its previous decision in amongst others, Ferreira v
Levin N0, 3 that a litigant who has standing may rely on the objective
unconstitutionality of a statute for the relief sought, even though the right
unconstitutionally infringed is not that of the litigant in question but
some other person. Therefore, the foreign nationals are entitled to rely on
any unconstitutional infringement of any of the rights of the South
African partners which was brought about by the failure of the Act to
grant any recognition to same-sex life partnerships.
The Court further examined the limitation by s 25(5) of the right to
equality (s 9 of the Constitution) and dignity (s 10). In the High Court's
3 1996 (!)SA 984 (CC).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
347
decision, Davis J found that s 25(5) constituted a clear limitation of the
s 9 guarantee against unfair discrimination because it differentiated on
the grounds of sexual orientation. Furthermore, under s 9(5), such a
differentiation being a ground specified in s 9(3) is presumed unfair
unless the contrary is established. According to the High Court, the
respondents' had not established the contrary.
The Constitutional Court held that, as with National Coalition for Gay
and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice 4 (the 'Sodomy case'), the rights
of equality and dignity are also closely related. Ackermann J followed the
approach laid down by the Constitutional Court in Harksen v Lane N0 5
and the Sodomy case. He further held that that the differentiation
brought about by s 25(5) is of a negative kind because it fails to extend
the same advantages or benefits to foreign same-sex life partners that it
extends to spouses.
Ackermann J rejected the respondents' submission that the conclusion reached by the High Court (that the omission in s 25(5) was
a differentiation based on sexual orientation) was incorrect because the
differentiation was based on 'non-spousal' grounds, rather than on
marital status, and did therefore not constitute unfair discrimination. He
also rejected the respondents' alternative submission that gays and
lesbians are free to marry as a 'meaningless abstraction'. The Court held
that this submission ignored the constitutional injunction that gays and
lesbians cannot be discriminated against on the grounds of their
sexual orientation. The better view, according to the Justice, was that
the discrimination in s 25(5) 'constitutes overlapping or intersecting
discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation and marital status,
both being specified in s 9(3) and presumed to constitute unfair
discrimination by reason of s 9(5) of the Constitution'. 6
V
IMPACT OF THE DISCRIMINATION
The deciding factor regarding the unfairness of discrimination was
the impact of the discrimination on the complainants or members of the
affected group, according to the Court. This entailed assessing
'cumulatively and objectively' various factors such as the position of
the complainant in society, the nature of the provision and the purpose to
be achieved, and any other related factors. In doing this, the Court
recognised the ruling by the Canadian Supreme Court7 that the central
purpose of its equality guarantee was the protection and promotion of
human dignity. In accordance with this decision, the Court held that the
discrimination denied gay and lesbian people equality and dignity which
are the foundations upon which the Constitution is based. The Court also
4
5
6
7
1999 (I) SA 6 (CC).
1998 (!)SA 300 (CC).
National Coalition para 40.
Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) (1999) 170 DLR (4th).
348
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
accepted that an enquiry into past disadvantage was important because it
revealed the vulnerability of the group. In this regard it made reference to
its decision in President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo, 8 where it
held that '[t]he more vulnerable the group adversely affected by the
discrimination, the more likely the discrimination will be held to be
unfair'.
In deciding the impact of the discrimination on the affected applicants,
the Court acknowledged the following:
(i) That there has been a change in societal and legal concepts regarding
family and what it comprises;
(ii) That in countries such as Canada, Israel, the united Kingdom and
the United States of America, there has been an increased
understanding and sensitivity towards 'human diversity in general
and to gays and lesbians in particular' .9
It therefore held that the impact of s 25(5) was to reinforce harmful and
hurtful stereotypes of gays and lesbians.
The Court also rejected the respondents' argument that it was of public
importance to protect the traditional institution of marriage. Ackermann J stated that protecting the traditional institution of marriage as
recognized by law may not be done in a way which unjustifiably limits the
constitutional rights of parties in a permanent same-sex life partnership.
Furthermore, there was no rational connection between the exclusion of
same-sex life partners from the benefits of s 25(5) and the government's
interest to be achieved. This was supported by the decision in M v H 10
where the Canadian Supreme Court held that the concern for the
protection of same-sex partnerships in no way implies a disparagement of
the traditional institution of marriage. The Constitutional Court
therefore held that s 25(5) constituted unfair discrimination or a serious
limitation of the equality right and the right to dignity enjoyed by gays
and lesbians.
VI JUSTIFICATION IN TERMS OF SECTION 36 OF THE 1996 CONSTITUTION
In terms of the s 36(1) justification analysis, the Court applied the test in
S v Makwanyane 11 (as adapted for the 1996 Constitution in the Sodomy
case 12), which includes proportionality in relation to the balancing of
interests. On one side, the Court held the effect of omitting same-sex life
partnerships from s 25(5) limits the rights to equality and dignity 'at a
deep and serious level'. The Court further held that there is no interest on
the other side that entered into the balancing process. Consequently,
8
9
10
II
12
1997 (4) SA I (CC).
National Coalition para 48.
(1999) 171 DLR (4th).
1995 (3) SA 391 (CC).
Note 4 above.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
349
there was no justification for the limitation and that s 25(5) is inconsistent
with the Constitution and invalid.
VII
BROADER APPLICATION OF THE DECISION
Ackermann J emphasised that the position of unmarried partners in
permanent heterosexual relationships and their omission from s 25(5)
was never at issue and that it could therefore not express a view on it. The
matter was therefore left open. He further held that the Court did not in
this case reach the question of whether, or to what extent, the law ought
to give formal institutional recognition to same-sex partnerships, and this
issue was also left open.
VIII
THE APPROPRIATE REMEDY
In reaching its decision the High Court opted for a 'declaration of
invalidity to provide that the section is inconsistent with the Constitution
to the extent that it confers an exclusive benefit on spouses and hence
discriminates on the grounds of sexual orientation, the rest of the section
could remain valid' .13 The Constitutional Court, however, held that
where the invalidity of a statutory provision results from an omission, it
is not possible to achieve notional severance by using words such as 'to
the extent that'. The only equivalent to severance would be 'reading in'.
In the present case, Ackermann J contended that there were only two
options: declaring the whole of s 25(5) invalid or reading in provisions to
cure the invalidity.
In declaring a section invalid, the Court recognised that regard should
be had to two issues: the first is to provide appropriate relief and the
second is the separation of powers, which involves 'restraint by the courts
in not trespassing onto ... the legislative field' . 14 As a result, the Court
concluded that reading in was the appropriate form of relief under s 38 of
the Constitution. The Court finally had to decide whether reading would
be 'just and equitable' and an appropriate remedy in this case.
In reaching its decision the Court had to have regard to a number of
factors including the fact that:
(i) A court should bear in mind that it will not be appropriate to read
words in, unless it can define with sufficient precision how the statute
ought to be extended in order to comply with the Constitution;
(ii) Striking down the section will deprive spouses of the benefits
conferred by the section;
(iii) An appropriate remedy must vindicate the rights of permanent
same-sex life partners to establish a family unit that receives the
same protection as marriages recognised by the law;
13 Note 2 above. See National Coalition para 62.
14 National Coalition para 66.
350
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
(iv) That the court should only provide the reading in remedy for samesex life partners involved in a permanent relationship, because it was
only in relation to them that the court was called upon to decide.
IX THE ORDER
The Court held that permanent same-sex partners are entitled to an
effective remedy for the breach of their rights to equality and dignity. In
this regard the remedy had to take effect immediately for it to be
effective. Furthermore, in order to avoid uncertainty, the order should
be limited and have no retrospective effect. The Court held that such an
order is 'just and equitable' because it will cause no prejudice to same-sex
partners who want to seek relief under the Act immediately after the
order has been granted.
SHIREEN MOTARA
Gender and Labour Law Consultant, Johannesburg
CIVILISATION AND ITS MALCONTENTS
PRESIDENT OF THE REPUBLIC OF SOUTH AFRICA V SOUTH AFRICAN
RUGBY FOOTBALL UNION
It is always possible to bind a considerable number of people in love, so long as there are
other people left over to receive the manifestations of their aggressiveness.
Sigmund Freud
Civilization and its Discontents (I929)
(trans Joan Riviere, 1930)
I INTRODUCTION: THE NARCISSISM OF MINOR DIFFERENCE
Spike Lee's film - Do The Right Thing- features a long set of jump-cuts
between several of the main characters, each uttering a quick rap of
bigoted expletive aimed at one of the numerous ethnic, racial and
religious groups represented in the movie. In the searing heat of a New
York summer, an African-American lays into his Italian-American
co-worker: 'Dago, Wop, Guinea, garlic-breath, pizza-slinging, spaghettibending, Vic Damone, Perry Cuomo, Luciano Pavarotti, solo mio,
non-singing, mother-fucker.' His Italian-American co-worker gives as
good as he gets: 'You gold teeth, cheap gold chain-wearing, fried chickenbiscuit-eating, monkey, ape, baboon, big thigh, fast-running, high
jumping, 360-degree basketball-dunking, titsoon, spade, take-yourpizza-back-to-Africa molanyone.' A Latino-American jumps in and on
Korean-Americans: 'You slanty-eyed, me-no-speaky English, own every
fruit and vegetable stand in New York, bullshit Reverend Sun Yung
·(2000) 16 SAJHR
351
Moon, Summer Olympic '88, Korean kick-boxing, son-of-a-bitch.' A
white cop gets in his vituperative two cents on Latinos: 'You Goya beaneating, 15-in-a-car, 30-in-an-apartment, pointy shoes, red wearing,
menudo-eatin', Puerto Rican, cock-sucker.' A Korean grocer rips into
his Jewish fellow New Yorkers: 'It's cheap, it's good, I got good price for
you, Mayor Koch, "How'm I doing", chocolate egg-creme drinking,
bagels and lox, B'nai Brith, Jew-asshole.'
This reflexive and aggressive privileging of one community's claims
against those of another might be understood in terms of what Freud has
described as 'the narcissism of minor difference' . 1 When the world creates
a sense of anxiety within us- as a dangerous and uncertain place is apt to
do - we often respond by searching aggressively for a specific, external
cause for that anxiety. More often than not, the cause we divine is
another person, a witch, or another people, say, the Gypsies, who live
within relatively close proximity. After blame comes the instinctual
upshot of our aggression: building walled ghettos, exile, burning at the
stake, lining them up to be shot. Given that South Africans of all hues
and creeds have so often borne the brunt of this narcissism of minor
difference, it is somewhat ironic, if all too human, that South Africans,
today, as members of different communities, have been so quick to find
that the fault with the world lies not with its inherently capricious ways,
but with a neighbour bent on destroying them or putting their livelihood
at risk.
This case comment opens with these two twentieth-century views of
communal relations- Freud's and Lee's- because I have a deepening
concern about South African politics and an abiding respect for the work
of its Constitutional Court. First, the architects of apartheid must be
given their due for turning the policy of 'apartness' into one of the best
case histories of 'narcissism of minor difference'. Their legacy, however,
has been to leave a state of balkanized communities, each tight and
united, but without the requisite contact with and trust of other
communities necessary to transform the new South Africa into a vibrant
constitutional democracy. Respect - one citizen for another - must be
I This phrase can first be found in Freud's Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego (1921)
(trans James Strachey, 1940):
In the undisguised antipathies and aversion which people feel towards strangers ... we may
recognize the expression of self-love- of narcissism. This self-love works for the preservation
of the individual. and behaves as though the occurrence of any divergence from his own
particular lines of development involved a criticism of them and a demand for their
alteration.
The analysis and characterization of group aggression itself dates back to Freud's The Taboo of
Virginity (trans 1918):
Of two neighboring towns each is the other's most jealous rival; every little canton looks
down upon the others with contempt. Closely related races keep one another at arm's length;
the South German cannot endure the North German, the Englishman casts every kind of
aspersion on the Scot, the Spaniard despises the Portuguese. We are no longer astonished
that greater differences should lead to an almost insuperable repugnance, such as the Gallic
feel for the German, the Aryan for the Semite and the white races for the colored.
352
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
paid. Second, I wonder how an institution - the Constitutional Court charged with the responsibility of modelling public discourse in a new
polity is to operate in an atmosphere almost wholly averse to constructive, civilised conversation. The answer is, I believe, on display in the
Court's judgment on the recusal application in President of the Republic
of South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union (SARFU). 2
Part II of this comment sets out SARFU's most salient facts,
allegations and conclusions: it suggests how the decision reflects both a
dramatic break with the past and a model for future adjudication.
Part III describes South Africa's law of contempt up to and through
SARFU: it suggests how the decision should alter an important area of
the law in a society not known for privileging open and candid discourse.
Part IV looks at SARFU as an example of how the Constitutional Court
has taken on the project of teaching South Africa's citizens how to engage
one another in reasoned, reflective and principled discourse.
II
THE FACTS AND THE JUDGMENT: NAMES WILL NEVER HURT ME
The case came to the Constitutional Court by way of the Transvaal High
Court. 3 In April 1998, the latter Court set aside the appointment
of a presidential commission of inquiry into the affairs of the
South African Rugby Football Union. The President, the Minister of
Sport and Tourism and the Director-General of the Department of Sport
and Recreation appealed that decision. The Constitutional Court agreed
to hear the appeal.
Three court days before the appeal was due to be heard, Dr Louis
Luyt, a former president of SARFU, filed a recusal application.
Although his allegations implicated each of the judges of the Court,
Dr Luyt directed the application at only five judges, stating that he 'left it
to the conscience' of the others to decide what to do. Dr Luyt did not
allege that any of the judges were actually biased. Instead his application
was based on what he described as a reasonable apprehension that
Chaskalson P, Langa DP and Kriegler, Sachs and Yacoob JJ would be
biased in favour of President Mandela and the parties and against him. In
short, the allegation of bias boiled down to several claims: (1) that
the Court decided it was the appropriate venue for appeal; (2) that the
Justices had been appointed by the President and would therefore be
beholden to him; (3) that their political association with the ANC prior
to their appointment would cloud their judgment; (4) that Chaskalson P
and President Mandela shared a close and long-standing professional,
political and personal relationship - which included Mandela's appearance at the wedding of Justice Chaskalson's son - which rendered
Chaskalson P unfit to preside over the case.
2 1999 (4) SA 147 (CC).
3 SARFU v President of the Republic of the RSA 1998 (10) BCLR 1256 (T).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
353
The application was unanimously dismissed. What is remarkable about
the judgment which followed- given the venom of the application- is its
muted tones. The Court noted that judicial officers are under a duty to
withdraw from cases if there is a reasonable apprehension that they will
not decide the case impartially: but no such grounds obtained in this case.
In rejecting the notion that politically suspect relationships existed
between President Mandela and various members of the bench, the Court
pointed out that in most democracies judicial officers engage in political
activity prior to their appointment to the bench and, after appointment,
have to decide cases with significant and unavoidable political
implications. Moreover, the Court added that one could hardly argue
that judicial officers do not have political preferences and that such views
are not made manifest in their judgments.
The Court did avail itself of the opportunity to make at least one
barbed reply to the failed application. Dr Luyt had alleged that because
of the public criticism of De Villiers J's decision in the Transvaal High
Court, the judges of the Constitutional Court would be afraid to act
impartially. In dispensing with this line of argument, the Court deplored
the tendency of those who disagreed with the decisions of the South
African courts to impugn the integrity of judicial officers rather than
engage the reasons for their judgments. While fully conceding that the
decisions of the South African courts were not immune from criticism,
the Court firmly insisted that political discontent or dissatisfaction with
the outcome of a case can be no justification for recklessly attacking the
integrity of judicial officers.
This justification for the rejection of the recusal application is
noteworthy for three reasons. First, the judgment emphasises that the
correct way to engage judicial pronouncements is in terms of the reasons
offered for those pronouncements. Second, the Court acknowledges that
judges are now drawn from all sectors of society and that we should not
expect that they will leave their backgrounds or political philosophies
behind once they take their place on the bench: an admission that judges
are, in the end, political actors. Finally, the judgment is noteworthy for
what it does not do. Though the Court was empowered by statute to do so, 4
4 The Constitutional Court has been granted, by statute, the power to deal with contempt.
Section 9,of the Constitutional Court Complementary Act 13 of 1995 provides:
(I) Any person who(a) during the sitting of the Court, wilfully insults any member of the Court or any
officer of the Court present at the sitting, or who wilfully hinders or obstructs any
member of the Court or any officer thereof in the exercise of his or her powers or
the performance of his or her duties;
(b) wilfully interrupts the proceedings of the Court or otherwise misbehaves himself or
herself in the place where the sitting of the Court is held; or
(c) does anything calculated improperly to influence the Court in respect of any matter
being or to be considered by the Court, may by order of the Court, be removed and
detained in custody until the rising of the Court.
(2) Removal and detention in terms of sub-section (I) shall not preclude the prosecution in
a court of law of the person concerned on a charge of contempt of court.
354
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
and though it possessed a long line of authority for such action, the Court
chose not to hold Dr Luyt in contempt in facie curiae for words or
conduct perceived as violative of the court's dignity, repute or authority
or otherwise having the tendency to interfere with the administration of
justice, nor did it avail itself of the summary procedures available for
such an offence. Instead, just as it admonished Dr Luyt and all other
critics of the Court, it chose reasons and arguments as the appropriate
response to intemperate remarks. It both established how the Court
would break from the manner in which judicial authority was wielded in
the past and demonstrated how public discourse ought now to be
modelled in a new South Africa still fraught with anxiety and aggression.
III CONTEMPT OF COURT: INTIMATIONS OF CHANGE IN THE WAY COURTS
MODEL PUBLIC DISCOURSE
Though the decision does not announce itself as such, the SARFU
judgment provides some indication of how the Court might choose to
rule upon certain kinds of contempt cases that come before it in the
future. Before we chart the Court's prospective new course, it would seem
worthwhile to document briefly the South African courts' doctrines in
this area of law.
The primary justification for the crime of contempt of court has been
that courts of law must be able to come to a proper decision without
improper inside or outside influences, and that justice can be upheld only
if the courts enjoy the respect and confidence of the public. Courts
consider contempt to have been committed when one unlawfully and
intentionally violates the dignity, repute or authority of a judicial officer
in his or her official capacity or of a judicial body, or when one
unlawfully and intentionally interferes with the administration of justice
in a matter pending before a court. 5
5 Following English common law classifications, the South African courts have divided contempt
of court into civil contempt and criminal contempt. This terminology is misleading because
both 'civil' and 'criminal' criminal contempt may, in appropriate circumstances, constitute a
criminal offence. However, the distinction still remains important because in the case of a civil
contempt, the court's sanctions are usually invoked at the instance of a private party and are
primarily designed to secure compliance with the court's order. Criminal contempt may be said
to fall into three categories: (I) Contempt in facie curiae; (2) contempt ex facie curiae with
reference to pending judicial proceedings; and (3) contempt ex facie curiae without reference to
pending proceedings.
(i) Contempt in facie curiae: Contempt in facie curiae is generally understood to consist of
insults, interruptions and other misdemeanors by either words or conduct. The words
or conduct have to be perceived as violative of the court's dignity, repute or authority or
otherwise having the tendency to interfere with the administration of justice. Contempt
in facie curiae differs from the other two species of criminal contempt in that the court
can summarily punish the offender - provided the offender is informed of the conduct
alleged to constitute the offence. The alleged wrongdoer must also be given an
opportunity to show cause why he should not be punished. The power to punish
summarily for contempt is deemed to be essential to uphold the dignity and authority of
the court. Less drastic measures would appear not to suffice.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
355
(a) Contempt of Court under apartheid
It is possible to read some of the reported decisions of the former
Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of South Africa (now the
Supreme Court of Appeal) and leave with the impression that there has
been a genuine effort to use the doctrine of contempt of court primarily
for the protection of the administration of justice.
But a comprehensive reading of the case law is apt to leave one with the
sense that a citation for contempt of court was designed to restrict
the expression of the party charged. Barend Van Niekerk, renowned for
his own problems with contempt citations, has argued that the problem
with most contempt of court doctrines is that they privilege the interests
of the judiciary and other legal institutions over the interests of free
speech, fair trials, individual rights and unfettered public discourse. The
better part of South Africa's contempt of court cases would appear to
support Van Niekerk's assertion.
In S v Pitje, 6 the accused was an articled clerk with the law firm of
Nelson Mandela and Oliver Tambo. As a protest against the courtsanctioned discrimination between black and white lawyers, Pitje refused
to sit at a table set aside for black lawyers. Pitje informed the court that
justice is colour-blind. Furthermore, in a sworn statement before the
court, Pitje claimed that the discriminatory treatment of African jurists
offended the most basic principles of fairness, decency and justice. For
stating the obvious, Pitje was convicted of contempt. Pitje appealed.
The Appellate Division confirmed his conviction on the grounds that the
sworn statement could only be interpreted as an insult to the magistrate.
No room was permitted for the expression of dissatisfaction with the
policies of separate development.
In S v Van Niekerk, 7 the accused was cited and sanctioned for
contempt for having criticised s 6 of the Terrorism Act 83 of 1967,
for having called upon the judges in the court a quo to refuse to accept
the creditworthiness of evidence obtained from detainees under the
(ii) Contempt ex facie curiae- pending proceedings: Contempt ex facie curiae often refers to
cases in which a publication allegedly prejudices a matter that is sub judice. The test for
such potentially prejudicial publications is that the matter must be pending and the
publication must have the 'tendency to prejudice' the outcome of the case. To satisfy this
test, however, it does not matter that the publication is unlikely to influence the judge
who is to hear the case.
(iii) Contempt ex facie curiae- scandalising the court: Contempt ex facie curiae may refer to
scandalising the court, where the contempt is committed outside the court, though not
necessarily with reference to any pending proceedings. It is said to be committed where
the contemnor scurrilously abuses a judge or the judiciary as a whole or where he or she
imputes bias, partiality or improper motives to a judge or the courts in their
administration of justice. This form of contempt does not depend on the nature of the
language used and liability does not depend on whether the scandalous matter is available to the whole world. It will suffice for contempt if the scandalous matter is made
available to only one person - even if that person is the judicial officer involved.
6 1960 (4) SA 709 (A).
7 1972 (3) SA 711 (A).
356
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
provisions of this Act, and for having argued that enforcement of the Act
by members of the bench ran contrary to what any truly ethical advocate
would call justice. On appeal, the Appellate Division determined that
while the accused's speech did not constitute that species of contempt
known as 'scandalising the court', it still tended to interfere with the
court's proceedings. The Appellate Division dismissed the appeal and
convicted the accused of attempting to defeat or obstruct the course of
justice. According to the Appellate Division, the proper test for contempt
was 'whether the statement or document in issue tends to prejudice or
interfere with the administration of justice in a pending proceeding'. 8
Because this test still depends on the judge's assessment as to whether the
accused's critical remarks will prejudice or interfere with the administration of justice, it is difficult to declare S v Van Niekerk a victory for
freedom of expression. 9
South African judges have been repeatedly urged to demonstrate some
inclination to diminish the rather reflexive tendency to protect their own
good names and to permit rational, if hotly contested, debate to enter the
courthouse doors. A perfect opportunity for such a demonstration arose
in S v Harber. 1 Counsel's compelling arguments in Harber showed just
°
8 Ibid 724H.
9 Whether the test invoked is 'scandalising the court' or 'interfering with the administration of
justice', the contempt doctrine has been used by judges to suppress all forms of criticism. In S v
Tobias 1966 (I) SA 565 (N), the accused referred to the magistrate as a 'bastard'. For this
untoward utterance, Tobias was convicted of contempt. InS v Zungo 1966 (I) SA 268 (N), the
accused was convicted of contempt of court for protesting that his late arrival to court was a
function of his impecuniousness and a 26 mile walk from home. InS v Mohale 1974 (I) SA 110
(T), the magistrate convicted the accused for continuing to claim, after his conviction but
before sentence, that he was innocent. In S v Shapiro 1987 (2) SA 482 (B), an advocate was
convicted for contempt of court because he had said that he regarded as invalid an executive
order preventing one of his witnesses in a case from entering the country and testifying. The
court set aside the conviction. However, this reversal did not raise any significant hopes for a
future change in course. While setting aside the particular conviction, the court in S v Shapiro
left the doctrine and the procedures intact: a court retained the right to try the person cited for
contempt in a summary manner without affording the accused a proper opportunity to defend
herself or himself.
10 1988 (3) SA 396 (A) 402G-I. In this case, the Appellate Division was given another chance to
right the contempt of court doctrine. In particular, the court was asked to choose between the
existing 'tendency test' and a stricter, reform-minded 'real risk test'. The tendency test holds
that those who criticise the judiciary may be convicted of contempt even when their actions
pose no real risk to the administration of justice. The real risk test, on the other hand, holds
that only those utterances that pose a tangible threat to the administration of justice may be
cited. Appellant's counsel argued that the foundations of the 'tendency test' were insubstantial
at best and were 'out of keeping with contemporary notions of Anglo-American jurisprudence'
(398-404). Counsel then canvassed both the insubstantial foundations of the test set out
in Van Niekerk (note 7 above) and the significant developments in the English and the
American doctrines. While traversing English law, Counsel noted that, 'at the very least,
the ratio of [the House of Lords in A-G v Times Newspapers Ltd [1973] 3 All ER 54 (HL)]
demands that for contempt of court there must be a real risk of prejudice'. Counsel also noted
that after several court battles over the parameters of contempt, the English Parliament
codified this approach in the Contempt of Court Act, 1981: 'The test of contempt is whether
the publication complained of creates a risk that the course of justice will be seriously impeded
or prejudiced.' The reformist, if tepid, English prose enabled Counsel to move on with
approval to the more robust positions laid out by the US Supreme Court some sixty years ago
(2000) 16 SAJHR
357
how far South Africa's jurisprudence was 'out of keeping with
contemporary notions of Anglo-American jurisprudence'. The argument
fell on deaf ears. No reformation followed.
(b) Contempt of Court after Apartheid: Recent Decisions
Calling for a change in the law and producing a change in the legal culture
are two different things. Despite countless arguments made by counsel and
commentator alike, the current law of contempt still enables judges to
shield themselves from unwanted criticism. This over-protectiveness is
apparent in such cases as Argus Printing & Publishing Co Ltd v Esse/en's
Estate. 11 In Esse/en, the Appellate Division defined contempt of court as
having been committed 'by the publication either in writing or verbally of
allegations calculated to bring Judges, magistrates or the administration
of justice through the courts generally, into contempt, or unjustly to cast
suspicion upon the administration of justice'. 12 Thus, pace Harber, it
would seem that the current common law of contempt continues to
criminalize expressive conduct which imputes corrupt or improper or dishonest motives
or conduct to a judge in the discharge of his or her official duties; or which reflects on
the administration of justice in an improper or scandalous manner; or which lowers the
authority of the court or unfairly or improperly criticizes the court in relation to
terminated proceedings or generally; or which scandalizes the court by imputing bias,
partiality or improper motives to a judge or the courts; or which is calculated to bring
into contempt a judicial officer in his or her judicial capacityY
Moreover, recent cases, heard under both the interim Constitution 14 and
the 1996 Constitution/ 5 confirm the courts' resistance to change. InS v
Lavhengwa, 16 the court faced a constitutional challenge to the summary
II
12
13
14
15
16
in Bridges v California 314 US 252 (1941). In Bridges, the Supreme Court held (263) that there
must be a 'clear and present danger' before speech could be curtailed and that the 'substantial
evil must be extremely serious and the degree of imminence extremely high before utterances
can be punished'. On the basis of the foregoing comparisons, the Appellant's Counsel found
the 'the tendency test' articulate in Van Niekerk to be 'out of keeping with modem
developments' and held that 'it should be rejected in favour of a test more in keeping with
modern developments'. (Harber, 398.) Indeed, Counsel called for not only a change in the
substance of the contempt doctrine, but for extreme caution in the procedures employed.
Counsel vociferously argued that summary procedures for contempt were inherently
dangerous and should only be used where the contempt was clear beyond a reasonable
doubt. If such a high standard could not be met, the better route, said Counsel, 'would seem to
be for the offender to be charged in the ordinary way by indictment' (404). But the past often
exerts a firm grip on the present. Having had the basis for radical change laid out before it, the
Appellate Division then decided that with respect to the matter before the Court there was no
palpable difference between 'the tendency test' and 'the real risk test'. Under neither test could
the articles in question be found to constitute contempt. Nothing changed.
1994 (2) SA I (A).
Ibid 29D-E.
G Marcus & D Spitz 'Freedom of Expression' in M Chaskalson et al (eds) Constitutional Law
of South Africa (1996, 5 rev 1999) 20-38.
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution).
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act I 08 of 1996 (1996 Constitution).
1996 (2) SACR 453 (W).
358
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
procedures contemplated ins 108(1) of the Magistrates' Court Act 32 of
1944 in respect of contempt committed in facie curiae. The court held
that the procedure was not unconstitutional. In particular, the court
rejected the proposition that the summary procedures violated the
accused's rights to (a) be informed with sufficient particularity of
the charge being laid; (b) be presumed innocent; (c) remain silent;
(d) choose and be represented by counsel; and (e) have a legal
practitioner assigned by the State if a substantial injustice would
otherwise result. With regard to constitutional challenges to contempt,
the decision by the court in Uncedo Taxi Service v Maninjwa 17 largely and
explicitly tracked the reasoning and conclusions in Lavhengwa. In short,
after hearing the various challenges brought under both s 12(1)(b) and
s 35(3) of the 1996 Constitution, Pickering J concluded that 'the fact that
contempt proceedings are brought summarily by way of notice motion
does not mean that they cannot be conducted fairly in consonance with
the provisions of the ... Constitution Act' . 18 However, the court did find
at least one aspect of the summary procedure invoked by the Magistrates'
Courts to be violative of the accused's constitutional rights. According to
Pickering J, to the extent that the summary procedure places
an onus upon the offender and requires proof of guilt only upon a balance of
probabilities, it is in conflict with the [1996] Constitution and such conflict is neither
reasonable nor justifiable in terms of s 36. 19
(c) Intimations of Change in Modelling Public Discourse from the
Constitutional Court
In keeping with its minimalist practice, the Constitutional Court has
twice engaged the subject matter of contempt of court in a rather oblique
manner.
During the litigation of Executive Council, Western Cape Legislature v
President of the Republic of South Africa, 20 one of the applicants,
Mr Pieter Marais, allegedly asserted that the Western Cape government
had an excellent chance of winning the case so long as the Constitutional
Court's judgment was not politically motivated. After having this
pronouncement brought to the Court's attention, Chaskalson P first
observed that it went without saying that the Court had not been
influenced in any way by Mr Marais's statement to the press. He then
went on to state that the report, if true,
17 1998 (3) SA 417 (ECD).
18 Ibid 429C-D.
19 Ibid 428A-B. Though it represents but a small crack in the edifice of the contempt of court
authorities, Uneeda is not insignificant. It recognises that contempt proceedings can deprive a
person of her liberty- and that such a deprivation is not to be taken lightly and certainly not
to be taken on the basis of a balance of probabilities. With so much at stake, Pickering J
reasoned, the state is obliged to satisfy the most stringent test and demonstrate the guilt of the
accused beyond a reasonable doubt.
20 1995 (4) SA 877 (CC).
(2000) 16 SAJHR
359
undermines not only this court but constitutionalism itself, of which this court is a
guardian. Having regard to the high political office held by the third applicant, the
consequences of a statement impugning the integrity of this court might have been
particularly harmful. All citizens are free to attend court, to listen to proceedings, to
comment on them and on the judgments given and to criticize such judgments, even
vigorously, where it is appropriate to do so, but it is irresponsible to make unfounded
statements which impugn the integrity of the court. I leave the matter there.Z 1
Gilbert Marcus and Derek Spitz have suggested that the Court's handling
of this issue could be viewed as unsatisfactory in two important respects:
(1) the Court appears to invoke a summary procedure and imposes what
amounts to a conviction without sanction; (2) the Court adopts a rather
uncritical attitude towards existing common-law contempt of court
authorities. Given that the Court has recently been granted the power to
deal directly with alleged contempt of its proceedings, the two authors
have expressed genuine concern regarding the potential for the speech of
would-be critics of the court to be 'chilled into an uneasy silence out of a
fear of contempt proceedings'. 22
As this comment has strongly suggested, the Court's decision in
SARFU should allay such fears. In this decision, the Constitutional
Court demonstrated a dramatically different demeanour in response to a
far more direct attack on its integrity.
The implication of personal bias, as well as political cronyism, lay at
the heart of Dr Luyt's recusal application. Though the Court was clearly
disturbed by the frontal attack on its integrity, its response was quite
reserved. It surveyed both South African and foreign jurisprudence on
recusal. Having done both, it denied the request and set about preparing
for an appeal on the merits. During the course of its patient survey of
both the charges and the law, the Court noted that its reputation,
however important, could not be used as a basis upon which to silence its
critics. The Court wrote:
At the very outset we wish to acknowledge that a litigant and her or his counsel who find
it necessary to apply for the recusal of a judicial officer has [sic] an unenviable task and
the propriety of their motives should not lightly be questioned. Where the grounds are
reasonable it is counsel's duty to advance the grounds without fear. On the part of the
Judge whose recusal is sought there should be a full appreciation of the admonition that
she or he should 'not be unduly sensitive and ought not to regard an application for his
[or her] recusal as a personal affront. 23 [footnotes omitted]
What is truly remarkable in this case, where contempt for the Court
and its members had been amply demonstrated, is that while the
Court deplored 'the tendency for decisions of our courts . . . to be
attacked by impugning the integrity of judicial officers rather than by
examining the reasons for their judgments', 24 it undertook as its chief
responsibility the development of the law on recusal. Put slightly
21
22
23
24
Ibid para 122.
Marcus & Spitz (note 13 above) 20-40.
SARFU (note I above) para 10.
Ibid para.
360
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
differently, instead of using the recusal application as an opportunity to
chill future expression that might be seen as 'recklessly attacking the
integrity of judicial officers', it actually used the moment to reinforce
the legitimacy of its own role as a forum for politically charged disputes in
South Africa's nascent constitutional democracy. Its decision in SARFU is
a model for how a public institution ought to respond to issues that fall
along South Africa's many fault lines. This decision is also a model for how
South African courts should engage the occasional reckless accusations
made by litigants. Most importantly, in a democracy struggling to throw
off the shackles of authoritarianism, the Court's decision in SARFU should
be read as a model for how all citizens ought to engage in public discourse.
With strong authoritative words. With reasons. Not with a big stick.
(d) Implications of SARFU for Current Contempt of Court Authorities
The Constitutional Court's decision in SARFU would appear to suggest
that for South African citizens to lay legitimate claim to freedom of
expression or the right to a fair trial, judges cannot be allowed to claim
that each and every criticism of their official actions and judgments
amounts to a cognisable and punishable offence or that any given affront
in court warrants summary sanction.
( i) Freedom of Expression
At the very core of freedom of expression lies the right to articulate one's
political beliefs, however unpopular, in the public square. Part and parcel
of this freedom is the right to contest abuses of state power wherever
citizens believe such abuses to have occurred.
While there remains amongst many jurists in South Africa a fairly
deep-seated belief that judges are not political in ways that would make
their positions and actions subject to the hurly-burly of public debate, the
facts do not support this perception. The Constitutional Court has
handed down an array of decisions - from striking down the death
penalty, to upholding provincial legislation regarding traditional leaders,
to reading in protections for individuals in homosexual partnerships that are undeniably political and have attracted political fire.
For the Constitutional Court, or any South African court, to suppress
expression which asserts political bias or a lack of ideological rectitude on
the part of members of the court is censorship, plain and simple. To go
further and punish such expression for impairing the dignity of the court
is, as Marcus and Spitz have argued, to resuscitate laws for sedition that
should have died with Apartheid.
Of course, the law of contempt attempts to regulate a broad range of
actions - from insults, interruptions or disorderly conduct within the
courtroom, to potentially prejudicial publications regarding pending
proceedings, to the imputation of such improper bias and motives of
judicial officers that the administration of justice itself is impaired. Not
(2000) 16 SAJHR
361
all such activities should be found to fall within the protective sphere of
the freedom of expression.
With respect to contempt in facie curiae, it is not at all apparent that
any disorderly conduct that occurs within the courtroom is entitled to
such protection. An especially strong case would have to be made that the
conduct itself constitutes the kind of expression that serves the values that
animate the right. For example, simply tossing chairs, cursing at the
judge, refusing to follow basic court etiquette or struggling with
the bailiffs are unlikely to advance our search for truth, press freedom or
political exchange. However, a case could be made that a defendant who
chooses to gag himself during proceedings is engaged in the kind of
political expression that warrants at least prima facie protection. The gag
could well be understood as a non-obtrusive critique of a system in which
the defendant is prevented from ever making herself truly heard. The
question, then, would be whether this 'statement' is justified under
the limitation clause. To the extent that the trial itself is not 'affected' by
this symbolic action, and no other state or private interest of
constitutional import is found to be impaired, then we might wish to
recognise that a contempt citation in such a circumstance is unwarranted.
Likewise, with respect to contempt in facie curiae regarding statements
which are allegedly violative of the dignity of the court and its members
or bring the administration of justice into disrepute, the Constitutional
Court would appear inclined to be rather generous with regard to the
kind of language that would both receive prima facie protection and
survive limitation analysis. The Court's reasons - as manifest in SARFU
- follow. First, we should hesitate before we commit ourselves to the
proposition that that the sensitivity of judges to public criticism rises to
the level of a constitutionally protected concern. Second, even if we were
able to find constitutionally defensible ends in the current law of
contempt and divine a rational relationship between the means employed
and the objective to be achieved by the current law of contempt, we
would be hard pressed to defend the proposition that the current laws of
contempt with regard to impairing the administration of justice reflect the
least restrictive means possible of achieving those ends deemed
constitutionally justifiable. It is one thing to restrict speech that actually
impairs the operation of the court. It is quite another to suppress speech
that takes the court or its members to task for their political beliefs- real
or imagined. This latter restriction cannot be justified in an open and
democratic society based upon freedom, equality and dignity. Our
limitation analysis would seem to suggest that an alternative, less
restrictive scheme exists for protecting those policies that underlie
permissible laws of contempt for scandalising the court.
( ii) Fair Trials
The notion that the law of contempt can always be squared with the right
to a fair trial must also be viewed with heightened suspicion. Unlike
362
FOCUS: THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT'S 1999 TERM
freedom of expression, however, the right to a fair trial would only
appear to be engaged with respect to contempt in facie curiae. For
only with respect to contempt in facie curiae are the courts permitted to
punish summarily the alleged contemnor. The right to a fair trial
includes, among other things, the right: (l) to be informed of the charge
with sufficient details to answer it; (2) to have adequate time and facilities
to prepare a defence; (3) to a public trial in an ordinary court; (4) to be
presumed innocent; and (5) to adduce and challenge evidence. The
summary procedures employed in many contempt in facie curiae
proceedings would appear to violate at least one if not all five of these
constitutional rights.
That leaves open the question of whether prima facie infringements of
the right to a fair trial - when they do occur via a summary contempt
citation - can be justified. While there may be a number of instances in
which summary sanctions trump various components of the right to a fair
trial, in the main it would appear that the Constitutional Court, as
evidenced by SARFU, would favour an alternative scheme less restrictive
of the defendant's rights. The Court could ask the Director of Public
Prosecution's office to investigate whether a charge of contempt is
warranted. After investigation, in the normal course of business, the
Director of Public Prosecutions could decide whether or not to bring
charges. The Constitutional Court could then feel confident that the
defendant would be likely to receive the benefit of all the rights denied her
under summary proceedings and punishment for contempt in facie
curiae.
IV
CONCLUSION:
A
FORUM OF PRINCIPLE AND A MODEL FOR PUBLIC
DISCOURSE
The fateful question for the human species seems to me to be whether and to what extent
their cultural development will succeed in mastering the disturbance of their communal
life by the human instinct of aggression and self-destruction .... Men have gained
control over the forces of nature to such an extent that with their help they would have no
difficulty exterminating one another to the last man. They know this, and hence comes a
large part of their current unrest, their unhappiness and their mood of anxiety.
Sigmund Freud
Civilization and its Discontents (1929)
(trans Joan Riviere, 1930)
Written just before Hitler's rise to power, and well over a decade and a
half before Hiroshima and Nagasaki demonstrated just how quickly we
could race to the last man, Freud's dire warnings about the dangers
associated with the narcissism of minor difference could have appeared in
yesterday's opinion and editorial pages.
Nothing in the SARFU recusal judgment provides any assurance that
our better angels will always get the better of us. Still the judgment does
provide some succour for those among us who have been concerned
about the rancorous debates over race in the media and the etiology of
HIVIAIDS in the general population.
(2000) 16 SAJHR
363
South Africa has far too many obstacles to overcome to permit one to
be overjoyed by a few careful words chosen by its highest court.
However, it is impossible to imagine South Africa overcoming the legacy
of Apartheid unless it politicians and citizenry learn to engage one
another in a manner which enables them to cooperate in attempting to
solve the problems which confront them.
We should not expect such lessons from the burly-burly of
majoritarian parliamentary politics. Indeed, we should expect politicians
to continue to exploit the narcissism of minor difference for political gain.
The Court, however, exercises a different set of institutional competencies
than those discharged by the coordinate branches. Unburdened by the
pressures of making good electoral promises, the Court finds itself in
the fortunate position of being able to articulate principles by which we
all ought to live. Unfettered by the demands of executing social policy, or
playing to the rabble, the Court - Constitution in hand - is able to offer
reasoned justifications for decisions which engage every issue from
distributive justice to socio-economic rights, from equality to the
appropriate dimensions of human sexuality, from criminal justice and
the need for order to the panoply of protections which are afforded
individual defendants. As any number of commentators have pointed
out, we need not believe that the Court will arrive at the 'one, true
answer' in order to acknowledge that its decisions will more thoroughly
ventilate the myriad considerations which the cases before it raise.
That, in the end, is what we should want and expect from the Court.
Relatively dispassionate and disinterested engagement with complex
questions which result in honest, principled responses. And that, in the
end, is what we received from the Constitutional Court in SARFU.
STUART WOOLMAN*
Lecturer, Columbia Law School
Research Fellow, University of the Witwatersrand School of Law
*
The author would like to thank Theunis Roux and Jonathan Klaaren for their support and
editorial assistance. The author would also like to thank Steven EHmann and Penelope Andrews
for permission to use material to be published in their forthcoming book, The Post-Apartheid
Constitutions: Perspectives on South Africa's Basic Law.
CONSTITUTIONAL COURT
STATISTICS FOR THE 1999 TERM
I INTRODUCTION
This section provides some descriptive statistics on the work of the
Constitutional Court in the past year, organised in eight tables. A ninth
table looks at the expected terms of the judges of the Court. This
information should supplement the more qualitative analyses presented
in the other pages of this issue. The method of constructing each table is
given in the text below the table. The 1999 statistics are primarily drawn
from data on the website maintained by the Faculty of Law at the
University of the Witwatersrand (www.law.wits.ac.za). This section
covers only cases in which a full, written judgment of the Court is
produced. Thus, matters disposed of without hearing - which would be
important from the point of view of examining issues such as the control
of the Court over its roll - are not included. The objectives and methods
of this section are more fully laid out in the 1995 edition and subsequent
editions of this section. 1
We present these statistics with caution and they should be read
likewise. Statistics are often misleading. Furthermore, these statistics
describe only a small number of cases. Finally, in this section, neither the
reasoning of the judges, nor the facts presented by the cases, is examined.
The data offered here should thus be taken as complementary, rather
than as conclusive, and should be interpreted with a high degree of care.
II SUMMARY
This is the fifth year in which these statistics have been presented, and it is
thus possible to begin to trace some trends that have been developing
over the past few years. The 1999 term was one in which the Court spoke
with a high degree of unanimity: of the nineteen cases decided in 1999,
78,9 per cent were unanimous, with a further 5,3 per cent having only
concurrences, but no dissents. There was a slight increase in the number
of cases showing any dissent, from 4,8 per cent in 1998, to 15,7 per cent.
In 1998, 81,0 per cent of the cases were unanimous, while in 1997 the
figure was 63,2 per cent, in 1996, 81,5 per cent, and in 1995, 57,1 per cent.
This high degree of concurrence for 1999 is reflected in table 4, which
sets out the voting alignments of the judges. The lowest figure for
agreement is 81 per cent, between Goldstone J and O'Regan J. This is the
I See 'Constitutional Court Statistics for the 1995 Term' (1996) 12 SAJHR 39; 'Constitutional
Court Statistics for the 1996 Term' (1997) 13 SAJHR 208; 'Constitutional Court Statistics for
the 1997 Term' (1998) 14 SAJHR 277; 'Constitutional Court Statistics for the 1998 Term'
(1999) 15 SAJHR 256, read with (1999) 15 SAJHR 446.
364
(2000) 16 SAJHR
365
same as the 1998 term (80 per cent between Sachs J and Ackermann J),
and is substantially higher than the lowest rate in 1997 (40 per cent). In
1996, the lowest concurrence was 66,7 per cent, and in 1995, 61,5 per
cent. Most judges agreed with each other at least 90 per cent of the time
in 1999.
The number of cases decided by the Court in 1999 (19 cases) was much
the same as in 1998 (21 cases), 1997 (20 cases), 1996 (27 cases) and 1995
(14 cases). There were relatively few criminal cases (26 per cent), a
substantial decrease on the 1995 proportion, where 64,3 per cent of the
cases were criminal.
The Court ruled in favour of government in 63 per cent of the cases,
substantially the same as the figure of 67 per cent recorded in 1998. This,
in turn, was similar to the government success rate of 63,2 per cent in
1997, and 66,7 per cent in 1996, and substantially greater than the 35,7
per cent recorded in 1995.
In 1999 there were no cases dismissed for lack of jurisdiction, a high
proportion of the cases (47,4 per cent) being direct appeals from the High
Courts. The average time between the date of the last hearing and the
date of judgment has also continued to decrease: 1999 (58 days), 1998 (89
days), 1997 (120 days), 1996 (146 days) and in 1995 (119 days).
LIST
OF
1999 CASES
Together with the abbreviations used in these tables, the cases decided
with written judgments in 1999 are listed in chronological order based on
the day the judgment was delivered.
(FNB) Mphahlele v First National Bank of SA Ltd
CCT 23/98; 1999 (2) SA 667 (CC); 1999 (3) BCLR 253 (CC)
(Pr)
Premier, Western Cape v President of the Republic of South
Africa
CCT 26/98; 1999 (3) SA 657 (CC); 1999 (4) BCLR 382 (CC)
(Ag)
August v Electoral Commission
CCT 8/99; 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (4) BCLR 363 (CC)
(DP)
Democratic Party v Minister of Home Affairs
CCT 11/99; 1999 (3) SA 254 (CC); 1999 (6) BCLR 607 (CC)
(NNP) New National Party of South Africa v Government of the
Republic of South Africa
CCT 9/99; 1999 (3) SA 191 (CC); 1999 (5) BCLR 489 (CC)
(SAN) South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence
CCT 27/98; 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC); 1999 (6) BCLR 615 (CC)
(Dl)
S v Dlamini; S v Dladla; S v Joubert; S v Schietekat
CCT 21/98; CCT22/98; CCT 2/99; CCT 4/99; 1999 (4) SA 623
(CC); 1999 (7) BCLR 771 (CC)
(SARI) President of the Republic of South Africa v South African
Rugby Football Union
CCT 16/98; 1999 (4) SA 147 (CC); 1999 (7) BCLR 725 (CC)
366
CONSTITUTIONAL COURT STATISTICS FOR THE 1999 TERM
(FEI)
President, Ordinary Court Martial v Freedom of Expression
Institute
CCT 5/99; 1999 (4) SA 682 (CC); 1999 (11) BCLR 1219 (CC)
(EC)
Premier of the Province of the Western Cape v The Electoral
Commission
CCT 19/99; 1999 (11) BCLR 1209 (CC)
(SAR2) President of the Republic of South Africa v South African
Rugby Football Union
CCT 16/98; 2000 (1) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (10) BCLR 1059 (CC)
(ECW) Executive Council, Western Cape v Minister of Provincial
Affairs and Constitutional Development; Executive Council,
KwaZulu-Natal v President of the Republic of South Africa
CCT 15/99; CCT 18/99; 2000 (l) SA 661 (CC); 1999 (12) BCLR
1360 (CC)
(CMC) Cape Metropolitan Council v Minister of Provincial Affairs and
Constitutional Development
CCT 34/99; 2000 (1) SA 727 (CC); 1999 (12) BCLR 1353 (CC)
(LB)
Ex parte President of the Republic of South Africa: In re
Constitutionality of the Liquor Bill
CCT 12/99; 2000 (1) SA 732 (CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 1 (CC)
(Le)
Lesapo v North West Agricultural Bank
CCT 23/99; 2000 (1) SA 409 (CC); 1999 (12) BCLR 1420 (CC)
(Tw)
S v Twala (South African Human Rights Commission
Intervening)
CCT 27/99; 2000 (1) SA 879 (CC); 2000 (l) BCLR 106 (CC)
(NC) National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of
Home Affairs
CCT 10/99; 2000 (2) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 39 (CC)
(Ba)
S v Baloyi
CCT 29/99; 2000 (l) BCLR 86 (CC)
(Ma)
S v Manyonyo
CCT 36/99; 1999 (12) BCLR 1438 (CC)
TABLE 1: VOTING PATTERNS IN CASES DECIDED -1999
Case
FNB
Pr
Ag
DP
NNP
SAN
Dl
SAR1
FEI
Ch
c
L
La
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
ct
ct
c
L
L
Ac
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
ct
c
Go
L
c
c
Kr
c
c
-
L
-
c
c
c
-
ct
ct
c
c
c
L
Judge
Md Mo
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
ct
ct
c
c
Ng
OR
-
c
c
c
-
-
-
D
D
L
c
ct
c
Ya
c
c
c
c
L
c
c
ct
c
Sa
c
c
Ca
-
-
L
-
c
c
c
-
c
ct
c
-
-
367
(2000) 16 SAJHR
TABLE 1: VOTING PATIERNS IN CASES DECIDED -1999 (continued)
Judge
Case
Ch
La
Ac
Go
Kr
Md
Mo
Ng
OR
Ya
Sa
EC
SAR2
ECW
CMC
LB
Le
c
ct
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
L
c
ct
c
L
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
ct
c
c
c
c
c
L
c
c
c
ct
c
c
c
c
-
c
ct
-
c
ct
-
L
ct
d
c
c
L
c
c
c
c
c
ct
c
ct
c
c
c
c
c
c
L
c
Tw
NC
Ba
Ma
-
c
-
c
-
-
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
L
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
ct
-
D
c
c
c
c
L
c
c
c
c
c
c
c
Ca
-
d
c
L
c
c
c
c
'L' indicates the leading judgment, containing the decision of the Court on the principal issue.
The leading judgment will often but not always contain the order of the Court. Where
several issues in different judgments are of significance, two or more judgments may be
termed leading. Reasonable minds may well differ on this identification.
'C' indicates a separate concurrence with reasons with the order of the Court.
'c' indicates a concurring vote without reasons.
'ct' indicates a concurring vote in a unanimous Court judgment not attributed to any judge.
'D' indicates a separate dissent with reasons with the order of the Court. A vote to dispose of
the case in any manner other than that adopted by the Court in its order is taken as a
dissent. Thus, judgments expressing both concurrence and dissent are classified as
dissents.
'd' indicates a dissenting vote without reasons.
'-' indicates that the judge did not participate in deciding the case.
In the NNP case, there are two leading judgments written by Langa DP and Yacoob J.
O'Regan J, in her dissenting judgment, concurred with Langa DP. but dissented from the
judgment of Yacoob J. The two SARFU judgments (SAR1 and SAR2) do not easily fit into these
tables. Both judgments were unanimous and no author was identified. For purposes of these
tables, each of the participating judges is given a 'c'.
The judges covered in this table are: Chaskalson P (Ch), Langa DP (La), Ackermann J (Ac),
Goldstone J (Go), Kriegler J (Kr), Madala J (Md), Mokgoro J (Mo), Ngcobo J (Ng), O'Regan J
(OR), Sachs J (Sa), Yacoob J (Ya) and Cameron AJ (Ca).
All judges sit in all matters before the Constitutional Court and are only absent for reasons of
illness, long leave or because they have recused themselves.
TABLE 2: ACTIONS OF INDIVIDUAL JUDGES- 1999
L vote
Ch
La
Ac
Go
Kr
Md
Mo
Ng
OR
Sa
Ya
Ca
2
3
1
2
1
2
1
1
2
2
1
Cvote
c vote
-
17
16
18
15
6
19
16
7
14
16
15
5
1
-
-
D vote
d vote
Total
-
-
19
19
19
17
7
19
19
8
18
19
17
7
-
-
3
-
-
This table is calculated on the same basis as Table 1.
-
1
-
1
368
CONSTITUTIONAL COURT STATISTICS FOR THE 1999 TERM
TABLE 3: UNANIMITY PERCENTAGE- 1999
Unanimous
With
concurrences
(without
dissent)
With dissent
Total
15
(78,9%)
1
(5,3%)
3
(15,7%)
19
(100%)
Cases
In this table, 'unanimous' means that all judges concurred in both the
judgment of the Court and the order. 'With concurrences (without
dissent)' means that at least one judge wrote separately but concurred in
the order of the Court and that no judge dissented. 'With dissent' means
that at least one judge would have made a different order.
TABLE 4: VOTING ALIGNMENTS: JUDGES OF THE COURT -1999
La
Ac
Go
19/19
100%
19/19
100%
19/19
100%
17/17
100%
17/17
100%
17/17
100%
7/7
17/17
100%
-
7/7
7/7
7/7
100%
19/19
100%
18/19
95%
8/8
100%
15/18
83%
18/19
95%
17/17
100%
6/7
86%
100%
17/17
100%
16/17
94%
6/6
100%
13/16
81%
16/17
94%
15/15
100%
5/6
83%
Ch
Ch
La
Ac
Go
Kr
Md
Mo
Ng
OR
Sa
Ya
Ca
19/19
100%
19/19
100%
17/17
100%
7/7
100%
19/19
100%
18/19
95%
8/8
100%
15/18
83%
18/19
95%
17/17
100%
6/7
86%
-
19/19
100%
17/17
100%
7/7
100%
19/19
100%
18/19
95%
8/8
100%
15/18
83%
18/19
95%
16/17
94%
6/7
86%
-
Md
Mo
Ng
OR
Sa
Ya
100%
19/19
100%
19/19
100%
19/19
100%
17/17
100%
18/19
95%
18/19
95%
18/19
95%
16/17
94%
8/8
100%
8/8
100%
8/8
100%
6/6
100%
15/18
83%
15/18
83%
15/18
83%
13/16
81%
17/17
100%
16/17
94%
17/17
100%
15/15
100%
-
7/7
7/7
-
7/7
100%
100%
18/19
95%
18/19
95%
18/19
95%
18/19
95%
16/17
94%
6/7
86%
18/19
95%
17/19
89%
8/8
100%
14/18
78%
Kr
100%
7/7
100%
7/7
100%
7/7
-
100%
7/7
100%
7/7
100%
6/7
86%
7/7
100%
-
18/19
95%
8/8
100%
15/18
83%
18/19
95%
17/17
100%
6/7
86%
-
7/8
88%
16/18
89%
17/19
89%
17/17
100%
7/7
100%
8/8
100%
7/8
88%
-
6/7
86%
8/8
100%
6/6
100%
6/7
86%
100%
15/18
83%
16/18
89%
6/7
86%
-
14/18
78%
14/16
88%
6/6
100%
-
16/17
94%
6/7
86%
7/7
100%
17/17
100%
17/17
100%
6/6
100%
14/16
88%
16/17
94%
5/5
100%
In this table, the second number represents the total number of cases in
which two judges have sat together. The first number represents the
number of cases in which two judges have either fully agreed in a
judgment of the other, co-written a judgment, or fully agreed in a judgment
of another judge. If a judge writes that he or she is concurring but only
overall or with certain reservations or with any restatement of the other
judge's views, this is not classified as full agreement. Thus, judgments that
are in substance very similar may well be counted as not agreeing for the
purposes of this table. The voting alignment of Cameron AJ is reflected
out of alphabetical order in the bottom row of the table.
369
(2000) 16 SAJHR
TABLE 5: SUBJECT MATTER OF CASES DECIDED -1999
Rights
Civil
SAN, NNP, DP,
Ag, FNB, NC,
Le, SAR1 (8)
Dl, Ma, Ba,
Tw
(4)
Criminal
Intra-Governmental
Total
Other
Total
SAR2
(1)
9
(47,4%)
FEI
(1)
Pr, LB, EC,
ECW, CMC (5)
5
(26,3%)
5
(26,3%)
7
(36,8%)
19
(100%)
12
(63,2%)
In this table cases are classified as 'criminal' when a person is subject to
the criminal or penal laws. 'Intra-governmental' cases are those cases
between two organs of government or, as in certification judgments, ex
parte on behalf of one organ. Other cases are civil. Cases are classified as
'rights' if the majority judgment on the principal issue turns on a
fundamental right.
TABLE 6: GOVERNMENT SUCCESS RATE -1999
For government
Against government
Civil
NNP, DP, FNB, FEI,
SAR1, SAR2, LB (7)
SAN, Ag, NC,
Ma, Le
(5)
Criminal
Dl, Ba, Tw
(3)
Intra-Governmental
Pr, CMC, ECW
(3)
Total
13
(68,4%)
EC
(1)
6
(31,6%)
Cases are classified as 'for government' if a central, provincial or local
government or an agency or a person in an official capacity prevails on
the principal issue. A case is also counted as 'for government' if the status
quo ante prevails. If the central government opposes another organ of
government, the case is classified as for the government if the central
government or a court, an agency or a person in an official capacity
prevails. If a Chapter 9 institution (1996 Constitution) opposes the
government, the case will be classified as 'against government' if the
Chapter 9 institution prevails. If agencies or organs of equivalent tiers of
government are opposed, the case is counted as neither for nor against
the government. Due to its relatively formalistic definition, this table
should be used with particular caution.
370
CONSTITUTIONAL COURT STATISTICS FOR THE 1999 TERM
TABLE 7: JURISDICTIONAL BASIS OF CASES -1999
Basis of Jurisdiction
Appeals
Appeals
Direct
Dismissed
Direct acctlSS Referral
(s 67(6)(a)
from
tor lack ol
PresidenUal
Direct
ol orders ~galnst
onlen appeals
jurlsdlcreferral
access
read with otlnvatldlly of Invalidity from HC
the SCA
(S 79(4)(b)) (S 167(6)(a)) s 167(4)) (s 172(2)(a)) (s 172(2)(d)) (s 167(6)(b)) (s 167(6)(b))
lion
LB
FNB, EC,
ECW
Pr
Ba, Le, Ma
FEI, NC
(5,3%)
(15,8%)
(5,3%)
(15,8%)
(10,5%)
Dl, DP, NNP,
SAN, Ag,
SAR2, Tw,
CMC
(42,1%)
AppllcaUon
tor
recusal
SAR1
(5,3%)
This table examines the basis of jurisdiction after decision by the Court,
rather than the jurisdiction invoked to place the case on the Court roll.
There may be cases which are both referrals of orders of invalidity and
appeals against orders of invalidity. Where this occurs, such as in NC, the
case is recorded as an appeal against an order of invalidity. 'Direct
appeals from HC' also includes applications for leave to appeal.
TABLE 8: TIME FROM HEARING TO WRITTEN REASONS* -1999
(Decision Date)
Days to Written Order
(29 March 1999)
(1 April 1999)
(13 April1999)
(13 April 1999)
(26 May 1999)
(3 June 1999)
(4 June 1999)
(24 August 1999)
(2 September 1999)
(1 0 September 1999)
(15 October 1999)
(11 November 1999)
(16 November 1999)
(2 December 1999)
(2 December 1999)
(3 December 1999)
34
13
15
28
62
105
28
91
99
120
52
72
63
16
107
24
(Hearing Date)
Pr
(23 February
Ag
(19 March
DP
(29 March
NNP
(16 March
SAN
(25 March
Dl
(18 February
SAR1
(7 May
FEI
(25 May
EC
(26 May
SAR2
(13 May
ECW
(24 August
LB
(31 August
Le (14 September
Tw (16 November
NC
(17 August
Ba
(9 November
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
1999)
Mean Time Hearing to Decision: 58 days
• 'Written reasons' refers to the day on which reasons were given. In SAR1 and EC the decision of the
Court was given before the written reasons. Where the hearing takes place over several days the
last day of the first continuous period of hearing is used for calculation. In some instances, cases
were disposed of without there being a separation between the hearing and the decision date. No
time calculation is made for such cases. FNB, CMC and Ma are not included in this table, since in
these cases there was no hearing at all.
371
(2000) 16 SAJHR
TABLE 9: PROSPECTIVE TERMS OF THE CONSTITUTIONAL
COURT JUDGES
Name
Date of birth
Age at
31/12/1999
(In years and
months)
Chaskalson
24/11/1931
68 yrs 1 mth
07/1994
11 /2001 (70)
1 yr 11 mths
Kriegler
29/11/1932
67 yrs 1 mth
10/1994
11/2002 (70)
2 yrs 11 mths
Ackermann
14/01/1934
65 yrs 11 mths
08/1994
01/2004 (70)
4 yrs 1 mth
Sachs
30/01/1935
64 yrs 11 mths
10/1994
01/2005 (70)
5 yrs 1 mth
6 yrs 10 mths
Date of
beginning of
term of office
Cut-off date
of term of
office*
Years untll
cut-off date
(from
31/12/1999)
Madala
13/07/1937
62 yrs 5 mths
08/1994
10/2006 (FT)
Goldstone
26/10/1938
61 yrs 2 mths
08/1994
07/2006 (FT)
6 yrs 7 mths
Lang a
25/03/1939
60 yrs 9 mths
10/1994
07/2006 (FT)
6 yrs 7 mths
Yacoob
03/03/1948
51 yrs 9 mths
02/1998
02/201 0 (FT)
10 yrs 2 mths
Mokgoro
19/10/1950
49 yrs 2 mths
10/1994
07/2006 (FT)
6 yrs 7 mths
Ngcobo
01/03/1953
46 yrs 9 mths
08/1999
08/2011 (FT)
11 yrs 8 mths
O'Regan
17/09/1957
42 yrs 3 mths
10/1994
07/2006 (FT)
6 yrs 7 mths
* (70) indicates that the judge will turn 70 before his/her maximum 12 years of office have
been completed.
(FT) indicates that the judge will be able to complete a full12-year term before his/her 70th
birthday.
The terms of office of Constitutional Court judges are dealt with in
s 176(1) of the 1996 Constitution, which provides that a Constitutional
Court judge is appointed for a non-renewable term of 12 years, but must
retire at the age of 70. This table identifies the prospective terms of office
of the Constitutional Court judges as of31 December 1999. Acting judges
are not included in this table.
ALLEN LEUTA
Student of Law, University of the Witwatersrand
KIRSTY MCLEAN
Student of Law, University of the Witwatersrand
MABATHO NTELEKI
Student of Law, University of the Witwatersrand
JACK PHALANE
Student of Law, University of the Witwatersrand
ANDREW SMITH
Student of Law, University of the Witwatersrand
JONATHANKLAAREN
Associate Professor of Law, University of the Witwatersrand