Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology
ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: www.tandfonline.com/journals/rbsp20
Beyond the Reach: Horror and Phenomenal Life
Daniil Koloskov
To cite this article: Daniil Koloskov (11 Sep 2024): Beyond the Reach: Horror and Phenomenal
Life, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, DOI: 10.1080/00071773.2024.2396635
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2024.2396635
© 2024 The Author(s). Published by Informa
UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
Published online: 11 Sep 2024.
Submit your article to this journal
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rbsp20
THE JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2024.2396635
Beyond the Reach: Horror and Phenomenal Life
Daniil Koloskov
Department of Philosophy and Social Sciences, University of Hradec Králové, Hradec Králové, Czech Republic
ABSTRACT
ARTICLE HISTORY
The goals of this paper is to offer a phenomenological analysis of the
phenomenon of horror and argue that horror displays an organization
of experience that cannot be traced back to the activity of the
constituting subject. The main claim is that the essential feature of
horror consists of its unintelligibility, which is neither reducible to
the psychoanalytical repression nor to the complete breakdown of
intelligibility but should be rather conceived as counter-intelligibility:
horror occurs when anomalies and irregularities that are normally
seen as disrupting the phenomenal field and undermining everyday
intelligibility turn into positive principles of a new organization of
experience. The confusion and perversion of horror consist of
transforming the negativities and counter-forces of the cultural
phenomenal field into a positive way of being. Horror is an optimal
way of bringing non-optimality and disarray, which is characterized
by self-exclusion from the cultural domain of intelligibility.
Received 30 November 2023
Accepted 20 August 2024
KEYWORDS
Horror; phenomenology;
affectivity; Heidegger;
Levinas; backrooms
Introduction: Methodological Attunement
Over the past century, the phenomenological tradition has offered several attempts to
methodologically privilege a certain modality of affectivity for the sake of reaching this
or that particular philosophical goal. We could think of Heidegger’s and Sartre’s respect
ive investigations of anxiety as a basic attunement (Heidegger Sein und Zeit; Sartre 1993),
which has helped them to clarify the way of being of Dasein/consciousness; we could
think of Heidegger’s investigation of boredom in the context of his analysis of tempor
ality (Heidegger 1996). We could also recall Levinas (Levinas Existence and Existents)
and the way the affectivity of horror provides him with a guiding threat into the
“event of Being.” Another example is Binswanger’s and Maldiney’s respective analyses
of psychosis; while Binswanger uses psychosis in order to investigate the continuity of
one’s own experience (Binswanger), Maldiney approaches it in the context of his inves
tigation of an event, i.e. genuinely transformative experience (Maldiney). Alternatively,
we could also think of Romano’s investigation of despair (Romano) in his own analysis
of eventuality. This approach has proven to be fruitful in twofold manner: while pursuing
the particular goals that are acceptable and clear within the phenomenological tradition,
CONTACT Daniil Koloskov
[email protected]
nám. Svobody 331/2, 500 02 Hradec Králové 2, Czechia
© 2024 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/
licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly
cited. The terms on which this article has been published allow the posting of the Accepted Manuscript in a repository by the author(s)
or with their consent.
2
D. KOLOSKOV
they have managed to substantially enrich and deepen the general understanding of our
affective dispositions, a discussion that extends beyond the narrowly conceived phenom
enological tradition.
The goal of this paper is reversed and, in this sense, much more modest. Its first and
primary goal is not to make a contribution to the phenomenological scholarship as such
but to apply its conceptual tools and provide a phenomenological analysis of the
phenomenon of horror. By discussing both particular cases of horror along with some
of the most prominent approaches to horror, I will seek to outline the essential structures
of the phenomenon of horror while preserving the continuity between those idealizations
and the factual, lived experience of horror. Given the limitation imposed by the form of
this investigation, I will not argue in support of the phenomenological method on which I
will rely (particularly as developed by Merleau-Ponty 1958; 1968). The analysis will
proceed under the assumption that the goal of explicating the self-standing meaning of
horror and the rules of its organization is sufficiently meaningful in order to be
pursued for its own sake.
The secondary and auxiliary goal of this paper consists of supplying an “affective illus
tration” of the general shift of attention that happened in modern phenomenological
research and especially in French phenomenology. Speaking as broadly as possible, we
could say that the modern scholarship puts a greater emphasis on the eventual character
of human existence; it stresses the inadequacy of approaching subjectivity in terms of its
power to “constitute” and explain phenomena arguing instead that the subject should be
seen as “receiving” itself from phenomena, which “happen” to it (see, for instance, Mal
diney; Marion 2002; Romano; Barbaras Being of the Phenomenon; 2021 etc.). The inves
tigation of horror will arrive at the conclusion that the appearance of horror presupposes
its fundamental unintelligibility to the subject of appearance; at the same time, I will
demonstrate how despite being unintelligible to the subject, the phenomenon of
horror displays a distinct meaning of its own. So, instead of referring to the constituting
subject, the phenomenon of horror will be explained in terms of the dynamics of the
phenomenal field. This, in turn, would turn horror into a methodologically privileged
phenomenon in the context of the investigation of unconstituted and unconstitutable
aspect of the phenomenal life.
1. Phenomenologies and Philosophies of Horror
In this section, I will provide a survey of some of the most relevant contributions to the
debate surrounding the phenomenon of horror while emphasizing the typical problems
that follow from such contributions. This survey will not be aimed at an exhaustive dis
cussion of various approaches to horror; by discussing them and their problematic
points, I will demonstrate the need to outline an alternative conception that will be pro
posed in section two.
One peculiar thing about the investigation of horror is that very different researchers –
ranging from Heidegger to Kristeva – seem to agree on what constitutes the most funda
mental trait of horror. Speaking on a very general level, the consensus sets horror as a sort
of a threat, which itself remains unknown; it comes from somewhere or from something
that resists clear identifications and challenges clearly established boundaries. The very
subject of the debate surrounding horror arises from the attempt to make sense of this
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
3
unknowablenessof horror, which proves to be a much more resilient task than defining
horror (at least on a general level).
That the unknown of horror has indeed a puzzling nature can be first demonstrated
based on Heidegger’s brief remark in Being and Time. While discussing fear, he notes that
horror is a modality of fear where abträglich, i.e. harmful, has the character of the
unknown (Heidegger Sein und Zeit 142). Unfortunately, Heidegger skips this topic
quickly, evidently showing little interest in the phenomenon of horror. Instead, he
quickly proceeds to the discussion of anxiety (Angst), for which he reserves a crucial
methodological role. However, if investigated more closely, Heidegger’s claim will
appear less trivial than it would seem at first sight. Of course, we could explain the
unknown of horror away as a lack of information, which is, in principle, rectifiable
(like, for example, when I am not sure exactly what kind of animal is running at me).
This, however, obviously goes against our constitutive intuition about horror, which
indicates – however obscure and preliminary this indication might be – that something
can appear to me exactly as unknown rather than something that is to be known better. If
our goal is to investigate the phenomenon of horror, we need to treat this unknown as a
positive determination of an appearance. Thus, we should ask ourselves how something
could positively resist the very attempt at identification and retain its positive indetermi
nacy. What is the structural unity of such an appearance?
Posing the question this way, we could notice an intriguing proximity between horror
and Heidegger’s description of anxiety (Angst); the “positive unknown” of the former
appears to have some similarity with the “nowhere” (Heidegger Sein und Zeit 186) of
the latter. As is well known, anxiety confronts Dasein with recognition of its own
freedom and its own way of being in general. Facing anxiety Dasein realizes that it
cannot pretend that its own ways of doing and saying things, its own identities and pre
ferences are objective determinations for which it is not responsible because Dasein itself
exists as the ecstatic openness to the world. Its essential determinations follow from its
free relation to the world, not otherwise. Since according to Heidegger “average intellig
ibility” or “everyday disclosure” is created in an attempt to hide this authentic self-rec
ognition, anxiety reveals something that by definition cannot be “known” or
meaningfully given (i.e. that is “nowhere” to be found) by the standards of everyday intel
ligibility of Das Man. Anxiety remains unknown because it belongs to a different order of
intelligibility. And yet, as Grundbefindlichkeit, i.e. fundamental attunement of Dasein
(Heidegger Sein und Zeit § 40) anxiety is presupposed by average intelligibility as the
condition of its possibility: even an attempt to avoid the recognition of its own way of
being itself presupposes this very way of being along with the anxious recognition that
no one will “choose my choices” (Heidegger Sein und Zeit 268) for me. Anxiety always
haunts everyday intelligibility, which has no words and no place for it.
It would seem that the unknown of horror can be approached in the same way: some
thing can appear as unknown because this something is at the same time unintelligible by
particular standards of intelligibility and presupposed by them nonetheless. In this sense,
horror, just like anxiety, could be seen as something like a call for a different type of intel
ligibility (“disclosedness”). The problem, however, is that this analogy between anxiety
and horror is partial. There also is a crucial asymmetry: while anxiety eventually
brings us to the recognition of our own way of being and awareness of the incomplete
ness of everyday intelligibility, horror does not presuppose any reconciliation. If
4
D. KOLOSKOV
unknowingness of horror is indeed constitutive of it, then transforming it into something
that makes sense – even if what makes sense is, in the end, the abyss of ground (Ab-grund)
of Dasein’s freedom (Heidegger 1998, 174) – would lead to the disappearance of horror as
a phenomenon. The unknown of horror appears to be deeper and stubborner than the
unknown of Heideggerian anxiety.
Early Levinas bases his account of horror exactly on this asymmetry. In order to expli
cate it, let me first briefly reconstruct the philosophical context in which Levinas’s discus
sion arises. In his early work, Levinas takes over Heidegger’s ontological problematics:
just like the latter, he seeks to explicate and clarify the meaning of Being (e.g. Heidegger
Sein und Zeit § 1; Levinas Existence and Existents 18). Unlike Heidegger, however,
Levinas opts for a more traditional usage of the term. While Heidegger uses it in a
sense that is closer to intelligibility or meaning of entities (“that which defines entities
as entities, that on the basis of which entities … are in each case already understood”;
for a more detailed discussion see, for example, Sheehan 2014 or Carman 2003),
Levinas opts for a more traditional usage of the term that is more closely related to
notions of “existence” or “presence.” Consequently, for him, the phenomenon or the
“event of being,” (Levinas Existence and Existents 18) which he describes with the
term “there is (il y a)” (Levinas Existence and Existents,19), signifies primarily the funda
mental positivity of Being that exceeds and surpasses our ability to make sense of it. As he
puts it, the “there is” of being is what is left after imagining “all things beings and persons,
returning to nothingness” (Levinas 1987, 46): even after all intelligible entities are wiped
out, there would still be something left, an irremovable surplus of Being, which Levinas
describes as “atmospheric density” or the “murmur of silence”. So he speaks about “exist
ence without existents” (Levinas Existence and Existents 57) where Being loses its orga
nized and differentiated character to which we are accustomed and transforms into the
hovering bulk, the pure “there is.” When describing this state of undifferentiation, he
speaks of “darkness of the night which is neither an object nor the quality of an
object. . . . There is no longer this or that; there is not ‘something’” (Levinas Existence
and Existents, 58). This phenomenon of Being, he says, “is essentially alien and strikes
against us” (Levinas Existence and Existents, 23).
The state of undifferentiation also concerns the subject itself. The absolute homogen
eity of Being threatens the individuality of the subject, leaving for it no room for escape.
The personal character of my own existence is swept away by the homogeneity, “sub
merged by the night, invaded, depersonalized, stifled by it” (ibid., 58). However, the
sense of pure existence is not. It is this experience of losing one’s own personality and
submerging in the positivity of Being, which Levinas identifies as the essence of
horror: “[t]he rustling of the there is … is horror” (ibid., p 60). Horror, in other
words, is an experience of the complete obliteration of all the names, all the possible indi
viduality that “carries out the condemnation to perpetual reality, to existence with ‘no
exits.’” (ibid., 62). And by inserting me in the hovering bulk of “there is,” horror
becomes an ultimate manifestation of Being rather than of particular beings. So, if Hei
deggerian anxiety confronts me with the recognition that nothing positive in the world
can unburden me from my way of being, horror reminds me that even this mineness is
inescapably bogged down in the positivity of Being as such. Heidegger’s anxiety “indivi
dualizes” (Heidegger Sein und Zeit 188) Dasein by reminding it of the possibility of
dying; Levinas’s horror, on the contrary, wipes out any hint of individuality and
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
5
proclaims the “death of death” denying even this fundamental possibility of escaping
Being. Commenting on the difference between anxiety and horror, Levinas says that
“[t]he pure nothingness revealed by anxiety in Heidegger’s analysis does not constitute
the there is. There is horror of being and not anxiety over nothingness, fear of being
and not fear for being; there is being prey to, delivered over to something that is not a
‘something’” (Levinas Existence and Existents 62).
In this way, Levinas explains to us how “something” can appear threatening while
remaining unknown at the same time. On the one hand, as an experience of the oblitera
tion of all names and identities, the “there is” of Being remains fundamentally unknow
able; it is not just a threat that is unintelligible, it is a threat posed to intelligibility as such.
On another, this unknowable something lies at the foundation of the ability to know any
thing: the brute, undifferentiated positivity to which we ourselves belong remains a con
dition of possibility of any differentiation and individuality. Horror, in this sense, haunts
us as a non-human foundation of being a human (see also Trigg 2014, 47–54 on explica
tion of this line of thinking). But despite making this important contribution to the dis
cussion of horror, Levinas’s account remains insufficient. It might be argued that taking
as his starting point the extreme case of horror, Levinas confuses particular extremal fea
tures of this experience for an essential trait of horror as such. Postulating the radical
breakdown of intelligibility as constitutive of horror becomes problematic when
applied to more subtle cases of horror, which appear more as a perversion of intelligibility
rather than its breakdown. As a result, rather than reaching the “idealization” of horror in
which we can “recognize” ourselves (Merleau-Ponty 1968, 87), Levinas ends up imposing
certain characteristics on the lived experience of horror.
Take, for example, Levinas’s night metaphor: he employs the figure of the night in
order to describe how the all-encompassing and monotonous positivity of the phenom
enon of Being abruptly overtakes and envelops the differentiated, intelligible world.
However, by regarding this experience as a constitutive trait of horror as such, Levinas
goes as far as to suggest that the actual terror of nights must have the same motivation.
The real reason why individuals are terrified of nights is that the night somehow reminds
them of this suffocating positivity of being. A quick survey into the lived experience of
being terrified at night will demonstrate, however, that we are not afraid of the night
because it threatens to dissolve our identity. Normally, it is due to creatures that
might live there – the malicious, twisted beings that want to grab us and tear us to
pieces. Something like a marginal and quite abstract concern for one’s own identity
can only be added here as a second-order logical complementation that reconstructs
rather than describes the phenomenon of horror. Similarly, the real reason why we are
terrified of ghosts, says Levinas, is because they remind us of the impossibility of
dying and departing from the positivity of being. Once again, this seems to be quite
far from the lived experience of horror: the threatening and malicious creatures who
enjoy inflicting pain and suffering on us just for the sake of it offer us far more immediate
reasons for concern. In both cases, Levinas places the horror in the face of Being as an
underlying motive of an actual horror, which naturally blocks him from accessing the
self-standing meaning of the phenomenon.
If we, contrary to Levinas, rely on this more subtle perversion as constitutive of the
intelligibility of horror, we would be able to satisfactorily account for a wider sample
of lived experience. Indeed, while the Levinasian phenomenon of Being comes off
6
D. KOLOSKOV
more like a crude denial of intelligibility (the radical Other that is “essentially alien and
strikes against us”), the “liminal creatures” of night display more inconspicuous signs of
confusion and perversion. If investigated on their own terms, their horns, the dispropor
tionally long limbs, their glowing eyes and endless lust for violence do not point towards
absolute unintelligibility but rather towards a different order of intelligibility that
remains, nonetheless, inaccessible to us. In horror, the identity of things is not annihi
lated completely but twisted and pushed to the limit; here we can see the interplay of
intelligibility where the familiar elements become confused up to a point where they
are no longer fully recognizable but still remind us of their identity.
A more systematic emphasis on this constitutive confusion of horror can be found in a
now-classic study The Philosophy of Horror: Or, Paradoxes of the Heart, by N. Carroll.
Here, Carroll offers us a technical definition of horror as an “abnormal, physically felt
agitation (shuddering, tingling, screaming, etc.)” (Carroll 27) caused by the presence
of a particular type of objects (or by the thought of their “possible” presence), which
he calls horror-monsters. What is essential about those objects, he claims, is that they
at the same time combine “the property of being physically (and perhaps morally and
socially) threatening” and “impure” (ibid.). The latter category performs the most impor
tant explanatory work. Realizing that horror cannot be sourced directly from the literal
dirtiness, Carroll treats impurity rather as a symbol of the transgression of cultural norms.
He claims that “an object or being is impure if it is categorically interstitial, categorically
contradictory incomplete, or formless” (ibid., 32). The literal impurity, in this sense, is
only an illustrative example of this “categorically interstitial.” Crossing boundaries of cul
tural identifications, monsters become an expression of confusion per se; they “are unnatural relative to a culture’s conceptual scheme of nature” (ibid., 34). As such, the
danger that is coming from monsters is not reducible to the possibility of inducing phys
ical damage. It comes from becoming a complex threat: in addition to being physically
threatening, they also are “cognitively threatening” as they “challenge” and “violate”
the very “foundations of a culture’s way of thinking” (ibid.).
This aspect also finds its expression in the typical places of residence of horror-mon
sters: “monsters are native to places outside of and/or unknown to the human world. Or,
the creatures come from marginal, hidden, or abandoned sites: graveyards, abandoned
towers and castles, sewers, or old houses—that is, they belong to environs outside of
and unknown to ordinary social intercourse” (ibid., 35). Again, the link to the abandoned
sites should not be considered literally: graveyards and old houses, claims Carroll are only
“a figurative spatialization or literalization of the notion that what horrifies is that which
lies outside cultural categories and is, perforce, unknown” (ibid.). Both the impurity and
the deserted places are meant, in the first place, to embody this confusion, which cannot
be clearly put in terms of the culturally established system of signification. The fact that
monsters settle in places which defy usual living conditions and which are supposed to be
normally avoided refers us in the first place to the “placeless place before language, law, or
cognition proper” (Kearney 196), which then receives its symbolical expression. Their
geographical and normative outsideness symbolizes the lack of concepts that could
help us to locate and identify them. Thus, the constant underlying motive of horror is
its anonymity. Monsters are “something,” they are a nameless force that lacks a properly
identifiable “face;” “[b]y means of pronouns like “It” and “Them” suggests that these
creatures are not classifiable according to our standing categories” (ibid., 33). In this
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
7
sense, we could say that the unknowingness of horror-monsters is produced by the cul
tural matrix; while negating and undermining the categorization and systematization of
ordinary life, monsters remain its intimate products.
Carroll’s account, however, remains substantially limited in its own way since his
explanatory strategy hinges entirely on providing such symbolic expressions of horror.
It doesn’t offer any account of the rule of formation of such an expression; thus, when
referring to typical objects of horror such as graves and impurity, Carroll rather presup
poses our grip on horror than explains it. For we can ask ourselves: what does it mean to
be a “figurative literalization” of horror? When an impure object becomes such a litera
lization instead of being plain dirty? When and why does a confusion become horrifying
confusion? Those questions remain at least partly unanswered because Carroll’s concep
tual tools are only sufficient to indicate facts of horror and, thus, provide a starting point
for the analysis of the structure, dissemination and typical aesthetics of horror. Nonethe
less, it stops short of explaining the genuine meaning of this fact; while Carroll is able to
point out certain typical features of horror, he is unable to emphasize its essential struc
ture. As a result, his distinguishing features of horror, if taken at face value, are clearly
insufficient. By themselves “formlessness” and “incompleteness” – and not even a “cat
egorical contradictoriness” of certain objects – can distinguish horrifying objects from
non-horrifying ones since we can easily imagine something that could be formless
(even categorically) but that wouldn’t be horrifying.
One particular attempt at explaining this aspect further, which I would like to discuss
briefly before proceeding to the phenomenological analysis of horror in section two, is
offered by psychoanalytically oriented authors. Developing Freudian insights, they
largely agree on the fact that horror, in the first place, refers us to this “categorically inter
stitial.” To give a couple of examples, Kristeva stresses that horror comes from a situation
where language, in a sense of customary categories of judgement “give[s] up” (Kristeva
Powers of Horror 11). It refers to a domain that is placed beyond what can be meaning
fully described and that follows from “a non-assimilable alien, a monster … that the lis
tening devices of the unconscious do not hear” (Ibid.). Commenting on Kristeva’s
account, Oliver claims that horror is “what is on the border, what does not respect
borders … what threatens identity; it is neither good nor evil, subject nor object … but
something that threatens these very distinctions” (Oliver 60). R. Kearney writes in a
similar way that monsters “defy our accredited norms” (Kearney 3); “‘monsters’ are
signal borderline experiences of uncontainable excess reminding the ego that it is
never wholly sovereign.”
Unlike Carroll, however, those authors offer more explicit explanations of why certain
categories can be seen as challenging our accepted ways of judging and thinking. Kristeva
for example, claims that horror “takes the ego back to its source on the abominable limits
from which, in order to be, the ego has broken away – namely, the non-ego realm of
archaic drive” (Kristeva Powers of Horror 15). According to this account, horror
appears to be a counterpart of socialization, which she identifies through the prism of
our ability to signify and place identities on the world around us and ourselves. Our
ego dismisses this realm of archaic drive as horrifying and irrational left over, something
she describes with the Platonic term khora – the “strange place” where our archaic “drives
hold sway” (Kristeva Powers of Horror 14) and where “elements are without identity, and
without reason” (Kristeva 1987, 235). Horror, in such a way, is a reminder of what we had
8
D. KOLOSKOV
to abandon and supress in order to become this socialized, language-using ego. As such,
it also nostalgically reminds us of what we have lost, “the height of harmony with the
promised land” (Kristeva Powers of Horror 18). According to a different account
offered by Kearney a monster “remains a personification of repressed Other. It functions
as a negative mirror image of ourselves which we project onto a fantasy world” (Kearney
118). Kearney additionally sees horror as provoking an ethical challenge. As “tokens of
fracture within the human psyche”, monsters leave us with a choice between trying “to
understand and accommodate our experience of strangeness” or repudiating “it by pro
jecting it exclusively onto outsiders” (Kearney 4).
While this approach can be true in many respects, we should generally indicate its
insufficiency when it comes to the investigation of the meaning of horror. Horror
might indeed have an intimate connection to traumas, phobias, repressions, counter-cul
tural forces, abjection and radical otherness; we might well agree with such authors as
McConnell who claim that a “psychic history of culture … could be written very efficien
tly from the morphology of its monsters, the history of those personifications of the void
which successive generations have selected as their central nightmares” (McConnell 136–
37). From the standpoint of investigating the phenomenal meaning of horror, however,
those elements can only be considered as a necessary condition of horror. Treating them as
a sufficient condition, however, effectively eliminates the very phenomenon itself. The
only reason why we speak about the phenomenon of horror as such is because horror
is not traumas or phobias; monsters do not appear to us as repressions, traumas or
“tokens of fractures.” “Phenomenalization” of horror, i.e. the deployment and
unfolding of this appearance, signalizes exactly the fact that it is no longer just a projec
tion of symbolic contradictions “which exists in the unconscious of each one of us”
(Kearney 120).
On the contrary, horror announces itself when traumas and contradictions are trans
formed into something else, something that doesn’t make us sad, nostalgic, lonely or even
agonizing but uncanny.1 This is an aspect that is especially familiar for horror-prose and
-film: most authors are well aware that traumas, crises and phobias only set the stage for
horror but not themselves horrifying; traumas and isolation lay at the very beginning of
horror’s deployment. So, monsters settle in token of fractures, traumas and phobias
without being reducible to them. Jumping ahead, we could agree with Kearney that
horror is just an attempt to put “a face on phobia” (Kearney 121) with one exception:
for an investigation of the self-standing meaning of horror, it would rather mean a starting
point of explanation rather than the explanation itself. What we should ask ourselves here
is what does this “acquiring a face” means exactly, how does it restructure the appearance
of an object and why does it push the appearance “outside” of the cultural matrix?
2. Counter-Intelligibility of Horror
So, the constitutive feature of horror, which we have emphasized in the previous section,
and which we will further explicate in this section, consists of the profound perversion
1
This usage of the term “uncanny” differs from Freud’s, who linked it with the imposition of the social taboo (we have
discussed the insufficiency of psychoanalytical approach above). I’m using the term in an everyday sense, meaning
something like an unsettling experience, mysterious unease that has an unclear but intuitive link to the supernatural.
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
9
that throws horrifying phenomena “outside” of the system of cultural significance, while
nonetheless retaining the reference to such a significance.
To do so, let me first offer an example of horror that would serve us as a model of dis
cussion. In particular, I would like to turn to a genre of internet folklore known as “cree
pypasta,” which is a collaborative online story-telling where users copy and paste (hence,
“pasta”) short horror stories or texts frequently altering the story or adding elements to it.
One of the outstanding examples of such story-telling is a story called “The Backrooms.”
“The Backrooms” was initially inspired by a single photo of an empty corridor with an
unpleasantly bright light that made people feel somewhat “off.” Elaborating on this
weird feeling, they came up with a story about a “place” – the backrooms – where
“people can slip” (or “noclip”) into and become lost or trapped. This place is “unreal”
or “parallel” to what is real – the bottom line is that it does not belong to a common,
shared space of ordinary life. In the beginning, the uncanny did not follow from “mon
sters” or any other tangible threats; the backrooms just “appear to be simply unoccupied
office space of banal manilla walls, long corridors and ugly carpets.” The sense of uneasi
ness follows from the inescapability of this place: the monotonous office spaces appear to
be endless and offer no exit, which creates an uncertain feeling that whoever finds himself
or herself trapped in the backroom will never find his way out. As the story developed,
another element emerges that solidifies the sense of horror. In the backrooms, there also
are other “things” and anyone who finds himself or herself locked in this place risks
facing its original inhabitants. As the frequently copy-pasted sentence puts it, “God
save you if you hear something wandering around nearby, because it sure as hell has
heard you.”
By itself, the narrative expresses very clearly the constitutive element of horror that we
have specified above. We could take the terms “unreal,” “parallel reality,” “irreality” as
expressing exactly this intuition of being outside of the domain of intelligible or, to
borrow Heideggerian term, being outside of “significance” (Bedeutsamkeit) i.e. the orga
nized holistic whole that ascribes place and function (“in-order-to”) to every particular
entity and event. But most importantly, we can also see clearly that the phenomenal
expression of this sense of “falling outside of intelligible” follows from the perversion
of the familiar, intelligible situation. To start with, “the Backrooms” have an understand
able spatial structure: it consists of a maze of interconnected rooms that reminds us of a
typical office space. Unlike the office space, however, the backrooms cannot be linked to
the system of other places to which we are accustomed. It is not clear how we got here or
how we can get out. There are no signs, windows or exits that would provide us everyday
orientations. Reminding us about the ordinary spatial configuration, it constitutes a
space that is isolated from it nonetheless; it is a place like all the other places, yet, in a
different, so far unexplained sense, it is definitely not like all the other places.
This oddity becomes more obvious and clear if we concentrate our attention on the
very content of the backrooms, which appears distorted as well. Backrooms contain fam
iliar, well-understood elements: by themselves, the yellow electric light, the monotonous
sound of ventilation, dull wallpaper, empty rooms and dusty wool carpeting pose no
challenge to our understanding. But the organization of those elements throws us off
course. Those elements are referred, in the first place, to a corresponding field of
smoothly operating work space and bourgeoning activity. Their intelligibility relies on
people running back and forth with stacks of pages in their hands, on the sound of
10
D. KOLOSKOV
ringing telephones and a background chattering. The lack of this appropriate phenomenal
field or, simply put, appropriate context inflicts systematic damage on the meaningful
ness of those elements. Each of them calls for a different setting and for a different organ
ization of the phenomenal field where they would appear as more optimal elements (“as
they are”) and make more sense. Until then, I find myself surrounded by a bunch of dis
parate things, which are thrown outside of their context of significance and that do not
appear as themselves for the most part. Exploring the backrooms, in such a way, I find
myself confronted with a sense of profound confusion; I am placed in the midst of
ruins of meaning where things rather remind us of their sense than make sense in a
given situation.
We could try to express this decay of meaningfulness by introducing the following
conceptual distinction. Namely, we might describe a normal, everyday situation where
things and events are situated within the appropriate phenomenal field and appear as
fully belonging to their own context as a “cultural height.” A cultural height situates
things, events are identities where they are supposed to be making it possible to reach
a certain optimal point of intelligibility. On the contrary, the situation of disorder or
anomaly, where things and events call for rearrangement and further explanation,
could be described as a “cultural cavity”; by anomaly here, we don’t mean something
marginal and rare in the first place but rather something that disrupts and undermine
the established intelligibility. A cultural cavity indicates the actor’ inability to respond
to the call for rearrangement; they are unable to situate things and events where they
are supposed to be even despite such a call. While the cultural heights give entities appro
priate settings to fully reveal themselves as they are, cultural cavities only let me encoun
ter entities in their constricted appearance; cavities only reveal the residues and
reminders of phenomena instead of letting them appear in a full sense of the word.
Naturally, every culture seeks to organize its “system of significance” (Bedeutsamkeit)
in a way that optimizes its phenomenal field(s): it takes care of the infrastructure by pro
viding the appropriate background and formulating the basic principles of its phenom
enal life. A cultural system of significance seeks to avoid events that are disruptive for a
given system of significance or seeks to downplay or explain away the phenomena that
are unavoidably disruptive (e.g. death as a “demise” (Heidegger Sein und Zeit 247)). If
we accept this general distinction, then we might explicate the exact nature of the “con
fusion” that induces horror in the following way. The backrooms start being terrifying
not just when I find myself surrounded by the cultural cavities, i.e. by the disorder
and decay of meaningfulness. It occurs when I obtain a first unclear feeling that here cav
ities are not anomalies but the constitutive principles of organization of this situation. A
horror-situation, i.e. a setting where horror can meaningfully appear, is characterized by
an inversed setting where something like a cultural cavity takes the position of cultural
height and cultural heights are moved to the status of an anomaly that themselves call
for an explanation and rearrangement; in backrooms, I myself become an anomaly.
This unclear sense of inversion receives its final articulation in the second part of the
story when it becomes complemented with a suspicion that something might live in this
place. Finding myself in inversed scenery where I encounter only traces and reminders of
phenomena, I start feeling that what appears to be an inversion or cavity for me might be
upright for something. Something settles among those cavities of phenomena, something
for which these bulges of phenomena wouldn’t be bulges anymore but phenomena
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
11
themselves. i.e. it would represent its own way of disclosing the phenomenal field. A
monster, an “unclean spirit,” a beast that rises “out of the sea,” is a densification of the
inversion of a cultural matrix, an inversion which reaches a critical point where it trans
forms into a positive principle. For a monster what counts as a cultural cavity becomes a
positive determination of its way of being. Its way of being is anchored in the negativities
and counter-forces of the cultural phenomenal field, its possibilities are a link between cul
tural cavities. “It” – something that can no longer fit into the cultural categorization – is
what finally reverses the polarity of the cultural matrix. Horror is an optimal way of bring
ing unoptimality and disarray to the phenomenal field. Conceived this way, we might
describe horror-monsters as evil; a horrifying evil2 as “‘the worst possible term of oppro
brium imaginable’ (Singer 185). It is ‘supernatural’ (See Clendinnen 79–113; Cole Myth of
Evil; “Deliver us from Evil”)” as it does not belong by definition to a cultural space.
As such, horror originally doesn’t refer us to wrongdoings or specific dangers like ones
that come from predators, murderers or natural disasters. Wrongdoings might violate
particular norms but they do not threaten the phenomenal field as such. The confusion
that is constitutive of horror, on the contrary, is irrevocably linked to the complete per
version of a phenomenal field: if everyday intelligibility is organized around cultural
heights seeking to secure the functioning of the phenomenal field, horror crystallizes
in the decline and folding up of phenomena. It presupposes this downward trend of intel
ligibility that distorts and disrupts the phenomenality but that at the same time claims for
itself a certain positivity and a certain appearance of this positivity. Horror announces
itself as a phenomenon at the cost of folding up the cultural phenomenality; being
born out of the straining of the symbolic system of a given culture and pulling off its hor
izons, horror swoops directly against the very deployment of a given cultural phenom
enal field. Thus, we could describe the phenomenon of horror as a counterphenomenon: a counter-phenomenon deploys its phenomenality at the cost of a foreclos
ing larger network of phenomena.3 It endangers, hunts down and exists as a constant
reminder of the fragility of the cultural “phenomenal spectrum” (Koloskov). As such,
it resonates with everything downgrading in a given culture. Horror lives in dirt and
decay, it is malicious and violent, it thrives on blood, sufferings and disappears under
the light. Monsters are, essentially, those “kings of flies” and the “great dukes of hell”
who settle in the inversed settings living on what normally would be subjected to ostra
cism and suppression. It is this combination of what is un-combinable, the possibility of
something that can live counter our life, that can enjoy what we suffer and suffer what we
enjoy that freezes the blood in our veins.
The danger that comes from horror, in this sense, goes hand in hand with its oddity.
Usual, mundane dangers are, in a certain sense, direct: diseases, murderers, disasters and
animals are dangerous insofar as they threaten this or that specific aspect of human exist
ence and as much as they threaten it (even in case of irrational phobias, the concreteness
of danger can be explicated despite its irrationality). Since horror does not threaten this
2
3
Of course, this conclusion does not extend itself automatically to the problem of evil as such; the question of whether
evil as such is horrifying or whether horror and evil are just an occasional combination is still open for further discussion.
This term here is used in a different sense from the way it is used by, for example, Merleau-Ponty who stresses that our
experience presupposes something that never appears but directly participates in enabling further appearances. I, on
the contrary, use it in a more direct way indicating something that actively obstructs the phenomenality. In this sense, it
is close in its meaning to Falque’s recent notion of extra-phenomenon (Falque 2018; 2022).
12
D. KOLOSKOV
or that particular aspect of human existence but represents a structural threat to the
deployment of the phenomenal field as such, the danger of horror comes from a
different trajectory. A smiling murderer, an unproportionally composed ghost, a
slowly moving murdering spirit are arguably less objectively dangerous than conventional
assassins, apex predators or plain tsunamis. The danger of horror comes not from objec
tive risks to which we are naturally exposed but from the total movement of winding
down of our phenomenal field. In this sense, the threat of horror is indirect: a direct
scare of being torn to pieces by a monster is just a culmination of the systematic challenge
that the monster poses to a given phenomenal field. And as such a challenge, it always
carries with itself some marks of distortion, which indicate that the threat that is
coming from a monster is, in fact, much more expansive than any direct threat that
we can think of. Extended limbs, a smile, horns are exactly those marks of perversion
that indicate the systemic threat of horror.
Their danger as well as their meaning in general remain, however, strictly speaking
unintelligible. Crimes and immoral acts are intelligible transgressions because, again,
they are still linked to the common-sensual frame of reference (for example, the sadistic
desire of torturing people might be distanced from a socialized individual but it is still
intelligible as it presupposes something like the shared principle of pleasure). Unlike
them, horror indicates a more fundamental rupture that separates it from the ordinary
– being constituted as a complete perversion turned into a positive way of being,
horror burns every bridge to the shared reality. The positivity of horror remains, thus,
inaccessible to us. We can only access horror as this Other whose essence is to threaten
our phenomenal spectrum; instead of arriving at a clear grip on what kind of entity is
horrifying, we are confronted with the feeling that there is this something that must
harm us according to its very essence. Horror retains this character of indefinite some
thing because we can know it only by suffering it. If expressed in clear-cut terms and situ
ated in the system of cultural significance, horror loses its horrifying character and
becomes transformed into a mundane phenomenon. So, instead of being clearly articul
able, horror advances in spurts unclearly indicating the possible counter-cultural connec
tions, identifying areas of tension and tacitly reversing their polarities. In the domain of
horror, we can only move by groping our way forward from one such area to another.
Here we also return to the border-like nature of the phenomenon of horror, which
finds it a place “outside” of the world. The constitutive unintelligibility of horror indi
cates exactly that it no longer belongs to the whole of significance: inverting the polarity
of the phenomenal field, changing cavities into heights and heights into cavities, the
horror finds itself on the flip side of the cultural space. The horrifying link between sig
nificant, intra-worldly phenomena – between a smile and murder, between blood and
thirst, between decay and prosperity – is not a link of this world. It can only be linked
from this other side. Horror renders these counter-cultural connections conceivable
exactly as unintelligible, as no longer belonging to the significant whole but to the flip
side of this whole where horror dwells. Our ability to conceive the counter-cultural
links, in such a way, goes hand in hand with excluding them from the ordinary reality
and its common sense. The monster that consolidates the purely negative character of
this inversion into something positive also causes dissection between the reality of every
dayness and the “unreality” of horror; ordinary situations and horror situations are
incommensurable and one can only be thought of as the “the other side” of another.
JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY
13
So, if horror appears, it appears from this other side; it penetrates the reality of the every
day world while not belonging to it for the most part. There is this movement of selfexclusion from the world of horror: the more it is manifested as horror, the less it
belongs to a particular cultural world. It can only be given as haunting reality and threa
tening our phenomenal spectrum, thus, being at the same time attached to and excluded
from it. We could, thus, see the deeper reason why horror is at the same time banned
“from entering its symbolic domain” and yet “not entirely absent” as haunting “the
edges of the culture” (Santilli 175).
Being separated from reality this way, horror needs some sort of special access in order to
get into the world in its never-ending lust for perversion and destruction. As a fundamen
tally incommensurable with everydayness phenomenon, horror cannot interact with other
entities and events, first and foremost. For the most part, it accompanies, indicates the poss
ible presence, whispers and hints – but does not occur. In order for horror to obtain a foot
hold in the world, some special circumstances must take place. The monster needs an
occasion, which would make the interaction between reality and unreality possible. This
occasion might take even a nominal form. We have seen, for example, how the Backroom
narrative simply expresses this special occasion with the term “clipping.” It might involve a
verbal invitation, the ritual summoning of a spirit or a satanic mass, which reverses the
Christian mass in order to imitate the presence of horror. It might require some special
locations, which by definition are situated closer to the reversive nature of horror (think,
for example, of mirrors with their natural reversive properties and how they are used in
horror-fiction of all sorts), the arrival of aliens or an unsuccessful scientific experiment.
The important thing is that border-like character, its position outside remains just as impor
tant as its unintelligibility. Thus, every particular depiction of horror as a phenomenon has a
natural motivation to explain how and why this border has been crossed.
Conclusion
We can see, in such a way, that horror deploys its own phenomenality by occurring
outside of cultural significance and goes beyond individual abilities to make sense of
the world. As such a counter-intelligibility, it demonstrates that our experience presup
poses the phenomenal initiative that is not of our own making. Horror displays a trajec
tory that goes contrary to any thinkable intentions of constituting subjectivity. Thus, it
becomes a prominent illustration of self emerging nature of phenomenality or, as Bar
baras puts it, of “phenomenalization without phenomena” (Barbaras Being of the
Phenomenon 164): the phenomenal movement of horror that by definition avoids any
kind of fixation by the subject and that is “always before or beyond the point where
one seeks to arrest it” and effectively requalifies the subject into an “advenant”; occur
rence of the phenomenon of horror can only be seen as a tendency of the phenomenal
field, not activity of the constituting subject.
Acknowledgment
The publication was supported as part of the “Competition for 2024-2026 Postdoctoral Job Pos
itions at the University of Hradec Králové”, at the Philosophical Faculty, University of Hradec
Králové.
14
D. KOLOSKOV
Disclosure Statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
References
Barbaras, R. The Being of the Phenomenon: Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology. Bloomington, Indiana:
Indiana University Press, 2004.
Barbaras, R. Introduction to a Phenomenology of Life. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University
Press, 2021.
Binswanger, L. Délire. Grenoble: Editions Jérôme Millon, 1993.
Carman, T. “What Is Fundamental Ontology?.” In Heidegger’s Analytic: Interpretation, Discourse
and Authenticity in Being and Time. Modern European Philosophy, 8–52. New York : Cambridge
University Press, 2003.
Carroll, N. The Philosophy of Horror or Paradoxes of the Heart. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Clendinnen, I. Reading the Holocaust. New York: Cambridge UP, 1999.
Cole, P. The Myth of Evil: Demonizing the Enemy. New York: Praeger, 2006.
Cole, P. “Deliver us from Evil.” The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Evil, edited by T. Nys
and S. de Wijze. Westport: Routledge, 2019. 177–88.
Falque, E. “Extra-phenomenal.” Diakrisis 1 (2018): 9–28.
Falque, E. By Way of Obstacles: A Pathway Through a Work. Eugene, Oregon: Cascade Books,
2022.
Heidegger, M. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1967.
Heidegger, M. Being and Time. New York: State University of New York Press, 1996.
Heidegger, M. Pathmarks. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Kearney, R. Strangers, Gods, and Monsters: Interpreting Otherness. London: Psychology Press,
2003.
Koloskov, D. “Fundamental Ontology, Saturated Phenomena and Transcendental Dilemma.”
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 53.4 (2022): 395–414.
Kristeva, J. Powers of Horror: An Essay on Abjection. New York: Columbia UP, 1982.
Kristeva, J. Tales of Love. New York: Columbia University Press, 1987.
Levinas, E. Existence and existents. Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: Duquesne UP, 1978.
Levinas, E. Time and the Other. Trans. Richard A. Cohen, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: Duquesne
University Press, 1987.
Maldiney, H. Penser l’homme et la folie. Bernin: Editions Jérôme Millon, 1991.
Marion, J.-L. Being Given: Toward a Phenomenology of Givenness. Redwood City, California:
Stanford University Press, 2002.
McConnell, F. D. The Spoken Seen: Film and the Romantic Imagination. Baltimore: The Johns
Hopkins UP, 1975.
Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception. Abingdon, Oxfordshire: Routledge, 1958.
Merleau-Ponty, M. Visible and Invisible. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1968.
Oliver, K. Subjectivity Without Subjects: From Abject Fathers to Desiring Mothers. Baltimore:
Rowman & Littlefield, 1999.
Romano, C. Event and World. New York: Fordham UP, 2009.
Santilli, P. “Culture, Evil, and Horror.” The American Journal of Economics and Sociology 66.1
(2007): 173–94.
Sartre, J.-P. Being and Nothingness. New-York: Washington Square Press, 1993.
Sheehan, T. Making Sense of Heidegger: A Paradigm Shift. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and
Littlefield Publishers, 2014.
Singer, M. G. “The Concept of Evil.” Philosophy 79 (2004): 185–214.
Trigg, D. The Thing: A Phenomenology of Horror. London: Zero Books, 2014.