Sot. Sci. Med. Vol. 36, No. 1, PP. 85-93, 1993
Printed in Great Britain. All rights reserved
Copyright 0
ISSUES OF GENDER
IN GAM ETE
0277-9536/93
S5.00+ 0.00
1993Pergamon Press Ltd
zyxwvutsrq
DONATION
ERICA HAIMFS
Department
of Social Policy, The University of Newcastle, Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 7RU, U.K.
Abstract-Gamete
donation refers to the practice whereby either semen or eggs are donated by a third
party to enable infertile individuals or couples to become parents. This paper examines the way in which
gender is deployed as a resource for organizing the meanings attached to that practice. The gender aspects
of gamete donation are not always immediately apparent since semen and egg donation are often described
as being essentially the same. However, a closer examination indicates that behind the claim of equivalence
lies a set of unstated assumptions about their difference. These assumptions are tied to ideas about the
ways in which men and women are thought to behave more generally in relation to reproduction and the
family. This paper draws on two sources of empirical data to reveal how these assumptions are used: first,
data from a detailed analysis of the Wamock Report (established by the British Government in 1982 to
inquire into and make recommendations on techniques of human fertilization and embryology), which
includes a cross-national and historical comparison with other government reports; second, data from a
series of in-depth interviews with members of the Warnock Committee. The analysis of the reports suggests
that historically semen donation was associated with ‘deviant’ sexuality (masturbation, adultery,
illegitimacy) though paradoxically the extant nature of Semen donation was then used to justify the
acceptance of egg donation in later reports. This is despite the fact that in these later reports there are
clear, albeit implicit, distinctions drawn between the two procedures in terms of donor motivation, the
risks of being a donor, and the consequences of donation. These differences were more marked in the
interview data. Committee members regarded egg donors as being very altruistic, whereas they frequently
raised doubts about the motivations of semen donors. It is suggested in the discussion section of the paper
that assumptions about gender and reproduction lead to egg donation being seen in a familial, clinical
and asexual context whereas semen donation is seen in an individualistic, unregulated context of dubious
sexual connotations. Therefore whilst assisted reproduction provides the chance to challenge gender
assumptions, what we find instead is that the everyday reasoning practices of those involved in these policy
discussions leads to a reinforcing of such views.
Key words-semen
donation, egg donation, gender
INTRODUCTION
Clearly these descriptions
of the techniques and
uses of gamete donation are not themselves unproblematic nor neutral; they raise many questions which
can be subjected to further investigation.
I wish to
Gamete donation involves the donation of either eggs
or semen by a third party to help another individual
examine just one aspect in this paper: the way in
or couple to have children. Semen donation (otherwhich gender is deployed as a resource for organizing
wise known as artificial insemination by donorthe meanings attached to the processes of gamete
AID; or donor insemination-DI)
has been used
donation, even at the same time as the apparent
since 1884 [l] though it gained in popularity in both
significance of gender can be denied. The starting
the United States and Britain in the 1940s. The
technique involves the depositing of a quantity of point in this examination is with the not uncommon
claim that egg donation is “the female equivalent of
donated semen in a woman’s vagina, by means of a zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIH
sperm donation” [2] or the “exact counterpart of
syringe rather than sexual intercourse. It is used when
AID” [3]. In so far as both procedures entail the
a male partner is either sterile or has a low sperm
giving of genetic material to others so that those
count or risks passing on a hereditary disease to any
genetically related children. It can also be used by others might have children (itself a deceptively simple
description of an enormously complex set of social
women wanting a child but wishing to avoid sexual
interactions) [4] this might superficially be true. Howintercourse with men.
Egg donation was first used successfully in 1984 in ever, a closer, empirically-based examination of the
ways in which semen and egg donation are characterAustralia, after the development of in vitro fertilizaized shows that they are in fact regarded very differtion in Britain in the 1970s. The technique involves
ently, even by those who on one level assert their
the co-ordination of the menstrual cycles of the donor
similarity.
and the recipient, the hyperovulation of the donor
In this paper I shall argue that these differences
and then the collection of the eggs using either
arise not just from the different physiological tasks
surgery, laparoscopy or ultrasound.
It is used
attributed to sperm and eggs in the fertilization
when a woman cannot produce her own eggs for
process, nor even from the different processes of
fertilization.
85
ERICAHAMIS
86 zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIHGFEDCBA
We were agreed that there is a need to maintain the absolute
donation (low-tech, non-invasive, low risk in the case
anonymity of the donor
Anonymity would give legal
of semen donation; high tech, highly invasive, high
protection to the donor but it would also have the effect of
risk in the case of egg donation), but from assumpminimizing the invasion of the third party into the family
tions about the ways in which men and women are
[5, P. 251.
thought to behave more generally in terms of reproIt was acknowledged that private arrangements might
ductive activities. These assumptions then reflect
occur
(between brothers for example) but this was
back onto and become incorporated into, the characseen
as
falling “outside any general regulation” [6]. In
terization of the physiological functions and methods
contrast
to this the Committee’s
position
on
of donation.
The empirical material upon which this analysis is anonymity in egg donation was as follows:
based derives from a study [4] I conducted on the
Despite our desire to maintain the anonymity of the donor
we recognize that because of the present practicalities of egg
work of the Warnock Committee [5], established by
donation, particularly the fact that eggs cannot be successthe British Government in 1982 to inquire into and
fully stored, it may not always at present be possible to
make recommendations
on, techniques of human
achieve this. An exception to the principle of anonymity
fertilization
and embryology.
These recommenwould occur where the egg was donated by a sister or close
dations were the basis of the British Human Fertilizafriend. In such cases particularly careful counselling for all
tion and Embryology Act, 1990. In this study I concerned would be necessary, and thought would have to
be given as to how and at what stage the child should be told
examined both the contents of the Committee’s final
about its parentage [5, p. 371.
report, comparing it cross-nationally and historically
with other reports on this subject, and also, through
Two points need to be made here. First, it is signifia series of depth interviews, members’ views on their
cant that though in egg donation the potential lack
participation in the Committee and the range of of anonymity is not exactly welcomed, it is not
techniques under investigation. The interviews in considered to be sufficient reason for banning the
particular provide detailed evidence of how gender is practice altogether. This might be thought surprising
deployed as part of everyday commensense reasoning
given the importance attached by the Committee to
to construct ideas about semen and egg donation. zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJ
the principle of anonymity as a whole. Second, there
is a significant difference in the manner and tone in
which this issue is discussed in relation to each
SEMEN AND EGG DONATION IN THE WARNOCR REPORT
practice: in particular, the association between lack of
anonymity and invasiveness which is made in the case
My initial reason for being interested in the work
of semen donation is absent in the case of egg
of the Warnock Committee grew from earlier redonation. Instead of “invasion” of a third party,
search on the management of information concerning
there is a “sister or close friend” who would be given
the genetic origins of children conceived through
“careful counselling”. It is also interesting to note
gamete donation. The position of the Warnock Comthat though the Committee mentioned the difficulty
mittee in this debate is interesting since they went
of recruiting semen donors [5, p. 271 the possible
against established practice by insisting that such
solution of using siblings was not proposed. The
children should be told about the circumstances of
circumstances surrounding egg donation seem to be
their conception, but at the same time confirmed
in less need of the protection thought to be afforded
elements of that earlier practice by also insisting on
by anonymity.
anonymity between all parties.
Each of these accounts is creating a world in which
This anonymity was one of three principles identthe reader is instructed to deploy different criteria for
ified by the Committee as central to all the procedures
perceiving, and then judging, the different practices.
of assisted reproduction.
It is important therefore to try to tease out what those
A number of the techniques we consider involves a third
hitherto unstated criteria might be. It is even more
party outside the infertile couple . In all cases, the
important to do this when we realise that, despite the
question is whether it is better that a third party who helps
a couple to overcome their infertility should be known to the
(uncommented on) differences in attitude towards
couple or that the third party should remain anonymous . .
anonymity, the Report states,
our general view is that anonymity protects all parties not
only from legal complications but also from emotional
difficulties. We recommend that as a matter of good practice
any third party donating gametes for infertility treatment
should be unknown to the couple before, during and after
the treatment, and equally the third party should not know
the identity of the couple being helped [5, p. 151.
However,
if the Report is read more closely the
principle of anonymity works rather differently in the
case of egg donation to that of semen donation. In the
discussion in the Report on the principles of good
practice for the future use of donor insemination, it
was said,
In weighing up the arguments for and against egg donation
we have concluded that since we have accepted AID and
IVF it would be illogical not to accept egg donation,
notwithstanding the relatively minor surgical risks to the
donor inherent in egg recovery . . It is both logical and
consistent that the law should treat egg donation in the same
way as AID and that the same principles of practice . .
should apply to both [5, p. 361.
Thus despite the fact that there are acknowledged
differences in procedure and unacknowledged
differences in overall perception of the two practices, the
Committee
thinks of them as being essentially the
Issues of gender in gamete donation
same and also regards itself as having treated them in
essentially the same way [7& Clearly the Committee
members were using unstated and perhaps unconscious assumptions about the social context of each
procedure which led them to distinguish between the
two on the basis of one of their central principles,
without being fully aware of the extent to which they
were actually doing this.
The question then becomes how to render explicit
those unstated assumptions so as to make visible the
reasoning processes whereby the above account in the
Report can be read as consistent. It was for this
purpose that I then interviewed the Committee members to try to discover their repertoire of concerns
when considering these matters. I shall present some
of the material from those interviews in the next
section.
However, before turning to the interview data, it is
worth pointing out that the Wamock Report was not
alone in containing this apparent inconsistency, nor
in conveying a sense of danger in relation to semen
donation/donors
which is not then attached to egg
donation/donors.
This can be seen by reference to
other reports, which were attempting a similar task of
reviewing, and making recommendations
for the
regulation of, forms of assisted reproduction.
In two of the reports which the Warnock Reports
itself cites as its predecessors, the attitude towards
semen donation was very negative. This was tied to
the perceived circumstances of donation, the consequences of using donated semen and possible motivations of the donors and recipients.
The Archbishop of Canterbury’s Commission [8]
recommended that semen donation should be criminalized since it involved masturbation by the donor
and resulted in an illegitimate child. They agreed that
this led to an inevitable secrecy surrounding the use
of donor insemination which was itself a further
indication of the unacceptability of the practice and
its constituent procedures. Such was their concern
about masturbation that they discussed a suggestion
from elsewhere that to avoid this, semen might be
collected from the donor’s wife’s vagina instead. This
procedure was further recommended on the grounds
that the donor’s wife might then feel that she too was
contributing to the donation [8, p. 151.
The Commission also expressed doubts about the
motivation of both the Semen donor and the female
recipient. They wondered, for example, whether semen donors sheltered behind ‘altruistic idealism’ to
disguise what was in fact ‘spiritual pride’ in their
ability to propagate large numbers of their own
children, thus asserting their greater virility [8, p. 271.
They also questioned the willingness of the wife of an
infertile man to become a mother through, “the seed
of a man not her husband”, which they said, “meant
the desire for motherhood must be judged to be
pathological” [8, p. 251. This is particularly significant
since there were debates at the time as to whether use
of donor insemination amounted to adultery.
87
The Feversham Committee [9] was similarly negative, expressing similar concerns about masturbation
and about the qualities and motivations of the semen
donors. Donors, they argued, might be considered
irresponsible given their apparent willingness to
father children with whom they would have no
further contact. The Report said of semen donation
in general,
it is an activity which might be expectedto attract more than
the usual proportion of psychopaths [9, p. 581.
Concern was expressed in both reports about the
feelings of the infertile husband concerning the use of
donated semen and his own infertility. Fletcher [lo],
writing in the same period, reported that doctors
‘often’ allowed the infertile husband to operate the
actual syringe containing the donated semen so
that he could say, “I impregnated
my wife”
[lo, p. 1251.
Though these are but snapshots from two very
detailed reports, it is already becoming clear that
these discussions about the use of semen donation
were implicity gendered. From the above comments
it is apparent that male concerns in reproduction
were presumed to revolve around ideas of virility,
genetic continuity and generally being assertive and
in control. Female concerns were presumed to revolve
around the need to become a mother which led to a
form of pathological assertiveness when otherwise the
woman’s role was characterized by passivity. It is
important to note, however, that these characteristics
were not just a feature of a practice disliked by the
two committees and thus deliberately portrayed in a
negative light, but were also part of what were seen
to be possible solutions to some of the problems
identified. For example, the donor’s wife is presumed
to be passive in the solution to masturbation and the
male is presumed to need to be in control in Fletcher’s
solution to the infertile husband’s feelings of inadequacy (itself dependent again on the passivity of the
woman being “impregnated”).
Finally, the whole
context of semen donation is, in these two reports,
associated with ideas of inappropriate
sexuality:
adultery, masturbation and illegitimacy. I shall return
to these observations in the final section of the paper.
An international review [4] of more recent reports
reveals that attitudes now appear to be more positive
towards semen donation and donors. The scope of
such reports is much wider too since, like the
Wamock Committee, most groups were asked to
consider the full range of assisted reproduction
including egg donation. Prominent amongst these
reports are those from the American Fertility Society
[1l] and a European Community commissioned
report known as the Glover Report [12]. These both
take a similar approach to that of the Warnock
Report in so far as both deem semen and egg
donation to be acceptable [13]. However, with varying degrees of explicitness, the criteria of acceptability
differ between the two forms of donation.
ERICAHAIMES
88 zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIHGFEDCBA
Once again the question of information about the
donor provides a forum for comparison.
For
example, the American Fertility Society judged each
third party conception in the light of its impact on the
child’s genetic lineage. It argued that identifying
information about the semen donor should only be
provided in ‘extreme situations’ but that in the case
of egg donation, though anonymity might be desirable the lack of it should not prevent the practice. A
lack of hard evidence about the benefits of identifying
semen donors was cited as grounds for retaining
anonymity in donor insemination, but a lack of hard
evidence about the dangers of using known donors in
egg donation was cited as grounds for not objecting
to that practice. The distinction here was not commented upon.
The Glover Report makes an interesting observation on these issues,
potential victim of either physical risks or emotional
risks resulting from pressure to donate. The possibility that egg donors may have questionable motives
or that semen donors be exploitable is not counten-
Policies on anonymity represent a social choice about the
meaning of donation [12, p. 361.
Sweden [14, p. 651.
though what is perhaps most interesting is that this
is a point raised about semen donation only: they do
not reflect on its significance for their own report.
Thus, despite their claim that,
Egg donation raises the same issues of social attitudes as
sperm donation [12,p. 381.
they construct a different framework of discussion for
each: a framework in which they perpetuate the
emerging trend of discussing semen donation in terms
of the wisdom of identifying donors, and in which
they discuss egg donation in terms of the wisdom of
using related donors. The Glover Report takes an
unusual line by advocating an experiment to identify
semen donors to the ‘child’ when 18. Their position
on egg donors is that either unknown egg donors
should be used or that there should be openness
about the use of related egg donors. There was no
mention of including unknown egg donors in the
experiment of giving ‘children’ access to donors’
names.
This difference in the policy on anonymity between
semen and egg donors should be seen against the
broader background of concerns expressed by the
Glover Committee about each practice. Again the
question of donor motivation is raised in relation to
semen donation. For example, they acknowledge that
semen donors may be altruistic but they also say,
perhaps some men do donate semen for money. But there
may be something more subtle about this. Men may have
other reasons for being willing to donate, but the payment
gives them a ‘reason’ which damps down further selfscrutiny about their motives [12, p. 341.
It is not clear what is being referred to here but it does
suggest that some motivations for being a semen
donor are not easily examined even by the donors
themselves, possibly for reason of guilt, shame or
embarrassment.
In contrast to this, the fears expressed about egg donation posit the donor as a
anced
One final report should be considered here, to show
that even when it is argued in explicit terms that
semen and egg donation should be treated differently
the arguments for doing so do not lie wholly within
the grounds of physiological or even collection procedure differences. The report from Sweden [14] on
fertilization outside the body states,
Egg donation does not occur in Sweden..
Egg donation
is a complicated
method of fertilization
which goes completely against
the natural
process of life. We cannot
disregard that the method can involve risks of physical and
mental strain for the pregnant woman and the developing
child
egg donation
is ethically indefensible.
In the
Committee’s
view egg donation
should be prohibited
in
This statement can be compared with two other
related policies in Sweden: the first allows semen
donation but provides access to identifying information about donors to the ‘children’ conceived [ 151;
the second prohibits the use of semen donation
coupled with zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQP
in vitro fertilization [14]. When the
statement on egg donation is compared to the first
policy the reader is invited to view semen donation as
a simpler but also more natural procedure, despite the
fact that semen donation raises a series of highly
complex issues which the policy on access to information acknowledges and despite the fact that natural processes too can be very complicated. The
additional argument about the strains for the pregnant woman and developing child is untenable since
the same might be said to apply to semen donation.
Had this point been made about the egg donor and
referred back to the procedures of donation it would
carry more weight, but here it simply raises more
questions. In a comparison between the policy on egg
donation and the policy rejecting the combination of
IVF and donor insemination we find that in the latter
the case simply rests on setting limits on “how far to
go regarding manipulations to remedy childlessness”
[14] and makes no reference to other standards of
practice, such as those set by ‘nature’. It would be
foolish to press the interpretation too far of what is
again essentially a snapshot but this last example does
at least raise further questions about the grounds on
which semen and egg donation are compared: in
particular why is nature invoked as an important
reference point for evaluating egg donation but not
for semen donation?
This review of the attitudes displayed in major
reports towards semen and egg donation shows that
there has been a change over time towards semen
donation which appears to have led to its greater
acceptability. This in turn has been used to establish
the acceptability, in most countries, of egg donation.
However, differences still emerge in attitude towards
Issues of gender in gamete donation
the two forms of donation even in reports which
characterize them as being essentially the same. This
has been shown to be the case with reference to the
debate on the management of information about
genetic origins, which has been structured along
different lines for each type of donation. In semen
donation, the debate is whether to identify donors
and although there are moves towards establishing
the case for identification, the overall preference so
far is not to identify them. In egg donation the debate
is tied to the use of known related donors and
although this could be seen as essentially the same
question as whether to identify semen donors, the
phrasing and development of the argument provides
a different picture which leads to a different conclusion: that the balance lies in favour of allowing
known donors if the alternative is to lose the practice
altogether [16].
What is even more significant is that there is little
cross over between the two discussions: using relatives as donors is very rarely discussed in the field of
donor insemination and explicit debates about access
to donor identifying information is hardly ever discussed in the field of egg donation. We have also seen
that the differences between the egg and Semen
donation are raised in other areas too, particularly in
the question of the motivation of donors and the risks
that donors are thought to incur through their participation in these procedures.
It is possible, therefore, to begin to identify different criteria in the evaluation of semen and egg
donation and I have begun, very tentatively to
suggest how these criteria are derived. However, the
picture so far is very fragmented: that there are
questions to be asked has been established but the
nature of those questions requires further explication.
The data from interviews I conducted with the members of the Wamock Committee provide the opportunity to investigate these questions further. By using
the technique of in-depth, face-to-face interviews I
explored the members’ views on semen and egg
donation, in order to gain further insight into the
apparent contradictions identified here.
SEMEN
AND EGG DONATION IN THE WARNOCK
COMMITI-EE INTERVIEWS
The interviews with committee members covered
a number of topics relevant to the wider research I
was conducting, but in this section I shall just present
data on gamete donation: how members regarded
each process individually and how they compared
the two [17].
In discussing donor insemination with committee
members, three positions seemed to emerge: those
who saw little problem with it (perhaps 4 members);
those who expressed fairly strong reservations (perhaps 9 members) and one person who was against it
on religious grounds. This range of views had not
been evident in the Report [ 181.
89
Of those who saw little problem with donor insemination most were aware of the objections contained
in the evidence submitted to the Committee. One
member said,
There was probably more hostility I think to AID than to
almost everything else, if you put it on the scales and
weighed it [19].
Even so, Iris view was that he had not much hesitation
in accepting it; though he had concerns about its
delivery he had no concerns about “the thing in
principle”. Another saw “no great moral problem”;
a third said she had no concerns and found it difficult
to explain the concerns expressed by others. It was a
very reasonable way for infertile couples to be treated . . it
seemed to work very well, produced very few problems
afterwards.
A second group was far less certain about donor
insemination and, in common with some members of
the first group, gave the strong impression that it was
simply the fact that it had already existed for at least
40 years that its continuance could even be contemplated:
We were very very much less sure that AID was a suitable
treatment. In fact our attitude to that was ‘it exists, we can’t
do away with it, we ought to regulate it and make it better
than it is now, but . in an ideal world maybe we wouldn’t
have it, but we’ve got it so we can’t do anything about it’.
Another view was “it’s here to stay and you’ve got to
get on with it”; yet another said “AID has been going
on since time immemorial” and another,
I think quite a few of us took a fairly robust view and said,
‘well it’s happened and let’s try and make it happen
properly’, but not try and get that genie back in the bottle.
Along with the length of its period of practice
members also cited the fact that that period had itself
seen fairly radical changes in opinion on donor
insemination; to a certain extent they felt they were
the ones who could finally bring it out into the open
and achieve a better quality of service.
Even if the force of history worked in favour of
accepting donor insemination, some members still felt
quite unsure about it:
EH: Could you say a bit about . . . what you felt uncertain
of?
06: I think that it’s the sort of ‘yuk’ feeling about it, which
I think is probably historical as much as anything. I don’t
know, I think it’s an instinctive dislike rather than being able
to identify it.
Other members were concerned about the degree of
intrusion in a marital relationship and the problems
for the husband. In other words, the members of the
Committee shared the concerns put to them in the
evidence, but nonetheless chose to accept it as a
treatment. One member explained this in the following way:
here we get into a very difficult area because I can’t say yes
and no in abstract. My position on these things is that I can
see theoretical objections to that process, AID, but not
90
zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIHGFEDCBA
ERICAHAIMES
theoretical objections which would counter effectively the
arguments in favour. In other words, it’s an argument on
balance.
However, it is very noticeable that not one member
put a positive case forward for semen donation
during the interviews. Therefore the arguments stated
in the Report in favour of its use could not be added
to, nor could they even be restated in the interviews.
Members were particularly disturbed by the selection and characteristics of donors in the United
Kingdom and preferred the French system of encouraging older, married men, who were already fathers,
to donate. That much is referred to in the Report, but
lying behind their uncertainties about the U.K. system was the figure of the Leicestershire (sometimes
known as the Nottinghamshire) postman: an individual who had been brought to their attention for
selling his own frozen semen, direct from his refrigerator to local hospitals. Reference to the figure acted
as a symbol of all their fears about donor selection,
from lack of screening, possible suspect motivations,
the inducement of cash and generally the ‘hole in the
comer’ attitude to donor insemination.
One member said there was a general question in
people’s minds about why anyone would want to
volunteer as a donor and that there were versions of
good and bad motivations for donating. The desire to
perpetuate one’s genes was a bad motivation,
. . the
thought was perhaps that if there was somebody who simply
liked the idea of the world being full of these (children)
whom he would never know, he would be a slightly cranky
sort of person and secondly if there was someone who
thought he could make a quick buck he was also not
particularly reputable . . . the motivation that seemed most
satisfactory is that people thought they were partly doing
some good, partly doing what was asked of him and, you
though why this was a bad thing was never clear
know, not particularly keen, necessarily, to have all these
children.
Another member had slightly mixed views on the idea
of donor motivation, saying that she did not agree
with the view that says a man who offers to donate
must be “pretty kinky” but followed this immediately
with:
Alright, they are odd in some way perhaps, but perhaps
they’re not . .
and anyway how serious a concern was this because,
I can’t see that that sort of bit is going to be handed on to
their children.
Therefore, a high degree of anxiety about donor
insemination was expressed but often without any
specific focus.
The Committee had to move beyond the difficulties
of donor insemination to consider a new form of
donation: that of eggs, which was made possible
through the development of in vitro fertilization. In
the interviews I asked members first for their views on
the IVF procedure, then on egg donation. Few
concerns were expressed about IVF and it was not
something that anyone wanted to discuss at length.
When I raised the question of egg donation I was
interested in several aspects: their general views on it
and then whether they drew any distinction between
the donation of ova and that of semen (here I used
the device of asking their opinion of the Swedish
proposal to ban egg donation, as a means of encouraging members to be more expansive in their replies).
A recurrent theme in the interviews was that egg
donation was the same in principle to semen donation, but different in terms of collection. This was
not necessarily a first response though:
I think some people sort of gulped and said, ‘oh yes’ and
then ‘what am I worried about? Am I worried about it?’ and
then they decided they weren’t, that really it was no
different.
Another described egg donation as “just the sort of
l%p side” of semen donation.
However, there is a
question of what the phrases “same in principle” and
“the equivalent”
said,
actually mean since one member
I regard it as the exact equivalent of sperm donation. The
difference is that it’s more stressful for the woman to donate
eggs than it is for the man to donate sperm.
Not many members could actually follow through to
explain exactly on which grounds semen and egg
donation were the same and on which grounds they
were different, nor did they explore the implications
these differences had for the argument that ‘in principle’, they were the same. Two members who attempted this both opined that there might be a case
for drawing psychobiological distinctions. One speculated that since semen is ‘exited’ from the body
for donor insemination and ova extracted for egg
donation,
one view may be is that he is not therefore
woman is to an egg.
attached
as a
but he himself did not really regard this as a valid
distinction, particularly as the egg is ‘exited’ every
month anyway. Curiously that monthly occurrence
confirmed for another speaker that there was “biological asymmetry” between semen and eggs, because
women had to think about their eggs on this monthly
cycle, whereas semen is treated “much more casually”. However, he argued that this did not constitute
a strong enough distinction to regard the two as
essentially different in terms of donation, though the
subject merited much more discussion, in his view.
On the whole though, members thought little about
the distinction made by the Swedes in banning egg
donation. Their responses included “if donation is to
be allowed for a man it should be allowed for a
woman”; “rather woolly thinking”; “it sounds as
though the politicians are really off their clogs”;
“another of those generalizations”; “a bit illogical. I
think one gift is the same as another gift”.
Yet many were worried about the problems of egg
collection even though they did not regard these as
Issues of gender in gamete donation
sufficient to stop its practice. In the Report the
problems associated with the actual collection of eggs
tend to be mentioned simply as part of the explanation of the technique. For the individual members,
however, they were more prominent. The issue of
informed and free consent of the donor taxed some
members. One argued that it should be taken very
seriously particularly as he regarded the “medical
business” as being “highly sexist” and likely to
presume consent. In his view a woman should not be
asked to donate eggs when lying on her back, about
to have a hysterectomy. Another also said he was not
at all happy about consent since some women were
in a very weak position to say ‘no’ since the people
asking for the eggs may be the same people providing
the original treatment. He regarded this as different
from semen donation since the donor there is not
under the same obligation. However, the first member
here felt fairly positive towards egg donation if that
opportunistic element were removed.
That positive attitude prevailed over members’
other concerns, such as the risks of superovulation,
the risks of anaesthetics while eggs were being
removed, and of the need for counselling to ensure
informed consent was given. The overall view was,
on the whole they assumed that the woman would he doing
it because it was no trouble to her in the circumstances and
that it would be thought to be good for somebody else.
Another member, acknowledging the concerns about
egg donation suggested nonetheless another view:
There are a lot of women about who have a feeling of
altruism as well. I mean they may need to be sugared by a
bit of money as well, but, nevertheless they may feel
altruistic and say, ‘I don’t mind giving an egg so that
somebody else may have a child’.
This view was confirmed by another member who
suggested there was a “lot of donative feeling about”
and that some women will “very joyfully” donate
eggs.
From these interviews it is apparent that there are
differences in attitude to egg and semen donation,
over and beyond the technicalities of donation. These
differences are found in the way the donation is
couched within other social practices and assumptions. For example, members made no mention of egg
donors as possibly being odd unlike their view of
semen donors; there was little mention in semen
donation of sibling donation; there was less mention
of exploitative practices in semen donation; there was
more mention of the generosity of the donor in egg
donation than in semen donation. Therefore, holding
the view that egg and semen donation are ‘the same’
means that since semen donation is acceptable, egg
donation must be as well. However, once the acceptability of egg donation has been established, it
becomes clear, on closer questioning, that there are
actually very different attitudes held about the two:
egg donation is generally seen in a positive light and
semen donation in a rather negative light. It is
91
perhaps worth speculating what the attitude towards
semen donation might have been if egg donation had
been developed first.
DISCUSSION
It is clear from both the reports and the interviews
that despite claims about the essential similarity
between semen and egg donation they are in fact
sharply distinguished from each other. These distinctions work on several levels but are particularly
prominent in two areas: the procedures of donation
and the motives ascribed to donors.
Semen donation is presented in the reports and in
the interview data as a simple, well-established procedure which nonetheless raises concerns in a number
of areas to do with forms of inappropriate sexuality,
such as masturbation, adultery and illegitimacy [20].
These associations remain strong despite the fact that
as a procedure it actually circumvents the need for
sexual intercourse whilst duplicating the essential
reproductive process of intercourse, the transmission
of semen. Egg donation, on the other hand, is
presented as a new and complex procedure, which
completely overthrows the procedures of reproduction from sexual intercourse, but is firmly located in
a clinical setting and is essentially asexual.
The motives of semen donors are seen as questionable, possibly because of the association with ‘deviant’ sexuality but also because of the fear that they
will be too active: by donating too frequently, by
wanting to father too many children and by invading
the families their donated semen helped to create. Egg
donors on the other hand are portrayed as more
passive, being subject not just to the clinical procedures of the collection (itself a more passive word
than ‘donation’) but also, potentially, being a victim
of the demands of relatives and exploitation by
clinicians. Thus, the egg donor apparently runs the
risk of physical damage through her participation in
the practice which serves only to enhance the view
that her motives must be altruistic whilst the semen
donor runs the risk of social damage, since there is
little physical risk attached to his participation but
some possibility of ‘illicit’ pleasure.
In a sense it is the very simplicity of semen
donation which has been interpreted as the source of
its danger. The image held by the Warnock Committee, and others, is of the semen donor as a stranger
with strange motivations: unknown, unregulated and
undesirable. Hence the fears that he might be invasive. Conversely, it is the complexity of egg donation
which appears to be the source of reassurance about
this practice. The egg donor is known to at least the
clinician and possibly the recipient: she is familiar in
person and familial in motivation. Both the clinical
and familial context of egg donation appear to
provide a sense of regulation and control. Hence the
view that anonymity is less important.
ERICAHAIMFS
92 zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIHGFEDCBA
However, the reassurance
which is derived from
the connection
between egg donation
and family
matters rests on a very particular type of family which
appears to inform such discussions.
It is a family
which is assumed to be heterosexual,
patriarchal and
nuclear. The family has to be heterosexual
for the
woman to woman donation of an egg to be seen as
completely asexual, in a way that the man to woman
donation
of semen apparently
cannot be seen as
asexual; it has to be patriarchal
for the involvement
of a female third party not to be seen as so invasive
or so significant a threat to the socio-political stability
of the family as a semen donor is apparently
regarded; it has to be nuclear since the boundaries are
seen as less threatened in egg donation than in semen
donation by an individual claiming genetic ownership
of the ‘child’ and thus displacing the social parent.
This threat is regarded as reduced in egg donation for
several reasons: first, the claim of the genetic mother
is balanced by the claim of the carrying mother;
second, if the donor is a sister any claim she could
make would be from within the boundaries
of the
nuclear family of origin; third, since the donor could
be from within the family the implication is that such
disputes are less likely to occur anyway [21]. In semen
donation, however, it might be feared that the boundaries are more easily breached since the social father
has a less obvious counter claim to that of the genetic
father.
Finally, a view which accepts egg donation more
easily than semen donation would also have to have
a version of the family in which the notion of
motherhood
rests at the centre. Accordingly,
egg
donation
would be consistent
with maternal
and
hence familial values, whereas semen donation would
have no such obvious moral corollary [22].
Identifying the links between ideas about gamete
donation
and ideas about the family exposes the
broader set of assumptions
surrounding
gender relationships and reproduction.
There is an irony in this
observation,
however,
since the very fact of egg
donation provides the possibility of at least loosening
the ties between women, sexuality, the family and
reproduction,
and semen donation provides the opportunity for re-thinking the male role in reproduction.
It has been argued by O’Brien that, prior to
assisted reproduction,
the male role has been one of
separation
[22, p. 511: the separation,
that is of the
man and the semen during intercourse
and then
between the man and the child resulting from that
intercourse.
The female role has, however, been one
of integration,
by the very fact of being the locus of
fertilization and gestation, as well as usually being the
main source of nurture. Semen donation might be
thought, initially, to reflect and indeed exacerbate
that process and sense of separation,
particularly
if
the dominant
view, apparent in this paper, is accepted. Equally, however,
semen donation
might
allow, through the elicitation
of the views of the
donors themselves, a reappraisal of male involvement
and motivation
in reproduction
[23]. Egg donation,
on the other hand, disrupts the picture of integration
and suggests a move is possible towards greater
separation.
Whilst O’Brien acknowledges
that for
men separation
is a form of ‘forced’ freedom
[22, p. 521 it could be argued that for women it would
be a potential source of true freedom: freedom for
example from assumptions
about the equivalence of
the ability to reproduce with the desire (or even need)
to reproduce. What we find instead is that ways of
talking about the two forms of gamete donation, both
independently
and in comparision
with each other,
seek to return each to that earlier framework
of
separation for the male role and integration for the
female role.
In providing at least some empirical data to show
how this return is effected, this paper has attempted
to display the nature of the assumptions on which this
is based. There are many other sources of empirical
data, researchable
by social scientists,
which will
extend our ability to question these assumptions even
further. Papers such as this demonstrate
that though
the analysis of reproduction
in terms of gender is not
new, it is still necessary. In showing how practices
such as egg and semen donation are gendered we have
shown how even the most fundamental
of biological
processes are socially defined and constructed.
Acknowledgemenfs--I
should like to thank Jane Keithley,
Peter Selman, Margaret
Stacey, Robin Williams and two
anonymous
referees for their assistance with this paper.
REFERENCES
Snowden R. and Mitchell G. D. The Arlificial Family,
p. 13. Allen and Unwin, London,
1981.
Downie S. Baby Making, p. 13. Bodley Head, London,
1988.
Cusine D. J. New Reproductive
Techniques, p. 129.
Dartmouth,
Aldershot,
1990.
See Haimes E. Family connections.
University of Newcastle Upon Tyne doctoral
thesis, 1990, for a more
detailed discussion of these interactions.
of Health and Social Security. Report of the
5. Department
Committee
of Inquiry into Human F&tili.&ionand
EmbrvoloPv. (‘The Warnock Report’), Cmnd 9314. Her
Majesty’s_Stationery
Office, London; 1984.
to
6. Elsewhere I have disputed the need for anonymity
provide legal protection
since other provisions
in the
Warnock Report covered this very adequately.
See for
example, Haimes E. Recreating the family? In The New
Reproductive Technologies (Edited by McNeil M. er al.).
Macmillan,
London,
1990.
7. I have suggested elsewhere (see Refs [4] and [6] above)
that the conflation
of semen and egg donation
in the
Warnock Report was part of a process whereby these
procedures
were differentiated
from other procedures
such as surrogacy
according
to a familistic ideology:
‘families-by-donation’
were seen as supporting
this
ideology whereas surrogacy was seen as challenging it.
Artifical Human Insemination:
the report of a Commis8. zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLK
sion appointed by His Grace the Archbishop
of Canterbury.
Society
for the Propagation
of Christian
Knowledge,
1948.
Issues of gender in gamete donation
93
9. Home Office and Scottish Home Department. zyxwvutsrqponmlkjihgfedcbaZYXWVUTSRQPONMLKJIHGF
Report of
17. Out of a potential 17 interviews, (16 members plus
the Departmental Committee on Human Artificial Insem secretary) I was able to conduct 14 interviews and I
ination (‘The Feversham Report’), Cmnd. 1105. Her
corresponded with a 15th person. The interviews were
Majesty’s Stationery Office, London, 1960.
conducted in May and June 1988.
10. Fletcher J. M orals and M edicine. Victor Gollancz,
18. Within the limits of this paper one can only speculate
London, 1955.
on why this range of views was not evident in the
11. American Fertility Society. Ethical considerations of the
Report. Perhaps it was clear to members that a pragnew reproductive
technologies.
Fertility
Sterility
matic approach would be taken towards most issues and
Suppl. 1, 46, 3, 1986.
that therefore explicit disagreements would need to be
12. Glover J. Fertilify and the Family Report on the
reserved for other, perhaps more pressing issues (such as
reproductive technologies to the European Commission
surrogacy and embryology), for which there were dis(‘The Glover Report’). Fourth Estate, London,
senting minority reports. That this question should even
1989.
arise is a testament to the necessity of conducting these
13. Neither report is exceptional in this respect; Walters
interviews rather than treating the Report and the views
reports that 12 out of 15 international reports take a
of the Committee members, as one and the same thing.
similar stance: “Egg donation in conjunction with clini19. Each quotation is a verbatim extract from the tape
cal IVF seems closely analogous to semen donation in
recorded interviews which were all fully transcribed.
connection with artificial insemination by donor.
20. This association has been extended by the risks now
Perhaps in part for this reason 12 of the 15 extended
attached to semen donation of being infected with the
Committee statements found egg donation to be ethiHIV virus.
cally acceptable without qualification”. Walters L.
21. Though the question of sibling egg donors has been
Ethics and the New Reproductive Technologies. Hastfiercely debated in the United Kingdom, both sides of
ings Center Report, Special Suppl. 17, 5, 1987.
the debate rest on the same set of assumptions about the
14. Statens Offentliga Utredningar, Sweden, Barn genom
‘normal family’ which differs little from the image of the
befruktning utanfor kroppen, p. 5, 1985.
family presented here: heterosexual, patriarchal and
IS. Statens Offentliga Utredningar, Sweden. Children connuclear. See for example, Craft I. et al. Voluntary
ceived by artificial insemination, 1983.
Licensing and IVF/ET. The L.uncet 16/5, p. 1148, 1987;
16. The current situation in Great Britain is less clear since
and Editorial The Luncet 16/5, p. 1126, 1987.
the highly influential Interim Licensing Authority now
22. O’Brien, for example, says a Hegelian analysis sees the
recommends that, “egg donors should remain anonyfamily as ‘the sole source and appropriate realm of
mous and for this reason donation for clinical purposes
female ethical being. Female morality, like women
from any known person including close relatives should
themselves, remains particular, and relates only to the
be avoided”: The Fifth Report of the Interim Licensing
individuals in the family, concentrating on biological
Authority for Human In Vitro Fertilization and Embrylife’. O’Brien M. The Poliiics of Reproduction, p. 26.
ology, p. 47, London, U.K., 1990. It is expected that this
Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1981.
issue will be considered under the code of practice to be
23. See, for example, Daniels K. Artificial insemination
published by the Human Fertilization and Embryology
using donor-semen and the issue of secrecy: the views of
Authority, which was established by the Human Fertildonors and recipient couples. Sot. Sci. M ed. 27,
ization and Embryology Act, 1990.
377- 383, 1988.