RST 41.1 (2022) 43–55
http://www.doi.org/10.1558/rst.21437
Religious Studies and Theology (print) ISSN 0892-2922
Religious Studies and Theology (online) ISSN 1747-5414
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of
Particulars: Criticism and Analytic Assessment
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
Sharif University of Technology, Tehran
[email protected]
The problem of God’s knowledge of particulars goes back to the beginnings of classical philosophy, and within the context of Islamic philosophy
and theology, diverse schools have arisen which respond to this problem
in different ways. The scope and depth of God’s knowledge of our world,
which also includes knowledge of human will and human action, is the
subject of Ibn Sina’s account of God’s knowledge of particulars, which we
set out to discuss in this paper followed by Mula Sadra’s main criticisms
of his premises and argumentation, finally providing our assessment of
these two philosophers’ positions.
Introductory remarks
According to a definition which has been historically influential, God is a
being whose non-existence is self-contradictory, and is hence a necessary
existent. Although fundamental challenges have been raised against the
idea of a necessary existent within the mind-independent external world,
it is fair to say that almost all Muslim philosophers affirm such a definition of God. From the perspective of classical Islamic philosophy, God is
a necessary existent whose essence is identical with His existence, in contrast to all other entities for which existence (or non-existence) is predicated upon essence only contingently, which is to say that an explanation
or a cause needs to be provided for the relevant predication. It is worth
Keywords: God’s Knowledge, The Particulars, The Universals, Ibn Sina, Mula
Sadra
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022, Office 415, The Workstation, 15 Paternoster Row, Sheffield, S1 2BX
44
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
observing that in Islamic philosophical literature, such a conception of
God is neither meaningless nor ambiguous. Ibn Sina, for instance, says:
Every being, if considered from the point of view of its essence and without consideration of other things, is found to be such that either existence
necessarily belongs to it in itself or it does not. If existence belongs to it
necessarily, then it is the truth in itself and that whose existence is necessary from itself. This is the Independent Reality… Therefore, every existent either has necessary existence in essence or has possible existence in
essence. (Ibn Sina 2014, 122)
Independent of the problem of God’s knowledge, both Ibn Sina1 and
Mulla Sadra2 developed their own theories of knowledge and perception.
It would be interesting to compare their general epistemologies with
their views on God’s knowledge to determine the internal consistency of
their bodies of thought. Despite the importance of this study, it is beyond
the scope of this paper.3
The problem of God’s knowledge is here taken only to concern God’s
knowledge regarding the physical world, which is to say material beings,
corporeal entities, and particulars in the actual world. Serious questions
may arise concerning God’s knowledge of Himself and how He knows Himself, although this too is not the focus of this paper. Similarly, all questions
regarding if and how God knows the world of intellects, the world of absolute souls, the world of celestial bodies, or the world of unchanging particulars, are excluded here.4 What remains is the actual, physical, and change1. Abū-ʿAlī al-Ḥusayn ibn-ʿAbdallāh Ibn-Sīnā [Avicenna] (ca. 970–1037), the outstanding
philosopher and physician of the Islamic world, known as the father and founder of
Peripatetic Islamic philosophy, who among Muslim philosophers has had the most
influence on western philosophers and theologians. See McGinnis 2010.
2.
Sadr al-Din Muhammad b. Ibrahim b. Yahya Qawami Shirazi [Sadra] (ca. 1571–1636),
arguably the most significant Islamic philosopher after Avicenna, known as Sadr alMuta’allihin (Master of the Theosophists) for his independent but integrated philosophy that combines theology, mysticism, and metaphysics. See Nasr 1972.
3. In his An Introduction to Classical Islamic Philosophy, Oliver Leaman argues that it is
invalid to assume that Ibn Sina’s theory of perception is designed to accommodate
his theory of God’s knowledge (Leaman 2001, 131–132). However, some have tried to
show that there is an inconsistency between these two viewpoints (see Zadyousefi
et al. 2018, 138). I believe, however, that Ibn Sina’s main theory of perception is basically consistent with his interpretation of God’s knowledge of particulars. For his
general theory of perception, see Ibn Sina 1375, vol. 2, 308–327.
4. Therefore, even if Marmura is correct that the terms “particular” and “universal”
are ambiguous in Ibn Sina’s texts, the reference (extension) of the term “particular”
is clear in our current study (Marmura 1962, 300).
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
45
able world, including our free will and actions, which must be considered
as physically engaged with our minds even for those who believe rigidly in
dualism (as did Ibn Sina himself). Nevertheless, a broader meaning of the
term particulars is used in this context, as summarized by Marmura:
Fakhr al-Din al-Razi classifies the particulars under the following
groups:
a. particulars that are neither changing nor are composed of form
and matter, e.g. God and the intellects;
b. particulars that do not change but which are composed of form
and matter, e.g. the celestial bodies;
c. particulars that change but which are not composed of form and
matter, e.g. the generable accidents and forms in the sublunary
world as well as the rational human souls;
d. particulars that are changing and which are composed of form
and matter, e.g. the bodies of the world of generation and corruption.
God, according to al-Razi, knows only group (a) individually. God cannot know group (b) because they are material. He cannot know group (c)
because they are changing and He cannot know group (d) because they
are both material and are changing (Marmura 1962, 305, citing Mabahith
II, 473–476)
In this paper, by particulars we refer to the fourth class cited above,
equivalent to the physical world and entities composed of matter with
the main characteristics of motion and temporality. To be clear, though,
human action within the physical world falls within this class, and hence
is the subject of this problem concerning God’s eternal essence and His
incorporeal and non-temporal knowledge of particulars.
Ibn Sina’s argument for God’s knowledge of particulars
Reconstructing Ibn Sina’s main argument
We reconstruct Ibn Sina’s Argument for God’s knowledge of particulars
as follows:5
1. God knows Himself (His essence).6 (Premise)
5. This is the modified reconstruction of Ibn Sina’s argument according to his main
texts on this subject. See Ibn Sina 2005, 288–290; Ibn Sina 1375, vol. 3, 298–308.
6. It is important to note that the word “essence” does not here refer to the so-called
“quiddity,” which in Islamic philosophical literature carries a meaning distinct from
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
46
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
2. God’s essence is neither changing nor changeable. (Premise)
3. God’s essence is one and simple. (Premise)
4. God’s knowledge is neither changing nor changeable. (Premise; 2
and 3)
5. The multiplicity of eternal beings is impossible. (Premise)
6. God’s essence is the cause of all beings. (Premise)
7. Knowledge (perception) requires intelligible objects known by
the knower. (Premise)
8. Knowing the cause implies knowing the effect. (Premise)
9. God’s knowledge of His essence requires His knowledge of all
beings. (1, 6 and 8)
10. God knows all particulars from eternity. (2 and 9)
11. Either God knows particulars by themselves or God knows particulars by universals7 from eternity. (7 and 10)
12. God cannot know particulars from eternity by themselves. (4 and 11)
13. God knows particulars from eternity by universals. (11 and 12)
14. The universals are either separate entities or inseparable from
God’s essence. (13 and Law of Excluded Middle)
15. Universals cannot be separate entities. (14 and 5)
16. Universals are inseparable from God’s essence. (14 and 15)
17. The inseparable universals are either parts of God’s essence
or consequential concomitants of His essence. (16 and Law of
Excluded Middle)
18. The universals cannot be parts of God’s essence. (17 and 3)
19. The universals are consequential concomitants of God’s essence.
(17 and 18)
the concept of “being”. Essence here is equivalent to being and existence, and not to
quiddity. Nevertheless, both Ibn Sina and Sadra are part of a major trend among
Islamic philosophers who believe in the identity of God’s quiddity and His being.
7. By universals, Ibn Sina means conceptual forms of particulars, as will be explained
below. He believes that a particular (juz’iyy ، )الجزئیis perceived by God in a universal way (‘ala nahwin kulliyy) علی نحو کلیIbn Sina uses the terms universals ) (الکلیاتor
universal forms) ) الصور الکلیةto explain how God would apprehend the particulars
) (الجزئیاتor changeables ) (المتغیراتor particular things ) (االمور الجزئیةor individual
things) (االمور الشخصیة, the synonymous words that have been used interchangeably
in Ibn Sina’s literature as far as God’s knowledge on particulars are concerned.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
47
20. God knows particulars by the universals that are consequential
concomitants of His essence. (Conclusion)
Premises of the argument
Propositions 1 to 7 appear in the argument as premises, and each is the
subject of extensive discussion in Ibn Sina’s metaphysics. Here we mention only a few points regarding these premises; a full consideration of
them would warrant separate papers.
First is Ibn Sina’s proof of why God knows Himself as sketched, for
instance, in the extract below:
The necessary existence is pure intellect because He is an essence dissociated from matter in every aspect… Hence, that which is free of matter and
its attachments and is realized through existence separate from matter is
an intelligible for itself. Its essence is hence at once intellect, intellectual
apprehender and intelligible. (not that there are multiple things here.
(Ibn Sina 2005, 285)
Indeed, since God is an ultimate and first cause of all beings,8 His knowledge of Himself necessitates his knowledge of all beings. It is thus clear
that Ibn Sina’s conclusion concerning God’s omniscience is not simply a
presupposition or a hypothesis drawn from Islamic culture.9
Second, in his major books, Ibn Sina tries to prove that God possesses
the main characteristics usually ascribed to Him: eternality, uniqueness,
simplicity, non-changeability, and non-corporeality. But Ibn Sina’s main
contribution centers on his claim that God’s essence and all His attributes
are not only identical but also share unique conceptions and meanings,10
an idea that provoked later philosophers to criticize him severely.11
This theory of the uniqueness of His essence and His attributes entails
that God’s knowledge is identical with God’s essence, specifically as far as
the non-changeability and non-corporality of God’s essence is concerned.
8. “Chapter 8. Remark: if There is a First Cause, it Must Be an Efficient Cause for Everything Else That Exists (18). Thus, if there is a first cause, it is a cause of every existence
and of the cause of the reality of every concrete existence.” (Ibn Sina 2014, 122).
9. Consequently, these texts must be interpreted in a way that is consistent with his
philosophical argument for God’s omniscience: “No individual object escapes His
knowledge and not even the weight of an atom in the heavens and the earth” or
“Nothing from existents escapes His knowledge.” (Ibn Sina 1984f, 123, quoted from
Zadyousefi 2019).
10. See Ibn Sina 1363, 21; Ibn Sina 1364, 249; Ibn Sina 1404, 367.
11. See for instance Sadra’s criticism according to which God’s oneness and His attributes are not identical conceptually, although they are all one in extension (Sadra
1410, vol. 6, 145).
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
48
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
Third, the absolute oneness of God and His attributes requires the
impossibility of the multiplicity of eternal entities. This is a substantial
principle that Ibn Sina uses to refute the idea that God’s disparate intelligibles might be eternal entities.
Fourth, Ibn Sina’s theory of knowledge presupposes that the perceiver
can be identified distinct from the perceived as well as the perception.
That is why he attacks Porphyry for his theory of unification.12
The structure of the argument
Step (9) is obviously the result of (1) and (6). Since God knows His essence,
and his essence is the cause of all beings, and given the principle of causality that the effect is the manifestation of the cause as such, God knows
all beings including particulars. Moreover, God’s knowledge is unchangeable since he is simple, and consequently step (10) follows, that God
should have known all particulars from eternity. The rest of argument is
designed to explain how God, within the confines of this definition, could
have known particulars from eternity. The quotation below gives a clear
expression of (9) and (10):
Because He is the principle of all existence, He apprehends intellectually
from His essence that of which He is a principle. He is the principle of
the existents that are complete in their concrete individual existence and
of the generable and corruptible existents—first in [terms of] their species and, through the mediation of these, in [terms of] their individual
instances. (Ibn Sina 2005, 287)
Step (11) is crucial as far as it refers to Ibn Sina’s theory of perception
according to which the perceived entities should be separate from the
perceiver and the perception. If it is accepted that the unification hypothesis is both meaningless and false (7),13 it follows that the particulars are
either the objects of God’s eternal knowledge (10) by themselves, or they
are known via their conceptual forms and universals, which is precisely
the two-fold logical classification which is currently at issue.
12. “Chapter 10. Anecdote: Concerning Porphyry’s “Bad ideas” on the intellect and intelligibles. To them belonged a man known as Porphyry. He composed a book on the
intellect and the intelligible. This book is praised by the Peripatetics, yet it is full of
bad ideas. They themselves know that they do not understand it, nor does Porphyry
himself [understand it either]. A man of his time contradicted him, and he contradicted that contradictor with what is more inferior than [the arguments of] the former.” (Ibn Sina 2014, 171).
13. Our domain of discussion is not God’s self-knowledge, for which indeed there would
seem to be an identity comprising perceiver, perceived, and perception.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
49
Step (12), derived from (4) and (11), is also explained further within Ibn
Sina’s texts:
It is not possible that the Necessary Existent would intellectually apprehend things from the things [themselves]. For then either His essence
would be rendered subsistent by what He intellectually apprehends and,
hence, its being rendered subsistent would be through things, or it would
accidentally occur to it to intellectually apprehend, in which case [the
essence] would not be a necessary existent in every respect and this is
impossible. [Moreover,] He would [be such that], if it were not for external
matters, He would not be of a state [of His own] and would have a state
that is not necessitated by His essence but by another, and thus another
would have an effect on Him. The principles previously [established]
refute this and its like. (Ibn Sina 2005, 287)
Ibn Sina’s response to the question of how an object could be known in
two manners is as follows:
It is permissible that in some manner the intelligible forms are acquired
from external forms as, for example, the form of the sky is acquired from
the sky. It is also permissible that the form first proceeds to the intellective power and then exists externally, as when you intellect a figure and
then you make it exist. It must be the case that whose existence is necessary intellects the whole in the second manner. (Ibn Sina 2014, 172)
Given (11) and (12), (13) means that if an unchanging and eternal God
knows the particulars not by themselves, but due to the properties of time
and change that are inseparable from the particulars, then God knows
them by the conceptual framework and universals from eternity. Via an
analogy, Ibn Sina provides an explanation of how knowledge of universals
would transfer over to knowledge of the particulars themselves.
Steps (14), (15) and (16) aim to rule out a conception of universals as
eternal but separate entities. Ibn Sina believes that universals that were
separate from God’s essence would be merely Platonic forms, which in
his metaphysics are impossible. Thus the universals must be inseparable
from God’s essence.
Steps (17), (18) and (19) determine how the universals are attached to
God, where the only two options are that they are parts of God’s essence,
or they are consequential concomitants of His essence. Since the former
contradicts the simplicity, uniqueness, and independence of the necessary being the only remaining basis for God’s knowledge is through the
universals that are consequential concomitants of His essence:
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
50
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
(20) God knows particulars by the universals that are consequential
concomitants of His essence. (Conclusion)
From universals to particulars
The following three texts set out how Ibn Sina understands the universal
nature of knowledge of particulars:
He would thus apprehend particular things inasmuch as they are universal—I mean, inasmuch as they have attributes. If these [attributes] become
specified individually in [the particulars], [this takes place] in relation to
an individuated time or an individuated circumstance. If this circumstance is also [simply] apprehended with its attributes, it will be in the
same positions [the particulars]. But, inasmuch as [these attributes] would
depend on principles where the species of each is [confined] to its individual [instance], they are attributed to individual things.
(Ibn Sina 2005, 288)
Particular things may be known as universal things are known, i.e., inasmuch as they are necessitated by their causes, as they are attributed to a
principle whose species is individuated in its particulars. This is exemplified by the particular eclipse; for the occurrence of such an eclipse may
be known due to the availability of its particular causes, the intellect’s
complete knowledge of these causes, and their being known as universals are known. This is other than the temporal particular realization that
judges that such an eclipse occurs now, that it occurred before, or that it
will occur later (Ibn Sina 2014, 174).14
Therefore, the knowledge that whose existence is necessary has of particular things must not be temporal knowledge such that it includes the
present, the past, and the future in order that change of an attribute of
its essence would occur. Rather, His knowledge of particular things must
be in a manner holy and above duration and time. He must know everything because everything is a necessary consequence of Him—whether
through an intermediary or without an intermediary. His destiny, which
is the detailing of his first determination, leads in a necessary manner to
[the existence of] everything individually, since, as you have learned, that
which is not necessitated is not (Ibn Sina 2014, 177).15
To summarize, particulars are known in two ways: first, via sensation and imagination, according to which particulars are perceived in a
14. In his masterful commentary on Ibn Sina’s Isharat, Khaje Nasir-al-din Tosi clarifies
the two above methods (see Ibn Sina 1375, 307–315).
15. Ibn Sina 1375, 315–320.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
51
way which depends on time and motion, and hence such knowledge is
restricted to the unending flux of corporeal entities; and second, via universals, where Ibn Sina states that if one knows the causes and all the
chains of causes and laws beyond the limitations of time and motion, one
necessarily knows the particulars through the causes and origins without
any reference to time whether past, present, or future. His use of the analogy of the solar eclipse is designed to indicate how knowledge of laws and
causes in a general and universal way could issue in knowledge of a particular, and that our ability to make specific reference to that particular
would not be via locating the event in its time but rather via the chains
of antecedents. This interpretation requires us to recognize a distinction between actualizing knowledge and actualized knowledge. While the
knowledge in the former case determines the particulars, the knowledge
in the latter case is acquired through our sensory or imaginative faculties
and is affected by spatial-temporal events in our actual world.
Sadra’s criticisms of Ibn Sina’s argument
Although Sadra rejected a number of objections to Ibn Sina’s theory of
God’s knowledge, he himself strongly criticized Ibn Sina’s argument.16
Three main objections advanced by Sadra in his masterpiece Asfar are
worth mentioning here. We discuss the objections below and analyze
them in the fourth part of this paper.
Three kinds of consequential concomitants of entities must be distinguished: consequential concomitants of the essence, i.e., quiddity (for
instance the concept of the contingency of the quiddity of human being);
consequential concomitants of mental existence (for instance the concept
of a natural kind to the essence of the human being); and consequential
concomitants of external existence (for instance the property of hotness to
the external fire). God lacks essence as opposed to existence, and thus the
first does not apply to Him; nor could God have consequential concomitants of mental existence as far as such concomitants apply only as far as
entities are subject to determinate-determinable relations, and it is clear
that God is not subject to such relations. What remains is consequential
concomitants of external existence, but this requires the intelligibles to
exist externally and be perceived, which contradicts the main hypothesis
that there are conceptual forms and universals that are objects of God’s
knowledge.
16. Sadra stated that all four main objections raised by Khaje Nasir-din Tosi are weak
and defended Ibn Sina against these and other criticisms (Sadra 1410, vol. 6, 209).
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
52
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
Here is an analytic reconstruction of the above objection:
3.1.1. God knows particulars by the universals (conceptual forms).
3.1.2. Universals are God’s consequential concomitant.
3.1.3. God’s consequential concomitants are either with respect to
His quiddity or His existence.
3.1.4. God’s quiddity is identical with God’s existence.
3.1.5. God’s consequential concomitant is either with respect to His
mental existence or His external existence.
3.1.6. God’s consequential concomitant cannot be with respect to
His mental existence.
3.1.7. God’s consequential concomitant is to His external existence.
3.1.8. Universals are externally (not mentally or conceptually)
existent.
Therefore, if (3.1.8) is correct, (3.1.1) is false.
Sadra contends that although knowing the cause requires the effect to
be known, this must be interpreted according to the principle of causality and the existential relation of the cause and the effect. Indeed, God’s
knowledge of His essence—which is no more than His absolute being—
requires the effect, i.e., the caused beings, to be conceived precisely as
they are caused externally, which is to say neither conceptually nor mentally. The reason for this revolves around the very demanding interpretation of the causality at work here, according to which God is the cause
of all beings as they are in the external and actual world, and hence they
must (as they are in the actual world) be the object of God’s knowledge.
We reconstruct the above objection as follows:
3.2.1. God is the cause of all beings, including the particulars.
3.2.2. God’s knowledge of His essence requires the caused beings to
be known as they are externally existent.
3.2.3. God knows the particulars by their external existences.
3.2.4. God does not know the particulars via their concepts or via
universals.
As stated before, the significant theme here is Sadra’s emphasis on the
existential relatedness between cause and effect, which entails that the
particulars are the external effect of the ultimate cause. The consequence
of this is that we must rule out the idea that universals are to be consid-
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
53
ered as the objects of God’s knowledge.
Sadra’s third objection to Ibn Sina’s theory appeals to the so-called
principle of the “contingency of the highest.”17 According to this principle, in the pyramid of existence and in the vertical regress of existents,
the highest degrees of the contingent existents are prior to and closer
to coming into existence than the less perfect and weaker ones, i.e., the
most exalted beings take precedence in existence. That is why the external substances are prior in existence to the mental existences and universals. Consequently, mental existents, concepts and universals are successive upon the actual substances, and since these intelligible objects are
God’s properties or accidents and not the actual substances, they cannot
be regarded as the beings that are prior to the actual substances.
Conclusion: Final assessment
To conclude, we briefly lay out our final assessment of the three criticisms to see if they are fatal to Ibn Sina’s arguments.
Re. 3.1. It seems that in attacking Ibn Sina’s argument, the conclusion
which Sadra thinks is so damaging is already a part of the main argument. In other words, Ibn Sina agrees with Sadra that the particulars
must be perceived by God as His externally consequential concomitants.
Nevertheless, while particulars cannot be considered as the objects of
God’s knowledge as far as they are corporeal and changing, God can know
them via the universal and conceptual forms. It is thus clear that having
knowledge of particulars qua the external consequential concomitants of
God is not restricted to having knowledge of the particulars qua corporeal
particulars. Therefore, If God knows particulars through universals that
are themselves God’s consequential concomitants, then Sadra’s objection
totally collapses. Furthermore, Ibn Sina would say that 3.1.8 is consistent
with 3.1.1, and indeed would insist 3.1.8 is in complete compliance with 18
in the main argument. To sum up, then, Sadra’s first objection fails.
Re. 3.2. The second objection is directed to criticizing Ibn Sina’s approach
to the principle of causality. That God is the cause of all beings does not
necessitate that the effects exist from eternity. To consider God as the
omniscient first and ultimate cause, according to Ibn Sina, requires that we
consider Him as the first cause in the vertical chains of causes and effects.
Furthermore, inasmuch as the particulars are not entitled to be perceived
as corporeal and changing, it remains that God must have known them via
universals, otherwise God is rendered non-omniscient. Therefore 3.2.3 is
17. See Sadra 1410, vol. 7, 244–257.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
54
Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra on God’s Knowledge of Particulars
false, due to its inconsistency with the simplicity, non-corporeality, and
non-temporality of God. It is also obvious that if the particulars lack the
characteristics of time and change, they would be the objects of God’s
knowledge without any reservation; the best instance of this is the world
of intellects, which are both God’s concomitants and necessary consequential effects. Thus, we think, the second objection fails too.
Re. 3.3. It is intriguing that Ibn Sina would rather casually affirm the
principle of the “contingency of the highest” in defense of his theory of
God’s knowledge of particulars. Recall that the principle states that the
more exalted the being, the greater priority it takes with respect to existence. This perfectly satisfies a theory of universals as abstract entities
and consequential upon God’s essence, and undoubtedly these entities
are closer to becoming existent than corporeal entities that are restricted
to being in time and space. Sadra in fact misuses the term substance here,
since the universals as God’s concomitants are prior to all other actual
beings including both substances or accidents, irrespective of whether
they are mental or external. Accordingly, the third objection is also weak.
Acknowledgments
This research and paper are supported by Research Program Grant at
Sharif University of Technology.
References
Avicenna [Ibn Sina] and S. C. Inati. 2014. Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics: An Analysis and Annotated Translation. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Avicenna, [Ibn Sina] and M. E. Marmura. 2005. The Metaphysics of The Healing:
A parallel English-Arabic text, al-Ilahīyāt min al-Shifaʾ. Provo, UT: Brigham
Young University Press.
Leaman, O. 2001. An Introduction to Classical Islamic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139164719
Marmura, M. 1962. “Some Aspects of Avicenna’s Theory of God’s Knowledge of
Particulars.” Journal of the American Oriental Society, 823: 299–312. https://doi.
org/10.2307/597641
McGinnis, Jon. 2010. Avicenna. Great Medieval Thinkers series. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Nasr, Seyed Hossein 1972. “Mulla Sadra and the Doctrine of the Unity of Being.”
Philosophical Forum 4: 153–161.
Nasr, Seyed Hossein. 1977. Sadr al-Din Shirazi and His Trancendent Theosophy, Background, Life and Works. Tehran: Institute for Humanities and Cultural Studies.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022
55
Seyed Hassan Hosseini and Alireza Kazemi
Zadyousefi, A. 2019. “Does God Know that the Flower in My Hand Is Red? Avicenna
and the Problem of God’s Perceptual Knowledge.” SOPHIA 2019. https://doi.
org/10.1007/s11841-019-0730-9
ابن سینا [ .)1363 ( ]Ibn Sinaالمبدا و المعاد ،زير نظر:محقق ،مهدی – مصحح :نورانی،
عبدهللا ،تهران ،موسسه مطالعات اسالمی دانشگاه مک گیل ،با همگاری دانشگاه تهران.
ابن سینا [ .) 1364 ( ]Ibn Sinaالنجاة ،چاپ دوم ،تهران ،انتشارات مرتضوی.
ابن سینا [ .)1375( ]Ibn Sinaاالشارات و التنبیهات ،نشرالبالغة ،قم ،المجلد األول و المجلد
الثاني ،مع الشرح للمحقق نصیر الدین الطوسی.
ابن سینا [.)1404( ]Ibn Sinaالشفاء( الهیات) قم ،تصحيح سعيد زائد -األب قنواتى ،مکتبة آیت
هللا مرعشی نجفی.
صدر الدین الشیرازی [ .) 1410( ]Sadraالحکمة المتعالیة فی االسفار االربعة ،المجلد الثالث و
المجلد السادس و المجلد السابع ،الطبعة الرابعة ،دارإحیا التراث العربي ،بیروت ،لبنان.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2022