WHY WE NEED NEEDS-BASED JUSTIFICATIONS
OF HUMAN RIGHTS
RITA FLOYD
Charles R. Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2009), 256 pp., £16.99/$29.95 cloth.
James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008),
360 pp., £17.99/$29.95 paper.
Beth A. Simmons, Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic
Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 468 pp., £20.99/$29.99
paper.
The topic of human rights is easily among the most popular research areas
in political science and political theory. Despite the sheer volume of research
produced on this issue, there still exists plenty of disagreement on what human
rights are and on their foundations. Alone the ostensibly simple claim that we
have human rights in virtue of being humans is complicated by the fact that
people disagree on what it means to be human. For example, some hold that
definitive of human beings is their capacity for acting morally (Hart 1984;
Donnelly 2003: 14), for others it is their ability to socialise and cooperate with
others (Freeden 1990; Doyal and Gough 1991), and one thinker even claims
that it is human rights themselves that make humans human (Booth 2007).
These disagreements, however, do not change the fact that human rights exist
in practice. And it is for this reason that some scholars explicitly reject the
idea that human rights have to be founded on intellectual consensus (Dembour
2010: 6) Yet other human rights scholars go further than this still, and reject
the whole idea of grounding human rights in human nature, suggesting instead
that ‘human rights are political values that liberal societies choose to adopt’
(Dembour 2010: 3). And yet a third group argues that we have human rights only
Journal of International Political Theory, 7(1) 2011, 103–115
DOI: 10.3366/jipt.2011.0008
© Edinburgh University Press 2011
www.eupjournals.com/jipt
103
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
because we talk about them, that is to say, human rights are discursive constructs
(Dembour 2010: 4).
I want to argue in this review essay that a particular form of justification
for human rights – what I, following David Miller (2007) call needs-based
justifications – enable the grounding of human rights in something that is both
objectively and universally valuable, and that can therefore serve as a potentially
consensual basis for enforcing human rights. I make my case by examining
three recent books on human rights by some of the foremost thinkers on this
issue. Although none of the three explicitly draws on human needs, I argue that
each of them would have benefited from recourse to needs-based justifications
of human rights. To strengthen my case, I have deliberately chosen three very
different approaches to the study of human rights, namely James Griffin’s
personhood approach, Beth Simmons’ empirical approach and Charles Beitz’s
practical approach.1 Each of these scholars comes to the subject of human rights
with different intentions and needs. Much simplified, Griffin is interested in
philosophically grounding human rights and in devising a definitive list of what
should and should not be a human right. Simmons is interested in questions
of compliance; specifically she examines the difference international human
rights treaties make to the lives of people. While finally, Beitz is concerned with
questions of intervention, and he seeks to ground human rights in how they are
practiced in contemporary international relations.
The argument is structured as follows. I begin by examining the personhood,
the empirical, and the practical approaches in turn, ending each section
by pointing to their respective shortcomings. I then introduce needs-based
justifications of human rights and I go on to show how a needs-based justification
remedies the shortcomings of each of the three approaches. My conclusion is
that although human rights and human needs are distinct concepts, they are
complimentary and human rights research as a whole would benefit from paying
attention to human needs.
Three Approaches to Human Rights
The Personhood Approach
Griffin holds that although human rights are now ubiquitous, there is still
insufficient clarity regarding what they are. As a philosopher Griffin considers it
his task, indeed his duty, to render the ‘indeterminate’ and nearly ‘criterionless’
concept of human rights determinate (1–19, 203, 210). His starting point is the
natural law tradition. He believes that in spite of today’s manifestation of human
rights in international law, ‘the idea is still that of a right we have simply in virtue
of being human, with no further explanation of what ‘human’ means here’ (13).
Griffin aims to render human rights determinate by fleshing out what it means
to be human. To this end he develops what he calls the personhood approach
104
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
to human rights. This approach starts from the idea that ‘human life is different
from that of other animals’ because humans alone are purposeful agents that
choose, assess and act in a way ‘to make what we see as a good life for ourselves’
(32). Contra utilitarians he contends that human standing is valued by many
much more than is happiness. Human rights are a testimony to this, as they are
protections of our human standing (personhood) as purposeful and normative
agents. Grounding human rights in personhood does not mean that anything that
contributes to human flourishing or the good life is a human right, but merely that
which is needed for human standing. Griffin identifies three high-level human
rights, each of which contains within it a large and not fully developed list of
lower level human rights. The three principal human rights are autonomy, liberty
and minimum provision. ‘Autonomy is self-legislation, deciding one’s own goals
in life, choosing one’s own conception of a worthwhile life; liberty is being free
to pursue that conception’ (243, emphases added); and minimum provision refers
to life and certain supporting goods necessary for being both autonomous and
free.
Personhood alone, however, does not render human rights sufficiently
determinate; human rights are determinate only when they take account of
practicalities. Practicalities include availability of resources in a given society,
developments of technology and science, and, in contrast to a number of other
philosophers, also limitations posed by human nature. ‘Moral deliberation must
take place largely on the common-sense level at which it occurs in ordinary
life’ (75). Griffin maintains, for example, that there are clear limits to the extent
to which humans would sacrifice themselves to save other people, or to which
they would, and indeed should, sacrifice their own child in order to save other
people’s children. In short, if human rights claims are to have any bearing in
practice, they simply cannot be too demanding on individual persons. This is
especially important given that Griffin holds that ‘A human right is a claim of all
human agents against all other human agents’ (177).
While Griffin’s idea of what it means to be human is internally consistent,
his account of rights is not. For example, at one point Griffin laments that
‘too often the form of argument for a human right, or a right of any kind is
to identify a value . . . and then conclude that there is a right that protects it.
But that is a blatant non sequitur’ (225). The problem is that Griffin can be
accused of the very same mistake. Thus he argues: ‘my account . . . grounds
human rights . . . directly in a central range of substantive values, the values of
personhood’ and ‘personhood [in turn] gives us a right to security of person’
(34, 37). With that, as Joseph Raz rightly observes, Griffin follows others in the
natural law tradition, by failing ‘to show that value establishes rights’. His logic
is the same as saying ‘if the love of my children is the most important thing to
me then I have a right to it’ (Raz 2010: 325).
The inability to ground rights is not the only shortcoming of Griffin’s
approach; another is their relation to their actual practice. Griffin argues, for
105
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
instance, that there are two general ways for philosophers to supply an account
of human rights. The first is top-down whereby ‘one starts with an overarching
principle, or principles, or an authoritative decision procedure . . . from which
human rights can be derived’ (29). The second is bottom-up, whereby ‘one starts
with human rights as used in our actual social life by politicians, lawyers, social
campaigners, as well as theorists of various sorts, and then sees what higher
principles one must resort to in order to explain their moral weight’ (29). Griffin
claims that his is a bottom-up approach, because ‘we need some understanding
of what human rights are independent of the principle or principles from which
they are said to be derivable, and their social use is the most likely source’ (29).
Yet the only thing in Griffin’s approach that has some bearing on reality is the
requirement of practicalities for human rights claims. Although this requirement
does a useful job in limiting human rights, practicalities alone do not make
for a bottom-up approach. The three principal human rights are superimposed
by Griffin as being valuable; they bear no resemblance to how human rights
are practiced, but rather are a collection of abstract principles whereby human
rights are closely connected to a particular conception of the good life. (cf.
Raz 2010: 324; Beitz 2009: 7 fn. 12, 59–68). In evidence of my claim that the
personhood approach is removed from the practice of human rights, consider
further here that under this approach human rights no longer apply to all human
beings but rather to normative agents only. While this does not mean that nonagents are outside of morality (after all there are other moral concepts than rights
alone, for example, justice, fairness and well-being), the suggested notion does
directly contradict the practice of human rights. Thus, one of the key groups
of non-agents indentified by Griffin are children, despite the fact that existing
human rights treaties – the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC) and the
Optional Protocol Relating to Children in Armed Conflict (OPCAC) – clearly
specify children as rights bearers, plus there is compelling evidence that both
treaties have had positive consequences for the lives of children (Simmons 2009:
307–48).
The Empirical Approach
Human rights treaties are Beth Simmons’ subject in Mobilizing for Human
Rights. In contrast to, for example, realist International Relations theorists,
who hold that ‘treaties have little purchase over government behaviour because
they are not likely to be meaningfully enforced’, she argues that the real
effect of treaties can only be known if we contemplate the domestic effects
of international treaties (116). The assumptions of realists are questionable,
at the least, simply because if there were no costs attached to treaties, why
is it that states often take long periods of time before they ratify a particular
treaty? Hence, Simmons poses the question: ‘Why do governments voluntarily
106
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
hand over the figurative “whips” . . . that then might be used by individuals,
groups, courts, and peers to criticise their own politics and practices?’ (58).
By way of an answer she proposes that with regards to treaty ratification
the behaviour of governments falls into one of three categories: 1) sincere
ratifiers, ‘those that value the content of the treaty and anticipate compliance’;
2) false negatives, ‘those that may be committed in principle but nonetheless
fail to ratify’; 3) strategic ratifiers, those that ratify the treaty for reasons
ulterior to their regard for the content of the treaty. Such alternative reasons
could be peer pressure (strongest when other countries in the region have
ratified the treaty), short-term benefits such as good press, and/or an improved
image at home and abroad. In a further step she proposes that ratification
is rationally expressive, meaning that it reflects a ‘government’s preferences
and practices, subject to the potential net costs that ratification is expected to
involve’ (64, emphasis added). The latter provides valuable insights into what
types of government (democratic, autocratic, and so on) are most likely to
behave in which of the three ways discussed above. In brief, she finds that
although Western democracies are the natural allies of human rights and most
likely to be sincere ratifiers, high legal integration costs (for example, those
stemming from the nature of the legal system) can result in non-ratification (false
negatives). Strategic ratification, in turn, is almost exclusively the behaviour
of non-democracies, who are not as accountable to their people as democratic
leaders.
Whatever the reason for ratification, the important point is that ratification
is not costless. Not only do treaties hold within them agenda-setting potential
for executives, but also ‘[t]hey can become powerful instruments in the
hands of rights claimants to hold governments to their promised behaviour’
(111). Simmons suggests two ways in which this can happen: 1) litigation
in that individuals and groups can and increasingly do use courts and treaty
commitments to hold government’s accountable; 2) mobilisation in which
individuals and groups of people organise in support of the established rights
(NGOs in particular are a good example). Mobilisation is easily the more
interesting strategy because unlike litigation, whose success depends on the
prior existence of structural means (such as the physical existence of courts),
the success of mobilisation primarily depends on the probability of succeeding
with a given demand in a given society. The latter has important consequences
for the types of regime in which mobilisation is highest. Simmons demonstrates,
for instance, that rights mobilisation is low in autocracies, because people tend to
be afraid of the long term consequences. It is also low in stable democracies, as
here human rights are mostly satisfied by existing legislation, and there is little
of added value to be gained from mobilisation. Mobilisation is highest though in
partially democratic transition countries. Here ‘individuals have both the motive
and the means realistically to press their governments to take international
human rights treaties seriously’ (153).
107
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
Simmons substantiates these findings through the use of comprehensive
statistical analysis. She suggests that her finding – that all six major human
rights treaties2 have empowered those in transition countries to turn their lives
around for the better by holding their own governments accountable for their
human rights record – brings with it the important policy advice that human
rights treaties are a more powerful tool for improving lives than humanitarian
intervention, economic sanctions and even untailored development programmes.
Simmons’ policy advice is, however, unnecessarily weakened because it is not
self-evident why human rights would unequivocally improve the world, let alone
compare favourably with other ideals. To make this argument convincing I will
suggest below Simmons would have had to show what well-being is and how
human rights relate to well-being.
The Practical Approach
Charles Beitz’s starting point in the development of his practical approach to
human rights is the idea that a theory of human rights must take account of
human rights as an ‘emergent political practice’ (xii). He believes that we can
get at the meaning of human rights only if we look at the function they fulfil
in global political life. Beitz holds that the function of human rights can only
be understood within the context of international society. Hence, Beitz adopts
a position similar to that which International Relations English School theorists
have been claiming for some time (see, for example, Donnelly 1998: 21; Dunne
2001: 76; Buzan 2004: 29; Hurrell 2007: 143). Beitz argues that human rights set
limits to states’ sovereignty. ‘Human rights are requirements whose object is to
protect urgent individual interests against certain predictable dangers (“standard
threats”) to which they are vulnerable under typical circumstances of life in
a modern world order composed of states’ (109). The maintenance of human
rights is in the first instance the responsibility of states. If a government violates
human rights by failing to uphold them, they become matters of international
concern. Importantly, however, in Beitz’s functional model outside agents do
not have conclusory reasons to act on human rights violations but merely pro
tanto reasons, which means that outside agents do not have a categorical duty to
act on human rights failures in other countries.
Once he has worked out the function of human rights as well as the nature
of the corresponding duty, Beitz moves on to the content of human rights.
He argues that in order for something to count as a human right it must
satisfy three conditions: 1) the interests it seeks to protect are ‘intersubjectively
recognizable as important or urgent’; 2) ‘that it would be advantageous to protect
the underlying interest by means of legal or policy instruments available to the
state’ (139); and 3) it must be shown that the issue or area of state failure is a
suitable object for international concern.
108
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
Especially when compared to Griffin’s tightly argued framework, Beitz’s
proposal seems somewhat vague. Not only are we left without a list of concrete
human rights, but also when he comes to define ‘urgent individual interests’ – a
key element in his definition of human rights – he maintains that ‘an urgent
interest is not necessarily an interest possessed by everyone or desired by
everyone’ (110). Similarly he insists that human rights are a social phenomenon
and that ‘it is not likely that the members of the discursive community that
sustains the practice will be unanimous about its salient elements’ (106). He
insists on these components because he wants to be able to theoretically capture
the evolving and oftentimes contradictory practice of human rights. Above all
else he does not want to superimpose an arbitrary normative standard that human
rights should protect, nor is he interested in identifying a moral minimum that
everyone can agree too.
As Miller has argued such a practical approach to human rights is initially
very appealing because ‘it tells us to put aside all the worries about the allegedly
sectarian character of human rights. Since human rights can be shown to
work, in the sense that they form the basis for an ever-growing international
practice . . . why worry too much about their philosophical foundations?’ (Miller
2007: 69). The problem is, as Miller further argues, that this approach works only
‘if the practice really is in good order, in the sense of there being a widespread,
unforced agreement to implement a set of human rights’ (2007: 170). This is
not the case. Not only does the practice of human rights (often) differ from
what international law prescribes, but also and as Simmons shows, international
treaties are not unanimously endorsed and as such cannot authoritatively inform
a theory of human rights that holds for everyone, everywhere and at all times. If,
in turn, we were to take the practice itself as authoritative then we are potentially
in even deeper trouble. And so, while Beitz’s pro tanto reasons clause might
capture what goes on in practice, it effectively allows states to walk away from
human rights obligations altogether.
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights and the Three Approaches
In the following I will argue that these problems in Beitz’s approach could be
solved by focusing on a needs-based justification for human rights. Interestingly,
and although Beitz does not acknowledge it, his practical approach relies
precisely on this universally applicable justification for human rights. That
Beitz draws on needs-based justifications for human rights is evident from his
discussion of three different cases: anti-poverty rights (rights to subsistence),
political rights (the right to democracy), and human rights for women. Before I
will discuss each of these three in turn, however, let me first discuss what I mean
by needs-based justifications of human rights.
109
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
The use of human needs as the basis of rights originates from within
development studies and development economics, where they serve as an
important marker for poverty reduction and human development. Ever since
the launch of Amartya Sen’s influential capability approach it is now generally
accepted that poverty is a multidimensional concept that cannot be measured
by income generation alone. Instead, poverty is the ‘deprivation of basic
capabilities . . . reflected in premature mortality, significant undernourishment
(especially in children), persistent morbidity, widespread illiteracy and other
failures’ (Sen 1999: 20). In short, poverty is tantamount to human ill-being.
Objective human well-being, in turn, is distinct from a person’s subjective
level of ‘happiness’ or ‘life satisfaction’ as popularised by psychologists. In
Sen’s terminology objective human well-being refers to a person’s freedom
(capabilities) that leave them in a position to achieve ‘valuable beings and
doings’ (functionings) (Alkire 2002: 2).
Human needs theorists spell out the nature of these capabilities. Some needs
theorists define human needs negatively as what is needed to avoid serious
harm, while others define human needs positively and focus on what is needed
for humans to flourish or achieve objective human well-being. Given that all
human beings have the same capacity for being harmed or to flourish, needs are
objectively valuable, yet the exact lists of human needs offered by human needs
theorists differs slightely due to varying conceptions of harm and flourishing. As
an example of how harm has been conceptualised by needs theorists consider
Doyal and Gough’s approach, which argues that a person is harmed when their
pursuit of goals that are deemed of value to them is inhibited, provided of
course that those pursuits and goals do not harm anyone else (Doyal and Gough
1991: 50). For Miller, in turn, ‘a person is harmed when she is unable to live a
minimally decent life in the society to which she belongs’ (Miller 2007: 181).
Despite these differences needs refer almost always to basic needs only and
certainly never to a person’s wants.
The problem with human needs is that they are unable to produce duties in
others, which is to say they are not easily motivated. To circumvent this problem
many human needs theorists connect human needs to human rights (Gasper
2007: 51–2). The appeal of human needs is that they can simultaneously ground
human rights in universally and objectively valuable facts while also setting
limits to the concept. Thus something qualifies as a human right only if it can be
shown that having that right fulfils human needs (Miller 2007: 179). Conceived
in this way then human rights protect right-holders from being harmed.
Let me now turn to Beitz’s three hard cases of human rights and how they
implicitly rely on human needs. According to Beitz poverty qualifies for the
status of human right because: a) ‘the interests protected by the rights are among
the most uncontroversially urgent of all human interests and the least open to
variation by culture’, and b) poor societies fail to provide their people with
adequate subsistence (163). From here he goes on to show at some length that
110
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
the reasons outside agents (rich countries) hold to alleviate poverty in poor
countries depend on the relationships (current or historical) that exist between
countries. Reasons for action include beneficence, the avoidance of harm, and
compensations for historical behaviour. From this Beitz concludes that ‘there
are anti-poverty rights even if there is no single distinctive reason or category
of reasons for action that explains why eligible agents should contribute to the
relief of severe poverty wherever it occurs’ (173). It is noteworthy, however, that
Beitz does not allow for pro tanto reasons to outweigh the need for action, which
is to say, while there may be no single reason why agents should act, the need
for action is bound up with the universal recognition of subsistence as an urgent
value in need of protection. In Beitz’s own words: ‘any value counted as a human
right should be such that a government’s failure to respect it could give rise to
reasons for external agents to act in its defense’ (127). In short, what matters
for action is not, in the first instance, the reasons any one state might hold, but
recognition of the importance of the need for subsistence.
Moving on to political rights, Beitz discusses here whether there should be a
right to democracy as has been suggested by international law. He explains that
although human well-being in stable democracies is highest due to unrivalled
levels of physical and material security, the guarantee of personal autonomy and
political equality, and also the recognition of individual preferences, empirical
evidence suggests that the same is not necessarily true for transition democracies,
many of which are only formally democratic. If then democratisation is forced
on countries as a matter of human rights this may not have the desired positive
outcomes. In the place of a right to democracy he proposes that there should
be a right to self-determination. The latter is not to be confused with self-rule;
instead it refers to a society where, following Joshua Cohen, three conditions are
being met: ‘political decisions result from and are accountable to a process in
which everyone’s interests are represented, there are rights of dissent for all, and
public officials explain their decisions in terms of a widely held conception of the
common good’ (181). According to Beitz, in such a regime, the shortfall from not
having democratic governance would be minimal. ‘Such a society acknowledges
its people’s fundamental interests in personal and material security and provides
access to adequate nutrition, shelter, health care, and education for all’, while
a common-good conception of justice renders political inequality insignificant
(183). In other words, much of the requirement for self-determination is its
capacity to satisfy basic human needs.
Finally, Beitz discusses the issue of whether there should be special human
rights for women. He argues that because women are subject to certain genderspecific threats they are entitled to certain special human rights concerning
primarily reproduction. On closer inspection, however, it emerges that these
special rights are rather more ordinary as all they do is protect women’s physical
security, material security and autonomy. ‘The importance of these interests
seems to be perfectly general. We see this by considering that their importance
111
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
would be conceded in any culture if the beneficiaries of the protections were
men’ (191). In short, quite unlike his categorisation of urgent human interest
suggests, human interests are in fact universally valuable. They concern the basic
human needs of physical health, material security and autonomy of all people
everywhere.
My suggestion that Beitz’s defence of these three rights implicitly relies
upon needs-based justifications of human rights is not, however, intended to
undermine or diminish Beitz’s practical approach; all I mean to say is that his
important approach would be strengthened if he made this connection more
explicit. Thus, if we allow for a formulation of Beitz’s approach where his
vague concept of ‘urgent individual interests’ is replaced with basic human
needs we can specify more easily than Beitz, just when a state’s failure to
provide for basic human needs becomes a matter for international action. And,
while we can accept that states may well have pro tanto reasons that would
prevent them from acting on human rights violations, needs-based justifications
for human rights trump these reasons, necessitating outside agents to alleviate
human rights violations abroad. The bottom line is that even proponents of
practical approaches to human rights cannot simply be content with offering
an analytical theory of how human rights work. Not only is the practice of
human rights too fragmented for such a theory to be feasible, but also, if human
rights are to function as a compelling moral force against state-based violence,
we need to aim for convergence on universally recognisable goods in need of
protection.
I have argued so far that needs-based justifications of human rights refine the
practical approach suggested by Charles Beitz. I will continue with suggesting
that such justifications also go some way towards remedying some of the
shortcomings of Griffin’s and Simmons’ theses as well. One of the shortcomings
of Griffin’s thesis is that he fails to adequately ground his list of human rights
as ‘claims rights’, which is the form of right chosen by him. A needs-based
justification for human rights would have allowed him to ground human rights
effectively. Unlike values needs are generally accepted as legitimate objects
for claims rights, although this is not to suggest that everyone agrees that
human needs are determinable. The fact though that Griffin does not do this
is especially noteworthy given that he too appears to see value in needs-based
justifications. Thus at one point in the book he argues that it is possible to regard
the personhood approach as ‘a kind of need account: what is needed to function
as a normative agent’ (90). What is more, a list of needs of functionings of
normative agents, together with a list specifying the needs of children and how
these are being met outside of a rights framework, would have rendered Griffin’s
approach considerably less ‘top-down’ and more ‘bottom-up’, and in the process
made it more convincing.
Moving on to Simmons’ thesis, I would like to suggest that recourse to needsbased justifications of human rights would have further strengthened Simmons’
112
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
findings, and there are also reasons to believe that Simmons herself would
endorse these approaches. Starting with the second point, it must first of all be
noted that Simmons’ interest in international treaties ultimately springs from
a concern with human well-being. Her rationale for conducting her elaborate
empirical study is nothing less than a desire to disclose ‘How and why the turn
toward the international legalization of human rights has taken place, and what
this means for crucial aspects of the human condition’ (3). The second thing
to note is that Simmons is not only very able in quantitative research methods,
but also that she is quite obviously convinced by their explanatory power. While
we already know that human needs are about human well-being, I have not yet
mentioned that many needs theorists rely on statistical data to examine the extent
of needs satisfaction across societies (see, for example, Doyal and Gough 1991;
Gough 2000: 1–65; Comim et al. 2008). The fact that needs-based justifications
of human rights both employ a research method after Simmons’ own heart,
whilst also being concerned with well-being, leaves me to conclude that out
of the many philosophical justifications available, she might be most inclined
to endorse this one. While this is of course purely speculative, it is also true
that human needs approaches to well-being would have strengthened Simmons’
case beyond where it presently stands. In effect she aims to show that wellbeing is improved by international human rights treaties, and yet, because she
does not conceptualise well-being she fails to measure the exact extent of this
improvement. Reference to the satisfaction of human needs would have allowed
her to do just that, thus rendering her policy advice even more acute.
Conclusion
My suggestion that needs-based justifications of human rights speak to the three
theses discussed here is important, I contend, beyond the arguments proposed
by Griffin, Simmons and Beitz because it suggests that human rights and human
needs are best thought of as complimentary concepts. Thus, unless theories of
human needs are complimented by human rights they cannot (easily) be realised,
because unlike ‘rights’, ‘needs’ do not produce duties. Without the capacity to
produce obligations in others, the quest for needs fulfilment by needs theorists
is likely to remain fruitless, which is why many needs theorists have reverted to
linking human needs to the concept of human rights.
The big weakness of human rights, in turn, is with their justification. Unless
human rights are grounded in something that is both universal and objectively
valuable, they are not easily translated from theory into practice. For example,
in the absence of sound foundations it is not clear what should be done if human
rights clash. This is where human needs come in. Not only do they specify what
is needed for humans everywhere to achieve objective human well-being, but
also they limit the sometimes limitless concept of human rights in useful ways
113
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Rita Floyd
because something qualifies as a right only if it can be shown to satisfy a human
need.
To conclude, neither one of the two concepts is in any sense ‘better’ than
the other, instead they are better off together. Human needs give foundation to
human rights, while so grounded human rights oblige states and/or individuals
to act on human needs. This finding combined with the fact that human needs
speak to all three books reviewed here suggests that attention to human needs is
a step in the right direction for human rights research more generally.
Acknowledgments
The author is grateful to Jonathan Floyd for repeatedly discussing the arguments
presented in this review essay. The author would further like to thank Stuart
Croft for reading an earlier version of this piece. All faults remain the author’s.
Notes
1
2
While both Griffin and Beitz use these labels, the label for Simmons’ approach is my own.
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), International Covenant
on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), Convention on the Elimination of
Racial Discrimination (CERD), Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or
Degrading Treatment or Punishment (CAT), Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of
Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), Convention on the Rights of Children (CRC).
References
Alkire, S. 2002. Valuing Freedoms: Sen’s Capability Approach and Poverty
Reduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Booth, K. 2007. Theory of World Security. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Buzan, B. 2004. From International to World Society? English School Theory
and the Social Structure of Globalisation. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Comim, F., Qizilbash, M., and Alkire, S. 2008. The Capability Approach:
Concepts, Measures and Applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Dembour, M. B. 2010. ‘What are Human Rights? Four Schools of Thought’,
Human Rights Quarterly 32(1): 1–20.
Donnelly, J. 1998. ‘Human Rights: A New Standard of Civilization?’,
International Affairs 74(1): 1–24.
Donnelly, J. 2003. Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 2nd edn.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Doyal, L. and Gough, I. 1991. A Theory of Human Needs. Basingstoke:
Macmillan.
114
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015
Needs-Based Justifications of Human Rights
Dunne, T. 1998. Inventing International Society: A History of the English School.
Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Gasper, D. 2007. ‘Conceptualising Human Needs and Wellbeing’, in I. Gough,
J. A. McGregor and L. Camfield (eds), Wellbeing in Developing Countries:
From Theory to Research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freeden, M. 1990. ‘Human Rights and Welfare: A Communitarian View’, Ethics
100(3): 489–502.
Gough, I. 2000. Global Capital, Human Needs and Social Policies. Basingstoke:
Palgrave.
Hart, H. L. A. 1984. ‘Are There any Natural Rights?’, in J. Waldron (ed.),
Theories of Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hurrell, A. 2007. On Global Order: Power, Values and the Constitution of
International Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Miller, D. 2007. National Responsibility and Global Justice. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Raz, J. 2010. ‘Human Rights without Foundations’, in S. Besson and J. Tasioulas
(eds), The Philosophy of International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sen, A. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
115
Downloaded from ipt.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 27, 2015