Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Social Norms and Legal Design

2015, SSRN Electronic Journal

CIRANO Le CIRANO est un organisme sans but lucratif constitué en vertu de la Loi des compagnies du Québec. Le financement de son infrastructure et de ses activités de recherche provient des cotisations de ses organisations-membres, d'une subvention d'infrastructure du Ministère de l'Économie, de l'Innovation et des Exportations, de même que des subventions et mandats obtenus par ses équipes de recherche. CIRANO is a private non-profit organization incorporated under the Québec Companies Act. Its infrastructure and research activities are funded through fees paid by member organizations, an infrastructure grant from the Ministère de l' l'Économie, de l'Innovation et des Exportations, and grants and research mandates obtained by its research teams.

2015s-44 Social Norms and Legal Design Bruno Deffains, Claude Fluet Série Scientifique/Scientific Series 2015s-44 Social Norms and Legal Design Bruno Deffains, Claude Fluet Série Scientifique Scientific Series Montréal Septembre/September 2015 © 2015 Bruno Deffains, Claude Fluet. Tous droits réservés. All rights reserved. Reproduction partielle permise avec citation du document source, incluant la notice ©. Short sections may be quoted without explicit permission, if full credit, including © notice, is given to the source. CIRANO Le CIRANO est un organisme sans but lucratif constitué en vertu de la Loi des compagnies du Québec. Le financement de son infrastructure et de ses activités de recherche provient des cotisations de ses organisations-membres, d’une subvention d’infrastructure du Ministère de l'Économie, de l'Innovation et des Exportations, de même que des subventions et mandats obtenus par ses équipes de recherche. CIRANO is a private non-profit organization incorporated under the Québec Companies Act. Its infrastructure and research activities are funded through fees paid by member organizations, an infrastructure grant from the Ministère de l' l'Économie, de l'Innovation et des Exportations, and grants and research mandates obtained by its research teams. Les partenaires du CIRANO Partenaire majeur Ministère de l'Économie, de l'Innovation et des Exportations Partenaires corporatifs Autorité des marchés financiers Banque de développement du Canada Banque du Canada Banque Laurentienne du Canada Banque Nationale du Canada Bell Canada BMO Groupe financier Caisse de dépôt et placement du Québec Fédération des caisses Desjardins du Québec Financière Sun Life, Québec Gaz Métro Hydro-Québec Industrie Canada Intact Investissements PSP Ministère des Finances du Québec Power Corporation du Canada Rio Tinto Alcan Ville de Montréal Partenaires universitaires École Polytechnique de Montréal École de technologie supérieure (ÉTS) HEC Montréal Institut national de la recherche scientifique (INRS) McGill University Université Concordia Université de Montréal Université de Sherbrooke Université du Québec Université du Québec à Montréal Université Laval Le CIRANO collabore avec de nombreux centres et chaires de recherche universitaires dont on peut consulter la liste sur son site web. Les cahiers de la série scientifique (CS) visent à rendre accessibles des résultats de recherche effectuée au CIRANO afin de susciter échanges et commentaires. Ces cahiers sont écrits dans le style des publications scientifiques. Les idées et les opinions émises sont sous l’unique responsabilité des auteurs et ne représentent pas nécessairement les positions du CIRANO ou de ses partenaires. This paper presents research carried out at CIRANO and aims at encouraging discussion and comment. The observations and viewpoints expressed are the sole responsibility of the authors. They do not necessarily represent positions of CIRANO or its partners. ISSN 2292-0838 (en ligne) Partenaire financier Social Norms and Legal Design* Bruno Deffains†, Claude Fluet‡ Résumé/abstract We compare fault-based and strict liability offences in law enforcement when behavior is influenced by informal prosocial norms of conduct. Fault tends to be more effective than strict liability in harnessing social or self-image concerns. When enforcement relies on fines and assessing fault is not too costly, the optimal legal regime is fault-based with a standard consistent with the underlying social norm if convictions would seldom occur under optimal enforcement; otherwise liability should be strict. When sanctions are nonmonetary or when stigmatization imposes a deadweight loss, the legal standard may be harsher or more lenient than the social norm. Mots clés/keywords : Social preferences, regulatory offences, law enforcement, strict liability, fault, legal standard, compliance, deterrence Codes JEL/JEL Codes : D8, K4, Z13 * We thank the participants of the CESifo Law and Economics 2011 Workshop , the 4th Law and Economics Theory Conference at Berkeley, the PET and ALEA conferences in 2015, and of seminars at the universities of Aix-Marseille, Bonn, Haifa, Lausanne, Laval, Lorraine, Mannheim, Nanterre, Tel-Aviv, Toulouse, Vanderbilt and Yale. Financial support from SSHRC Canada is gratefully acknowledged (SSHRC 435-2023-1671). † Université Panthéon Assas and Institut Universitaire de France. E-mail: [email protected] ‡ Université Laval, CIRPEE and CRED. E-mail: [email protected] Social Norms and Legal Design Bruno De¤ains Claude Fluetyz This version, September 2015 Abstract We compare fault-based and strict liability o¤ences in law enforcement when behavior is in‡uenced by informal prosocial norms of conduct. Fault tends to be more e¤ective than strict liability in harnessing social or self-image concerns. When enforcement relies on …nes and assessing fault is not too costly, the optimal legal regime is faultbased with a standard consistent with the underlying social norm if convictions would seldom occur under optimal enforcement; otherwise liability should be strict. When sanctions are nonmonetary or when stigmatization imposes a deadweight loss, the legal standard may be harsher or more lenient than the social norm. KEYWORDS: Social preferences, regulatory o¤ences, law enforcement, strict liability, fault, legal standard, compliance, deterrence. (JEL: D8, K4, Z13) Université Panthéon Assas and Institut Universitaire de France. E-mail: Bruno.De¤[email protected] y Université Laval, CIRPEE and CRED. E-mail: [email protected] z We thank the participants of the CESifo Law and Economics 2011 Workshop , the 4th Law and Economics Theory Conference at Berkeley, the PET and ALEA conferences in 2015, and of seminars at the universities of Aix-Marseille, Bonn, Haifa, Lausanne, Laval, Lorraine, Mannheim, Nanterre, Tel-Aviv, Toulouse, Vanderbilt and Yale. Financial support from SSHRC Canada is gratefully acknowledged (SSHRC 435-2023-1671). 1 Introduction Illegal behavior ranges from crimes of great antiquity such as murder carrying strong moral opprobrium down to lesser ‘quasi-crimes’, e.g., misleading advertising, tax noncompliance or …shing out of season. An important issue in legal design is the categorization of o¤ences. Should they be criminalized or quali…ed as mere violations? Legal systems have been dealing with this question since the mid 19th century owing to the multiplication of modern regulatory o¤ences, e.g., in factory legislation or food and drug laws. There has been a resurgence of the issue in the wake of the recent criminal law reforms in many countries. It is also debated in new …elds of law such as competition law, …nancial regulations and environmental protection legislation. In their survey of the economic theory of public law enforcement, Polinsky and Shavell (2007) discuss the various policy choices facing the state, one of which concerns the sanctioning rule: “The rule could be strict in the sense that a party is sanctioned whenever he has been found to have caused harm (or expected harm). Alternatively, the rule could be fault-based, meaning that a party who has been found to have caused harm is sanctioned only if he failed to obey some standard of behavior or regulatory requirement.” Whether there should be strict liability crimes is nevertheless contentious. To give but two examples, the Model Penal Code of the American Law Institute in the 1960s rejected the principle of strict liability in criminal law. By contrast, in the 1990s Australia reformed its criminal code squarely on the basis of the fault-based versus strict liability dichotomy.1 We analyze this legal design issue from the perspective of harnessing 1 For a glimpse of the debates in other countries, see Law Reform Commission of Canada (1974), Faure and Heine (2005), Horder (2005), Simester (2005), Spencer and Pedain (2005), Wils (2007), and Law Commission (2010). For earlier in‡uential discussions, see Kadish (1963) and Fitzgerald (1965). For recent assessments of the evolution in the US, see Singer (1989) and Brown (2012). 1 normative motivations. The standard model of legal enforcement is extended to incorporate social preferences and pre-existing socially e¢cient norms of conduct. At one extreme, the social norm has little salience (e.g., few people feel concerned) so that policy prescriptions are the same as in the standard model without social preferences. At the other extreme, the social norm has high salience. Individuals who are thought not to care meet strong disapproval, a source of disutility. We inquire how the salience of the social norm, together with social or self-image concerns with respect to deviations from the norm, a¤ects the relative performance of fault-based versus strict liability o¤ences from a deterrence and enforcement cost point of view. As in the standard model, society faces a trade-o¤ between enforcement costs and the deterrence of socially undesirable behavior. The law may be under-enforced because enforcement is costly. Nevertheless, some individuals behave e¢ciently from a social point of view. Some do so out of intrinsic moral or prosocial predispositions. Others have no such predispositions but would like people to believe that they do or perhaps would want to perceive themselves as having such concerns; that is, they care about social approval or self image. To the extent that informal motivations su¢ce, legal enforcement is of course super‡uous. We consider situations where an individual’s actions are only vaguely observable by one’s reference group or would only be self-servingly recalled by the individual himself. However, convictions for o¤ences provide hard information from which inferences can be drawn about the intrinsic predispositions of the individuals involved. Under either fault-based or strict liability o¤ences, social and self image concerns therefore provide incentives to mimic the virtuous. A basic result of our analysis is that fault-based o¤ences tend to be more e¤ective in harnessing image concerns. Legal sanctions are then more informative. A strict liability o¤ence conveys that the o¤ender committed a harmful action but says nothing about the circumstances in which the action was committed. A fault-based o¤ence unambiguously reveals reprehensible 2 behavior, thereby providing more precise information about the individual’s character. When the social norm has high salience with potentially strong stigmatization of violators, socially useful incentives are therefore provided by the signaling role of fault, allowing greater deterrence or lower enforcement costs. When the social norm has relatively low salience, however, it may be that strict liability does better in harnessing image concerns. The optimal legal regime and enforcement policy are interdependent and depend in a complex way on the underlying situation. When the norm has high salience and assessing fault is not too costly, the best regime is faultbased. If enforcement relies on …nes, the optimal legal standard of fault then replicates the underlying social norm and convictions are rare events under the optimal enforcement policy. Otherwise, when the best regime is strict liability, convictions (and therefore o¤ences) are frequent events. With nonmonetary sanctions such as imprisonment or when stigmatization e¤ects entail a social deadweight loss, other considerations come into play. Under an optimal fault-based regime, the legal standard of fault may then be more lenient than the underlying social norm. The dichotomy between fault-based and strict liability o¤ences partly captures the distinction between “criminalized” o¤ences and purely “regulatory” o¤ences. In our analysis, the legal design problem is approached from a standard utilitarian perspective. The stigmatization e¤ects of legal sanctions are considered for their incentive properties. Fault-based o¤ences tend to do better for acts that are clearly bad from a moral or social point of view. When there is only a weak pre-existing norm, strict liability does as well and is less costly. Our analysis therefore provides an economic interpretation of the usefulness of the distinction between malum in se and malum prohibitum 2 for optimal legal design and enforcement (see the discussion in 2 Malum in se means wrong or reprehensible in itself independently of regulations or laws. Malum prohibitum refers to conduct that is wrong only because it is prohibited by law. The di¤erence is often decribed in terms of iussum quia iustum and iustum quia iussum, namely something that is commanded (iussum ) because it is just (iustum ) and 3 Dau-Schmidt, 1990). Section 2 reviews some of the relevant literature. Section 3 presents the basic setup. Section 4 compares the incentives under di¤erent legal regimes and enforcement policies. Section 5 derives the implications for e¢cient legal design when enforcement relies on …nes. Section 6 extends the analysis to nonmonetary sanctions and discusses the possibility that stigmatization entails a deadweight loss. Section 7 concludes. Proofs are in the Appendix. 2 Literature review Our analysis belongs to a recent microeconomic literature on social preferences emphasizing that one’s actions may reveal unobservable predispositions and that some predispositions are socially valued, hence social pressure may in‡uence behavior through the individuals’ image concerns (e.g., Bernheim 1994, Bénabou and Tirole 2006, 2011, Daughety and Reinganum, 2010). Numerous experimental or …eld studies show that image concerns are important motivators of prosocial behavior (Masclet et al. 2003, Dana et al. 2006, Ellingsen and Johannesson 2008, Andreoni and Bernheim 2008, Ariely et al. 2010, Funk 2010, Lacetera and Macis 2010, among others). Another strand of literature deals with the interaction between formal legal sanctions and informal nonlegal sanctions. Part of this literature analyzes the substitutability between legal and nonlegal sanctions, stressing that stigma or loss of standing in a community may deter undesirable behavior just as or more e¤ectively than formal legal sanctions (Macauley 1963; Ellickson 1991; Bernstein 1992). Another part discusses the potential complementarity between formal and informal sanctions, noting that legal penalties may in‡uence the existence and impact of informal sanctions (Kahan, 1998, Posner 2000; Cooter 2000a, 2000b; Teichman 2005; Iacobucci something that is just (iustum ) because it is commanded (iussum ). 4 2014). This also relates to the role of stigma and shaming penalties in relation to criminal activity; see Rasmusen (1996), Harel and Clement (2007), and Zasu (2007) among others. The “norms and law” literature also discusses the relationship between morality and law. Posner (1997), Shavell (2002), and McAdams and Rasmusen (2007) provide a general discussion of legal sanctions versus informal motivations as regulators of conduct. Shavell compares the two in terms of the social costs of enforcement and the e¤ectiveness in controlling behavior. He argues that, if the expected private gain from undesirable action and the expected harm due to the conduct are large, it is optimal to have law supplement morality and, if morality does not function well, law alone is optimal. Mialon (2014) analyzes the e¤ectiveness of moral norms in an evolutionary context, showing that legal rules may be necessary when norms are easily swayed by social interaction in the long run. Legal design also bears a relation to the concept of “expressive law”. According to this view even “mild law”, i.e., law backed by small nondeterrent sanctions or weakly enforced, can have desirable e¤ects on behavior; see Cooter (1998b), Tyran and Feld (2006), and Galbiati and Vertova (2008, 2014). In a paper related to the present one, although in a civil litigation context, De¤ains and Fluet (2013) model how tort rules and social pressure interact to provide incentives to take care. In their analysis, the extent to which liability rules are privately enforced and the characteristics of the tort rules themselves are taken as given, e.g., if found liable the injurer must pay compensatory damages to the victim. In the present paper we consider legal design together with optimal public law enforcement. The design problem is whether o¤ences should be strict or fault-based and the determination of the legal standard of fault in the latter case. Enforcement concerns the detection of violations and the setting of sanctions, whether monetary or nonmonetary. 5 3 Set-Up We start with a simple version of the economic model of public law enforcement.3 The model analyzes the use of legal rules for preventing socially harmful behavior and of public agents to detect and punish o¤enders. In the standard model, individuals violate the law when their private net bene…t from doing so is positive given the risk of legal sanctions. We use this framework to de…ne strict liability and fault-based o¤ences. Next we extend the framework to incorporate social preferences. The standard model. Risk-neutral individuals obtain a private gain g from committing an act that causes an external harm of amount h. The private gain, equivalently the opportunity cost of not committing the act, varies between individuals and depends on the circumstances.4 The probability distribution is F (g) with density f (g) on the support [0; g], where g > h. Social welfare is the sum of the gains individuals obtain from committing the act less the harm they cause to others. Denoting behavior by e 2 f0; 1g, where e = 1 means commission of the act, and denoting with e(g) the behavior in the circumstance g, social welfare is Z g e(g) (g h) f (g) dg: 0 Socially optimal behavior is e (g) = 1 if g h; 0 otherwise. (1) The harmful act is assumed to be sometimes socially warranted, allowing a meaningful distinction between strict liability and fault-based legal regimes. 3 Well known surveys are Polinsky and Shavell (2000, 2007). We di¤er by explicitly introducing a costs of ascertaining fault. 4 Acts can be interpreted from di¤erent perspectives, namely acts of “omission” (not complying with some regulation, e.g., …re detectors) versus “positive” acts (driving through red lights). 6 The harmful act is quali…ed as a strict liability o¤ence if it is illegal irrespective of circumstances. For the time being the sanction for violating the law is taken to be a …ne s, a socially costless transfer of money. The enforcement cost is c(p) where p is the probability of detecting harmful acts and c(p) is the per capita expenditure with derivatives c0 > 0, c00 0. An individual does not comply with the law if his private gain exceeds the expected …ne, g ps. For a given enforcement policy, welfare is therefore Z g (g h) f (g) dg c(p): ps An optimal policy maximizes this expression with respect to the value of the …ne and the probability of detection. Becker’s (1968) maximum sanction principle applies: to economize on detection costs, the …ne should be set at the highest feasible level, say the individuals’ wealth or some given upper bound on allowable …nes which we denote by sM . Given the maximal …ne, welfare is maximized with respect to the probability of detection. Assuming an interior solution, the …rst-order condition is (h psM ) dF (psM ) = c0 (p): dp (2) The left-hand side is the marginal social bene…t from deterrence, the righthand side is the marginal enforcement cost. The …rst-order condition requires h > psM , implying that optimal enforcement entails underdeterrence compared with …rst-best behavior. Some individuals, those for whom psM g < h, will commit the harmful act even though it is not socially warranted. Optimal enforcement trades-o¤ some ine¢ciency in behavior against savings in enforcement expenses. With fault-based o¤ences individuals who cause harm are sanctioned only if they failed to obey some standard of behavior. The legal standard is in terms of the circumstances under which the harmful act is committed. An individual’s private bene…t must be above some threshold gb in order for him to avoid liability; otherwise, he is considered to be at fault. Committing the 7 harmful act is illegal when the circumstances are g < gb, in which case the individual is subject to a …ne if he is detected; when the circumstances are g gb, the harmful act does not constitute an o¤ence. Individuals therefore commit the act when g min(ps; gb). Enforcement costs include the cost of detecting harmful acts and the additional cost k of assessing circumstances. For a given probability of detection, the enforcement cost is now c(p) + kp [1 F (min(ps; gb))] where the second term is the per capita cost of assessing the circumstances of the harmful acts committed by undeterred individuals. The optimal policy consists in choosing the …ne, the probability of detection and the legal standard so as to maximize Z g (g h) f (g) dg c(p) kp [1 min(ps;b g) F (min(ps; gb))] : The maximum sanction principle still applies and it is easily seen that an optimal policy requires gb psM , otherwise enforcement costs could be reduced with no detrimental e¤ect on deterrence. An interior solution yields the …rst-order condition (h + pk psM ) dF (psM ) = c0 (p) + k [1 dp F (psM )] : (3) Optimal enforcement may now entail either underdeterrence or overdeterrence compared with …rst-best behavior. Overdeterrence would reduce the frequency of harmful acts and therefore the cost of ascertaining circumstances. As with strict liability o¤ences, there is a trade-o¤ between enforcement costs and some distortion of behavior. If assessing circumstances involves no additional cost (that is, k = 0), enforcement costs are the same under fault-based and strict liability o¤ences. Condition (3) reduces to (2) and welfare is therefore the same under either 8 legal regime. Strict liability and fault-based o¤ences are then equally e¢cient. When k > 0 the optimal legal regime is strict liability. Thus, when both the legal regime and the enforcement policy are optimally chosen, welfare is maximized by strict liability o¤ences unless assessing fault is costless, in which case the legal regime does not matter. Moreover, in the optimal policy individuals are underdeterred to some extent. Another observation is that, under a fault regime, any standard gb psM yields the level of deterrence psM . In other words, the legal standard is irrelevant. A …nal observation is that a standard above the upper bound of g) is equivalent to strict liability because committing possible gains (i.e., gb the act is then illegal irrespective of possible circumstances. Social preferences. In the standard model behavior depends on private costs and bene…ts as conventionally de…ned. We now consider normative motivations. There are two types of individuals. A proportion , referred to as type t = 1, is intrinsically motivated to behave in a socially responsible manner. Such individuals are “good citizens” with moral predispositions. The other group, referred to as type t = 0, has no such predispositions. However, prosocial predispositions are socially valued and those who are thought to be good citizens earn social esteem or status. The utility of a type-t individual is ut = w t max(e e ; 0) + ; t = 0; 1: (4) The …rst term, w, is net “material” payo¤ as in the standard model. In the middle term, the parameter t is the disutility (“guilt”) su¤ered when one causes external harm while deviating from the socially responsible behavior e . Misbehavior occurs when e = 1 and e = 0. For the good citizens, 1 > 0 and is su¢ciently large to intrinsically motivate the individual5 ; for the bad citizen, 5 It su¢ces that 0 1 = 0 and the middle term vanishes. As de…ned here, the h, i.e., the good citizen “internalizes” the harm he causes. 9 social (or moral) norm of conduct is what everyone should be doing given the circumstances, which amounts to a simple version of Kant’s categorical imperative (see Brekke et al. 2003). The third term in (4) is the utility from one’s social image. parameter and is a positive is society’s belief about the individual’s type. The belief will depend on information concerning the individual, i.e., equals the con- ditional expectation E (t j I) where I denotes publicly available information. Given our de…nition of types, the conditional expectation is simply the posterior probability that the individual is a good citizen. All individuals care equally about social approval; may be interpreted as the utility of being perceived as a good citizen, given that the utility of being perceived as a bad citizen is normalized to zero. The parameter captures both the importance individuals attach to social approval and the importance (“social pressure”) society ascribes to being a good citizen in the case at hand. Both proportion and the of good citizens re‡ect the salience of the social norm with re- spect to the situation (and therefore possible acts) considered. For instance, when the harmful act is widely viewed as particularly reprehensible, will be large and presumably so will be . It is useful to re‡ect on the assumptions made so far. Consider the possibility of a multiplicity of moral types t 0, as in De¤ains and Fluet (2013). Di¤erent individuals then trade-o¤ di¤erently the moral disutility of acting bad against material payo¤s. The basic logic of our analysis would nevertheless remain the same. Similarly the importance of image concerns could di¤er between individuals, i.e., they have di¤erent ’s. As long as the ’s are positive, the basic logic would still be una¤ected. Obvioulsy, if the bad citizens in our two-type set-up were characterized by = 0, we would be back to the standard enforcement model with respect to regulating their behavior (the law being super‡uous for the good citizen). To push things further, it could be that the bad citizen has < 0, i.e., he enjoys being seen as bad; for instance, his reference group consists only of bad citizens. 10 Image concerns would then have antisocial e¤ects and much of the results of our analysis would need to be reversed. Rather than seeking to harness image concerns, optimal legal design should seek to mute signalling e¤ects; strict liability o¤ences would then tend to perform better. Our assumptions disregard such possibilities. In e¤ect, they describe a cohesive society with commonly shared notions of what is good, although some individuals lack inner moral strength.6 Welfare is de…ned in the usual way as the sum of utility over all individuals, W = Z g [(1 )u0 (g) + u1 (g)] f (g) dg (5) 0 where ut (g) is the utility (or expected utility) of a type-t individual in the circumstance g. Before proceeding, we show that …rst-best behavior in the present set-up is the same as in the standard model without social preferences. Assume that individuals can both cause harm or su¤er harm caused by others. Consider an omniscient regulator who can directly impose the action pro…le e(g), g 2 [0; g]. The average net material payo¤ is then w = w0 + Z g e(g) (g h) f (g) dg: (6) 0 where w0 is initial per capita wealth. Let the action pro…le eb(g) be welfare maximizing and suppose that the regulator has the option of either publicizing or preventing any information about the individuals’ types. If an optimum entails that no information is disclosed, then eb(g) maximizes W subject to the resource constraint (6), given that beliefs satisfy = where is the prior belief about types. This implies eb(g) = e (g) as de…ned in (1). 6 In the terminology of social network analysis with one’s reference group consisting of one’s “neighbors”, we are assuming an integrated social network in the sense that the distribution of types among neighbors re‡ects the population distribution (see Bramoullé et al. 2012). 11 Combining (4) and (5), the …rst-best welfare then equals W = w0 + Z g (g h) f (g) dg + : (7) h The action pro…le e (g) would also be optimal when full or imperfect information about types is disclosed. First, because the omniscient regulator is able to independently control the ‡ow of information, there would be no reason for him to distort behavior from the wealth maximizing action pro…le. Secondly, welfare would also be as in (7) because reputational bene…ts and losses simply cancel out.7 O¤ences and labeling. Society at large is assumed not to be able to directly observe the circumstances faced by an individual nor his behavior. The assumption prevents social pressure from bearing directly on individuals independently of the legal system. Otherwise one’s type could be inferred directly from one’s behavior. When is large enough there would then be situations where the legal system plays no useful role. Direct informal reputational sanctions would su¢ce to induce socially appropriate behavior. Public enforcers can detect harmful acts and can ascertain the circumstances; that is, they are able to enforce the law when o¤ences are faultbased. Legal proceedings against o¤enders constitute public information from which society at large draws inferences about the individuals’ type. For simplicity, we assume that the only information publicly available about an individual is either G for “guilty”, in which case the individual is known to have been found guilty of an o¤ence, or N for “no news”. The latter means that either the individual did not commit an o¤ence or that he did but was not convicted. The publicly available information a¤ecting one’s social image is therefore the binary signal I 2 fN; Gg. Society’s belief about an individual will then be either tN = E(t j N ) or tG = E(t j G). 7 The result follows from the law of iterated expectations and the linearity of reputational utility in the beliefs about one’s type, that is, E(E(t j I)) = E(t) = . 12 The signi…cance of the signal depends on what the events “no news” and “guilty” reveal about one’s type in the social equilibrium. This will depend on the legal regime, namely whether o¤ences are strict or fault-based, the legal standard in the latter case, and on the enforcement policy. Generally speaking, the event “guilty” will be detrimental to one’s reputation. Other things equal, individuals wish to avoid being labeled as o¤enders. We have stressed social signaling which requires that convictions constitute public information. In practice convictions often receive little publicity. However, as in Bénabou and Tirole (2006), our framework can also be reinterpreted in terms of self-signaling. A simple formulation is Bodner and Prelec’s (2003) dual-self model. In the latter, an individual’s total utility is the sum of the “outcome utility” from choosing a particular course of action, which depends on one’s fuzzily known true inner predispositions, and of a “diagnostic utility” whereby an individual draws inferences about his true self from information about his past behavior. For example, one may occasionally exceed the speed limit in a school zone or evade tax, but would feel shame from being labeled an o¤ender even if convictions are not publicized.8 4 Equilibrium under a Given Regime This section describes the equilibria under given legal regimes and enforcement policies. A perfect Bayesian equilibrium is characterized by the individuals’ action pro…les and the beliefs about individuals’ type conditional on the “guilty” and “no news” events. The legal regime is de…ned by the standard of fault when committing the harmful act. The regime is fault-based if the standard is less than the upper bound of possible gains, otherwise liability is strict. The enforcement policy is de…ned by the sanction for unlawful conduct and the probability of detecting violations. 8 See McAdams and Rasmusen (2007) on the distinction between guilt, social disesteem, and shame. 13 We proceed in three steps. First we derive the action pro…les taking as given the posterior beliefs conditional on the “guilty” and “no news” events. Next we derive these beliefs as a function of action pro…les. Finally we solve for the equilibrium wherein action pro…les and beliefs are consistent with one another. Incentives. Denote the sanctioning rule by (g; gb) where (g; gb) = 1 if g < gb and is otherwise zero. The expected utility of a type-t individual in the circumstance g is ut = w + e [g + p (g; gb)s] t max(e pe (g; gb)tG + (1 e (g); 0) pe (g; gb)) tN ; e 2 f0; 1g; t 2 f0; 1g: The …rst two terms comprise material payo¤ as conventionally de…ned. The …rst term, w, is the part of the individual’s wealth that he takes as given. This consist of initial wealth minus the average harm caused by others plus the per capita tax to …nance the enforcement policy (expenditures minus …nes collected). The second term is the expected net material payo¤ from committing or not committing the harmful act. The third term is the moral disutility from committing the harmful act when it is socially unwarranted. The fourth term is the expected reputational utility. If the individual does not commit the act (i.e., e = 0) or if he would not be legally at fault when he does (i.e., (g; gb) = 0), the belief about his type will be tN for sure, the posterior probability that he is a good citizen given “no news”. If he unlawfully commits the act, he is detected with probability p and the belief about his type is then tG , the posterior probability conditional on “guilty”. If he is not detected, the belief is again tN . These beliefs are determined at equilibrium but are taken as given by the individual. If the harmful act is not committed, utility is w + tN for either type. If it is committed and is lawful, that is g gb, the utility of the nonprosocial is w + g + tN . Hence it will then be committed. In circumstances where 14 the act is unlawful, expected utility is ps) + (ptG + (1 w + (g and the act is then committed if g p(s + p)tN ) ), where tN tG will be referred to as the legal stigma, i.e., the reputational loss from being convicted. The term ps is the standard material incentive to comply with the law, the term p is the reputational motive. Altogether a nonprosocial commits the harmful act when g min[b g ; p(s + )] g0 ; (8) where g0 is short-hand for the private gain threshold of nonprosocial individuals. In turn the threshold determines the proportion F (g0 ) of nonprosocial who do not commit the harmful act. Good citizens are also motivated by legal sanctions and reputational concerns. In addition, their behavior re‡ects an intrinsic concern for complying with the social (as opposed to the legal ) norm conduct. Given 1 su¢ciently large, a good citizen never commits the harmful act in circumstances g < h. When g h, the harmful act entails no guilt and the good citizen then be- haves the same as the nonprosocial. The harmful act is therefore committed if g max(h; g0 ) g1 (9) where g1 is the gain threshold for good citizens. The proportion of good citizens who do not commit the harmful act is F (g1 ). The following summarizes the preceding discussion. Lemma 1 g0 gb and g1 = max(h; g0 ). We shall say that type-t individuals are underdeterred (resp. overdeterred) when the equilibrium threshold gt is less (resp. greater) than the …rst best h. Whether individuals comply with the law is di¤erent. As 15 noted, the legal standard may di¤er from the …rst best (and social norm). A consequence of Lemma 1 is therefore that, if there is some overdeterrence (which requires gb > h), then all individuals are equally overdeterred. Oth- erwise they either all e¢ciently behave or the good citizens do while bad citizens are underdeterred. Moreover, bad citizens never overcomply with the law but good citizens might (when gb < h). Beliefs. The conditions (8) and (9) de…ne the best response functions of individuals of either type given the behavior of others. How others behave a¤ects the payo¤s from one’s actions through its e¤ect on the social signi…cance of the “guilty-no news” events, as captured by the beliefs tG and tN . The posterior beliefs are obtained from Bayes’ rule given the frequency of convictions among good and bad citizens. From Lemma 1, g1 is a function of g0 . Hence posterior beliefs and therefore the legal stigma can be written as a function of g0 . Lemma 2 If gb h, and is decreasing in g0 down to = when g0 = gb. If gb > h and g0 < g1 = h, > 0 and is decreasing in g0 . If gb > h and g0 = g1 h, = 0. Unless both types behave the same, bad citizens are more likely to commit the harmful act. Therefore they are more likely to be convicted, implying that the event “guilty” is bad news concerning the individual’s type compared to “no news”. When the legal standard satis…es gb h, good citizens are never found guilty. A conviction then reveals perfectly that the individual is nonprosocial, so that tG = 0 and = tN . The more the nonprosocial behave like good citizens, the smaller tN . When everyone behaves the same, the event “no news” is uninformative because it occurs with certainty, so the posterior probability then equals the prior that an individual is a good citizen.9 When gb > h, as would be the case with a strict liability o¤ence, both good and bad citizens will at times be convicted, hence tG > 0. As 9 = is the disutility from being perceived as a bad rather than an average citizen. 16 long as violating the law is more likely for bad citizens, tN > tG and the legal stigma is positive.10 When both types behave the same, the events “guilty” and “no news” are uninformative and posterior beliefs equal the prior in either case. The legal stigma then vanishes. ∆ ∆ B ( g0 ) ∆ A ( g0 ) λ 0 h ĝ B g0 Fig. 1: Legal stigma curves Figure 1 provides examples of the legal stigma as a function of the bad citizens’ threshold under two di¤erent legal regimes. The probability of detection is the same in both regimes. In case A, the legal standard corresponds to the social norm, gbA = h, so that g0 h. The legal stigma is then prosocial conform to the social norm (i.e., g0 h). When the non prosocial bounded below by . In case B, the legal standard is above the social norm, gbB > h, hence g0 gbB . The legal stigma then vanishes when all the non- The event “guilty” is then an out-of-equilibrium event with zero probablity, implying that tG cannot be computed using Bayes’ rule. The legal stigma at equilibrium is obtained from limg0 "bg = limg0 "bg tN = . This can also be rationalized in terms of Cho and Kreps’ (1987) D1 criterion. 10 Strict liability disregards circumstances. Good citizens will then sometimes e¢ciently choose not to comply with the law given their knowledge of circumstances. See Shavell (2012). 17 are only slightly underdeterred, the legal stigma under regime A is therefore larger than under regime B. As depicted, the curves intersect. This need not occur but it is a possibility when the nonprosocial are su¢ciently underdeterred. We discuss this further in Section 6. Equilibrium. An equilibrium consists of private gain thresholds and of a legal stigma that are mutually consistent. Proposition 1 Let the legal regime and enforcement policy satisfy gb ps. There is a unique equilibrium with g0 g1 . (i) If ps h, then g0 = g1 = ps. (ii) If ps < gb h, then g1 = h, g0 2 (ps; gb] and is increasing in p and s so long as p(s + ) < gb, otherwise g0 = gb; in either case, g0 is increasing in gb. (iii) If ps < h < gb, then g1 = h, g0 2 (ps; h) and is increasing in p and s, it may be increasing or decreasing in gb. Legal design matters for incentives only when ps < h. The Figures 2 to 4 illustrate di¤erent equilibria for this case. Good citizens then conform to the social norm. In the …gures, (g0 ) is the legal stigma as a function of the bad citizens’ threshold under a given legal regime and enforcement policy; g0 ( ) is their threshold as a function of the legal stigma under the same regime and enforcement policy. The perfect Bayesian equilibrium is the intersection of the two curves (at point E). Figure 2 compares the equilibria under two di¤erent legal standards satisfying gb < h. With the standard gbA the equilibrium is at EA , a corner equi- librium where everyone complies with the law. With the standard gbB > gbA , we have an interior equilibrium at EB . In either case, deterrence increases with a strengthening of the legal standard because this shifts the stigma curve to the right (so long as gb < h). The intuition is that strengthening the standard increases the signi…cance of the “no news” event. 18 ∆ g 0B (∆) g 0A (∆) ∆ B ( g0 ) ∆ A ( g0 ) EB EA λ ps 0 ĝ A ĝ B h g0 Fig. 2: Equilibria with gb < h ∆ g 0 (∆) ∆( g 0 ) λ E h − ps pβ ps 0 h g0 Fig. 3: A corner equilibrium with gb = h In Figure 3, the standard is the …rst-best gb = h. In the case represented all individuals comply with the law and therefore are optimally deterred. This arises when p(s + ) h. In the …gure, the latter condition holds as a strict inequality, hence the detection probability could be reduced while still preserving …rst-best deterrence. Thus, under a fault-based regime, …rst-best 19 deterrence is feasible even though ps < h. Indeed, when p h, …rst-best deterrence obtains with purely symbolic convictions with no material legal sanctions. The …gure illustrates the role of “mild law” as de…ned in Tyran and Feld (2006), i.e., law backed by nondeterrent sanctions. ∆ ∆ A ( g0 ) g 0 (∆) EA ∆ B ( g0 ) EB 0 ps h ĝ A ĝ B g0 Fig. 4: Equilibria with gb > h In Figure 4, gb > h and both types will then sometimes not comply with the law. First-best deterrence then cannot be achieved with ps < h. Strengthening the legal standard further may shift the legal stigma curve upwards or downwards. As before, a stronger standard increases the signi…cance of “no news”. However, it also reduces the signi…cance of the “guilty” outcome because more good citizens are convicted, so the net e¤ect on deterrence is ambiguous. In the situation represented in Figure 4, weakening the standard from gbB to gbA shifts the stigma curve upwards, so deterrence increases. Increasing the probability of detecting illegal acts increases the signi…- cance of “no news”, with no e¤ect on the signi…cance of the “guilty” event.11 In the …gures, the legal stigma curves shifts (or rather rotate) upwards. Because o¤enders are now more likely to be convicted, a larger probability of 11 The conditional expectation tG does not depend on p while tN is increasing in p. See the proof of Lemma 2. 20 detection also shifts the deterrence curve to the right. Thus, greater detection unambiguously increases deterrence, except at corner solutions where all bad citizens are e¢ciently deterred as in Figure 2. A larger …ne increases deterrence because it shifts the deterrence curves to the right.12 5 Optimal Legal Regime and Enforcement Welfare equals the …rst best W as de…ned in (7) minus the loss from socially ine¢cient behavior and minus the per capita enforcement expenditure: Z h Z h W = W f(1 ) (h g) f (g) dg + (h g) f (g) dgg g0 g1 C(p; g0 ; g1 ; gb) (10) where g0 and g1 are equilibrium thresholds as derived in Section 4. The expression inside the brackets is the loss from ine¢cient behavior; the formulation allows for the possibility of overdeterrence13 . The third term is the enforcement cost function. When the legal standard gb = g, the regime is strict liability. Enforcement expenditures then reduce to the cost of detecting harmful acts: C(p; g0 ; g1 ; g) = c(p): (11) When gb < g, o¤ences are fault-based. Enforcement expenditures then in- clude the cost of assessing the circumstances of the harmful acts that are detected: C(p; g0 ; g1 ; gb) = c(p) + pk [1 (1 )F (g0 ) F (g1 )] ; gb < g: (12) Deterrence maximizing legal design. We …rst take the enforcement policy as given and compare di¤erent legal designs in terms of deterrence. 12 Greater detection has an ambiguous e¤ect on the equilibrium legal stigma. A negative e¤ect may be interpreted as greater legal enforcement partially crowding out informal motivations; a positive e¤ect re‡ects complementarity between legal enforcement and informal sanctions. By contrast, a larger …ne always reduces the legal stigma. Rh Rg 13 When gt > h, gt (h g) f (g) dg = h t (g h) f (g) dg > 0: 21 Proposition 2 When ps < h, deterrence of the nonprosocial is maximized by either strict liability or the fault-based regime with the standard gb = h. The result contrasts with the irrelevance of the legal standard in the standard model without social preferences. Strict liability and fault-based o¤ences are no longer equivalent because they yield di¤erent legal stigmas, which in turn a¤ects incentives. Moreover, if deterrence is maximized with a fault regime, the e¢cient legal standard equals the social norm. When ps h, the standard is irrelevant provided that gb ps. Individuals then behave as in the standard model and are either e¢ciently deterred or equally overdeterred. The intuition for Proposition 2 is that deterrence of the nonprosocial increases with the legal standard when gb < h. If it can be increased further still with gb > h, deterrence reaches its maximum at the upper bound gb = g. For an enforcement policy satisfying ps < h, deterrence is therefore maximized either with the legal standard gb = h or with the standard gb = g, where the latter amounts to strict liability. Legal design and reputational incentives. Figure 5 illustrates why one regime may perform better. Regime A is fault-based with the standard gb = h, regime B is strict liability. The …ne and the probability of detection are the same, hence enforcement need not be optimal. We compare two situations, L and H, which di¤er in the intensity of reputational concerns with L < H. In situation L the deterrence curve is not very sensitive to beliefs about one’s type and deterrence under either legal regime is relatively low. As shown, it is greater under strict liability. Situation H yields the opposite. The social norm has high salience and individuals are very sensitive to reputational penalties. Deterrence is then relatively high and is greater with the fault regime. 22 ∆ ∆ B ( g0 ) ∆ A ( g0 ) g 0L (∆) EBL g 0H (∆) E AH λ 0 ps h Figure 5. Stigma e¤ects of legal design when g0 L < H The foregoing presumes that the stigma curves intersect. As remarked in Section 3, this need not occur. Convictions are more revealing about intrinsic predispositions in a fault-based than in a strict liability regime. However, while the event “guilty” constitutes more unfavorable news about an individual’s type under the fault regime, the event “no news” is not more favorable under fault than under strict liability. Because reputational incentives depend on the di¤erence in beliefs between the “guilty” and “no news” events, the stigma curves may intersect. Lemma 3 The stigma curves under strict liability and the fault regime with the legal standard gb = h intersect at most once and do so if and only if p> 1 : 1 + (1 2 )F (h) The condition (13) in the lemma cannot be satis…ed if p (13) 1=2 or if 1=2. Put di¤erently, the situation depicted in Figure 5 cannot arise when good citizens constitute a majority or when a majority of harmful acts are undetected. Given ps < h, a fault regime then always induces greater deterrence than strict liability. 23 Optimal policies. The optimal legal regime and enforcement policy must be jointly chosen. Which policy is best depends on the underlying situation, e.g., the proportion of good citizens, the salience of the social norm, the likelihood of the circumstances under which harmful acts would be socially warranted, and the cost of detecting o¤enders and assessing circumstances. Proposition 3 Under an optimal legal regime and enforcement policy, the …ne is maximal and the probability of detection satis…es psM < h. (i) If liability is fault-based, the legal standard is gb = h, the probability of detection satis…es p(sM + ) h and the nonprosocial are underdeterred or e¢ciently deterred; convictions constitute a rare event, p(1 )(F (h) 1 F (g0 )) < : 2 (14) (ii) If liability is strict, the nonprosocial are underdeterred. When ascertaining circumstances is not too costly, (iii) liability is fault-based if 1=2 or if sM or are su¢ciently large; if liability is strict, convictions (and therefore o¤ences) constitute a frequent event, 1 : (15) p [1 F (h) (1 )F (g0 )] 2 The left-hand side of (14) is the frequency of convictions under a fault regime. The left-hand side of (15) is the frequency of convictions under strict liability.14 The maximum sanction principle still holds for the usual reason: a larger …ne allows the same level of deterrence to be achieved with a smaller probability of detection, thus saving on enforcement costs. By contrast with the standard model, however, a fault regime may now be optimal even though assessing fault is costly and …rst-best deterrence may be optimal. 14 Everyone commits the harmful act in circumstances g prosocial also commit the wrongful act. 24 h; for g in [g0 ; h) the non Overdeterrence is never optimal. It would require psM > h, in which case reputational incentives vanish and strict liability does as well as the fault regime and strictly better if k > 0. But then this is dominated by strict liability with psM = h which in turn is dominated by strict liability with some degree of underdeterrence and possibly also, if k is not too large, by the fault regime with either …rst-best deterrence or some degree of underdeterrence. ∆ g 0B (∆) ∆ A ( g0 ) g 0A (∆) ∆ B ( g0 ) EB λ 0 EA p A sMA pB sMB h g0 Fig. 6: Possible optima under a fault regime In Figure 6, the optimal regime is fault-based when the maximal …ne is sA M . As shown, the outcome is the corner equilibrium EA : The probability of detection is then pA such that pA (sA M+ ) = h and enforcement satis…es the corner condition pA kf (h) dg0 dp c0 (pA ) + k [1 F (h)] : (16) p=pA The right-hand side is the increase in detection and fault assessment costs from a marginal increase in the probability of detection. The left-hand side is the resulting savings in fault assessment costs due to a marginal increase in deterrence up to g0 = h. The derivative in (16) is a left derivative; the 25 right derivative is zero because increasing detection slightly beyond pA has no e¤ect on deterrence, as is obvious from Figure 6. Note that a corner solution as in (16) cannot arise if ascertaining fault is costless, i.e., k = 0. The equilibrium at EB illustrates an interior optimum where the maximum …ne is smaller and is capped at sB M . The optimal probability of detection is then pB such that pB (sB M + ) < h, hence the nonprosocial are underdeterred. The marginal social bene…t from greater detection is smaller than in case A because of the smaller …ne. The …rst-order condition is now (h + pB k g0 )f (g0 ) dg0 dp = c0 (pB ) + k [1 p=pB (1 )F (g0 ) F (h)] (17) Whether the optimum is interior or at a corner, fault-based o¤ences may do better than strict liability even though assessing fault is costly because of the larger legal stigma attached to convictions. The condition (14) in Proposition 3 is then necessary. If it did not hold deterrence could be increased by switching to strict liability under the same enforcement policy, as this would then yield a larger stigma (see the proof). Because this would also save on the fault assessment costs, strict liability would be unambiguously better. Part (iii) of the proposition provides su¢cient conditions for a faultregime to be optimal when assessing fault is not too costly. The condition that good citizens are su¢ciently numerous follows directly from Lemma 3. Even when good citizens are not a majority, fault-based o¤ences do better when either the maximum permissible …ne or image concerns are su¢ciently large. In either case, appropriate deterrence (including …rst-best deterrence) can be achieved with a relatively small probability of detection, which ensures that the fault regime is deterrence maximizing. Condition (15) in Proposition 3 requires p > 1=2 and is necessary for strict liability to be optimal when assessing fault is not too costly. If the condition did not hold, switching to fault-based o¤ences would increase deterrence under the 26 same enforcement policy. The condition need not hold when ascertaining circumstances imposes signi…cant costs. The optimality of strict liability then follows solely from the fact that assessing fault is too costly. 6 Costly Sanctions and Stigmatization We consider two extensions of the foregoing analysis. First, we inquire how the optimal policies di¤er when enforcement relies on nonmonetary sanctions rather than …nes. Next we relax the assumption that reputational consequences only serve to motivate and examine the possibility that they also entail a social cost. Nonmonetary sanctions. We take imprisonment as an example but the results would carry over to other forms of nonmonetary sanctions such as community service or suspension of a licence. Let s now denote the length of prison sentence, with sM as the maximum allowable. The disutility is assumed to be proportional to the sentence. While a …ne is a pure transfer involving no social costs, imprisonment is a net loss in the utilitarian calculus. In addition society may bear a resource cost which we represent by qs where q is the administrative cost per unit of sentence. Nonmonetary sanctions are in practice rarely imposed for strict liability o¤ences. Even with fault-based o¤ences, they make sense only because they extend the range of sanctions, given that e¤ective …nes are capped due to the individuals’ limited wealth. Consider …rst the standard framework without social preferences. Compared with the formulation in Section 3, enforcement costs are now augmented by the addition of Z g b p(s + qs)f (g) dg; min(ps;b g) the per capita costs of the sanctions imposed on convicted o¤enders. Whether the regime is strict liability or fault-based, the optimal policy is again to set 27 the sanction at the maximum permissible level.15 Under strict liability and by contrast with the case of …nes, the optimal probability of detection may now entail overdeterrence relative to …rst-best behavior. The possibility arises because increasing deterrence may reduce prison costs: while o¤enders are more likely to be sanctioned, there will also be a smaller number of them. Under a fault regime, the optimal legal standard satis…es gb = psM and everyone then complies with the law (see Shavell 1987). Undeterred individuals should not be found to be at fault even though they behave inef…ciently from a social point of view, otherwise unnecessary sanction costs are incurred. When sanctions are socially costly, the advantage of fault-based liability is therefore to rely on the threat of sanctions while avoiding the cost of actually imposing them. When assessing fault imposes no additional cost, a fault-based regime is clearly preferable. Indeed, fault is preferable if k < (1 + q)sM , i.e., the cost of assessing fault is smaller than the social cost of the nonmonetary sanction. With gb = psM , deterrence under a fault regime is the same as under strict liability with the enforcement policy psM . Enforcement costs are c(p) + kp[1 F (psM )] < c(p) + (1 + q)sM p[1 F (psM )] where the left-hand side refers to the fault regime and the right-hand side to strict liability. In an optimal fault regime there may also be overdeterrence because increasing deterrence reduces fault assessment costs. We now turn to the the model with social preferences. The properties of the equilibria derived in Section 4 remain the same. The only change is 15 For any given level of deterrence ps, detection costs are reduced if s is raised and p is reduced proportionnaly, with no e¤ect on sanction costs. One could also consider a combination of …nes and imprisonment. See Polinsky and Shavell (2007). 28 with respect to the social welfare function which is now W = W (1 Z f )f Z h (h g) f (g) dg + p g0 h (h g) f (g) dg + p g1 C(p; g0 ; g1 ; gb): Z Z g b (s + qs)f (g) dgg min(g0 ;b g) g b (s + qs)f (g) dgg min(g1 ;b g) (18) The terms inside each set of brackets are the social loss from ine¢cient behavior (again allowing for the possibility of overdeterrence) and the social cost of sanctions imposed on detected o¤enders. We focus on the characteristics of an optimal fault-based regime. Proposition 4 With nonmonetary sanctions, when the optimal legal regime is fault-based the legal standard may be above or below the social norm. When gb > h, the sanction is maximal, psM = gb and all comply with the law. When gb h, either the sanction is maximal, p(sM + ) = gb and all comply with the law; or s sM , p(s + ) < gb and some of the nonprosocial do not comply. Compared with the case of …nes, the di¤erence is that the legal standard may now di¤er from the underlying social norm. Compared with nonmonetary sanctions in the standard model, the di¤erence is that the sanctions may actually be imposed. Another di¤erence is that the sanction may be less than maximum. When psM = gb > h, everyone complies with the law and is equally overdeterred. Sanctions are then at the maximum allowable level because they are never actually imposed. The possibility of a standard gb < h arises because, while a higher standard would increase deterrence, the number of convictions would also increase. Speci…cally, @[F (b g) F (g0 )]=@b g > 0; see Figure 2. This would increase welfare when sanctions consist of …nes, but with costly sanctions more convictions imply that sanction costs increase. At corner solutions where everyone complies with the law and gb 29 h, sanctions are again maximal because they serve only as a threat. When not everyone complies, however, they may be less than maximal. To see the latter, recall that the equilibrium threshold of the nonprosocial solves g0 = p(s + (g0 ; p)); (19) where the legal stigma is written as a function of g0 and of the probability of detection. For a given level of deterrence, the trade-o¤ between the probability of detection and the sanction is s dp p ds where p concerns, = g0 =ct s s+ (20) p denotes the partial derivative. When there are no reputational = 0 and therefore = 1. This yields the argument in the standard model, i.e., it is always desirable to increase the sanction and reduce the probability of detection proportionally. When > 0 but the optimal policy entails overdeterrence, the same argument applies because all individuals are then equally overdeterred, hence the legal stigma vanishes and p = 0. However, when gb h and the nonprosocial undercomply with the law, the legal stigma is positive and p > 0, implying < 1. Increasing the sanction and reducing the probability of detection so as to keep deterrence constant then reduces detection costs but also increases sanction costs. The net e¤ect may be to increase costs. Socially costly stigmatization. Historically one of the main arguments against strict liability o¤ences was the risk of stigmatizing respectable entrepreneurs.16 Similar arguments have been made in the discussions accompanying the recent criminal law reforms. One way to capture social aversion to stigmatization risks is to express reputational utility as a con16 See Paulus (1977) on the debates about “welfare o¤ences” to counter food adulteration in mid 19th century Britain. 30 cave function of the beliefs about one’s type.17 To facilitate comparison with our previous formulation, we write the reputational term as v( ) where v is increasing and strictly concave with v(0) = 0 and v(1) = 1. The overall utility function of a type-t individual is now ut = w t max(e e ; 0) + v( ); t = 0; 1: (21) An omniscient utilitarian regulator would impose the same wealth maximizing action pro…le e (g), but he would not disclose information about the individuals’ type because reputational gains and losses no longer cancel out. Hence the …rst-best welfare is W = w0 + Z g (g h) f (g) dg + v( ): (22) h All of the results of Section 4 continue to hold provided the legal stigma is rewritten as = v(tN ) v(tG ). Assuming that enforcement relies on …nes, welfare is now W =W f(1 ) Z h (h g) f (g) dg + g0 Z h (h g) f (g) dgg g1 [v( ) v1 (1 )v 0 ] C(p; g0 ; g1 ; gb) (23) where v t is the average reputational utility of a type-t individual, v t = p max[F (b g ) F (gt ); 0]v(tG )+f1 p max[F (b g ) F (gt ); 0]gv(tN ); t = 0; 1: (24) In equation (23) the term inside the curly brackets is the loss from inef…cient behavior. The third term is the deadweight loss from stigmatization. In the …rst best, reputational utility is v( ) for all individuals. Under a given legal regime and enforcement policy, the average reputational utility is equal to v where v (1 )v 0 + v 1 : 17 A similar approach has been used in models of self-signalling, see Köszegi (2006) and Dal Bó and Terviö (2013). 31 Because v is concave, v v( ) with strict inequality unless everyone behaves the same. Social aversion to stigmatization therefore introduces a trade-o¤ between the usefulness of legal stigma for motivating appropriate behavior and the deadweight loss from stigmatization.18 Proposition 5 Under stigmatization aversion and with sanctions consisting of …nes, the optimal legal regimes and enforcement policies are as in Proposition 3 except for the legal standard of fault which satis…es gb h. In a strict liability regime, both good and bad citizens will at times choose not to comply with the law. When the nonprosocial are underdeterred, tN > tG at equilibrium and therefore v < v( ), meaning that there is a social loss from legal stigmatization. This loss could be reduced by increasing the probability of detection because the equilibrium v is increasing in p. Indeed the loss would vanish if the nonprosocial were made to behave like good citizens with an expected …ne psM h. However, it is easily shown that the loss from stigmatization is of the second order when enforcement is marginally reduced from the level ensuring …rst-best deterrence. Hence, under strict liability, bad citizens are optimally underdeterred as in Proposition 3. Under a fault regime, the optimal enforcement policy is similar to part (i) of Proposition 3 except that the legal standard of fault may now be below the social norm, i.e., the law is more accommodating than the underlying social norm. In a corner solution, the deadweight loss from stigmatization vanishes because everyone complies with the law. The legal standard may be less than the …rst-best because strengthening the standard reduces the average reputational utility: a stronger standard increases deterrence, but some of the nonprosocial then no longer comply with the law. A standard 18 A parallel can be made with Polinsky and Shavell (1979) who discuss the optimal …ne and enforcement policy when individuals are risk averse with respect to income. Optimal enforcement may then be non stochastic. 32 gb < h is also possible in an interior solution where some of the nonprosocial do not comply with the law. ∆ ∆ ( g 0 , h) g 0 (∆) ∆( g 0 , gˆ A ) λ ∆( g 0 , g ) 0 psM g 0′ ĝ A g 0′′ h g0 Fig. 7: Legal standards and stigmatization Figure 7 illustrates the advantage of a fault regime together with the possibility of a standard less than the social norm. Suppose the probability of detection p is the best enforcement policy under a strict liability regime, yielding the deterrence curve g0 ( ). We denote the stigma curves under the same probability of detection as (g0 ; gb). The curve for strict liability (g0 ; g) and the equilibrium deterrence level is then g00 . Switching to a is fault regime with the standard gb = h would increase deterrence up to g000 . However, this need not increase welfare because the loss from stigmatization may be much greater than in the initial situation under strict liability.19 However, as shown in Figure 7, a fault regime does unambiguously better than strict liability (assuming assessing fault is costless) if the legal standard 19 It is easy to provide numerical examples where, at comparable levels of deterrence, the social loss from stigmatization is substantially larger under a fault regime than under strict liability. 33 is weakened to gbA , which corresponds to the stigma curve (g0 ; gbA ). All individuals then comply with the law, so there is no stigmatization. 7 Concluding Remarks Violating the law does not have the same social meaning under strict liability and fault-based o¤ences. The latter is a stronger signal about one’s character. Fault-based o¤ences will therefore usually perform better in harnessing reputational concerns for the purpose of motivating socially appropriate behavior. Nevertheless, the result does not always follow because the social meaning and incentive e¤ects depend on the frequency of convictions. In many situations, socially unwarranted behavior will be a rare event because most individuals are socially minded. Convictions may also be rare because the enforcement policy achieves substantial deterrence. A faultbased regime that seeks to harness reputational incentives should aim at reducing apparent unlawfulness. Not …nding fault may then be banal, therefore posterior beliefs conditional on “no news” do not di¤er too much from the prior. But then convictions yield substantial disesteem. By contrast, when convictions would be a frequent event under a fault regime, o¤ences are banal. A strict liability regime would then perform better because it increases the signi…cance of “no news”. The argument is reminiscent of Bénabou and Tirole’s (2006, 2011) discussion of how acceptable behavior arises from the interplay of “honor” and “stigma”. High stigma is attached to a behavior that “is just not done”, only the worst type will do it. Alternatively, when “everyone does it”, the same behavior carries little stigma. But then “not doing it” yields prestige. In the case of legal regimes, whether a conviction imposes signi…cant stigma or whether “no conviction” confers signi…cant honor depends on the underlying situation but also on the legal regime itself together with enforcement possibilities. 34 Our analysis emphasized the information conveyed by o¤ences under di¤erent legal regimes given a pre-existing e¢cient social norm. One could also remark that di¤erent regimes have di¤erent “expressive content”. In our analysis, the underlying social norm was that individuals should be socially minded and behave accordingly. Under a fault regime, the norm can be “expressed” by the duty or obligation with respect to which fault is de…ned. Indeed, we found that, when enforcement relies on …nes, the optimal legal standard of fault is identical with the social norm. Strict liability is fuzzier in this respect. However, when enforcement relies on socially costly legal sanctions such as imprisonment or when stigmatization entails a social deadweight loss, the optimal legal norm will generally di¤er from the underlying social norm. To economize on costly sanctions or enforcement costs, the standard of fault may be either more lenient or harsher than the social norm. To mitigate the deadweight loss from stigmatization, the standard may be more lenient than the social norm. Strict liability and fault-based o¤ences may di¤er in other ways with respect to expressive content. In particular, when individuals are imperfectly informed of the harm they may cause, a legal standard of behavior conveys information. Its prescriptive content helps socially minded individuals to coordinate on socially appropriate conduct. Imitative behavior due to social or self image concerns may then induce some bunching by the nonprosocial on the socially appropriate behavior. Appendix A Proof of Lemma 1. The claim follows directly from (8) and (9). Proof of Lemma 2. Applying Bayes’ rule, tN = 1 [1 p max(F (b g ) F (g1 ); 0)] p [ max(F (b g ) F (g1 ); 0) + (1 )(F (b g) 35 F (g0 ))] ; (25) tG = max(F (b g ) F (g1 ); 0) F (g1 ); 0) + (1 )(F (b g) max(F (b g) F (g0 )) (26) where (26) is unde…ned when g0 = g1 = gb. If g0 < gb h = g1 , tG = 0 and therefore = tN = 1 This is decreasing in g0 with = 1 p(1 = )(F (b g) F (g0 )) when g0 = gb. If g0 : (27) g1 = h < gb, [1 p(F (b g ) F (h))] p [ (F (b g ) F (h)) + (1 )(F (b g ) F (g0 ))] (F (b g ) F (h)) ; (F (b g ) F (h)) + (1 )(F (b g ) F (g0 )) which is positive and decreasing in g0 with g1 < gb, (25) and (26) yield tN = tG = = 0 when g0 = h. If h < g0 = so that = 0. For h < g0 = g1 = gb, we take the limit of the preceding result, so that again Proof of Proposition 1. Let gb = 0. ps. We …rst show uniqueness of the equilibrium. From Lemma 1 either g0 = g1 > h or g0 2, the …rst case implies (28) g1 = h. By Lemma = 0. Thus, it arises only if ps > h and the equilibrium is then simply g0 = g1 = ps. A policy with ps h therefore yields the second case. The relevant domain for g0 is then the interval [ps; min(b g ; h)]. If ps = min(b g ; h), the equilibrium is trivially g0 = ps, so let ps < min(b g ; h). From (8) the equilibrium g0 is a solution to g0 = min [b g ; p(s + where (g0 ; gb; p))] (g0 ; gb; p) is de…ned by (27) or (28) for the cases gb respectively. Equivalently, the equilibrium g0 solves '(g0 ) min [b g ; p(s + (g0 ; gb; p))] therefore '(ps) > 0. For the case gb 0. Because h or gb > h g0 = 0, g0 2 [ps; min(b g ; h)]; where '(g0 ) is a continuous function. By Lemma 2, '(b g) (29) h, (b g ; gb; p) = (30) (ps; gb; p) > 0 and > 0 and therefore (g0 ; gb; p) is strictly decreasing in g0 in the relevant 36 domain, so is '(g0 ) and the equilibrium is therefore unique. For the case gb > h, (h; gb; p) = 0 and '(h) < 0. Again '(g0 ) is strictly decreasing, ensuring uniqueness. (i) The claim for the case ps h follows directly from the above argu- ment. (ii) For ps < gb (ps; gb]. If p(s + If p(s + p(s + h, the above argument shows that g1 = h and g0 2 ) gb, '(b g ) = 0 and the equilibrium satis…es g0 = gb. ) < gb, '(b g ) < 0 and the equilibrium is g0 < gb solving g0 = (g0 ; gb; p)). Di¤erentiating totally with respect to gb and p yields p @g0 = @b g 1 p s+ dg0 = dp 1 From (27), g0 is negative while p g b ; (31) g0 +p p g0 and g b p : (32) are positive. Hence (31) and (32) are both positive. To complete the argument, when p(s + ) g0 = gb and is then also increasing in gb. gb, (iii) For ps < h < gb, the argument is similar except that the solution now satis…es g0 2 (ps; h). Di¤erentiating (29) totally with respect to gb and p again yields (31) and (32) but with g0 and p are as before but that of now de…ned by (28). The signs of g b is now ambiguous (see the proof of Proposition 2). Thus (32) is positive but the sign of (31) is ambiguous. How g0 varies with s is derived similarly and is left to the reader. Proof of Proposition 2. Let g0 (b g ) denote the equilibrium as derived in Proposition 1 for some ps < h, so that g0 (b g) g1 = h. The deterrence maxi- mizing legal regime solves maxgb g0 (b g ). We consider separately the possibility that the solution satis…es gb If gb h or gb > h. h, the function g0 (b y ) satis…es part (ii) of Proposition 1 and is strictly increasing, therefore gb = h. If gb > h, the function g0 (b g ) satis…es part (iii) of Proposition 1, hence g0 (b g ) < h. Either gb = g or gb is an interior 37 solution in (h; g). In the latter case, recalling (31), the solution must satisfy the …rst-order condition @g0 (b g) @b g = g b=b g p 1 g g b(g0 (b ); gb ) = 0; g ); gb ) g0 (g0 (b p where the right-hand-side is as in (31) but with (33) de…ned as in (28). The second-order necessary condition is that @ 2 g0 (b g) 2 @b g = g b=b g p g g bg b(g0 (b 1 ); gb ) g ); gb ) g0 (g0 (b p (34) be non positive, where the expression is obtained given that (33) holds and therefore g g b(g0 (b ); gb ) = 0. Because the denominator in (34) is positive, the second-order condition requires g g bg b(g0 (b where ); gb ) = = F (b g) g g bg b(g0 (b 2p (1 ); gb ) 0: From (28), )(F (h) F (g0 (b g ))) >0 [ (1 p ]2 F (h) (1 (35) )F (g0 (b g )): Thus, the necessary condition does not hold, implying that the corner solution gb = g is the only possibility. Proof of Lemma 3. Solve (27) and (28) in the proof of Lemma 2 for the value of g0 consistent with the same fault regime with gb = h. This yields F (g0 ) = 1 2(1 ) (1 under either strict liability or the 2 )F (h) 1 p p : (36) The equation has a solution F (g0 ) > 0 only if the condition in Lemma 3 holds. Proof of Proposition 3. We …rst show that ps < h. Suppose to the contrary that ps h. Proposition 1 then implies g0 = g1 = ps. If assessing 38 fault is costless the optimal regime is then indi¤erent, otherwise it must be strict liability. In either case, using (10), @W = (1 @p ) (h g0 ) f (g0 ) @g0 + (h @p g1 ) f (g1 ) @g1 @p c0 (p): (37) For ps > h, @g0 =@p > 0 and @g1 =@p > 0 so that (37) is negative. At ps = h, the preceding derivatives are discontinuous. Taking the left derivative, @W @p c0 (p) < 0: = ps=h Thus, an optimal policy entails ps < h. By Proposition 1, this implies g0 g1 = h. Next we show that s = sM . From (10), under any legal regime, a policy change that reduces p with no change in g0 is bene…cial because @W @p If gb > h, p and s solve where p p(s + ) > 0. If gb = Cp < 0: g0 =ct g0 = p(s + (g0 ; gb; p)): (38) h, either g0 < gb and p and s solve (38); or g0 = gb and gb. In all of these cases, it is possible to reduce p and increase s with no change in g0 . Hence the optimal …ne is maximal. Finally, we now show that, for any enforcement policy with psM < h, the optimal legal regime is deterrence maximizing. From (10), @W = (1 @g0 The sign follows because Cg0 )(h g0 )f (g0 ) Cg0 > 0: 0; it is zero under strict liability and is negative if the regime is fault-based and k > 0. Because welfare is strictly increasing in g0 for all g0 h, Proposition 2 implies that the optimal regime is either strict liability or the fault regime with gb = h. (i) Suppose the optimal regime is fault-based. The possibility of …rst- best deterrence with p(sM + ) = h is discussed in the text. Otherwise, 39 p(sM + ) < h and g0 < h. We now prove (14). If fault-based liability is optimal for the probability of detection p, we must have @g0 @b g + p = 1 g b=h g b(g0 ; h; p) p g0 (g0 ; h; p) 0: (39) where the expression is a right-derivative and is the same as (33) in the proof of Proposition 2. Now, the inequality must be strict because, as shown in the proof of the same proposition, @ 2 g0 @b g2 + > 0; g b=h again a right-derivative. If (39) held as an equality, g0 would be increasing in gb in a neighborhood of h, implying that gb = h is not deterrence maximiz- ing. Therefore g b(g0 ; h; p) < 0. From (28), the latter inequality reduces to condition (14). (ii) psM < h implies g0 '(g0 ) Recalling that g1 = h. Under strict liability g0 solves p(sM + (h; g; p) = 0, '(h) (g0 ; g; p)) psM g0 = 0: h < 0. Because '(g0 ) is strictly decreasing, the equilibrium satis…es g0 < h. (iii) If k = 0, for any p the best regime is the one that maximizes deterrence. By Lemma 3, this is always the fault regime if or are su¢ciently large, one can obtain g0 = h with p p(sM + ) = h, e.g., when sM necessarily satis…es p Therefore, for p 2h or 1=2. When sM 1=2 satisfying 2h. An optimal policy then 1=2. Condition (13) in Lemma 3 requires p > 1=2. 1=2, the fault regime dominates strict liability in terms of deterrence. By continuity, the same argument applies if k is positive but not too large. To conclude, we prove (15). Using the same argument as in (i), if the optimal regime is strict liability with gb = g, it must be the case that g b(g0 ; g; p) 0, otherwise deterrence would be maximized with the fault regime gb = h. From (28), this is equivalent to condition (15). 40 Before proving the next propositions, we derive a result for corner equilibria. Lemma 4 Let p (sM + ) = gb h so that g0 (p; gb; sM ) = gb when (p; gb) = (p ; gb ). Then the right and left derivatives satisfy @g0 @b g @g0 @b g @g0 @p @g0 @p + = (p ;b g ) p 2 (1 )f (b g ) ; 2 1 + p (1 )f (b g ) = 1; (40) (41) (p ;b g ) + = 0; (42) (p ;b g ) = (p ;b g ) sM + 1 + p (1 2 )f (b g ) Proof: By Proposition 1, when gb < h and p(s + implies (41) and (42). When p(s + and (32) respectively where = g b : (43) ) gb, g0 = gb which ) < gb, @g0 =@b g and @g0 =@p satisfy (31) satis…es (27). From the latter it is easily seen that g0 gb < h; = p(1 )f (b g ) and p = 0 for g0 = gb h. (44) Substituting in (31) and (32) then yields (40) and (43). Proof of Proposition 4. We only discuss the case where the optimal policy does not overdeter. At a corner solution, p(s + ) = gb h. Increasing s and reducing p while preserving the preceding equality has no e¤ect on sanctions (which are not incurred) but reduces the enforcement cost c(p) + pk[ (1 F (h)) + (1 )(1 F (b g )]: Hence the sanction must be maximal. To see that gb < h is then a possibility, di¤erentiate welfare in (18) with respect to gb. At a corner solution p(sM + ) = gb < h, @W = (1 @b g )f (b g ) (h + kp gb ) 41 @g0 @b g p(1 + q)sM 1 @g0 @b g : Substituting from Lemma 4 yields sign @W @b g + = sign fp(1 )(h + kp gb )f (b g ) g b (1 + q)sM g : If k is not too large, this is negative for gb su¢ciently close to h. At an interior solution where g0 < gb, the argument for the possibility that gb < h is similar. To see that s < sM is then a possibility, set k = 0 for simplicity. At the policy (p; gb; s), " @W = (1 ) (h + p(1 + q)s @p @g0 g0 )f (g0 ) @p (1 + q)s Z g b f (g) dg g0 c0 (p) = 0: # (45) The derivative with respect to s is " @g0 @W = (1 ) (h + p(1 + q)s g0 )f (g0 ) @s @s p(1 + q) Z g b # f (g) dg : (46) g0 Substituting from (45) in (46) yields pc0 (p) @W = @s s where (1 )(1 )p(1 + q) Z g b f (g) dg (47) g0 s@g0 =@s = p@g0 =@p s+ s +p : p The expression follows from (31) and (32); (27) implies p Substituting back in (47) yields " @W = sign c0 (p) ( sign @s Z +p p )(1 )(1 + q) > 0 when g0 < gb. g b g0 # f (g) dg : Thus, the sign may be negative. Proof of Proposition 5. We only prove (i) that gb < h is possible when the optimal regime is fault-based, (ii) that there is underdeterrence when the optimal regime is strict liability. 42 (i) When gb h, g0 g1 = h. Setting k = 0 for simplicity, welfare in (23) reduces to W =W (1 ) Z h (h g) f (g) dg )(1 p(F (b g) [v( ) v] c(p) g0 where v = [ + (1 F (g0 ))] v(tN ) (48) and tN satis…es (27). Consider the set of corner policies (p; gb) with g0 = gb and p(sM + ) = gb: (49) A necessary condition for a policy in this set to be optimal is dW = (1 dp )(h gb)f (b g )(sM + ) c0 (p) = 0: (50) Let (p ; gb ) satisfy (49) and (50) and note that gb < h. For this policy to be optimal it must also not be bene…cial to move to an interior solution by marginal independent changes in either p or gb. The gain from a marginal change in gb while keeping p = p is @W = (1 @b g )(h gb )f (b g ) @g0 @v + @b g @b g (51) where the notations refer to either the right or left derivatives. From (48) and (27) @v = @b g p (1 )f (b g ) 1 = p (1 )f (b g ) 1 @g0 @b g @g0 @b g v( ) + v 0 ( ) v( ) v0( ) : Substituting from (52) in (51) and recalling Lemma 4, @W @b g = (1 )(h (p ;b g ) 43 gb )f (b g ) @tN @b g @g0 > 0; @b g (52) i.e., reducing gb from gb is not bene…cial. @W sign @b g + = sign p (1 )(h gb )f (b g ) (p ;b g ) Hence, increasing gb from gb is not bene…cial if p (1 )(h gb )f (b g ) v( ) v( ) v0( ) v 0 ( ); : (53) where the right-hand side is positive by the concavity of v. Similarly the gain from a marginal change in p while keeping gb = gb is @W = (1 @p where )(h @v = p (1 @p Then @W @p gb )f (b g ) @g0 @v + @p @p )f (b g ) v( ) v0( ) c0 (p ) (54) @g0 : @p (55) + = c0 (p ) < 0: (p ;b g ) Substituting from (55) and (50) in (54) and again using Lemma 4, sign @W @p = sign p (1 )(h gb )f (b g ) + v( ) (p ;b g ) v0( ) : Thus (53) also ensures that it is not bene…cial to marginally change the probability of detection. (ii) Under strict liability with the policy psM = h, the e¤ect of a marginal decrease in p is given by the left derivative @W @p = psM =h @v @p c0 (p) (56) where v = p [(1 )(1 + f1 p [(1 F (g0 ) + (1 )(1 F (h))] v(tG ) F (g0 ) + (1 44 F (h))]g v(tN ): tN and tG are de…ned in (25) and (26) with gb = g and g0 solves (29). It is then easily veri…ed that @v @p = 0; psM =h hence (56) is negative, implying that p should be reduced from the full deterrence level. References [1] Andreoni, J. and B.D. Bernheim (2009). “Social Image and the 50-50 Norm.” Econometrica 77, 1607-1636. [2] Ariely, D., A. Bracha and S. Meier (2009). “Doing Good or Doing Well? Image Motivation and Monetary Incentives in Behaving Prosocially.” American Economic Review 99, 544-555. [3] Becker, G. (1968), “Crime and Pumishment: An Economic Approach.” Journal of Political Economy 76, 169-217. [4] Bénabou, R. and J. Tirole (2006). “Incentives and Prosocial Behavior.” American Economic Review 96, 1652-1678. [5] Bénabou, R. and J. Tirole (2011). “Laws and Norms.” NBER wp 17579. [6] Bernheim, B.D. (1994), “A Theory of Conformity.” Journal of Political Economy 102, 905-953. [7] Bernstein, L. (1992), “Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry.” Journal of Legal Studies 21, 115-157. [8] Bodner, R. and D. Prelec (2003). “Self-Signaling and Diagnostic Utility in Everyday Decision Making.” In I. Broca and J. Carillo (eds), The Psychology of Economics, Vol. I, Oxford University Press. 45 [9] Bramoullé Y., Currarini S., Jackson M.O., Pin P., Rogers B.W. (2012), “Homophily and Long-Run Integration in Social Networks.” Journal of Economic Theory, 147, 1754-1786. [10] Brekke, K.A., Kverndokk, S. and K. Nyborg (2003), “An Economic Model of Moral Motivation.” Journal of Public Economics 87, 19671983. [11] Brown, D. K. (2012). “Criminal Law Reform and the Persistence of Strict Liability.” Duke Law Journal 62, 285-338. [12] Cho, I. K. and D. Kreps (1987), “Signaling games and stable equilibria.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 102, 179-221. [13] Cooter, R. (1998a), “Models of Morality in Law and Economics: SelfControl and Self-Improvement for the Bad Man of Holmes”, Boston University Law Review, 78, 903-930. [14] Cooter, R. (1998b), “Expressive Law and Economics.” Journal of Legal Studies 27, 585-608. [15] Cooter, R. (2000a), “Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis.” Virginia Law Review 86, 1577–1601. [16] Cooter, R. (2000b), “Three E¤ects of Social Norms on Law: Expression, Deterrence and Internalization.” Oregon Law Review, 79, 1–22. [17] Dal Bó, E. and M. Terviö (2013), “Self-Esteem, Moral Capital and Wrong-Doing.” Journal of the European Economic Association 11, 599633. [18] Dana, J., D.M. Cain and R. Dawes (2006), “What You Don’t Know Won’t Hurt Me: Costly (but Quiet) Exit in Dictator Games.” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100, 193-201. 46 [19] Dau-Schmidt, K.G. (1990), “An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference-Shaping Policy.” Duke Law Journal, 1-38. [20] Daughety, A. and J. Reinganum (2010), “Public Goods, Social Pressure, and the Choice Between Privacy and Publicity.” American Economic Journal: Microeconomics 2, 191-222. [21] De¤ains, B. and C. Fluet (2013), “Legal Liability when Individuals Have Moral Concerns.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 29, 930-955. [22] Ellingsen, T. and M. Johannesson (2008), “Pride and Prejudice: The Human Side of Incentive Theory.” American Economic Review 98, 9901008. [23] Ellickson, R. C. (1991), Order without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes, Harvard University Press. [24] Faure, M. and G. Heine (2005), Criminal Enforcement of Environmental Law in the European Union, Kluwer International. [25] Fitzgerald, P.J. (1965), “Real Crimes and Quasi-Crimes”. Natural Law Forum 10, 21-53. [26] Funk, P. (2010), “Social Incentives and Voter Turnout: Theory and Evidence.” Journal of the European Economic Association 8, 1077-1103. [27] Galbiati, R. and P. Vertova P. (2008), “Obligations and Cooperative Behavior in Public Good Games.” Games and Economics Behavior 64, 146-70. [28] Galbiati R. and P. Vertova P. (2014), “How Laws A¤ect Behavior: Obligations, Incentives and Cooperative Behavior.” International Review of Law and Economics 38, 48-57. 47 [29] Harel, A. and A. Klement (2007), “The Economics of Stigma: Why More Detection of Crime May Result in Less Stigmatization.” Journal of Legal Studies 36, 355-378. [30] Horder, J. (2005), “Whose Values Should Determine When Liability is Strict?”. In A. Simester (ed.), Apraising Strict Liability, Oxford University Press. [31] Iacobucci, E.M. (2014). “On the Interaction Between Legal and Reputational Sanctions.” Journal of Legal Studies, 43, 2014. [32] Kadish, S.H. (1963). “Some Observations on the Use of Criminal Sanctions in Enforcing Economic Regulations.” University of Chicago Law Review 30, 423-442. [33] Kahan, D.M. (1998), “Social Meaning and the Economic Analysis of Crime.” Journal of Legal Studies 27, 709-622. [34] Köszegi, B. (2006), “Ego Utility, Overcon…dence, and Task Choice.” Journal of the European Economic Association 4, 673-707. [35] Lacetera, N. and M. Macis (2010), “Social Image Concerns and Prosocial Behavior: Field Evidence from a Nonlinear Incentive Scheme.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 76, 225-237. [36] Law Commission (2010), Criminal Liability in Regulatory Contexts, Consultation Paper No 195, London. [37] Law Reform Commission of Canada (1974), Studies on Strict Liability, Information Canada, Ottawa. [38] McAdams, R.H. and E. B. Rasmusen (2007), “Norms in Law and Economics.” In Polinsky, A. M. and S. Shavell (eds.), Handbook of Law and Economics, Vol. 1, North-Holland. 48 [39] Macaulay, S. (1963), “Non-Contractual Relations in Business,” American Sociological Review, 28, 55-70. [40] Masclet, D., C. Noussair, S. Tucker and M.C. Villeval (2003), “Monetary and Non-Monetary Punishment in the Voluntary Contribution Mechanism”, American Economic Review 93, 366-380. [41] Mialon, S. (2014), “Declining Moral Standards and The Role of Law.” Mimeo. [42] Paulus, I. (1977). “Strict Liability: Its Place in Public Welfare Offences.” Criminal Law Quarterly 20, 445-467. [43] Polinsky, M.A. and S. Shavell (1979), “The Optimal Tradeo¤ between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines.” American Economic Review 69, 880-891. [44] Polinsky, M.A. and S. Shavell (2000), “The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law.” Journal of Economic Literature 38, 45-76. [45] Polinsky, M.A. and S. Shavell (2007), “The theory of public enforcement of law.” In Polinsky, A. M. and S. Shavell (eds.), Handbook of Law and Economics, Vol. 1, New York: North-Holland. [46] Posner, R. (1997), “Social Norms and the Law: An Economic Approach”, American Economic Review 87, 365-369. [47] Posner, E. (1998), “Symbols, Signals, and Social Norms in Politics and the Law.” Journal of Legal Studies 27, 765-798. [48] Posner, E. (2000), Law and Social Norms. Harvard University Press. [49] Rasmusen, E. (1996), “Stigma and Self-Ful…lling Expectations of Criminality.” Journal of Law and Economics 39, 519-544. 49 [50] Shavell, S. (1987). “The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent.” American Economic Review 77, 584–592. [51] Shavell, S. (2002), “Law versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct.” American Law and Economics Review 4, 227-257. [52] Shavell, S. (2012), “When is Complying with the Law Socially Desirable?” Journal of Legal Studies 41, 1-36.378-405. [53] Simester A. (2005), “Is Strict Liability always wrong?” In A. Simester (ed.), Apraising Strict Liability, Oxford University Press. [54] Singer, R. (1989), “The Resurgence of Mens Rea: The Rise and Fall of Strict Criminal Liability.” Boston College Law Review 30, 337-408. [55] Spencer, J.R. and A. Pedain (2005), “Approaches to Strict and Constructive Liability in Continental Criminal Law.” In A. Simester (ed.), Apraising Strict Liability, Oxford University Press. [56] Teichman (2005), “Sex, Shame, and the Law: An Economic Perspective on Megan’s Laws.”Harvard Journal on Legislation 42, 355–415. [57] Tyran, J. and L. Feld (2006), “Achieving Compliance When Legal Sanctions are Non-Deterrent.” Scandinavian Journal of Economics 108, 135156. [58] Wils, W. (2006). “Is Criminalization of EU Competition Law the Answer?” In Cseres, K.J., Schinkel, M.-P. and F. Vogelaar (eds.), Criminalization of Competition Law Enforcement, Edward Elgar Publishing. [59] Zasu, Y. (2007), “Sanctions by Social Norms and the Law: Substitutes or Complements?” Journal of Legal Studies 36, 379-396. 50