LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1. ISSN 2029-0187 print/ISSN 2029-0209 online
I. EUROPE AND ITS OTHERS
“PLURALITY IN UNITY”: EUROPEAN IDENTITY
AND EUROPEAN CITIZENSHIP
Evert van der Zweerde
Centre for Ethics, Radboud University Nijmegen,
P.O. Box 9103, NL-6500 HD Nijmegen, Netherlands
E-mail:
[email protected]
In this paper, an argument is developed in favour of further integration of
“Europe” and, most importantly, its increased “politicization”. It is not based
on any romantic or idealistic vision of a positive European cultural identity,
but on an assessment of Europe’s reality as already integrated economically,
socially and ecologically, however lagging behind politically in terms of democratic government and citizenship. The seemingly endless discussions about
Europe’s identity, limit, unity, civilization, etc. are not a problem that is yet to
be solved, but are, precisely, the core of what makes Europe what it is: a plurality in unity instead of a “unity in plurality”, as one of the official slogans of the
European Union (EU) has it. Current social, economic and environmental problems require European solutions as well as a more active European citizenship.
However, European civil identity that is to match European societal reality, will
not be a unitary and homogeneous identity, but heterogeneous and diverse, covering a plurality of perceptions, preferences and ideals – it will be plural, not
as a first step towards unity, but in its core; and it will be divided, but not along
national lines.
Keywords: citizenship, “civilizationalism”, discursive space, European integration, identity, plurality.
DOI: 10.3846/2029-0187.2009.1.5-25
“The idea of a ‘return to Europe’ differs profoundly from the slip of the
tongue common among Western European commentators, in which the enlargement of the EU becomes the ‘expansion of Europe’”, Ralf Ragowski,
Charles Turner (Rogowski, Turner 2006: 19).
“<…> the problem of politics is not identification, but identification and its
failure”, Ernesto Laclau, Lilian Zac (Laclau, Zac 1994: 35).
“There was a positive choice in the “no”: the choice of the choice itself”,
Slavoj Žižek (Žižek 2008: 270).
5
6
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
Introduction
If “we”1 are to judge by printed and televised media, citizens of many European
countries have become more “euro-sceptic” and perhaps even “euro-phobic” over the
last couple of years. The Dutch and French “no” to a constitutional treaty has been followed by an Irish “no”, and the attempts by the French president, Nicolas Sarkozy, to
compensate Czech EU presidency by a stronger financial policy show a lack of political will to “go for Europe”.The recent Eastward and Southward enlargement – the Baltic
states, Romania and Bulgaria, Cyprus, Malta, Slovenia – is experienced by many as a
form of “expansion”; relatively recent member-states such as Poland, Czech Republic
and Hungary have lost much of their initial enthusiasm, and many people in established
EU member-states fear the free flow of labour force from the new member states, not to
mention the dread associated with the leaky walls of “fortress Europe”. The EU seems
to be experienced, by many, though certainly not all, as an inevitable phenomenon that
is at best convenient, but does not generate any warm sentiments: at the level of political
passions, Europe is lukewarm at best2.
Contrary to these apparent tendencies, I want to develop in this paper an argument
in favour of a gradual further integration of “Europe” and, most of all, in favour of an
increased “politicization”. My argument is not, however, based on any romantic or idealistic vision of a positive European cultural identity, let alone a “civilizational” European
mission. On the contrary, it is based on the following three considerations, two of them
realistic and one idealistic, but not per se European: (i) an integrated Europe is an economic, social and ecological reality already and increasingly so, but it is not matched
by a political structure that allows Europeans to address their common problems; (ii)
there is a relatively coherent and delineated European “identity”, even if its borders are
unclear and even if it has to be defined in negative rather than positive terms; (iii) there
is a positive ideal, call it “democratic”, of self-government or self-determination that I
subscribe to, and that is hampered rather than promoted by the current political state of
Europe. As Žižek recently put it: “So, although the French and Dutch “no” is not sustained by a coherent and detailed alternative vision, it at least clears the space for it…
<…> It is time for us, citizens of Europe, to become aware that we have to make a properly political decision about what we want. No enlightened administrator will do the job
for us” (Žižek 2008: 276).
It is important to emphasize what I am not doing in this paper. I am not engaged in
an attempt to offer a blueprint for a better or more democratic Europe – rather I try to
articulate a few principles against which any such model or proposal should be measured. Secondly, I am not working towards stating a positive European identity – rather
I try to point out how the discussion about identity is fundamentally misled if it seeks
to articulate identity “positively”. Thirdly, my aim is not to develop a “political philoso1
Throughout this paper, “we” means all people who positively identify with the idea of an integrated Europe
(regardless of its territorial delineations and of the degree and form of unification – alliance, confederation,
federation, unitary state, etc.); this “we” can thus be understood as “a European dèmos in the making”.
2
See Evert van der Zweerde 2008.
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
7
phy for Europe” – rather I try to develop a number of notions and ideas that, though
European in terms of their historical background and no doubt “euro-centric” in some
respects3 intentionally point beyond Europe (or any other continent) to a “universal”
political philosophy which can be applied, among others, to Europe. In the first section,
I offer a brief outline of this political philosophy. In the next sections (2–10), I develop
argumentative lines that in the concluding section (11) are brought together in a position that, hopefully, is as inspiring as it is realistic. The inspiration will contribute, I
hope, to an extension and intensification of the “we” referred to in the first sentence of
this introduction; the realism will, preferably, make this “we” more influential – even
if I do not think that it is up to me, as a political philosopher, to seek direct political
influence.
1. Political philosophy – a brief outline
Of course, the space of this section does not allow for more than a succinct and rather
schematic outline of what I think could be a viable conception of political philosophy. It is based on the following principles – each of which here has the status of an
assumption.
i. I assume that “politics”, in the broad sense of that term, refers to many possible
and actual forms of dealing with “the political”, and the latter I define as “the dimension of possible conflict that is intrinsic to and therefore ineradicable in all (including discursive and symbolic) forms of social human life”. “Dealing with”, in
this context, can mean many different things, including denying and overlooking,
but it cannot mean “effectively doing away with”. In this sense, the political, understood as the possibility of conflict, is objectively there. The notion of “politics”
covers many things, from contesting social movements to political parties, from
micro-politics in organizations to the macro-politics of bodies like the EU, and
from a Solomon’s judgment to settle a dispute among children to the constitutions
of European polities. If “politics” is an umbrella term to cover the “forms of dealing with the political”, the proper object of political philosophy must be “politics
and the political” in their intertwinement.
ii. Conflict is, essentially, the conflict between “powers”, i.e. actualized potentialities
(latin potentiae, french puissances). In human society, these powers come in many
forms: physical force, economic power (“buying power”), psychic force (indoctrination), persuasive force (including temptation), disciplinary power, rational force
(the power of the better argument), etc. Political power (latin potestas, french pouvoir) is a specific type of power that organizes the other forms, sometimes by using
them, sometimes by channelling them, sometimes by transforming them, sometimes by generating them, sometimes by counteracting or oppressing them, but
always subordinating them to itself and thus always bound up with them – there is
3
In my view, the judgement concerning the X-centric nature of some phenomenon can never be left to X – there
even is something hypocritical in attempts to articulate one’s own X-centeredness: if you can articulate it,
you might as well overcome it.
8
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
no such thing as pure political power. Political power is necessary in any society4
in order to reduce the conflict potential of the existing forms of power, without
ever being able to annihilate this potential and, in fact, introducing a new source
of possible conflict, namely precisely between political power and other forms.
Political power is generally, though not necessarily, and therefore not always, in
the interest of the otherwise less powerful – political power thus can indeed be
seen as an ideal in its own right (Kangaspuro 2007: 12). Seen from this angle, democracy is good inasmuch as it entails maximum transformation of social power
(the power of the multitude) into political power of the dèmos (Wiesner 2007: 46f);
political rights and liberties are good inasmuch as they allow for the bottom-up
articulation of potentially conflicting forces and their transformation into political
conflict. Consequently, liberal democracy is not a bonum in se, but the arguably
most promising type of polity for the transformation of societal conflict into political struggle5.
iii. Political power can be both legitimate and illegitimate, i.e. legitimacy is a quality that political power can have, but legitimate political power is not sui generis:
the legitimacy of political power stems from a source other than this power itself.
Major candidates are, of course, the will of the people, e.g. as expressed in elections, and law, esp. constitutional law. However, these are not “absolute” sources of
legitimacy, but only within the context of a liberal-democratic Rechtsstaat. To this
can be added, as a secondary source of legitimacy, the effective success of political power in organizing the other forms of power, such as violence and economic
power: an effective monopoly on the use of violence, for example, can increase the
legitimacy of political power just as its failure to exclude violence from society can
reduce it. At this point, however, one must be careful not to confuse legitimacy
and efficacy: as anti-terrorist policies show, it is very well possible to have efficacy
without legitimacy – this is also why legitimacy is not to be confused with popular
acceptance. Illegitimate political power reverts to apolitical power, i.e. it becomes
mere force.
iv. The actual power structure of society, including the political power that organizes
it, can never exhaust the dimension of possible conflict within society, because
it is, itself, an effect of the execution or application of pre-political power, which
transforms itself into political power in the very execution. As the institution of
political power is, by definition, a transformation of pre-political power, this transformation itself cannot be an effect of political power, as there is no political power
before the transformation takes place. This is another way of saying that political
power, despite the fact that, once constituted, it becomes itself productive, is always and necessarily the organization of something pre-existing, and this some4
5
not an a priori exclusion of anarchism, which, to my mind, does not deny political power, but any
asymmetrical distribution of it.
This is
At this point, I derive my inspiration from the idea of “agonistic democracy”, elaborated by theorists like
Chantal Mouffe, Iris Marion Young, and William Connolly; see, for example, Young 2000, p. 49f.
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
9
thing thus must be ontologically prior to it. And this is another way of stating the
primacy of the social over politics. The consequence of this is that political power,
irrespective of its capacity and scope, is always and necessarily re-active: it can
repress and oppress, it can control and canalize, but it cannot encapsulate or incorporate all forms of power. There is an ontological limit to political power – even
if it is not per se clear where this limit. If existing powers, i.e. at the ontic level,
transgress this limit, apolitical power comes in at the other end in the form of tyranny, intrigue, etc.
v. Politics can never exhaust the political, i.e. there is always a remainder, a moment
of “pure”, arbitrary and by definition illegitimate power exercise. This is why any
decision, any form of politics, any power constellation can always be contested.
There is, consequently, an irreducible gap between a concrete constellation of political and other powers, and its acceptance as natural, divinely sanctioned or historically necessary, and this gap is bridged by ideology which can be defined as
any self-concealing mechanism of justification (motivation/legitimization) of past,
present or future action and/or state of affairs through unwarranted claims and
images, concerning non-experiential entities (typical examples being the People,
the Nation, the Party, Reason etc.). Ideological formations can make a “jump”, e.g.
in claiming that a capitalist market economy is natural or that the hegemony of
liberal democracy, at least as an idea, marks the end of history, but they also can
claim the opposite of social reality. Soviet ideology, for example, claimed that all
Soviet citizens were engaged in the construction of a socialist society.
vi. If the possibility of conflict is intrinsic to society, if, therefore, the fundamental
tension in politically organized society is that between political power and the free
play of forces, each of which pre- supposes and restricts the other, if, consequently,
the question is not whether, but how these two should be related to each other
(which is the question of the capacity (Tilly 2007: 15f) – scope, impact, etc. – of
political power vis-à-vis non-political powers, including those generated by political power itself, e.g. bureaucracy), and if, finally, the existing constellation of
powers can never be “fixed”, but is always and necessarily a matter of checking
and balancing, then the primary task of political philosophers is to point out these
fundamental relations and constellations, rather than to suggest either a solution of
this tension or to “sublate” the existing tensions to a higher-level synthesis. There
is no end to politics, because the political is ineradicable – where this disappears
from sight, politics must be reinvented.
It is from these five assumptions, briefly outlined here, that I approach the “political state of Europe”6.
6
I use “state” in this context not in the traditional sense of the nation-state, but in the broader sense of the
juridical-political state – or: condition of a given polity. Étienne Balibar poses the question as follows: “…la
question… sur laquelle… nous devrions continuer à réfléchir, est la suivante: Qu’est-ce que l’État aujourd’hui
en Europe ?” and he specifies that he does not mean any kind of ‘European state’, but the actual constellation
of state functions : “il s’agit de demander… ce que deviant tendanciellement, et comment se comporte, quelles functions remplit l’État dans l’espace européen” (Balibar 2001: 236).
10
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
2. Borders in and of Europe
The first topic to address in this connection is that of borders. Białystok, like
Białowieża, both locations of recent conferences on Europe and its borders, is located
near the border of the EU. This border is, in many respects, an edge: it is sharp and it
can hurt physically, morally and emotionally. First of all, it is the border between two
political spaces, the EU and bordering non-EU Europe (in this case, Belarus), and in
this capacity it is much sharper than any border within the EU. Citizens cannot simply cross it. It is a place where the EU protects its political space against illegal immigration (it has delegated this task to the Polish government, providing the means
to execute it), and it separates different political systems, one based on the idea of
individual rights and freedoms, the other on the denial of these principles. Secondly,
this border is an economic one as becomes clear from the extensive trade, legal and
illegal, across it. It separates different economic systems, it separates the protected inner common market (including labour market) of the EU from the economic
space of the heirs of the Soviet economic space, and, last but certainly not least, it
separates relative wealth from relative poverty. Even if this border is not impenetrable, it is still clear-cut. Political borders are “cut” because they result from “cision”.
They are not, however, mere symbolic constructions: borders are always also made
of wood, concrete, steel, floodlight etc., and they are always also physical barriers,
that can stop bodies from moving from one place to another. This is different from
cultural, ethnic and religious borders: the borders between cultural traditions, ethnic
composition and religious affiliation are rarely clear-cut, in fact, they are very rarely
“cut” – they rather cut across society in many different, overlapping and fragmented
ways and they are discursive and symbolic as much, or more, as they are tangible. In
some places, a Huntingtonian fault line between civilizations – between the WesternChristian and the Orthodox worlds, for example – may be almost visibly present, but
even there it is not as sharp as the border between countries, which, if there is a need,
can be established very exactly.
If, following Niklas Luhmann and Anthony Giddens, we conceive of society as a
continuum, i.e. as a world society by default, we can perceive all these borders as cutting across society, creating new divisions and differences, rather than expressing existing ones (Luhmann 2000: 220; Giddens 1999: 16). This clearly applies to Europe:
borders have always shifted in the course of its history, and any attempt to establish
borders, that would match pre-existing objective differences is bound to fail – rather,
borders organize and establish differences as such. As a result, such borders, even if
we accept them as facts of life, necessarily retain an aspect of artificiality and contestability. In fact, I think, that it is difficult to find in Europe (to which this discussion limits itself) borders that could not be reasonably contested by individuals and
groups, living near them. The first conclusion is that in Europe no border is self-evidently given (with the possible exception of sea shores). Consequently, discourses –
political, scientific, philosophical, and folk – are developed to either justify or question the existence or precise location of such borders. These discourses become more
important and hence forceful – potentially even aggressive – as the borders are less
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
11
obvious and, therefore, have to be actively drawn by participants. This is the case
with the border of the EU. Discourse about “European identity” and about the “limits” of enlargement is so complex and discordant because neither of them is obvious
and both are a matter of self-determination of a very complex “agent” – they cannot
therefore serve as the foundation of real, i.e. physical borders, and yet something has
to serve as such.
3. European discursive space
Any discourse occurs in a concrete situation and is developed from a position within
a field. Obviously, this situation and this position themselves can become objects of
deliberation and discussion, which makes the situation reflexive. There is no external, let alone Archimedean, point from which issues about society, including those
that concern the borders that cut across it, can be addressed. Discourse is local and
immanent by definition. This is not to deny that there is a dimension of generality and
universality that goes beyond the situation in which discourse is developed; but it is to
argue, and emphatically so, that this is a movement out of that situation – the movement of thought is one of transcending an initial immanence. In this respect, society
can be present as an object of discourse, e.g. in social science or in politics, but it
never is an object: it is always a subject-object that, in a disharmonious multitude of
discourses and meta-discourses, speaks about itself. From a sociological perspective
that means to Luhmann’s words: „Eine Gesellschaft, die sich selbst beschreibt, tut dies
intern, aber so, als ob es von außen wäre“ (Luhmann 1997: 15). From a philosophical
perspective, however, this “speaking about itself” must be understood as a form of
reflexivity, i.e. the relation between “internal” and “external”, is itself internal.
Discourse takes place in what I suggest to call discursive space. In contrast with
physical space or spatial environment, discursive space is both infinite and limited
in a specific manner. It is filled – with “discourse”, obviously – at the very moment
of its generation: even if it is empty, it is filled with meaningful silence (there is a
difference between empty discursive space and absence of such space). Moreover,
any “stretch” of discursive space can only be filled in one particular way. At the
same time, it is infinite: any point in discursive space can be the starting point of a
new stretch. By way of imperfect illustration, compare it with text balloons in comics (especially the less “mainstream” ones – I am thinking of such authors as Gotlib
or Greg): they can have any size, take any shape, have layers and be filled with any
content, including “emptiness”, but they are always connected to some point in physical space, i.e. to one of the figures in a picture (of course, they can also “float” in the
air – but in that case they are meaningfully not linked to a speaker).
When filled, discursive space obtains a “materiality” of its own – this is why
“official talk”, however shallow or void of meaning it may be (think of the langue
de bois produced in the former Soviet bloc, but more generally think of any type of
official discourse or propaganda), is never without significance: although discursive
space is infinite in the sense that any filling of it can be compensated or matched,
12
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
hidden or drowned, it is limited in the sense, that its filling cannot be “undone”.
Therefore, even empty talk has a certain significance. It means that serious talk, at
the same time and place, in the same communicative situation, has to affirm itself
against it. Typically, different instances of discourse fight over the same discursive
space, despite the fact that new discursive spaces can be opened infinitely. It is this
materiality of discourse, together with its always having a “real” source as well as
“real” addresses – “people” – that precludes any understanding of discourse as innocent hot air, and that excludes any conception of discourse analysis as dealing with
mere symbolic constructions. These “constructions” please or hurt human beings of
not only mind, but also flesh and blood, and they express their real opinions, needs,
wants, ideals and anxieties. Names do hurt, albeit not in the same manner as sticks
or stones, and “hate speech” (or “love talk” for that matter) is not a metaphorical expression. Consequently, discursive space is not only a place of exchange and expression, but also of contestation and struggle.
One thing that can be assessed against this background is that there is in Europe
a multitude of often conflicting discourses about Europe and these discourses do not
simply co-exist, let alone peacefully. Academic conferences are, of course, one part
of them. One way to describe a conference is as a place where various discursive and
argumentative lines touch upon each other in conflict, convergence and overlap, thus
creating, at least for some time, a new discursive situation. Participating in a conference is one way of transcending one’s own being-situated, obviously with a varying
degree of success. If, however, we realize that, for example, scholarly journals and
academic research projects often arise from conferences, it is clear that conferences
are nodal points in the development of discursive and argumentative networks. They
not only open up new spaces, they also organize and structure them.
At the same time, they are only one type of nodal point within discursive space:
discourses not only conflict with each other, very often they remain simply independent from each other or are only connected in indirect ways. And there are many
such nodal points and networks. A hypothesis that follows from these considerations
is that we may already be in the process of genesis of a European discursive space,
without necessarily being aware of it (i.e., the process does not depend on our awareness of it, even though it does make a difference). This space is filled with a multitude of discourses, but it is not a unitary space that can be surveyed from a vantage
point outside it. One consequence of this is that the exploration of this European discursive space necessarily involves “hermeneutics”, since the meaning of discourse is
never given without its context. However, the fact that discursive space is never harmonious has the further consequence that participants – those who generate discourse
and those at whom it is addressed in a given context – do not have an exclusive right
to determine the meaning of discourse. One and the same speech, for example, can
both express the cultural heritage of a particular people and violate the rights to cultural expression of an ethnic minority, irrespective of whether it is meant to do so. To
be sure, this is not an argument in favour of relativism: participants can and should
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
13
always broaden the horizon of understanding both their own and others’ discourse,
even if this understanding never becomes “perfect”.
4. Reflexivity and identity
The notion of discursive space leads to the question, from which position this paper
then is written? This is not an irrelevant question, if discourse about “Europe” by
Europeans is a part of Europe. To be sure, this does not imply a “partisan” position;
it rather implies a reflexive one: it means to be aware of the practical dimension of
intellectual discussion. I cannot and ought not deny that I speak and write from the
relatively comfortable and safe position of an academic, from one of the members
of the “first generation” European community (Benelux and European Community
of Coal and Steel). My position thus is an established European one. When asked to
define my own approach, I would describe it as a reflexive realism that, in a world
full of idealizing and simplifying discursive constructions, out of necessity includes
deconstruction as a political ideal (this, however, is a specific and not a neutral position). The aim of deconstruction, it should be noted, is not destruction or cantankerousness, but the making available of construction elements for new constructions. To
give an example: it is not destructive, but constructive to analyze the contradictions,
contained in frequently heard expressions like “What kind of Europe do we want?”
because they wrongly suggest that “Europe” is something like a given object of possible volitions and because it, wrongly again, suggests that there already is such a
“we”, while in fact this “we” would precisely have to be the outcome of a particular
kind of yet-to-emerge Europe. As Claudia Wiesner rightly states, a “European identity”, and the European dèmos that it defines, are conditions, but not pre-conditions
of European democratization (Wiesner 2007: 35–38). There thus is an unwarranted
“jump”, contained in the “we” of the question itself – and this is what makes such
questions ideological (see above, 1.v). However, once thus deconstructed, we can use
the same question to point out that, by posing the question and trying to answer it,
a particular kind of Europe is already being made, irrespective of what “we” want.
In asserting, then, that European society is not the object of a given collective subject, one contributes – I contribute, in this case – to the coming-to-be of Europe as a
subjective-objective reality. This is a reflexive realization of what is going on.
The critical focus on this and similar questions is, more generally, a part of an attempt to understand from a participant’s perspective the reality of European – my, our
reality, the reality of this discursive community (conference audience, author-cumreaders) as part of Europe. It does make sense to ask, for example, how far Europe
extends culturally or “civilizationally”; it does make sense to relate this question to
such questions as to whether Turkey, Tunisia or Ukraine should or should not at some
point be accepted as members; and it does make sense to link this question to a
discussion about the parameters of European identity. Just as it does make sense,
obviously, what kind of immigration policy, Human Rights policy or environmental policy we, European citizens, prefer. But it is more relevant from a philosophi-
14
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
cal point of view to realize that “Europe” is precisely the discursive space in which
these questions are being posed in the first place and in which, by trying to “find out”
what this notorious “European identity” is that we allegedly “have”, we identify as
Europeans. In other words: it is also by disagreeing about such issues, that “we” takes
shape, which implies that the identity of this “we” is not homogeneous but heterogeneous and conflict-ridden.
If identity is not a pre-given “thing” that can be “found” or discovered, but a
construction that stems from processes of self-identification and other-identification
(Mouffe 2005: 25–29; Laclau, Zac 1994: 31–35), i.e. something that is performative
rather than empirical, then it is the joint-yet-differentiated search for such an identity which is the very “identity” and which generates the “imagined community”
(Anderson 2006) that “shares” this identity. Put more radically: to ask “Who are we?”
or “Which identity do we have?” is not to embark on a quest or to announce a discovery, but to establish oneself as a self-constituting subject seeking community with
others. An important consequence of this discussion is that “European” as an identity is a matter not of empirical survey or historical analysis, but of essentially failing
self-identification, failing in the sense that the result is never something objectively
there, but something actively and inter-subjectively constituted and re-produced.
5. Identity and energy
If identity is not something that can be “found” (and hence every claim to have found
it necessarily is ideological), it is, curiously, not something that can be made either
(and hence every proposal to “construct” it is a badly concealed form of domination over public discourse). The question is not whether “identity” can or should be
“fixed” or “fluid”. The question has to do with the nature of what should be fixed or
fluid. A possible paradigm from which this issue can be addressed, and which avoids
both an essentialism that suggests a pre-existing core in every individual as well as
a radical constructivism that fails to do justice to the attachment of people to “who
they are”, is a perception of human beings as, primarily, bundles of energy, existing
for a certain stretch of time and moving and acting in a series of more or less stable
situations (their stability – negentropy – partly depends on themselves). One of the
characteristics of such bundles of energy is their self-organization and their attempt
to preserve themselves in whatever environment they find themselves. One of these
environments is society, and a part of it is discursive space: in the interaction with
others, each individual must in order to survive develop a “core” which, on the one
hand, generates stability, but, on the other hand, has to have a considerable degree of
flexibility; the outcome is what we usually call a “self”.
As we all know, both the “mix” of stability and flexibility and the amount of energy it takes to reproduce and, eventually, adapt this mix, varies strongly from one
individual to the other. In addition, individuals are not simply “selves”, but relate to
themselves as selves, i.e. they have their own self and that of others before them as
objects that they can study, love, influence etc. From this angle, “identity” can be
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
15
conceived as the shortest description of a “self”. If we assume that in order to exist and interact with others people need an “identity” and if we further assume that
this “identity” is neither pre-given nor ready-made, then what follows is the general
hypothesis that “identity” comes into being and is acted upon in a process of mutual
self-identification, i.e. of self-identification that can take the form of a quest for “what
one really is” and other-identification that works as a “constitutive outside” (Mouffe
2005: 15) for one’s own identity. And this process can take place under more or less
free conditions: under some conditions it can end up in a celebration of difference
for the sake of difference, under other conditions it can lead to the establishment of
a national enemy, or even a external scapegoat such as the one yielded by the fabricated Jewish-Masonic Protocols of the Elders of Zion, in order to establish oneself
as a “we”.
6. European identity – whose job?
The question about European identity (the assumption behind this question being that
such an identity is important for Europe in order to be as much of a selfpreserving
political community as is needed in the present-day world) is, in light of the above
considerations, complicated by the fact that European identity consists of a mixture
of at least three elements: a number of (a) national identities (to be more precise: conglomerates of discourses that generate and reproduce “national identities”); (b) a rather high-brow intellectual tradition of “thinking about Europe” that works towards a
cultural European identity; (c) EU-fostered political and social scientific projects that
try to yield building blocks for the construction of a civil European identity. The distinction between these three elements, obviously, is analytical rather than empirical,
but it helps to point to a number of problems:
1. the opposition between (a) and (b) explains much of the widespread perception of
Europe as something of and for an intellectual and political elite – what Markku
Kangaspuro labels a “new European nobility” (Kangaspuro 2007: 11);
2. the difference between (a), (b) and (c) serves to explain the anxiety of intellectuals that their ideas may be politicized: a case in point is the notion of Leitkultur
elaborated by Bassam Tibi (belonging to (b)) – much to his surprise and dislike
(Tibi 2002: XIIff), it was quickly “usurped” by, on the one hand, nationalist
agenda’s in Germany, the Netherlands and elsewhere (a) and, on the other hand,
the EU (c) which tries to foster something like a European Leitkultur of which
Don Quixote, Copernicus and Sherlock Holmes might be constitutive elements;
3. the difference between (a) and (c) reflects what seems to be one of the biggest
problem of Europe today: the persistence and indeed growing presence of national discourses, national governments and national “interests” while their so cioeconomic and political importance decreases. To my mind, this is an example
of an ideology that articulates, in a compensatory manner, the opposite of social
reality (see 1.v);
16
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
4. the difference between b) and a) points to a tension between a free discussion, the
outcome of which could, in principle, be that there is no given European identity
and a goal-oriented discussion, the aim of which is to contribute to the coming-tobe of a European identity. My preliminary conclusion with respect to this situation
is that: (c) the EU should hold back in this matter, (b) intellectuals should realize
that their discussion is a part of the identity (Europe as a discursive tradition) and
(a) national identity discourse should be given time to wither away. My not so
preliminary thesis is that if identity becomes an object of political preferences and
priorities, it becomes ideology (a)/(c), while if it becomes the object of philosophical debate, it deconstructs itself (b).
7. European identity is what it is not!
Given these considerations, one may wonder what, then, could be positive sources of a
European identity that does not fall prey to the afore-mentioned pitfalls (see 5). First of
all, it would have to be based on a clear understanding of what identity as a discursive
entity is – the question is not what is Polish identity (or any other), but what is “Polish
identity” (see above 4 and 5). Secondly, it would have to be reflexive, i.e. acknowledge that the very discourse is part of the identity – it is part of what it means to be
European to approach such issues as a matter of discussion (rather than, for example,
indoctrination, educational programs or other state policies). Thirdly, it would have to
define itself in terms of its constitutive outsides. In an attempt to do this (engaging,
that is, in what is pointed at in 6.b) and referring back to a habitual list of factors, that
can form the identity of a polity’s “nation”, viz. shared, language, religion, ethnicity,
political goals and history, I suggest the following elements.
i. With its present 23 official languages and 3 working languages, plus a large number
of regional languages that claim their rights, the EU does not appear in a position
to claim a language-based identity, even though Europe has the shared memory of
Latin as a lingua franca, and even though a “reduced” form of English is quickly becoming the second language of most Europeans (this shift is remarkable not
only in Central and Eastern Europe, but also in, for example, France). To the extent to which the EU as a polity affirms itself and to the extent to which, within
that setting – the setting of borders – economic and social, including demographic,
integration takes place, English is bound to become the new lingua franca, especially of the “new European nobility” (Kangaspuro). But Étienne Balibar is right, I
think, to claim that English will not be “la ‘langue de l’Europe’” because, on the
one hand, it is a global lingua franca that exceeds Europe and, on the other hand,
it does not replace the existing multitude of languages (Balibar 2001: 318)7. MORE
IMPORTANT, therefore, and relevant as a constitutive outside, is the rejected notion of mono-linguality: the point is not that any European should stop speaking
7
Referring to Umberto Eco, Balibar suggests that the language of Europe is “la traduction (ou si l’on veut la
métalangue concrète faite de toutes les équivalences et de toutes tentatives pour surmonter ‘l’intraduisible’
entre les idiomes)…” (loc.cit.).
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
17
her or his native language, but that speaking only one language means to enclose
oneself in an imagined polity, the “nation-state” that, in socio-economic and political terms, already is a thing of the past. To be European means to speak with
other people in another language than your native one without identifying them
as foreigners, but it also means to recognize that no single language can lay claim
to being the European language. The empirical fact that English is assuming this
role not only is a matter of pragmatism rather than of political domination, but also
goes along with an impoverishing of that language itself (reduction of its idiomatic
character, for example) that is, though in reverse direction, not incomparable with
the splitting off of classical Latin from the forms of vulgar Latin that later became
vernaculars. To be European thus means to give priority to communication over
vernacular and it means to be bi- or multi-lingual.
ii. Religion, it seems to me, is not a viable element of a European identity either,
because of the plurality and variety of religions in Europe’s past and present:
Christianity in its three major forms (Orthodoxy, Catholicism, Protestantism) and
many sub-forms, including new evangelical movements, Judaism, Islam, and a variety of more or less religious world views such as Freemasonry, Anthroposophy,
etc. MORE IMPORTANT and relevant as a constitutive outside is rejected monoreligiosity either as the idea that Europe as a whole should have a single religion
(which could then only be a re-unified Christianity), or as the idea that parts of
Europe should have a national religion (Poland as Roman Catholic by nature,
Romania and Greece as Orthodox, etc.) (van der Zweerde 2003, 2005). To be
European thus means to acknowledge and defend that no “religion” can lay claim
to a public impact that goes beyond the actual size and weight of its community of
faithful.
iii. Ethnicity can even less serve as a common denominator than religion: to identify,
e.g., Europe with Indo-Germanic or Indo-European ethnicity not only implies the
exclusion of the substantial numbers of immigrants in most European countries as
well as the “mixed offspring”, that results from their presence (and increasingly
will), but also of such traditionally European ethnic groups such as the Finns or
the Magyars. MORE IMPORTANT, again, and relevant as a constitutive outside,
is the rejected idea of mono-ethnicity as a relevant political factor, an idea that has
manifested itself in European history many times: in World War II, of course, but
also in the ethnic cleansing campaigns in parts of former Yugoslavia and in the attitude towards Roma in some European countries. To be European thus means to
reject the idea of ethnic purity.
iv. Political goals. The idea of a political community on the basis of shared political
goals rather than religious, ethnic or linguistic factors (which, broadly speaking,
was the agenda of Romantic counter-Enlightenment) has come most typically to
the fore during and after the French Revolution of 1789, but is also present, for
example, in the Confoederatio Helvetica. Interestingly, it there includes the right
of religiously, ethnically and linguistically relatively homogeneous communities to
retain a large degree of autonomy. While it is clear that Europeans generally share
18
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
a number of political convictions that can, roughly, be said to form the basis of
the constitutional liberal democracy including Human Rights, which, in local variants, is the reality of most European countries (and, obviously, a condition for EU
membership), it is also clear that a Habermasian Verfassungspatriottismus, which
would build a European identity on the basis of these convictions, is too meagre
and too rational. Moreover, Europe is still home to a broad spectrum of conceptions of political and socio-economic justice. MORE IMPORTANT, therefore, is
the protest of Europeans against any monopoly on the interpretation of justice and,
against forms of injustice including Human Rights violations, privileges, brute use
of power, arbitrary decisions and systematic exclusion of individuals and groups,
not only in those cases when they themselves are victims of it, but also when this
affects others, including their political adversaries or people who are not their cocitizens. It is not accidental that the actual violations of Human Rights, particularly
of immigrants who yet have to be qualified as illegal, but have no way of protesting against that verdict, have to be hidden from public attention. To be European
thus means to have a historically informed sensitivity to injustice.
v. History is often pointed at as a factor that unites Europeans around a shared identity. In fact, the four elements just discussed can only be understood against the
background of the history that Europeans share. However, it seems clear to me not
only that this “shared” history must include the colonial pasts of many European
countries (José Casanova)8 and, obviously, many other black pages, but also that
this history is perceived differently and, fundamentally so, from one European
country to another. Out of the many possible examples I give only three: the perception by Czechs and Russians of the events of 1968, the perception by victims
and perpetrators of the occupation of European countries (Poland, but also France
or the Netherlands) by Nazi Germany, and the perception by Croatians, Bosnians
and Serbs of the war in former Yugoslavia. It usually suffices to cast a quick glance
into locally used history school books to get an idea. What Europeans thus have
in common, is not a single shared history, but the presence of a multitude of often
diametrically opposed narratives of their past: this profound difference of opinion
is a vital part of their Schicksalsgemeinschaft. One problem, it seems to me, is that
while this is easy to assess at the level of intellectual debate (see 6.b above), it is
rejected as not only potentially, but indeed actually undermining national identity
(6.a) and attempts to work towards a common perception (6.c) will invariably strike
as artificial. The only real “remedy” to this problem is of course historical time itself, but it can be assisted by the attempts, within that time, by historians to write
a history of Europe (e.g. Davies 1997) rather than of a multitude of Fatherlands,
and it can be fostered by, for example, educational projects that compare history
school books. Still, it would and ought to be an illusion to think that one happy
day all children in all schools in all European countries would be using the same
8
José Casanova pointed this out in a yet unpublished paper at a conference, “Politik, Religion und Markt: die
Rückkehr der Religion als Anfrage an den politisch-philosophischen Diskurs der Moderne”, in Innsbruck,
Austria, 5–7 June 2008.
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
19
history book. MORE IMPORTANT, therefore, and relevant as a constitutive outside,
is the rejected idea of a mono-logical account of history be it national or European.
To be European thus means, among others, to be aware of the fact that, for example,
Frenchmen and Germans have a different perception of the Vichy regime just like
Germans, Poles, Jews, and Roma have different perceptions of Oswięcim/Auschwitz.
8. A “weak” identity
What unites these five items, first of all, is something that arguably is a part of the
“core” of a European identity: the acceptance of plurality and the non-acceptance of
this plurality as a ground for discord. As Hermann Lübbe stated, “das Hauptcharakteristikum europäischer Identität, kulturelle und politische Vielfalt namentlich in engen
Räumen, wird im Rahmen der einheitsstiftenden erweiterten Union noch aufdringlicher sein als bisher” (Lübbe 2001: 222). To be sure, it is always possible to undo
plurality, either by forced assimilation or by some form of “homogenization”, but one
of the effects of the sheer size of the EU is, it seems to me, that no single ethnic or
religious group will be in a position to impose such a policy (just like, at the political level, the possibility of the domination of European politics by one or a few large
members – in the recent past: the axis Bonn-Paris – becomes less likely with each
new member). All this leads to the “proposal” of a European slogan that does not, as
is the case now, point to “Unity in Diversity”/“Einheit in der Vielfalt”, but to Plurality
in Unity.
A second common dominator of these five items is their “negativity”. They are
more easily formulated in terms of what distinguishes them from their constitutive
outside, i.e. from what they are not, than in terms of what they are positively. This
negativity is, I think, very important, because to realize it fully is to become skeptical
of attempts by European authorities to work constructively at the creation of a positive
identity (6.c). The resistance that such attempts meet with – this resistance is another
feature that Europeans have in common – is explicable not only in terms of the content of such identity, but also of the artificial nature of the very attempt.
A third element that the five elements have in common, related to the negativity just alluded to, is the fact that each of them draws a line or points to a limit. If
Europe’s political borders are primarily meant not to keep the citizens in, but to limit
and control the access of “foreigners”, the lines drawn by the potentially constitutive elements of a European identity just outlined are also meant to keep something
out: nationally motivated monolingualism, unwarranted claims by religious communities and organizations, ethnic purification or homogenization, monopoly on justice
and a mono-logic historical narrative. This is important, it seems to me, because this
makes it much easier to combine European and national identity, something that many
Europeans continue to attach great value to. As surveys indicate, the vast majority of
Europeans either consider themselves to have only a national identity or a national
plus European identity – the two categories cover well over 80% in most countries –
while minorities around 10% claim a European plus national identity and very small
20
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
numbers “only European” (Buonanno, Deakin 2004: 87). This does not necessarily
pose a problem: if “national” and “European” are not perceived as mutually exclusive
identities, they are compatible (Wiesner 2007: 42–46) – though not necessarily in a
harmonious manner.
On the whole and for the reasons just indicated, I venture the hypothesis that a
European identity must be a weak and primarily “negative” identity, marked more
by its constitutive outsides than by its “positive” elements. Understanding this reflexively, I suggest, that to write about European identity in this manner and to discuss
the borders of Europe is to take part in the shaping of a European identity already. It
is, to return to a notion discussed above (under 4), one way of organizing one’s intellectual energy around a core. The answer to the question “What does it mean to be
a European?” is not primarily found in theoretical deliberations but in practices and
in ways of doing – it is, to put it in Hegelian terms, more a matter of Sittlichkeit than
of Moralität. A typical, much less high-brow example of this is the remarkable fact
that though attempts to build a European identity around such things as an anthem9,
a flag and other symbols may have failed due to artificiality (Neumann 2007: 24), the
European flag gains “identity potential” when it is used elsewhere, e.g. in the USA
or in Russia, and the everyday use of the euro as the EU’s currency has a clear, longterm effect on the “sense” of Europeans – a generation is taking shape that thinks
European in terms of what they have in their pockets.
9. No civilizationalism!
From this attempt at a delineation of a “weak” European identity (under 6–8), a critique can be derived of the Huntingtonian paradigm. It can be summarized by the
thesis that Europe does not possess – or is covered by – a single civilization and that
this constitutes not its weakness, but its strength. This is not to say, that Samuel Huntington did not have a point: his conception does point to tensions, and even if they
are more complex than his idea of fault lines between civilizations suggests, such fault
lines can be found. However, there are at least three good reasons against a simplified
application of his civilizational paradigm to Europe:
It suggests more homogeneity than is actually in place: not only is Europe as a
whole a multi-ethnic, multi-religious and multi-lingual cultural space that includes,
e.g., Russia, Belarus, Ukraine and Turkey, but also the predominant European polity, the EU, contains countries with a predominantly Catholic, Protestant or Orthodox
religious tradition, and it will contain in the foreseeable future, at least one predominantly Muslim country (Bosnia-Herzegovina), it includes highly “secularized” as well
as highly traditionally Christian countries. There is not a fault line running across
Europe, but Europe is built on a plurality of “inner fault lines”.
9
For a hilariously funny analysis of the EU anthem, the “Ode to Joy” in Ludwig van Beethoven’s 9 th
phony, including the role of the marcia Turca, see Slavoj Žižek 2008, p. 270–274.
Sym-
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
21
It puts civilization before culture, thus suggesting a level of objectivity that is not
matched by the cultural process that takes place within any society, and that stems
from the fact that society is as much a self-constituting subject as it is an “object”.
There are, of course, objective sides to every society but they derive their meaning
and the possibility of their future changes from the fact that the members of that society, from average citizens to politicians, relate to these objective sides – culture is
a general name for the way in which people relate actively to the circumstances and
realities they find themselves surrounded by.
Ideas have the capacity to be working ideas (Moтрошилова 1991: 6), a fact which
explains why intellectuals can try to develop ideas that have an impact on social reality. Huntington’s idea of civilizations and of fault lines is an example of this because,
rather than being an objective, empirical description of social facts, it is a discursively embedded concept which, if accepted, tends to work as a self-fulfilling prophecy.
Huntington’s later book, Who are we?, which is an attempt to delineate (draw limits!)
American identity, leaves a little doubt as to his culture-political agenda (Huntington
2004: 8–12, and passim). A single intellectual, with respect to these formative issues,
who is claiming “This is how it is!” has already changed “how it is”.
10. No neutrality!
It follows from this last example, that, at least in the social sciences and the humanities, scientific research and academic discussion are never politically neutral or innocent. To do research in a seemingly neutral manner is therefore either to run away
from responsibility or to engage in ideology, i.e. to make a concealed political move.
To be European, for example, means to be aware of the inner potentialities of Europe’s
cultural and intellectual heritage – including totalitarianism that has seduced grand
thinkers like Martin Heidegger, Jean Paul Sartre, György Lukács, Carl Schmitt and
Giovanni Gentile. Without denying the specific responsibility and guilt on some parts,
we can safely state that all European nations have struggled or are still struggling,
with their 20th century past. If this is true, what Europeans have in common, is not
only the experience of a nasty, brutish and short 20th century (Eric Hobsbawm), but
also the recognized necessity to come to terms with it, to engage in Vergangenheitsbewältigung. Even if they have succeeded in this to varying degrees, one can argue
that the readiness to come to terms with the less appealing parts of one’s history without putting the blame exclusively on “the Other” is a positive part of the European
heritage. The pressure on Turkey to recognize the Armenian genocide is, I believe,
more important precisely in the sense of a requirement to an open, enlightened society
to deal with its past, than in the sense of a recognition of a particular guilt. Within
Europe, Germany has been exemplary in this respect, which appears, for example,
from the stark contrast between German Wiedergutmachung with respect to Poland
or to Jewry, and the position post-Soviet Russia takes with respect to the systematic
destruction, during roughly 40 years, of the economies and civil societies of Poland or
Hungary, not to mention Lithuania or Estonia. This, arguably, disqualifies Russia as a
22
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
European country on precisely this point. What is at stake, in the process of coming to
terms with Europe’s past is not the answer to the question “Who is to blame?”, but the
communicative process of the coming-to-terms itself, the coming-to-be of a reflexive
community. This community, paradoxically, is stronger if it does not arrive at a single
answer. The German Historikerstreit thus is a more significant contribution to a European discursive space when it ends undecided than if it is solved.
The fact that Europeans, for more than half a century, have asked themselves and
each other which have been the real causes of the tragedies that soaked Europe in
blood, without finding a clear-cut answer to this question, is not a failure but, paradoxically, a success. This implies that intellectual responsibility is a matter of drawing clear lines: we, Europeans may not know who we are or what we want, but we do
know very well what we are not and what we do not want.
11. Back to citizenship: instead of the conclusions
What is needed today is a political philosophy that matches European realities
rather than fears and dreams. Neither a mere philosophy “about politics”10, nor
one that designs ideal models, but one that invokes and revives the direct link between philosophy and politics, that has been constitutive ever since Plato and Aristotle – and, not to be forgotten, Democritus. Too often is European philosophy
determined either by wishful thinking about a common European Schicksalsge meinschaft or by fearful thinking about the loss of political autonomy and cultural
identity. Those who, like Jacques Derrida, dared to think beyond the boundaries of
their national tradition, often jumped to a cosmopolitanism that does retain large parts
of the European intellectual legacy, esp. of Kantian Enlightenment, but loses sight
of the complex socio-economic and political reality that is Europe. As a result, this
cosmopolitanism often ends in fruitless repetitive discussions about whether or not
Kantian “eternal peace” is a real possibility or not. My suggestion is that a focus on
the European polity is a way out of this dead-lock: we can make better sense of the
idea of cosmopolitan citizenship, if the EU makes it a stated goal of its foreign policy,
that every world inhabitant should be citizen of a polity which is based on a rule of
law and that has Human Rights, included in its bill of civil rights. The number of
such polities then is a different issue; one that can but must not be the focus of our
concern. It is imaginable that, in the very long run, the whole world will become
“Europe”, just as it once was “America”. In that case Immanuel Kant’s rationalist dream would get close to coming true. It is more likely, however, that, for a
long time to come, Europe will be one among a plurality of larger and smaller
polities – among which it will be one of the larger and more powerful blocks.
To be such a polity it requires not, I venture, the fixation of an identity or the selfsatisfactory celebration of a civilization, but the drawing of borders, contestable and
10
Here and elsewhere, I employ a triple definition of political philosophy: philosophy of politics, philosophy of
the political and philosophy, that realizes its own political nature – here I have in mind, primarily, the third
meaning.
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
23
liable to future change, but clear-cut as borders in order to create the space in which,
among others, discussion about European culture, civilization, identity, and politics
can continue and “flourish”.
What we need to be concerned about most of all is the inside of the European
polity. The “political state of Europe” is a hybrid mixture of “old” nation-states
and a trans-national juridical-political structure that has partly replaced them. Also,
this political state of Europe is markedly less democratic than the nation-states that
form it: to the extent to which the trans-national European “state” holds real political power (and it does through legislation, regulation, European Court for Human
Rights etc.), its “democratic deficit” means a net loss of democratic control, even if
it is “the best developed example of a democratically organized political entity on
a transnational level” (Wiesner 2007: 38). If it is true that, on the one hand, many
current social, economic and environmental problems require European rather than
local solutions – think of labour market, drugs policies, immigration, emancipation of minorities, the financial crisis of 2008 – and the ideal of political power, as
opposed to social and economic power, requires more rather than less state capacity at EU level; and on the other hand, national governments for obvious reasons
tend to focus on national rather than on common European interests; then it is clear
that a more active European citizenship is required. There is nothing new about the
transition from the status of subject – which Europeans all are – to that of citizen
which, formally at least, we also are. But there is something crucially new about
shifting active citizenship from the national to the European level, giving rise to
European public space, European civil society etc. Policies and discourse that seek
to foster such developments by reference to a shared European identity forget one
thing: every society is divided in itself, and contains antagonistic relations between
different social, economic, cultural etc. groups. Every polity, therefore, must somehow address these antagonisms by suppressing, canalizing or transposing them to
the political arena. Every democratic society is disharmonious by nature, if and
because it succeeds in transforming all forms of societal antagonism into agonistic
political struggle. Therefore, a European “civil identity” that is to match European
societal reality, will not be a unitary and homogeneous identity that is supplementary to a national identity, the homogeneous identity of which is just as illusionary.
On the contrary, such an “identity” will be heterogeneous and diverse; it will cover
a plurality of perceptions, preferences, and ideals. It will be plural, not as a first step
towards unity, but in its core, and it will be divided, but not along national lines. If
they want to make a difference to the European reality that already is their socioeconomic, intellectual and cultural environment, Europeans will have to transpose
their political ideals to a European public sphere and European political arena that
comes into existence, albeit not with immediate visibility, in and through the very
process of transposing.
24
Evert van der Zweerde. “Plurality in Unity”: European Identity and European Citizenship
References
Anderson, B. 2006. Imagined Communities. London and New York: Verso.
Balibar, É. 2001. Nous, citoyens d’Europe? Paris: Éditions la découverte.
Buonanno, L.; Deakin, A. 2004. “European Identity”, in N. Nugent (Ed.). European Union Enlargement. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 84–102.
Davies, N. 1997. Europe – A History. London: Pimlico.
Giddens, A. 1993. Runaway World: How Globalisation is Reshaping Our Lives. London: Profile
Books.
Huntington, S. P. 2004. Who Are We? The Challenges to America’s National Identity. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Kangaspuro, M. 2007. “Introduction”, in M. Kangaspuro (Ed.). Constructed Identities in Europe.
Helsinki: Aleksanteri Institute, 7–16.
Laclau, E.; Zac, L. 1994. “Minding the Gap: The Subject of Politics”, in E. Laclau (Ed.). The
Making of Political Identities. London and New York: Verso, 11–39.
Lübbe, H. 2001. Politik nach der Aufklärung. München: Fink.
Luhmann, N. 2000. Die Politik der Gesellschaft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Luhmann, N. 1997. Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Mouffe, C. 2005. On the Political. London and New York: Routledge.
Neumann, I. B. 2007. “European Identity and Its Changing Others”, in M. Kangaspuro (Ed.).
Constructed Identities in Europe. Helsinki: Aleksanteri Institute, 17–32.
Rogowski, R.; Turner, Ch. 2006. “Europe: Law, Politics, History, Culture”, in R. Rogowski,
Ch. Turner (Eds.). The Shape of the New Europe, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1–22.
Tibi, B. 2002. Europa ohne Identität? Leitkultur oder Wertebeliebigkeit (aktualisierte Taschenbuchausgabe). München: Bertelsmann.
Tilly, C. 2007. Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wiesner, C. 2007. “European Identity and Its Relation to EU Democratisation: Normative and
Methodological Considerations”, in M. Kangaspuro (Ed.). Constructed Identities in Europe. Helsinki: Aleksanteri Institute, 33–48.
Young, I. M. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford University Press.
Zweerde van der, E. 2003. “Europe – A Christian Super-Nation in a Globalizing World?”, in
J. Sutton, W. van der Bercken (Ed.). Orthodox Christianity and Contemporary Europe. Leuven:
Peeters, 145–162.
Zweerde van der, E. 2005. “All Europeans are Equal... But Aren’t Some Less European than
Others? Reflections on Europe and Orthodox Christianity”, Journal of Eastern Christian Studies
57(3–4): 257–289.
Žižek, S. 2008. In Defense of Lost Causes. London and New York: Verso.
Moтрошилова, Н. В. 1991. Рождение и развитие философских идей. Moсква: Политиздат.
LIMES, 2009, Vol. 2, No. 1: 5–25
VIENINGUMO PLIURALUMAS: EUROPIETIŠKASIS TAPATUMAS IR
EUROPIETIŠKASIS PILIETIŠKUMAS
Evert van der Zweerde
Santrauka
Tolesnė „Europos“ integracija ir svarbiausia – vis dažnesnės „politinės diskusijos“ šia tema yra remiamos ir skatinamos. Vadovaujamasi ne romantine ar
idealistine pozityvaus europietiškojo tapatumo vizija, bet Europos ekonominės,
socialinės ir ekologinės integracijos vertinimu bei požiūriu, esą ji politiškai atsilieka demokratinio valdymo ir pilietiškumo atžvilgiais. Tariamai nesibaigiančios diskusijos Europos tapatumo, ribų, vieningumo, civilizacijos ir panašiais
klausimais nėra ta problema, kuri jau turi būti išspręsta, bet iš esmės sudaro tokios Europos, kokia ji yra, pagrindą: vieningumo pliuralumas vietoj „pliuralumo vieningumo“, kaip skelbia vienas iš oficialių Europos Są jungos (ES) lozungų. Nūdienės socialinės, ekonominės ir aplinkosaugos problemos reikalauja europietiškų sprendimų ir kur kas aktyvesnio europietiškojo pilietiškumo. Tačiau
norint, kad europietiškasis pilietinis tapatumas atitiktų europietišką ją socialinę
tikrovę, jis neturi būti bendras ir homogeniškas, bet, atvirkščiai, heterogeniškas
ir įvairialypis, apimantis daugelį suvokimo perspektyvų, privilegijų ir idealų.
Jis turi būti pliuralus, bet ne kaip pirmas žingsnis vieningumo link; jis turi būti
iš esmės dalus, tačiau ne pagal valstybių sienas.
Reikšminiai žodžiai: pilietiškumas, „civilizacionalizmas“, diskursyvi erdvė,
europietiškoji integracija, tapatumas, pliuralumas.
Received 10 February 2009, accepted 30 March 2009
25