33
Technology
Richard Iveson
Introducing Extremes
D
ramatic technological innovations in the fields of genetic and genomic
engineering are today producing sites and bodies of unforeseen indistinction that
render untenable every distinction between ‘living’ beings and ‘non-living’ objects.
As they inevitably emerge as arenas of intense political and ethical contestation, the
urgency of the questions they raise calls for critical interrogation from all across the
Humanities. These questions are particularly pressing for scholars of animal studies,
however, as not only are they likely to set both the agenda and the limits of the field
in the future, but also quite possibly determine whether ‘animal studies’ in fact even
has a future, at least in its current incarnation. Here, it will be argued that innovative technologies provoke a very different kind of question for animal studies than is
generally taken to be the case, one that reveals the entire field to be in need of radical
reconfiguration.
Key to this is a concern that perhaps produces more anxiety across the political
and religious spectrums than any other: that technological innovation, in trespassing
ever more explicitly upon the realm of the gods, ultimately promises only the collapse
of civilisation itself. Examples of this anxiety can be found in the prevalence of technological dystopias and the recent resurrection to popular consciousness of the longdead zombie genre, as well as our increasing fascination with millenarian religious
fundamentalisms of all kinds. At the heart of this is the fear that very soon it will no
longer be possible to maintain a secure ontological division between living beings
and technological artefacts – an operative distinction that serves as the foundation of
our traditional discourses of morality and law. Indeed, it is the struggle of the moral
few to endure amid surroundings of utter lawlessness and senseless destruction that
typically drives narratives of imminent apocalypse and technological dystopia today.1
However, it will be argued here that all such polemics of fear are based upon a
single fundamental error: the failure to understand that a secure distinction between
living beings and non-living things never has existed and never will exist. Moreover,
we must consequently reconsider our basic assumption that, when dealing with ‘mere’
objects, future effects can be unerringly predicted in the present on the basis of simple
relations of cause and effect.
For a number of reasons, extremophiles provide the key examples of the kinds of
bodyings who occupy this indistinct zone at the intersection of life and matter. Consequently, to think with extremophiles is to radically resituate the place of ethics today
and tomorrow. Moreover, to resituate the ethical domain in this way is necessarily to
5628_Turner.indd 504
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
505
refuse to accommodate the innumerable atrocities being committed right now upon
billions of ‘mere’ animals and, as such, opens an entirely new direction in animal studies bringing unforeseen possibilities of future engagement. In having shown themselves
to be wildly unpredictable, extremophiles explicitly contest our habitual conceptions
of nature and objecthood – the very same conceptions, as we shall see, which would
otherwise serve to ground their own exploitation. Finally, I will argue, thinking with
extremophiles shows how through the evolution of technology itself the priority of
its own ethical dimension is ultimately revealed, as too is the central role played by
technological artefacts in what amounts to nothing less than the collapse of all ethical
programmes hitherto.
Before any of that, however, let us briefly consider just who, or what, constitutes an
extremophile. First discovered in the late-1970s, at its simplest the term ‘extremophile’
refers to any entity capable of thriving within an environment previously thought too
extreme to support life – environments of extreme temperature or pressure, for example, or consisting of drastic concentrations of salt or toxic gases, or with high levels of
atomic radiation, or environments that are strongly acidic or alkaline. Put more succinctly, however, ‘extremophile’ names the vast set of entities capable of synthesising
self-protective extremolytes – a definition that reveals the apparent ‘extremeness’ of
extremophiles as nothing more than an effect of anthropocentric perspective.
Obtaining necessary nourishment from chemical gradients rather than sunlight
and calorific food, extremophiles utterly transform our conceptions of life and being,
and thus their importance for contemporary accounts of ontology, temporality, evolution and causality cannot be overstated.2 Not least, these miracles of survival bear
almost limitless biotechnological potential within their coded forms of matter, promising any number of genetically based applications and processes that would bring
huge medical, military and industrial profit in the future.3 Embodying a fundamental
indiscipline, however, extremophiles also promise something very different: namely,
a material promise to exceed all bounds of control. As such, not only are extremophiles both archetype and telos of the cyborg as identified by Donna Haraway in
her hugely influential ‘Manifesto for Cyborgs’,4 but they also serve as perfect placeholders for other non-human animals generally. In other words, while the following
chapter is principally concerned with the evolution of technological artefacts into the
future, this is by no means to assume that the situation today is therefore ethically
acceptable.
It is generally accepted that extremophiles are living beings. However, their ontological status is far less clear once they are displaced to the discipline of the laboratory
and thus incorporated within the narrative that ‘Science’ constructs for itself. Moreover, this ontological uncertainty is further intensified by the fact that extremophiles
today are largely being suborned as the material building blocks of a human future
perceived beyond our biological truths. To this end, staggering sums of money and
time are being spent on experiments aimed at the reverse bioengineering of extremophiles and their subsequent fabrication from whole cloth within the laboratory in the
hope, among other things, of dissolving the various planetary restrictions that today
somewhat hamstring the continuing expansion of capitalism.5
Paradoxically, however, these experiments can only ever be justified on the basis
of an absolute distinction between ‘living’ beings and ‘non-living’ objects. In other
words, the legitimacy that allows for the fabrication of just these technological entities
5628_Turner.indd 505
16/10/17 6:02 PM
506
richard iveson
is founded upon contradictory premises: namely, that extremophiles are both singular
forms of life and simple mechanisms indistinguishable from clockwork mice. Moreover, this inconsistency is absolutely necessary, insofar as it is only this fundamental
contradiction that allows such experiments to conveniently sidestep the issue of ethics
altogether. In other words, it is only insofar as extremophiles are objects, and therefore not ‘living’ entities, that scientists are able to assume that their acts of today
can be unerringly predicted into the future in accordance with simple calculations
of restricted cause and effect. The risk of experiments aimed at fully exploiting their
potential value as singular forms of life can, in short, only ever be ethically justified on
condition that extremophiles are simultaneously simple, lifeless mechanisms.
As we shall see, what technological innovation in general – and extremophiles
in particular – teach us is that it is only with the collapse of the simple distinction
between ‘life’ and its absence that relations of unfettered instrumentalisation cease to
be possible. Admittedly, this is somewhat counterintuitive. After all, common sense
dictates that to be recognised as living, as a bona fide lifeform, serves as the best
defence against basest forms of exploitation – one must not, after all, treat other
living beings in the same instrumental fashion that defines our relations with mere
objects. Things, however, are not that simple: relations of unfettered instrumentalisation are rather founded upon the exclusivity of perfect opposites: either this or that,
but never both.
Approaching Extremes . . .
To fully grasp what is at stake in the habitual approach to technology today, it
is necessary to begin with what many regard as the inaugural gesture of Western
philosophy itself: Plato’s attempt to demarcate the domain of philosophy as proper
to knowledge and thought.6 It soon becomes clear, however, that identification of
such a domain is possible only on the basis that we already know exactly what it is
that constitutes proper philosophical knowledge. In order to escape the trap posed
by such circular logic, Plato abruptly shifts ground, attempting instead to fabricate
the positive domain of philosophy on a foundation of its own negation, that is to
say, through the prior exclusion of all that is not proper to knowledge until only
the domain of philosophy remains. To this end, Plato begins with the exclusion of
all such technical expertise common to the everyday sphere (tekhne) and ultimately
ends up disposing the proper domain of philosophy to the immaterial realm of
essential and atemporal truths.7 As a result, it is no longer thought possible to gain
knowledge through existential experience, the coming into being over time characteristic of material existence having become, by definition, the absolute exclusion of
proper philosophical knowledge.
Shortly after this, Aristotle serves the ‘merely’ technical its second, almost fatal
blow. First, he follows Plato by establishing the privilege of essential atemporal
truths (episteme) over and against such ‘practical’ thinking suited to the everyday
temporal world (tekhne) on the basis that only the former constitutes an end in itself,
whereas the latter is merely the means for constituting such ends that exist outside
of it.8 Second, in the complementary argument, Aristotle establishes the privilege of
nature (physis) over and against fabricated objects (also tekhne), again on the basis
5628_Turner.indd 506
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
507
that the efficient cause of the latter exists outside of themselves rather than as an
immanent principle. Consequently, to be deemed tekhne is thus to be relegated to
the status of a ‘mere’ tool existing entirely for human ends.9 Furthermore, taking
the twin arguments together, Aristotle’s tekhne extends to the entirety of matter, and
thus to being itself.
Hence, what begins in the West as a simple, albeit somewhat ignominious desire
to sidestep circular reasoning ultimately sets in train the mythic division of being itself
into two mutually exclusive categories. On one side of the rift exist purposeful beings
who are born, live and die, while on the other is lumped everything else, all the dumb,
inanimate objects lacking any value or reason of their own.
In this way, the technological becomes synonymous with the mechanical, and it
is at this point that it first becomes possible to reductively reinterpret the world as
nothing more than an external stockpile of matter awaiting its eventual instrumentalisation as a means for human ends – a picture of the world that has now held sway
for millennia.
While one might be forgiven for thinking that this particular world picture has presumably been superseded given the recent encroachment of technology into the once
sacrosanct domain of the biological, the ultimate incorporation of what is currently
called ‘life’ to within the vast stockpile of technologies awaiting instrumentalisation
is simply one more step along the same path. To understand not only this, but also
the central role played by notions of causality in the constitution of a newly inclusive
domain of ethical concern, the post-Kehre works of Martin Heidegger remain indispensible. According to Heidegger, the picture of the world as a stockpile carries with
a particular modus operandi or ‘mode of revealing’ that he calls ‘setting-upon’. This
serves to reduce the ‘external’ world to an undifferentiated mass in which any composite part is indistinguishable from any other. As a consequence, it is the potential value
for commodification, or absence thereof, of a given entity that ultimately determines
whether it is to be counted as a purposeful being, and thus deserving of ethical concern, or merely an object and as such prohibited by definition from making any such
claim whatsoever.
While we will return to this in the conclusion, most important at this stage is that
we do not confuse the ‘setting-upon’ process that renders every individual indistinguishable and thus exchangeable with the positive collapse of ontological difference
disclosed by the resolute indistinction of extremophiles.
Encroaching Extremes . . .
As living beings and biological artefacts as well as fossils, technologies and machines,
extremophiles, more than anything currently imaginable, break down the livingnon-living dichotomy. Consumers, engineers, producers and reproducers: they are
at once the repository of a billion years of evolution and of a genomic code that, if
unlocked, promises to reconfigure the world and all of its inhabitants in ways that
defy imagination.
Last but by no means least, extremophiles enable us see just what, exactly, remains
of ethical choice today by exploding the myth of linear causality as fully determining in the case of any entity classified as an inanimate object by human animals,
5628_Turner.indd 507
16/10/17 6:02 PM
508
richard iveson
obliging us instead to recognise that the future effects of inanimate causes too can
never be predicted with absolute surety. Ironically, however, this latter is also what
makes extremophiles so very valuable to the future of bioengineering and, indeed, of
technology in general. It is also the reason why technological evolution itself must
ultimately disallow its own continuance on the basis of a traditional separation of
natural beings and technological artefacts and, in so doing, disclose ethical concern
as a formative condition of its being.
At the heart of this is the extremophile’s extraordinary ability to synthesise
extremolytes in such a way as to protect its macromolecules and cells from external
damage.10 This has resulted in extremophiles frequently being represented within scientific discourse as embodying nothing else but a promise of human protection and
perfection in perfect two-step with patentable future technologies.11 Extremophiles, in
other words, cease being extraordinary forms of life and become instead the promise
of a new sunblock capable of protecting our future human bodies against UV damage
or a newly patented fibre offering protection from radiation and even blast damage.
More spectacular still, they become the promise of a future in which trademarked
technologies safeguard our previously finite human bodyings from the damage of time
itself. In other words, with the revelation that immortality is not uncommon among
extremophiles, their hugely diverse ways of existence are entirely subsumed by the
chance to conquer death itself, and thus render practically immortal all those human
animals wealthy enough to pay the cost of purchase.
In potentially harbouring within themselves the twin grails of both ‘more life’ and
‘more death’, it is hardly surprising to find immense sums of time and money currently
being wagered in the hope of countering the various diseases and disorders that befall
human beings as a result of harsh environments. In this, extremophiles all too clearly
also embody the potential for astronomical profits – in military as much as economic
terms. So, whereas extremophiles evolved their coveted abilities over countless eons,
technoscience is now hard at work attempting to fabricate extremophiles from whole
cloth. Irrespective of when or if such attempts succeed, this task already raises the
absolute breakdown of traditional distinctions between life and nonlife to a further,
dizzying degree. According to the traditional concept of ‘life’, the notion of fabricating
life in the laboratory is pure fiction, the stuff of gothic horror and fantasy SF. In our
post-extremophile universe, however, the possibility is all too real.
At the very least, laboratory-engineered extremophiles promise to radically
rewrite not only what it means to be ‘human’ or even what it means to be ‘living’,
but rather what it means to be biological. As evolved form of life and technological fabrication, the bioengineered extremophile heralds a future of extraordinary,
unforeseeable transformation – human into superhuman, perhaps, or else into something no longer human, and perhaps not even living if we still suppose that life
presupposes death. What is clear, however, is that the question of ethics too must be
radically resituated.
Today, who or what the extremophile is, and who or what he or she or it or they
might become, remains up for dispute. At stake here are the fundamental philosophical concepts of beinghood and thinghood, of subject and object. As such, we should
not be surprised to see these questions increasingly becoming the site of intense ontological, social, economic, political and ethical dispute. And, as the very matter of
5628_Turner.indd 508
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
509
foundational collapse, what is being contested through these sites and these bodies is
just how the future will play out – a battle that inevitably comes down to the demolition or restoration of human in the future.
Emerging . . .
In order to fully grasp the promise of extremophiles, and thus possible futures of technological innovation, we must begin once again, this time with the purported ‘origin’
of life. According to scholars of Non-Equilibrium Thermodynamics (NET), a newly
emerged subfield of thermodynamics generally, the discovery of extremophiles transforms the story of life. Eric Schneider and Dorion Sagan, for example, argue that life
can be traced to the energy flows of an energetic universe. . . . Deep in the chemical
cycles of present-day bacteria are metabolic pathways, chemical traces repeating,
with variation, the steps by which matter came to life. . . . Recent discoveries of
deep-sea ecosystems feeding not on light or food but on chemical energy suggest an
origin of life, paradoxically but poetically, in fire and brimstone.12
Key here is the notion of life originating in the repetition with variation of chemical
traces, building on the notion that the reproduction of all living entities – and only living entities – depend for their ongoing species survival upon the chance of mutation,
that is, upon a process of repetition-with-variation, or reiteration – one that, if successful, brings about accelerating feedback loops and, if not, ends in the decomposition or
‘death’ of the entity entirely in accordance with the Second Law of Thermodynamics.
Hence, in accordance with the thesis that life ‘originates’ in the reiteration of traces,
Schneider and Sagan suggest that the innovation of life in the form of extremophiles
is a consequence of them having ‘probably evolved’ into ‘the earliest natural copying
machines’.13
This point is absolutely crucial: life, before it is anything else, is a copying machine,
a technological artefact that, having adapted through reiterated mutations in order to
record and reiterate patterns and codes, has evolved (Schneider and Sagan’s word) the
capacity to reproduce. Indeed, Schneider and Sagan insist on this point: ‘Life’, they
write, ‘must be regarded, at the deepest level, as a matter as much of energy transformation as of genetic replication.’14 At the most fundamental level, then, ‘life’ is a
machine defined by ‘the calculable programming of an automatic repetition’.15
All of this perfectly accords with an understanding of evolution as a process of
reiteration at every level of complexity, with selection for mutation being necessarily
nonlinear insofar as innovation depends upon strong mutual interactions (or feedback)
between components. Fracturing Darwin’s original conception of evolution as a strictly
linear affair resulting in the perfect manifestation of a single optimal design, this founding nonlinearity presupposes only what Manuel DeLanda terms ‘gradients of fitness’,
wherein a gradient functions only so long as differences of fitness remain so as to fuel
a selection process that favours the reiteration (repetition-with-variation) of one kind
over another.16
But, as DeLanda insists, this is not only a matter of life. This point is critical. Gradients
apply as much to ‘molecular replicators and their different capacities to produce copies of
5628_Turner.indd 509
16/10/17 6:02 PM
510
richard iveson
themselves’ as they do to ‘the differential reproductive success of embodied organisms’.17
In other words, gradients – or energetic differences – organise everything from hurricanes
to hiccups and hippos. Whether evolved or engineered, entities must similarly adapt in
unpredictable fashion according to the pressures of selection gradients. As a result, rather
than demonstrating the natural absence of any ethical dimension, this a priori unforeseeability of evolutionary processes is instead the mark of its absolute necessity.
Furthermore, it will be argued in the next section, this must therefore be true of
every technological process. Unpredictability or nonlinearity, in other words, constitutes the condition of possibility of material presencing, that is to say, of existing, of
being. Or, put in somewhat axiomatic form: Beings can only be by being other than
what they are.
Despite the difficulty of the logical and linguistic contortions involved, it is imperative that we understand exactly what is at stake here – a task of ever-increasing urgency
given just how much is routinely being wagered today on the basis of a misplaced faith
in the reliability and accuracy of projections into the future. Before we can do so,
however, it still remains to engage in some depth with what philosopher Jacques Derrida calls the ‘structure of nonpresence’18 or, more simply, the trace – the importance
of which cannot be overstated.
Philosophising . . .
Schneider and Sagan’s relocation of the origin of life to coincide with the emergence
into being of extremophiles is, as we shall see, a copying machine of a very different
order – of Aristotle, of Kant and of Derrida above all.
Put as schematically as possible, Derrida argues that the becoming-time of space or
the becoming-space of time represents the originary synthesis of the trace understood
as the double movement of protention and retention.19 Most importantly, the structural unity of the trace demonstrates that an indivisible presence – that is, an entity
fully present in and of itself – can never in fact be. Rather, for an entity to appear on
the ‘scene of presence’, it must already keep within itself ‘the mark of the past element’
while at the same time letting itself ‘be vitiated by the mark of its relation to the future
element’.20 For an entity to endure in time and thus appear as present, in other words,
it is required as a prior condition of this appearing to bear the traces of both its past
and its future. As a result, the appearance of anything deemed to be present, deemed to
be, is shown rather to depend a priori upon its relation ‘to what it absolutely is not’ in
that, in order for the present to be itself, an interval or spacing must already separate
the present from what it is not.21
Furthermore, given this prior dependence upon what it absolutely is not, any
instant of the now, of the present, can only appear by disappearing, and thus can only
be inscribed as a trace. Hence, this means that every trace is necessarily spatial – what
Derrida describes as the becoming-space-of-time – insofar as spatiality is defined by
the ability to remain in place despite temporal succession. For an entity to endure, in
other words, it must be spatial, must take place. At the same time, however, spatiality
can never be absolute simultaneity, as the very concept of simultaneity depends upon a
temporalisation that links one point in space to another, meaning that spacing is also
a becoming-time, without which there could be no trace in the first place. As such, the
5628_Turner.indd 510
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
511
structural logic of the trace is, by definition, constitutive of everything temporal, that
is, of each and every entity that, living or not, endures and thus exists, however briefly,
as a present being.22
Strangely, however, in Of Grammatology Derrida argues instead that the ‘emergence’
of the trace is synonymous with the emergence of life.23 As such, Derrida is suggesting
that, yes, in fact, there is an identifiable origin to be found here, the event in question
presumably having taken place at a specific and seemingly locatable moment in time
– indeed, the precise historical moment in which, thereafter and forever, the originary
technicity of the living being emerged into being.24 Ultimately, in insisting upon a determinable origin of life, Derrida – as, extremophiles notwithstanding, Schneider and Sagan
will do so after him – bases his project on an unquestioned and unfounded faith that
to live is to be exceptional, that is, to be absolutely ontologically distinct from all such
entities deemed merely to endure until they do not. As a result, Derrida is already condemned to repeat the inaugural gesture of philosophy even before he begins: constituting
an allegedly ‘proper’ domain of life entirely negatively by way of the exclusion of the
non-living.
In fact, all such claims as to a determinable origin of life are founded upon two
irreconcilable premises that ultimately show them to be nothing more than productions of zoocentric bias: (1) Life emerges as a distinct ontological category, and (2)
Life is dependent upon machinic repetition. On one hand, the first living being must
be ontologically distinct from every previously existing being – meaning that the genesis of life is a creative event that, by definition, could not have been predicted on the
basis of linear causality. Hence, life as invention, as creation, is necessarily nonlinear.
On the other hand, however, the ‘first’ living being can only ever be one more replication of what already is. As such, every attempt at distinction relies upon a completely
arbitrary stopping point in what is in fact a ceaseless process of reiteration that both
precedes and succeeds any notional location of ‘origin’. Life, therefore, merely reproduces nonlife: continuum rather than difference.
Insofar as the trace structure constitutes the general possibility of any entity actually being (whether that be a thing, body, artefact, idea or whatever), however, this is
also to inscribe chance as a constitutive possibility of that entity’s being. The trace, if it
is to trace anything at all, is the movement of past and future, the moment of retention
and protention. As such, rather than determining the origin of life, the generalising
of the trace is also the generalising of futural causality, inscribing nonlinearity as an a
priori condition of each and every formed being. Any thing that exists, in other words,
does so as the possibility of both machinic repetition and creative event.
It is only this clear understanding of the trace that enables us to leave behind spurious theological fantasies of exceptionalism on the one hand, and an equally obnoxious reduction of life to nonlife on the other. Hence, while a generalising of the trace
demands the concomitant deconstruction of the living-non-living binary for reasons
of logic, it is equally important to recognise that the deconstruction of the living-nonliving binary simultaneously demands an extension of the trace structure, albeit for
reasons of ethical imperative. Only by deconstructing the lines of exclusion that keep
living from non-living, biology from artifice and being from object does instrumentalisation cease to be possible. As such, it is central to any accounting of who, or what,
will ‘count’, ethically and politically, as a posthuman being in the future. While the
5628_Turner.indd 511
16/10/17 6:02 PM
512
richard iveson
trace necessarily structures all forms of being, for us today, it is extremophiles who
embody this structure most explicitly.
Mutating . . .
All of that is, however, for the future. For the moment, the focus of technoscience is
ostensibly taken up with possible experiments aimed at the bioengineering of very specific mutations with the capacity to dissolve – quite literally – the various actual and
imminent ecological crises that are today imposing limits on global capitalism’s operative principle: expansion. Extremophiles, in other words, serve today as the building
blocks from which entities with a single purpose are be constructed: that of being able
to thrive upon a diet of industrial pollutants ranging from nuclear waste, oil spills,
discarded plastics, contaminants in the water table, and the vast lagoons of faeces
expelled from the enormous, windowless blocks that are factory farms and Concentrated Animal Feeding Operations (CAFOs). After all, as the story goes, what point in
living forever if the world is to perish any minute?
Not by chance, however, this prioritising of environmental concerns serves also
to reassure an anxious public. For a significant percentage of the global population,
contemporary research into genetic and genomic modification continues to be a cause
of intense anxiety. Unsurprisingly, this anxiety focuses almost exclusively upon the
threat to the future of unforeseen gene actions coming to alter metabolism and brain
function in ways that for many would be indistinguishable with the end of our world.
However, the issue facing us today is in fact far more commonplace and extensive: a
major consequence of the deconstruction of the living/non-living binary is the impossibility of all future prediction. Every present configuration of particles, in other words,
is also the possibility of wildly unpredictable reiterations in the future. Even a single
gene alteration targeting weight loss, for example, must inevitably affect a number of
other interrelated pathway genes, and this pattern follows for even the most minor
technology and seemingly mundane object.
It comes as no surprise, then, to find extremophiles being mined first of all in
respect to possible applications of microbial metabolic potential. Known as bioremediation, this process is far less contentious than the engineering of human enhancement,
for example, and is widely accepted as being an ‘environmentally benign economic
measure’.25 Despite this consensus, however, this construction in the media of bioremediation as ‘natural’, and so environmentally benign, is once again nothing more
than sophistic rhetoric, mere means to an end in the form of a further ‘trick argument’
constructed upon three largely unrelated and contradictory assumptions:
• Remediation and bioremediation technologies are more or less the same.
• A secure ontological border exists between living and non-living beings.
• The universe is wholly deterministic.
In contrast to bioremediation technologies, remediation is a process that utilises alreadyexisting chemicals in order to disperse or dissolve pollutants in the environment, such as
introducing the compounds alkylphenol or 2-butoxyethanol into oil spills. Considered
an entirely ‘natural’ – i.e. environmentally sensitive – process, remediation technologies
5628_Turner.indd 512
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
513
are therefore deemed as being without any ethical dimension whatsoever. From there, it
is only a short step to the introduction of bioremediation technologies as being ‘practically’ the same and, hence, equally ‘natural’ (although with ‘natural’ here undergoing
an unmarked but nonetheless significant shift of meaning) – technologies such as Oil
Spill Eater II (OSE II), for example.26 A biological multi-enzyme introduced into the
ocean, OSE II converts spilled oil into a food source for bacteria that are described in
its promotional literature as ‘native’, but which are in fact populations of indigenous
bacteria that have previously undergone ‘suitable enhancement’. Despite this, OSE II
and other bioremediation technologies are generally perceived as being very similar
to remediation processes, and it is by way of this assumed identity that bioremediation is deemed as similarly lacking in ethical dimension. Looking deeper, however, it
quickly becomes clear that the apparent ‘naturalness’ of bioremediation and remediation processes is itself founded upon the traditional living-non-living dichotomy – the
very opposition that the shift from chemistry to biology or from alkylphenol to Oil Spill
Eater II in fact renders untenable.
Put another way, alkylphenol and 2-butoxyethanol are, first of all, excluded from
ethical consideration on the basis of being only things, that is, by virtue of being nonliving ‘objects’ and thus merely the means to human ends. Second, insofar as they are
objects, it is assumed that their future effects can be unerringly predicted according to
simple calculations of restricted cause and effect. But what happens once the separation between living being and non-living object breaks down? The idea of introducing
living beings into scenes of environmental crisis, by contrast, has long been condemned
in ethical terms due to the utter unpredictability of its effects – in this regard, one need
only recall the introduction of cane toads into Australia from Hawaii.27 So, alkylphenol and 2-butoxyethanol are perceived as ‘natural’ and thus benign – i.e., safe and
reliable – environmental supplements only because they are merely ‘things’ as it is only
on this basis are they judged entirely predictable and thus safely controllable into the
future. In contradistinction to living beings, the future interactions of mere objects are
deemed fully determined by simple causality and thus fully accountable. The key selling point of bioremediation technologies, then, concerns the introduction of what are,
according to its own classification, natural living entities. Concurrent with this, however, bioremediation technologies must also reduce these living beings to base matter,
must allot them the ontological standing of objects and no more, in order to justify
their exemption from issues of ethical concern.
Given this, it is incumbent upon the promoters of bioremediation, as it is too upon
those of remediation, to bolster faith in a secure living-non-living dichotomy. This,
however, serves only to maintain a dangerous delusion: that a baseless attribution of
objecthood can serve as a guarantee of future safety.
Concluding . . . Après le deluge
In the end, following millennia of trick arguments, we are returned to extremophiles.
Beyond the illusions of vitalism, beyond delusions of safety constructed upon the
politics of exclusion alone, unpredictability is disclosed as the structure of being itself.
Furthermore, as a consequence of this nonlinearity of being, it is therefore impossible, by definition, to predict the emergence of a novel existent in the future, be that
a new form of being or a technological innovation. Obviously, this renders massively
5628_Turner.indd 513
16/10/17 6:02 PM
514
richard iveson
problematic any decisions made today on the basis of apparently reliable and accurate
predictions as to the future. Rather, this oxymoronic notion of ‘accurate prediction’
is only ever possible on the basis of an ordered deterministic universe. It is somewhat
ironic, therefore, that definitive of any such universe is the fact of its being without a
future insofar as its future has already been contained and prescribed by its past.
Of course, this is not to say that the ‘hard’ sciences generally, and technoscience in
particular, are unaware of the immense risks currently being run should prediction itself
prove to be wildly unreliable. Indeed, warnings to that effect proliferate exponentially
whenever concerns are raised about extremophiles, bioremediation and biotechnology
more generally. More specifically, it is widely recognised that since genetically engineered organisms lack the relative stability that comes from the evolution of genetic
patterns, one requires, first of all and above all, a fully reliable prediction regarding
future recombinative events. The problem, however, remains the same insofar as the
solution is always preconceived as a need for increased reliability, and thus for a complete knowledge of the present context in terms of a synchronous cross-section of networked cause-and-effect. Ultimately, what today’s scientific rationality fails to recognise
is that the very notion of reliable prediction, like that of a deterministic universe that
founds it, is nothing but a myth – a failure of recognition that, if there are to be futures
beyond imagining, needs to be urgently redressed.
As specialists in science policy and risk communication Michael Tyshenko and
William Leiss acknowledge, scientific researchers remain largely ‘unconcerned with
the gap between things that “can be done” and “will be done,” placing science
innovation as a technical exercise apart from any ethical concerns’.28 This lack of
concern is simply unacceptable, however, once scientific determinism no longer
holds. Since Aristotle, as we have seen, living beings have been considered ontologically distinct from fabricated artefacts by virtue of their being natural. It is unsurprising, then, that a certain concept of ‘nature’ still underwrites the instrumental
approach to ‘simple’ objects. One that, by continuing to ensure the exclusion of
‘technical exercises’ from the realms of ethical concern in the process, clears the
ground for just such an unheeding saturnalia of headlong technological acceleration
as we have witnessed in recent decades.
First of all, the absence of a perceived ethical dimension in relation to the ‘exercise’
of technoscientific knowledge depends upon the ‘fundamental notion that the world
of nature is essentially a field in which human ingenuity can be exercised without
restriction’.29 In this view, the ‘world of nature’ is reduced to an external realm of
‘things’ that exists entirely for-us, that is to say, everything that exists ‘naturally’, i.e.,
every non-human living being, exists only as a means to human ends. Such a reductive
conception of nature inevitably results in a wildly skewed vision of the world, with the
Earth itself reconfigured as an enormous storage facility stocked with ready-to-hand
instruments to be used as fit by humanity alone. Under the sway of this world picture,
it matters not at all in terms of their usefulness as means if a given instrument is ‘natural’ or fabricated, if it is physis or tekhne, that is, possesses or does not possess within
itself its own effective principle. Nonetheless, it is exactly this distinction that serves
as its ‘ground’. It is exactly this distinction that, beneath layers of obfuscation, continues to function today solely as a means to human ends. As previously mentioned,
the later work of Heidegger is crucial. Modern science, he argues, first constructed the
fundamental relationship of humanity to the world as a ‘standing reserve’ [Bestand]
5628_Turner.indd 514
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
515
in this fashion, and did so through the entrapment of nature ‘as a coherence of forces
calculable in advance’.30
As the herald of today’s ‘ordering attitude’ [Ge-stell], the mass of technological
artefacts are never simply tools, however, never merely the means to ends that lay outside of themselves. Rather, continues Heidegger, these entities are themselves constitutive of a ‘mode of revealing’.31 Moreover, the particular mode of revealing that rules
contemporary technoscience is that of a ‘setting-upon’, which first challenges nature
to unlock its concealed energy, only to then reorder all of nature’s secrets in a global
‘standing reserve’ that will thereafter be forever transformed, stored, distributed and
regulated in a ceaseless circle of revealing. In this process, every part becomes indistinguishable from every other part and the whole becomes the undifferentiated order that
humanity decrees makes up its outside.
It is, however, in the face of this ordering attitude definitive of global capitalism that
we must reiterate ever more urgently what for Heidegger is the grounding question in
this matter: namely, what happens if, just for a moment, we suppose that causality is
rather ‘veiled in darkness with respect to what it is’?32 While the unprecedented ways
of extremophiles disclose the universe as an incalculable, incoherent continuum of
being, the sway of Ge-stell has nonetheless already ordered their transformation into
everything else and nothing else: mere ‘stock’ awaiting economic viability. Hence it is
not without a certain irony that, in occupying a site of extreme anxiety in regards to
our global future, it can be hoped that these unprecedented miracles of our biotechnological survival might in fact bear within their coded forms of matter a very different
promise: the end of a world reduced to a mere stockpiling of means to human ends.
And here too resides the promise of animal studies: namely, the chance of a future that
can only take place beyond the narrow constraints constitutive of human imagination.
Notes
1. See, for example, the hugely popular films 28 Days Later, dir. Danny Boyle (UK: DNA
films, 2002) and I Am Legend, dir. Francis Lawrence (USA: Warner Bros, 2007). The narrative of these is in clear contrast to the struggle to escape the confines of place characteristic of earlier examples of the genre such as The Dawn of the Dead, dir. George A. Romero
(Italy: Dawn Associates, 1978) and The Evil Dead, dir. Sam Raimi (USA: Renaissance
Pictures, 1981).
2. Largely because of their extraordinary physical appearance, the best-known examples of
extremophiles today are the tardigrade and the blobfish. See Koki Horikoshi, Extremophiles: Where It All Began (Tokyo: Springer, 2016); Extremophiles: Microbiology and
Biotechnology, ed. Roberto Paul Anitori (Norfolk: Caister Academic Press, 2012); and
Extremophiles: Sustainable Resources and Biotechnological Implications, ed. Om V. Singh
(Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013). For up-to-date developments, see Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences (PNAS).
3. Extremophiles have also been proven crucial to the development of bioengineering. A
particularly well-known example is the so-called tag polymerase enzyme isolated from
the extremophile Thermus aquaticus. This enzyme is fundamental to the procedures of
the polymerase chain reaction (PCR) procedure that has revolutionised biotechnology. Cf.
Sonoko Ishino and Yoshizumi Ishino, ‘DNA Polymerases as Useful Reagents for Biotechnology – The History of Developmental Research in the Field’, Frontiers in Microbiology
5 (2014), p. 465.
5628_Turner.indd 515
16/10/17 6:02 PM
516
richard iveson
4. See Donna Haraway, ‘A Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science, Technology, and Socialist Feminism in the 1980s’, in The Haraway Reader (New York: Routledge, 2004), pp. 7–45.
5. For details of recent studies, along with just why this expenditure will almost certainly
increase exponentially over the next decade, see Pabulo Rampelotto (ed.), Biotechnology
of Extremophiles: Advances and Challenges (New York: Springer, 2016).
6. I am thinking primarily here of Meno and Phaedrus, particularly §80–7 and §244–50 respectively. See Plato, Complete Works (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997), pp. 870–97, 506–56.
7. The great irony here is that Plato in fact only appears to extricate knowledge, and therefore a proper philosophical domain, from the circularity of its own logic. Moreover,
it is an appearance built not upon the eternal timelessness of truth, but rather fabricated through expert employment of learned techniques and practical skills. See Richard
Iveson, Zoogenesis: Thinking Encounter with Animals (London: Pavement Books,
2014), pp. 33–6.
8. Nicomachean Ethics and Metaphysics in The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Modern
Library, 2009), pp. 689–934, 935–1126.
9. Aristotle, Physics, pp. 218–397. Ibid.
10. Extremolytes, or organic osmolytes, are compounds accumulated in response to environmental pressures (such as increased temperature), as well as to increased solute extracellular
concentrations (of salt, for example) in a process of equalisation known as osmosis, which
thus protects biological macromolecules and cells from damage by external stresses. See G.
Lentzen and T. Schwarz, ‘Extremolytes: Natural Compounds from Extremophiles for Versatile Applications’, Applied Microbiology and Biotechnology 72:4 (2006), pp. 623–634,
and Maurice B. Burg and Joan D. Ferraris, ‘Intracellular Organic Osmolytes: Function and
Regulation’, The Journal of Biological Chemistry 283:12 (2008), pp. 7309–13.
11. Despite their quality, the articles by Lentzen and Schwarz and Ishino and Ishino cited previously are nonetheless typical in this regard.
12. Eric Schneider and Dorion Sagan, Into the Cool: Energy Flow, Thermodynamics, and Life
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2005), pp. xii–xiii.
13. Ibid. p. xii.
14. Ibid. p. xiii.
15. Jacques Derrida, Without Alibi, trans. Peggy Kamuf (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2002), pp. 71–160, p.72.
16. Manuel DeLanda, Philosophy and Simulation: The Emergence of Synthetic Reason
(London: Continuum, 2011), p. 48.
17. Ibid.
18. Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1974, 1997), p. 84.
19. Jacques Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1984), p. 13.
20. Ibid.
21. Ibid.
22. The ontological underpinning of this position is detailed in my book, Being and Not Being:
On Posthuman Temporality (London: Rowman & Littlefield International, 2016).
23. Derrida, Of Grammatology, p. 84.
24. As to just why Derrida might equate the trace with ‘life in general’, see my ‘Being Without
Life: On the Trace of Organic Chauvinism with Derrida and Delanda’, forthcoming in
Rosi Braidotti and Rick Dolphijn (eds), Philosophy after Nature (London: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2017).
25. Romeela Mohee and Ackmez Mudhoo, ‘Elements of Sustainability and Bioremediation’,
in Bioremediation and Sustainability: Research and Applications (Salem, MA: Scrivener
Publishing, 2012), p. 5.
5628_Turner.indd 516
16/10/17 6:02 PM
technology
517
26. British Petroleum tested the OSEI Corporation product Oil Spill Eater II at Louisiana
State University in 2010–11. See <http://osei.us/pdf%20files/osei_sum.pdf> (accessed
28 August 2017).
27. Cane toads were introduced to Australia from Hawaii in 1935 in an attempt to control the
native beetle populations and so safeguard sugar cane profits. Consequently, biodiversity
became majorly depleted, with the ecological balance suffering a series of severe breakdowns.
28. Michael Tyshenko and William Leiss, ‘Life in the Fast Lane: An Introduction to Genomics Risks’,
CTheory 2005, n.p., <http://journals.uvic.ca/index.php/ctheory/article/view/14534/5381>
(accessed 28 August 2017).
29. Ibid.
30. Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William
Lovitt (New York: Perennial, 1977), p. 21.
31. Ibid. pp.12–13.
32. Ibid. p. 6.
5628_Turner.indd 517
16/10/17 6:02 PM