Special Section: Methodology in Philosophical Bioethics
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
JOHN HARRIS
The Argument
Matti Häyry’s new book is deliberately challenging; it tells six contemporary
bioethicists, and all who share their methodologies or even their general
approach, that they have got it badly wrong. From the striking photograph of
Häyry himself on the front cover to the very last line, the genetic challenge is
issued and elaborated. Häyry has divided his protagonists into three pairs, of
which I find myself a member, and this makes responding a duty as well as
a pleasure. Although I cannot speak for my partner in crime, Jonathan Glover,
I am at least in the very best of all possible company.
Häyry’s book is self-consciously a work on methodology in bioethics. John
Coggon has exposed many of the weaknesses of Häyry’s methodological
approach,1 and because I cannot usefully add to these, I believe, decisive objections to Häyry’s overall approach, I want to take up two themes that are not
prominent in Coggon’s analysis.
Nonconfrontational Ethics
A key element in Häyry’s approach is that he recommends and espouses
a ‘‘nonconfrontational’’ notion of rationality that he believes is the key to the
best methodological approach to the ethical problems posed by genetics. My first
problem is that I do not see much merit in a nonconfrontational approach to the
resolution of ethical problems. This may be a matter of personality as much as
methodology; I happen to enjoy a good argument, both in the sense of
appreciating a convincing set of reasons for believing or doing something and
because I also enjoy a frank exchange of views and often find the exchange
illuminating as well as satisfying. However, I also think there are good reasons to
believe that the ideal of avoiding confrontation involves commitment to a
dysfunctional sort of political correctness and one which is rarely productive of
clear thinking or concise argument. Evil and wickedness need to be confronted,
and even apparently milder forms of error in matters ethical can matter hugely
for the very reasons that make them ethical issues. I am fond of the idea that if
morality is the science of the good, then ethics is the study of that science. If this is
right, then we see clear reasons for, and justification of, confrontation. As in
anything that is, in principle, demonstrable, it is important to try to arrive at the
truth or, more modestly, at the most satisfying explanation of the way the world
I am grateful for helpful comments from John Coggon, Sarah Chan, Simona Giordano, and Rebecca
Bennett. I acknowledge with gratitude the stimulus and support of the iSEI Wellcome Programme in
the Human Body, its Scope, Limits, and Future.
204
Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics (2011), 20, 204–215.
Ó Cambridge University Press 2011.
doi:10.1017/S096318011000085X
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
is or the most effective strategy for achieving one’s goals. The best course of
action in ethics is often demonstrable, and part of this demonstration can involve
revealing as conclusively as possible the errors in, or problems that beset,
alternative views.
However, confrontation is not necessarily hostile, even though people often
take offense when others try to point out the error of their ways or the mistakes in
their reasoning. Philosophy is essentially, and indeed etymologically, a love of
knowledge or wisdom. As the Oxford English Dictionary suggests in the first
definition of philosophy: ‘‘ 1. (In the original and widest sense.) The love, study or
pursuit of wisdom, or of knowledge of things and their causes, whether
theoretical or practical.’’2
Falsehood or bad argument is not loved or indeed pursued amorously by
philosophers; quite the reverse! That is not just how it is, but how it should be. In
science, error can cost not only time and money but also lives, and the same is
true in ethics, and particularly in what Häyry calls ‘‘genethics.’’ Ethical
conclusions are, like those of science, also very often, as I have suggested,
demonstrable in that a combination of evidence and argument can prove
conclusive in their articulation and acceptance. Certain conclusions in ethics
unequivocally recommend themselves to reason, not least because there is often
an overwhelming agreement about the ends to be achieved (saving lives,
minimizing suffering, making the world a better place), and the best means to
realize these are also often obvious and compelling. To take some clear examples,
once effective and safe vaccines for smallpox and polio had been developed the
conclusion of the practical syllogism was obvious: disseminate them as widely
and as speedily as possible. This is true for all established connections between
threats to life and safe3 means of neutralizing or minimizing those threats. The
connection between diet, exercise, and heart disease, between smoking and lung
cancer, and between some genes and illness are all examples of such connections
that indicate safe preventive strategies.
Häyry lists seven ways of making people better and discusses ethical
approaches to the legitimacy of utilizing these ways. But to fail to make people
better when we can is necessarily to leave them worse, or worse off, than they
need be; sometimes this means that they are fatally worse off. This matters! Of
course, where individuals do not want to be protected from harm or have their
conditions or circumstances ameliorated, this is absolutely a matter for them. I
believe, however, that there are the strongest moral reasons to persuade, and where
necessary confront, the views and the individuals who stand between people and
what often is their only chance to have a better life or make their lives better.
To confront, with evidence and argument, the views of others should not and
need not be hostile or offensive. Philosophers, and indeed all people of good will,
should welcome criticism of their research and their views and be happy to engage
in the discussion that alone can lead to better research and better conclusions, even
where that discussion is conducted vigorously. Engagement, moral, political, and
theoretical, may involve confrontation, but I would suggest it is no worse for that.
The alternative is not necessarily more reasonable or more rational, or more
civilized, and it may be less committed, less open, and less honest.
In the last chapter of Häyry’s book, which he calls tellingly, ‘‘Taking the Genetic
Challenge Rationally,’’ he strongly implies that this is what his methodology is
doing and has done throughout, with the implication that some of those who do
205
John Harris
not accept his methodology are not taking the genetic challenge rationally. It is
somewhat ironic, then, that Häyry continuously castigates me in the book for
allegedly tending ‘‘to see opposing views as irrational.’’4 Indeed, Häyry lists this
tendency of mine as the second main problem with my entire approach.5 It is
perhaps also of some psychological interest that Häyry regards castigating me for
valuing and using rationality as an example of nonconfrontational ethics!
In his last section to this chapter Häyry writes of his book that it
provides all the normative guidance that books on philosophical ethics
can. It presents the main arguments for and against genetic and related
techniques and practices, with commentaries on their strengths and
weaknesses. Intelligent readers can, in the light of these, articulate their
own views on the activities involved and make their own moral
judgements concerning them. Secondly the book refuses to claim
absolute validity for particular norms on philosophical grounds. Philosophical considerations can show that some arguments are flawed and
others open to discussion, but they cannot prove to everybody’s
satisfaction the rightness or wrongness of selection, cloning, or new
treatments. The practical point of the book, then, is to empower readers
to make up their own minds on genetic and related technologies, and
not to lull themselves into thinking that they can find ready-made
answers of universal validity in philosophical writings.6
We will come in a moment to Häyry’s first claim about the reliability of his
presentation of the arguments of others. His second claim: ‘‘Intelligent readers
can, in the light of these, articulate their own views on the activities involved and
make their own moral judgements concerning them’’ goes of course also for all
intelligent readers of any book whatsoever; no difference between us there. Even
Häyry cannot subvert the intelligence of his readers and neither can I. Nor does
either of us, I am sure, want or intend to do any such thing. Häyry claims another
virtue for his book: ‘‘the book refuses to claim absolute validity for particular
norms on philosophical grounds.’’ The implication is again that others, probably
those he takes as his protagonists, do make absolute claims. At the risk of
seeming confrontational I am bound to say: ‘‘big deal!’’ Neither I nor, I am sure,
any of the other authors on whose judgments and methodologies Häyry provides
‘‘commentaries on their strengths and weaknesses’’ would claim anything so
stupid. So that there can be no ambiguity, I have never claimed absolute validity
for anything. What I do often claim on the basis of the evidence and argument I
adduce is that there are good reasons to accept the conclusions to which I or
others come. If there are not, neither I nor anyone would have any business
coming to any conclusions at all. Even Häyry has been known to come to
a conclusion or two, and when he does I assume he believes it is on some rational
basis. This, I suggest, must mean that his conclusions recommend themselves to
reason more powerfully than alternatives, that is, they are more rational than
(and ipso facto confrontational of) less plausible views. To the extent that they are
overwhelmingly persuasive, they will become as ‘‘objective’’ as are scientific
theories or facts that have attained the same degree of persuasiveness.
Evidence and Argument
A second problem I have is with elements of Häyry’s methodology that he does
not highlight as of methodological interest at all. I would like to suggest two
206
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
essential elements to any adequate methodology in bioethics or indeed in any
other field. One is to represent those whose work you criticize, if not objectively,
at least accurately. Every decent academic tries to do this, and I am sure Häyry
believes he has also done so. The second is to demonstrate this accuracy by
allowing your opponents to speak in their own voice, and to do this it is
necessary to quote chapter and verse and to accurately reference the quotations.
By this I mean it is necessary to quote at sufficient length for it to be obvious to
the reader that your protagonist has actually said what you say she has said. This
methodological safeguard protects us all, as far as it is possible so to do, against
the charge of misrepresentation.
Häyry, however, does not often let his protagonists speak in their own voice or
their own words. Rather he chooses to offer characterizations of the positions he
believes we hold in his own words and even sometimes tells his protagonists off
when their views do not quite match his caricatures of them!7
Thus, when he criticizes me and others, he often puts our thoughts into his
own words, neither citing works nor usually giving page references to where our
alleged statements are to be found.8 He also sometimes goes further! On page 157
of his book he says, ‘‘The idea Harris suggests, and especially its application to
ova harvesting, can be challenged from at least three angles.’’ He then rather
lamely adds in a footnote,9 ‘‘Harris does not discuss this in his paper, so some of
the criticisms are to Harris-like rather than actually Harris-related views.’’
Readers can judge the effectiveness as well as the respectability of a methodological device like this.
This demonstrates the literally fiendish cunning of the Matti Häyry methodology. He has sprung his trap and even that other great professorial ‘‘M’’ of
diabolical stratagems, the incomparable Professor Moriarty himself, could not
have secured a more complete victory. For in attributing to me, for example,
positions that I do not hold, have never held, and for which he provides no
evidence in the form of quotations or citations, he invites me to show where and
when I did not in fact say the things attributed to me. But if you ask me where
and when I do not say these things I would have to answer, rather lamely, that I
always do not say them and I do not say them everywhere! References for my
denial would have to be to every page of every book and paper that I have
written.
Another key methodological device Häyry adopts is to choose a label for
the philosophical positions of his opponents and then, having set out
the defining characteristics of the position to which he attaches the label,
he proceeds to find fault with us for departing from his conception of the
position he thinks we ought to hold. This is of course a highly effective
methodology!10
The Evidence
Because I appear throughout Häyry’s book, this paper might have turned out to
be very long indeed. To avoid this disaster, I am being selective. I take just one
set of examples from Chapter 2, not least because they are characteristic of
problems with his methodological approach. Of course there are also many
places where Häyry does me justice, and even more than justice, and for these
I am grateful.
207
John Harris
Example 1
This occurs in Chapter 2 and I start at page 29. I adopt the practice of setting out
Häyry’s claims in full by direct quotation and then answering them.
According to Glover and Harris, then, one fundamental reason against
killing people and failing to save their lives is that these choices would
eliminate the worthwhile future existence of a currently existing person.
Similar reasons can be extended to reproductive choices. Failure to
conceive and a decision to terminate a pregnancy would also eliminate
the future existence of a person, albeit a currently nonexistent one.
Therefore the view stipulates that it would be wrong not to bring about
a life worth living or of value, provided that the life is qualitatively so
good that it does not lower the average goodness of the lives of the
population as a whole.11
This section is footnoted as follows: ‘‘Glover 1977, pp. 69–70, 140; cf. Harris, 1992,
pp. 176-7.’’
I shall not comment on whether the attributions to Jonathan Glover are correct.
He is well able to defend himself. The citation ‘‘Harris, 1992’’ is to my book
Wonderwoman and Superman.12 However, neither on the pages cited nor anywhere
else do I say anything remotely like this, not least because I do not think anything
remotely like this.
Indeed so far from it being true that ‘‘according to . . . Harris, then, one
fundamental reason against killing people and failing to save their lives is that
these choices would eliminate the worthwhile future existence of a currently
existing person,’’ I am on record as both denying this and saying something
fundamentally different, not least because I believe that the entitlement of an
existing person to experience the future is not dependent upon the worthwhile
nature of that future. People are entitled to live even lives that are not worthwhile
(either on their own judgment or on that of anyone else) if they want to.
On the very page that Häyry cites (page 177 of Wonderwoman and Superman) on
the contrary I say:
However the wrong of all presently existing individuals, say, simply
deciding not to reproduce, simply deciding that the present generation
should be the last, is of a different order. It is different because it would
not involve violating the will to live of any person, nor the destruction of
the ecosystem. Indeed there is a sense in which it might be better for the
ecosystem as a whole if this were to happen—better in the sense that the
system (humans apart) would be less in danger of total destruction. . . .
However, it would I think be wrong for two distinct and important
reasons. The first is that it would be to prefer a universe with less
happiness and less satisfaction of desires than the alternative in which
persons did continue to exist, and secondly because it might involve the
permanent end of the only creatures anywhere who have both these
capacities.
Note that I do not say anything to imply objection to the elimination of the
worthwhile ‘‘future existence of a currently existing person.’’ Nor do I say
anything about the elimination of ‘‘the future existence of a person, albeit
a currently nonexistent one’’ whatever that may mean! (How can you eliminate
a nonexistent person either now or in the future?) The pages Häyry cites are not
about decisions adversely affecting existing people at all. My thoughts on the
pages Häyry cites are about possible worlds scenarios, they are about what sorts
208
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
of people there should be in the future and whether there are good moral
arguments to ensure that there will be future people at all. Nothing I say or
believe about the ethics of such scenarios involves at any stage or in any
way deployment of or even consideration of a ‘‘fundamental reason against
killing people and failing to save their lives,’’ which turns on the fact that ‘‘these
choices would eliminate the worthwhile future existence of a currently existing
person.’’
Indeed in my most recent book I point out that so-called future of value
arguments, such as those Häyry attributes to me, are just forms of the potentiality
argument, a form of argument I have consistently rejected in print since 1985.13 I
will not discuss here the question of whether it is confrontational or not to
attribute views one wishes to attack to someone when there is no basis for
believing he holds them.
Häyry has placed me in the position in which Sir Arthur Streeb-Greebling
found himself in a radio interview with Dudley Moore, when questioned about
his groundbreaking (or rather wave-breaking) work as a naturalist. Sir Arthur
was forced into a confrontational stance. Moore asked him: ‘‘Where did you strat
your work?’’ Sir Arthur’s response is legendary:
I think it can be said of me that I have never, ever strated my work. That
is one thing I have never done. I can lay my hand on my heart, or indeed
on anyone else’s heart, and say I have never strated my work, never
strated at all. I think what you probably wanted to know is when I
started my work.14
Example 2
Put in terms of worth, Glover and Harris postulate three categories of
lives: those more worth living, those less worth living; and those not
worth living.15
No reference is given to the claim that I postulate this. Of course, it is evidently
true that some lives are better than others. I myself envy the lives (and indeed the
lifestyles) of many other people. Some lives are more worth living, some less, and
some, a few, are truly not worth living, and I have certainly said that there are
some lives that are definitely worth ‘‘not living.’’ But the way that Häyry puts this
point seems to imply that I believe there exist three classes of individuals who
have lives of ascending or descending value in the sense that those with lives
more worth living are people who matter more, have lives that are more worth
saving, or have more civil, political, or moral rights and so on than those with less
valuable lives. When I say ‘‘I wish I could still play squash and envy those who
can,’’ I am not implying that I am in a morally ‘‘different category’’ to those who
can play squash. What Häyry seems to attribute to me I certainly do not believe,
and I have never said anything that could imply such a division of living persons
into lives of different value in the sense of lives of different moral worth or lives
that are more or less worth saving than those of others.
My concept of personhood, outlined in my book The Value of Life, and repeatedly
since,16 is clearly set out as, and explicitly stated to entail, that personhood is
a threshold concept and that once over the threshold all people have the same
moral status. I have repeatedly stated that this applies to all existing persons
regardless of quality of life, life expectancy, race, religion, nationality, level of
209
John Harris
disability, and much more besides! Moreover the threshold is a very low one, so
that all self-conscious human beings, however disabled and regardless of quality of
life, will qualify. This will include all infants at some point, probably17 in the first
six months of life, and all adults, save those who have permanently lost
consciousness, for example, those in a permanent vegetative state.18
As I have frequently said:
People are equal and equally worth treating or saving and equality is
not health status dependent. When we say all are equal we exclude
discrimination on the basis of all the usual suspects: race, gender,
religion, and so on. The moral principle outlawing discrimination
protects (or should protect) all persons equally. People’s lives and
fundamental interests should be given equal weight regardless of race,
creed, colour, gender, age, life expectancy or quality of life so long as that
quality of life is worth having for the person whose life it is.19
It is difficult to know how I could be or could have been more explicit than this or
how I could more emphatically rebut the claim that: ‘‘Put in terms of worth,
Glover and Harris postulate three categories of lives: those more worth living,
those less worth living; and those not worth living.’’
These qualifications matter because the parody Häyry offers of my views
distinctly sharpens on the following page.
Glover and Harris would not kill existing people against their will,
presumably because they would have sufficient respect for the subjective
worth or value of their lives. But they would, in the light of their theory,
prefer a world with human lives which are more rather than less
worthwhile. If I could easily be replaced by a better copy, Glover and
Harris would have no problem with me being lost, because they have
no respect for me as an objectively separate entity. And this is exactly
the logic by which they also ignore the individuality of embryos and
fetuses.
I have to say that I would be sorely tempted to take Häyry at his word and
replace him and his book with better copies if I could. Happily for Häyry, but less
so for the plausibility of his claims about what I say or believe, I would not even
consider doing it even if I could. However, the fact remains that Häyry has totally
distorted what I, and I believe Glover, think and have said. Again, readers must
judge whether these claims of Häyry’s on such a fundamental and controversial
a set of issues are the words or actions of someone who sincerely abjures
confrontation. I, on the other hand, feel I have to confront such a serious
misrepresentation of my views.
There is no reason for Häyry to have to resort to ‘‘presume’’20 anything,
because I have set out my theory of personhood and the elements of it that
explain why it is normally wrong to kill innocent people against their will, and
these reasons are not subjective in any degree whatsoever. They derive from
objective, that is, publicly observable and discoverable, capacities that are
possessed by all individuals who have what is sometimes called ‘‘a right to
life,’’ but which I usually say are features that make life valuable in the sense that
we have strong moral reasons to save or preserve that life, if we can, and equally
strong reasons not to end such a life deliberately.21 These features are not only
observable but there are reliable and accepted methods of testing for them even
when they are not self-evident. The features to which I refer are those that permit
210
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
self-consciousness, such as the ability of an individual, in John Locke’s famous
words, ‘‘to consider itself the same thinking thing in different times and
places.’’22 To translate this, it is the ability to possess and exhibit awareness of
oneself as existing over time and possessing the ability to have a view about
whether one wants that existence to continue or not. For any language user the
test is simple to apply: you ask them if they want to go on living or not, and
a simple yes or no or the gestural equivalent is objective evidence that they
possess the requisite state of consciousness. Of course, there may be doubt in
individual cases, just as there may be doubt about whether the evidence for any
objective feature of the universe has been established in a particular case. But that
doubt does not turn the objective into the subjective; rather it makes the
objectivity of the claim doubtful in a particular case. I may not be able to find
the evidence as to whether or not a particular painting is a genuine Vermeer; that
evidence may not be known; but whether it is a Vermeer or not remains
a question of fact. Either Vermeer painted it or he did not!
John Coggon (in a personal communication) has suggested that Häyry’s use of
‘‘subjective’’ is supposed to refer to the individual’s self-evaluation as contrasted
with an evaluation that accords with some contradictory account of the good that
Glover and I take to be objectively existent. In other words, Häyry may be using
‘‘objective’’ to refer to what I think is, in fact, worthwhile from a rational viewpoint
and ‘‘subjective’’ to refer to what a person thinks himself, even if that flies in the
face of the rational. Despite the temptation to accept Häyry’s compliment in
suggesting that what I think is worthwhile from a rational point of view is
‘‘objective,’’ I would never (I hope!) have used such an ambiguous and selfaffirming term in such a context, not least because I believe that the individual is
absolutely entitled to have her own determination of the good for herself respected.
And this is why, either way, Häyry is (fortunately) perfectly safe from me even
if a better copy of him could be produced. He is manifestly a self-conscious being
who has demonstrated this objectively, not least by writing his book. So not only
is it not the case that I would have no problem with his being ‘‘lost,’’ as he so
elegantly puts it, I would defend his entitlement to life (and that of any copies of
him that may be produced) as strongly as I would defend my own; and those
who know me know there is nothing stronger than that!
And as for ‘‘And this is exactly the logic by which they also ignore the
individuality of embryos and fetuses,’’ I am not sure I even understand the
charge. I have never ignored the individuality of embryos or fetuses. I think Häyry
is using the term ‘‘individuality’’ as a surrogate for ‘‘moral status’’ and is trying to
say that the same reasons that lead me to be sanguine about his death lead me to
accept abortion and embryo experimentation. Because I am not sanguine about
disposing of Häyry (except metaphorically or with argument), no extrapolation
can be made to my views on embryos and fetuses. However, and for the record, I
have argued23 that the ‘‘logic’’ that applies to embryos and fetuses is entirely
different precisely because they are not persons and lack the objective feature of
self-consciousness. Logic in English law (and that of any jurisdiction that permits
some abortions but no murders) is also relatedly different.
It may, of course, be that Häyry could show that my theory of personhood is
subjective and not objective, but this would take some attempt at an argument on
his part.
Häyry concludes this section as follows:
211
John Harris
But with the division (of lives into three rather vague categories)
introduced by Glover and assumed by Harris, the conclusion can be
manipulated to match our predetermined views. If we do not want to
condone the birth of individuals with a specific congenital ailment, we
simply define this ailment as making their lives not worth living, and no
further calculations are needed. This I would like to argue, is not
consequentialism in its purest form.24
Note first that what was originally described as ‘‘Glover and Harris postulate
three categories of lives [my emphasis]’’ has now been weakened to ‘‘introduced
by Glover and assumed by Harris [my emphasis].’’ It looks as though Häyry has at
some point realized that I have never used these categories in the way that he
requires.
The implication of this passage is that unscrupulous people like Glover and
Harris have set things up so that they can simply define any ailment as severe
enough to make life not worth living and, on the basis of this, justify either
abortion or embryo selection to avoid the birth. However, my theory of the value
of life does not require either abortion or embryo selection to be justified on any
grounds other than the moral status of the embryo or fetus, and certainly, for me,
disability or ‘‘ailment’’ does not add one jot to the justification for embryo
selection or abortion. In other words, for me, the legitimacy of abortion or embryo
selection or indeed research on embryos does not depend in any way on those
embryos or fetuses having any ailment whatsoever, congenital or not! And
because, for me, neither embryos nor fetuses have lives the ending of which
requires justification, other than in terms of their moral status (shared by all
embryos and fetuses), no calculations of any sort are called for. So that so far from
‘‘no further calculations’’ being needed, following some labeling exercise, no
calculations are needed at all, nor indeed is any labeling exercise. To be plain, for
me, the quality of potential life, or disease state, of embryos plays no part in the
justification for selecting against them or ending their existence. This is for
the simple, and for me sufficient, reason that they will never live to experience
the bad effects of that life or that disease state. We have no more responsibility for
selecting against them or ending their existence than we do for failing to conceive
an embryo that will expectedly have a good life. If, on the other hand, we choose
to keep them alive, then we do have a responsibility for the foreseeable state in
which they are likely to live.25
Finally, there is what I take to be a suggestion that I am inconsistent because I
have occupied a position which is ‘‘not consequentialism in its purest form’’ . . .
Ouch! Well, I do not claim to be a consequentialist, pure or impure, although I
sometimes admit to that charge when leveled against some of my arguments.26
This is a label applied to me by Häyry and others, and if I do not conform to their
stereotypes of what a consequentialist should be, that is nothing to me!
Häyry concludes:
I see two main question marks in the model advocated by Glover and
Harris. The first is their division of life’s worth or value into three levels
of ‘‘more,’’ ‘‘less,’’ and ‘‘none.’’ . . . My second problem with the model is
its tendency to see opposing views as irrational. All appeals to
prevailing norms and values, be they grounded on religion, local
custom, or people’s actual beliefs, are dismissed as going against
reason—unless they happen to support the ideas championed by Glover
and Harris, in which case they go unquestioned.27
212
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
I have dealt with the first question mark. For the rest, in my approach to ethics I
have identified a number of very general principles that I believe recommend
themselves to reason not least because they appeal to justice or to prudential selfinterest or to the protection and promotion of the lives, liberty, welfare, and
flourishing of all persons. There are good reasons to prioritize all these values
and in showing how they are promoted or frustrated by any act or omission,
policy program, or practice. I have tried, throughout both my philosophical work
and my contributions to, or interventions in, public policy and public affairs
more generally, to promote these values using a combination of evidence and
argument, in short by using reason. I defend the views I hold because they
recommend themselves to reason and because they promote the values I hold
and have just identified. In criticizing opposing views I always try to show why
they are not supported by evidence or argument or are not thereby adequately
supported. I do not think those who disagree with me are irrational. I do not
think, or have ever implied, that they are irrational in an existential sense—that
they have no reason or have poor powers of reasoning. I criticize what I perceive
to be flaws in the principles they espouse or with the evidence or arguments they
produce to support what they say or because they produce neither evidence nor
argument in support of them.
It is unworthy of Häyry to suggest that either Glover or I dismiss ideas of others
unless they happen to agree with us (is this suggestion of Häyry’s confrontational?)28 We disagree with them because we have found reason to believe that
they may be wrong. When we give these reasons, this is not as an attempt to
dismiss or suppress their views, but always as a challenge for these views to be
justified and our own contrary or divergent views to be shown to be flawed.
One further but fundamental disagreement that I do have with Häyry’s general
approach is that he believes there are different kinds of rationality. There are not.
There are many different ways of being rational and many different forms of
argument and of considerations that may count as evidence. To understand these,
or as many of them as possible, is a lifetime activity. The next challenge is to use the
tools available to the mind to enable us, for example, to suit means to ends and to
find ways of testing hypotheses and of evaluating arguments, in short of acting
rationally. This is not the place for a more thorough discussion of rationality. Häyry
is right that no one has a monopoly of rationality or privileged access to rational
processes, but none of his protagonists have, I believe, claimed otherwise.
Häyry is an excellent philosopher who has produced and continues to produce
work of the first quality. We do have fundamental disagreements, not least in
style and also in methodology. But we also have many points of agreement. He is
a courteous and stimulating philosopher with whom to engage. His book is
decidedly worth reading and contains some superb insights. I cannot forebear to
cite, with pleasure and admiration, at least one:
Parity of reasoning arguments polish the rails leading from one
normative position to another, but where the train ends up depends
on the direction in which our moral intuitions steer it.29
I would have substituted the heavenly twins ‘‘evidence and argument’’ for his
‘‘moral intuitions,’’ but the thought is admirably memorable and apposite.
Finally, I hope the arguments of my contribution to this exchange are robust.
That is, I hope my arguments are minimally flawed and minimally vulnerable to
213
John Harris
objections. This hope (perhaps ambitious) is one I am sure Häyry and I share
about our respective work. But I also hope this paper has been robust in another
sense, a sense to which I aspire in everything I write; that is, I hope it is clear,
strong, forthright, and forcefully expressed. This is because I believe that the
purpose of philosophy is not just to understand the world but to change it.30 Of
course I believe that change should be change for the better, which is why I have
written so frequently and over such a long period about human enhancement. To
argue for, and hence to advocate, change for the better and to attempt to discover
what constitutes such change is, I strongly believe, one of the fundamental
purposes of, and justifications for, philosophy and indeed for science. Socrates
and Plato understood this, as did Hobbes, Bentham, Mill, Marx, Russell, and
Jonathan Glover. All were in some sense confrontational philosophers, and I am
not ashamed of following, albeit at some considerable distance, their inspiring
example. This sort of robustness may well be appropriately characterized as
confrontational; I make no apology for that. The fact that I adopt a robust
approach may be as much a matter of personal style as it is of devotion to
methodology. Those I most admire seem to have this quality, but that is simply
a biographical remark about me. Very often, however, style is also important in
the persuasiveness of an argument and hence is a rhetorical device often as
potent as the syllogism. Many will prefer Häyry’s avowedly nonconfrontational
credentials to my more direct approach on that ground alone. Both Häyry and I
will, I hope, want them to go behind the style to the content. Hence this exchange.
Notes
1. Coggon J. Confrontations in ‘‘genethics’’: Rationalities, challenges, and methodological responses.
Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2011;20(1):46–55.
2. The Shorter Oxford English Dictionary Third Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1968.
3. The word safe, of course, can only mean safe enough, the degree of risk being relative to the
quantum of benefit.
4. Häyry M. Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press; 2010:41.
5. See note 4, Häyry 2010:40.
6. See note 4, Häyry 2010:238.
7. See note 4, Häyry 2010:31. Here Häyry attributes a view to Jonathan Glover and me (which I
believe neither of us holds). He then says complainingly, ‘‘This, I would like to argue, is not
consequentialism in its purest form’’ as if (a) we are committed to consequentialism in that form
and (b) we are committed to the view he ascribes to us!
8. See, for example, Häyry’s attribution to me, without any evidence or citation, of a range of things I
have never said. See note 4, Häyry 2010:31, para 2 (discussed in more detail below).
9. See note 4, Häyry 2010:31, note 36.
10. See note 8.
11. See note 4, Häyry 2010:29–39.
12. Harris J. Wonderwoman and Superman. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1992.
13. See Harris J. Enhancing Evolution. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press; 2007:168ff,
and Harris J. The Value of Life. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; 1985:10–27, 134, and 162.
14. Cook P. Tragically I Was an Only Twin. Cook W, ed. London: Arrow Books; 1993:101.
15. See note 4, Häyry 2010:30.
16. See also Harris J. The concept of the Person and the value of life. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal
1999;9(4):293–308.
17. Because when infants acquire personhood is essentially an empirical and hence objective matter
on my theory, there will be some uncertainty in individual cases.
18. See note 16, Harris 1999.
214
The Challenge of Nonconfrontational Ethics
19. Harris J. It’s not NICE to discriminate. Journal of Medical Ethics 2005;31(7):373–5. See also Harris J.
Resource allocation, victims of circumstance. In: Singer P, Kuhse H, eds. A Companion to Bioethics,
2nd ed., Oxford: Basil Blackwell; 2009:374.
20. Indeed, Häyry himself knows that there is no reason for any such presumption because he states
on page 214 of his book that ‘‘for Harris the point of our existence—its ‘meaning’—is to lead
worthwhile lives; and anything that interrupts this against our own wishes is bad.’’
21. See note 13, Harris 2007, note 13, Harris 1985, and note 16, Harris 1999.
22. Locke J. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London: Oxford University Press; 1964:bk II,
p. 188.
23. See note 13, Harris 2007, and note 13, Harris 1985.
24. See note 4, Häyry 2010:31.
25. I do not suppose that this brief summary of my position on the moral status of embryos or fetuses
is set out in sufficient detail to be convincing. For that, please see my The Value of Life (see note 13).
I merely summarize the argument here to show that, valid or not, it is not what Häyry thinks it is.
26. Although I do, like almost every other theorist, use consequentialist arguments, and in my own
case, admittedly somewhat frequently.
27. See note 4, Häyry 2010:40.
28. ‘‘Was this ambition?’’ See Shakespeare’s Julius Caesar for the irony of this note and this quote!
29. See note 4, Häyry 2010:225.
30. See my espousal of Marx’s famous remark from Theses on Fuerbach, No XI, in Feuer LS, ed. Marx
and Engels. London: Collins Fontana; 1972, cited in my Wonderwoman and Superman, note 12, p. 162.
215