Sport, Ethics and Philosophy
ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rsep20
Sport and Politics in the Twenty-First Century
Sandra Meeuwsen & Lev Kreft
To cite this article: Sandra Meeuwsen & Lev Kreft (2022): Sport and Politics in the Twenty-First
Century, Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2152480
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2152480
© 2022 The Author(s). Published by Informa
UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group.
Published online: 07 Dec 2022.
Submit your article to this journal
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rsep20
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2152480
ARTICLE
Sport and Politics in the Twenty-First Century
Sandra Meeuwsena and Lev Kreftb
a
Erasmus School of Philosophy, Erasmus University Rotterdam, Netherlands; bUniversity of Lubljana,
Slovenia, Balkans
ABSTRACT
KEYWORDS
In this article, we address the aporia(s) of the Olympic discourse
produced by the troubled split between sport and politics. To start
our argument, we will show that sporting governing bodies continuously insist that they are still on the other side of any kind of
politics. Guided by Aristotle, who presented the reciprocity of ethics
and politics, we will unveil the fallacy of this discourse. In a short
genealogy of the relationship between sport, ethics, and politics,
we will highlight the Munich Olympics 1936 and Mexico Olympics
1968, where political engagement of sport was exposed clearly. At
the same time, the supposed political neutrality of sport manifested
an aristocratic preference for radical right regimes. After that, we
will analyse the contemporary relation between sport, ethics, and
politics in the light of recent developments, including sport’s
ambiguous reaction on the Ukraine war. Further argument will be
that sport’s in- and external politics, supported by sport ethics and
the inherited mantra of the split between sport and politics, is more
than just a hypocrisy. At the start, modern sport claims autonomy of
governance to keep away from state domination, yet this very
autonomy also freezes sport’s ethical core, forbidding athletes,
coaches and others active in sport, to express any political engagement, other than passive acceptance of the regulation by governing sport bodies, as the only politics to be respected without
deliberation. In the final part an alternative understanding of the
dynamics between politics, the political and sport’s ethical core, will
be presented to be included in the philosophy of sport and fully
developed in following articles.
Sport; politics; ethics;
governance; agency
To build up our argumentation, we start with shedding a different light on the Olympic
discourse, and political engagement of sport governing bodies under IOC regime. Why is
the separation of sport and politics still considered to be undisputable, and how has this
split been introduced in sport initially? And how come sport governing bodies still believe
themselves to be on the other side of any kind of politics?
A Different Genealogy
‘No kind of demonstration or political, religious or racial propaganda is permitted in the Olympic
areas’ (Olympic Charter 2021, Rule 50.2, 93).
CONTACT Sandra Meeuwsen
[email protected]
© 2022 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License
(http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, and is not altered, transformed, or built upon in any way.
2
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
If we walk slowly, enjoying the surroundings, there is no awareness of breathing. But the
moment when we start to run and adapt our breathing to the fact, awareness of breathing
arises and starts to occupy a running body. The same goes for politics. Once we gain
insight in the politicized nature of modern sport, the constitutive element which has
always been considered as a neutral position on ‘the other side’ of politics, shall be
unveiled as politics itself, and a need for change comes to mind. This awareness seems
to currently hit the IOC community of sport, facing the fall of the bipolar system of
political balance on a global scale1; sport’s so-called political neutrality, even split from
any kind of politics, is revealed to be deeply politically affected. And not by any kind of
politics, but merely by radically conservative, aristocratic, and non-democratic politics.
How did this ever happen to our precious social practice?
The first reason to consider is the transformation of global political powers, as a result
of the fall of the formerly binary division between the Soviet Union and the West. A cynical
response could be, that history is over because there are no choices left but the prevailing
(neo)liberal way of politics. During the process of adaptation to this new global political
reality, new constellations of values and ideologies come together, with renovated old
and emerging new superpower pretenders. Such shifts need and cause new understanding of what is actually taking place, as ‘. . . historical reality is changed from an epoch to
another together with modifications on the scales of values’.2. Sport authorities until now,
did not adapt by reconsidering the attitude which made their conservative right-wing
politics detectable and visible, although they can no longer hide their political preference
behind an overlay of political neutrality.
Let us return to the beginning. Rule 50 in the Olympic Charter is very concrete and
narrows the field of strict separation to ‘Olympic areas’, which function only during the
Olympic Games, and puts the political at the same level as religious or racial propaganda.
It thus contains a certain conception of what politics is about. The most comprehensive
declaration of political positioning of the Olympic Movement can be found in the
Fundamental Principles of Olympism (5): ‘Recognising that sport occurs within the framework of society, sports organisations within the Olympic Movement shall apply political
neutrality’. (Olympic Charter 5; 11). Political neutrality which can be applied to governments, civil administration, or nation-states’ attitudes, respectively means that the person
neutral is above conflicts—in this case, above political conflicts. This implies autonomy
from all conflicting political positions and powers, and that is exactly what the Olympic
Charter defines, as a specific promise: ‘They (sport organizations and associations) have
the rights and obligations of autonomy, which include freely establishing and controlling
the rules of sport, determining the structure and governance of their organisations,
enjoying the right of elections free from any outside influence and the responsibility for
ensuring that principles of good governance be applied’. (Olympic Charter 5; 11). The
separation of Olympic sport (including the Olympic Movement as a global community of
sport organizations and associations) from politics is not an absolute principle, but
a fundamental condition to introduce autonomy of sport governance and management
from political interference, and to disable political demonstrations in sport events.
However, it also works the other way around: sport accepted autonomy and in return
gave up its political potential. This dialectical reciprocity between sport and politics is the
object of our research. We need some genealogy to comprehend its implications an open
up to the future.
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
3
For how did the IOC understand its neutrality and how did they prevent athletes from
introducing their political statements into competition? The iconic and notorious example
of the Berlin Olympics and all the struggles about rules of participation at these games,
show how these two principals—neutrality and non-politics—were applied at the time.
As for political neutrality, the Olympic Movement, de Coubertin and Brundage in front, did
give their gratuitous support for the National-Socialist concept of the Olympics, with
some lesser compromise concerning unwanted political messages, and finally allowed
some presence of Jewish and Black athletes. Synchronizing these liberal values with an
autocratic political discourse, gave rise to modern sports as the globally expanding social
practice, sanctioning racist and sexist ideals. And as for athletes, those who might show
some outspoken signs of criticism towards the Nazi regime and its racist and terrorist
treatment of non-Nazi and non-Arian subjects, were strongly discouraged to do so. The
only way to do it was by boycotting the Berlin Olympics, sacrificing their Olympic
opportunities. A boycott was the only possible political stance against the legitimizing
Nazi Games, because Olympic neutrality implicitly—and in the end: explicitly—meant
Olympic support for the rising National-Socialist political agenda. The point of political
neutrality which accepted and even elevated games of 1936 into a standard to be
followed by the others was found in the muscular nationalism as a typical politics of all
fascisms, but not just them. Here, the organizer of Berlin and promotor of later Munich
games Carl Diem, and Pierre de Coubertin are in perfect agreement. Carl Diem: ‘I do not
think I am going too far in saying that Germany is the country where we have the best
approach to the goal of strengthening the national energy through the systematic
practice of physical exercises’. (Diem 1943). De Coubertin: ‘. . . in this laicised century,
a religion was at our disposal; the national flag, symbol of modern patriotism rising to the
food of victory to reward the winning athlete, this is what would continue the cult with
rekindled hearth’. (de Coubertin 1967 (1929), p. 114). A standard was set. Virtuousness and
duty to Olympism became the constituting moral axes building the dominant ethical
discourse in sport.
Unfortunately, the primacy of ethics also provided a covering legitimacy, idealizing the
virtuous nature of true sportsmanship. As this moral agency of sport gained strength,
producing specific concepts and methods, the political vacuum in sport grew as well,
politicizing sport even more. Let us unpack this statement in two steps, before we return
to our genealogy. The current body of knowledge in sport ethics is strongly inspired by
Aristotle’s virtue ethics. However, Aristotle related the questioning of moral issues, virtues
and vices, brought together in the discipline of ethics, systematically to the conception of
the political aspect of life, simply: politics. As Aristotle says in both his Nicomachean Ethics
and his Politics, morality is not just a disposition of good character, a quality of our
intimate self, but this virtuous subjectivity is always related to achieving the Good,
performing an activity or function in the world, both in private life, ruling a household
or property (oikonomia), and in public life, as a citizen of the ancient polis (Nicomachean
Ethics, 1094a1-1096a6). So the first pre-juridical ‘community’ Aristotle discerns is the
oikonomia, the private household. And he does so in his main treatise on ethics.
The first book of Aristotle’s Politics is again devoted to household management, as an
example of ruling the state (polis) on a natural basis, yet in a smaller way. As it appears,
Aristotle considers both realms of life, so both the oikonomia and the polis as the political,
in which we should manifest excellent virtues, be it in different ways. It is in this respect
4
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
that we should comprehend his famous statement: ‘Man is by nature a political animal’.
(Politics, 1253a1). One might even say that Aristotle’s definitions and assumptions prelude
the contemporary complex relation between politics and economy, referred to as political
economy. To conclude for now: ever since antiquity, the striving towards virtuousness has
been at the heart of political science. Aristotle’s major premise on the ontological
reciprocity between morality and the political, might inspire both the sporting community and the philosophy of sport to recapture the political, complementary to the
prevailing moral discourse.
Our second justification is derived from the thought of Alain Badiou (1937 -). Badiou
critically addresses the tendency in modernity to absolutize ethical discourse, isolated
from the political, creating an ethical doctrine, religion alike (Badiou 1993). In this paradigm politics is considered to be a derivative of ethics. The ‘canonisation’ of supposed
universal, yet strongly politicized concepts like human rights, fairness, freedom and
equality are examples of this ethical ideology. Badiou unveils the modern concept of
both deontological and virtue ethics as a semi-religious dispositive, in which our own
perspective (dominantly Western, masculine, neoliberal) determines the norm, and ‘Evil’ is
placed with the Other, even under the guise of ‘recognition of the other’. The Other is only
acceptable if it confirms itself to the dominant moral regime, to the appropriate as
defined by the ruling majority. This ethical ideology is based on the principle of identity;
the morally preferred corresponds to the demand and morality of a transcendent, virtuous subject, setting the standard. The persistence with which any difference is disqualified
from this sacred self, even from the principle of diversity, can be seen, for example, in the
fight against radicalisation or populism. From our Western perspective, we firmly condemned the Chinese regime during the Beijing Winter Olympics, thus demonstrating an
unprecedented, rather elitist example of ‘Eurocentrism’. Why accept that things can be
different, based on a moral standard that we do not (wish to) know? Difference is allowed,
as long as it fits in the dominant Western tradition, meeting our superior moral standards.
This ideologizing, almost sacred concept of ethics is clearly constitutive for modern
sports. The primacy of morality is expressed in concepts like Fair Play and sportsmanship,
and values like equality or integrity. The prevailing sport ethics tradition, combining
Kantian deontological ethics (collective duties) with Aristotelian virtue ethics (individual
behaviour) might be seen as the ethical ideology Badiou uncovers to be nihilistic: ‘The
power of ethics is a symptom of a universe ruled by a special combination of resignation
to the necessary. . .. The modern name for necessity, as we know, is economics’. (Badiou
1993). As the field of economics has no intrinsic ontological value, besides a financial aim,
an ethical ideology is desperately needed to add morality, obedience, and intrinsic values
to political economy. Famous studies in our field of knowledge, like ‘Ethics in Sport’
(Morgan 2001) and the more contemporary ‘Sport and Moral Conflict’ (Morgan 2020),
state that moral reflection is the best thing to do, to find a response to distortions and
moral debilities of sport, like corruption and the use of doping. The Olympic ideals are
described as intrinsically constituting sport, which puts the moral congruence of the IOC
to strain. Instead of turning the problems modern sports are facing into a political inquiry,
the authors argue that we should stick to an even more intense moral scrutiny: ‘And if we
are going to be successful in plying that moral scalpel, we will need to be able to see sport
both for what it really is and what it is capable of at its best’. (Morgan 2001, Preface). This
discourse, like many others in our field, admires sportsmanship as a moral extraordinaire.
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
5
In this approach, the essence of sportsmanship cannot be derived from a legalistic code; it
is a pure spirit, a special attitude, a unique manner of living by the rules. Another classic in
this respect, McNamee’s ‘Sports, Virtues and Vices’ (Mcnamee 2008), situates ethics at the
very heart of modern sports, offering an aretaic, virtue-ethical account. Although neoliberal phenomena, like the MacIntyrean interpretation of Aristotle’s virtue ethics, rule-based
moralities and the tendency towards codification, are taken into question, the central
purpose again is to strengthen sport’s inherent ethical core and improve ethical development in and through sport, as the way out of a highly politicized field. It will not come as
a surprise that in both publications, the index does not contain the word ‘politics’, nor the
lemma ‘political’. To summarize, the prevalence of morality in sport created a ‘sporteconomic trinity’ between modern sport, ethics, and (the lack of) politics.
With these concerns in mind, let’s take up our genealogy. The Second World War
profoundly changed what political neutrality meant, merely by adding those fundamentals which were included in United Nations basic documents: condemnation of fascism
and Nazism, and establishment of human rights as the most important international
guarantee of individual and group freedom, and restriction of state and government
unrestrained abuse of power. Under these circumstances, and during bipolar political
division of the global world, the case of the 1968 Mexico Olympic Games can demonstrate
on the kind of political neutrality, on the kind of prohibition of athletes’ political statements in competition, and what kind of attacks against Olympic monopoly over global
sport appeared at that time. Let’s try and comprehend this case in critical philosophical
terms.
Ciudad de México in 1968 became the first Latin American city hosting the Olympics,
the first city from developing and non-aligned countries, and the highest location of
competitions, but also the first city with typical third world conflicts. Government under
president of Mexico Gustavo Díaz Ordaz had a history of long repression of trade unions
and farmers movement. The possibility that public unrest would deny the glory of
organizing such a complicated and luxurious event, conditioned the explosion of state
violence against protesters (mostly students), culminating in that unbelievable Tlatelolco
massacre against unarmed people 2 October 1968: only ten days before the Olympics
were to start. The number of killed and wounded was and is still disputed, but
a conservative assessment says that several hundred died and at least 1500 were
wounded. In a most cynical sense, sport and politics met at a distance guarded by guns
and tanks, just to embrace each other at the opening of the Olympic Games. The freedom
to speak up, denied to those revolting students, was not allowed to athletes either. At the
200 meters medal ceremony, Tommie Smith (gold medallist) and John Carlos (bronze)
appeared, raising their black-gloved fists, and wearing black socks instead of shoes, to
show support for the civil rights movement. Australian white athlete Peter Norman (silver)
did not raise his hand, or followed the attire of the other two, but he also wore a civil rights
badge. Smith and Carlos were expelled from the Olympic Village and persecuted sometime later as well, and Peter Norman’s career ended because of his gesture of solidarity: he
never made it again to represent Australia. A second standard was set.
Putting politics apart from sport, legitimized by the acclaimed autonomy of sporting governance bodies, meant that athletes were not allowed to politicize at the field
of competition, or they could expect harsh sanctions. Now where did the principal of
human rights go? Jacques Rancière (1940 -) introduces the axiom of equality as the
6
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
rise of the political, against all differences of race, sex, gender, class, nation—whatever. Universality of equality’s appeal cannot be reduced. The principal of human
rights as the moral archè of Western politics shares the same faith. Political discourse
presupposes undisputable principals, not belonging to politics. As Rancière clearly
states: nothing is political by itself (Rancière 2017). In modern sport this double
political vacuum—the ban of politics and sport’s not politically validated principals
—easily produces a hegemonic order, proclaiming moral superiority sanctioned by
absolute principals like equality, fairness, and human rights. Again, stressing sport’s
ethical core and the primacy of sport ethics merely rendered a harmless, attractive
cover up, reinforcing the ongoing political-economic exploitation of modern sports.
Contemporary Situation
The first generation of executives in modern sports had aristocratic roots, and governed this booming social practice in an autocratic manner, being involved in all kinds
of in- and external politics. Collectively they showed sympathy for nation-state leaders
of similar regimes, namely autocratic inclination. Together they shared a view that
nation states would turn decadent if democracy and individualism should rule. People
need strong muscular role models, reaching excellence under an autocratic discipline,
to stay open to any kind of collective nationalist sacrifice. To those first executives, the
power and the glory of sport should be grounded on a strong regime, controlling and
perfectioning human bodies. Horne and Whannel (2012, p. 128) state three broad
categories in the politics of recent Olympics: boycotts, ‘reputation promotion’ (that is,
image enhancement) and ‘neo-liberalisation’ of the Olympics.3 If we include exclusions from competitions into the boycott-category, and agree that neo-liberalisation is
the ruling governing power in modern sport, this listing is contemporary enough. Yet
we need to take one step further; what at first appeared as the Olympic involvement
in conflicts over racism, colonialism and capitalism versus supporting socialism in
a bipolar world, nowadays is fought in terms of financial calculations, about deals
with corporations, and in relation to new media appearances. As stated earlier: politics
has turned into political economy. But why is economy qualified to be political?
Because neoliberal economy turns relations between people into relations of things,
community human relations into market competition of commodities. And these
transactions are deeply governed by politically validated objectives.
In sport we see this reflected in the primacy of business models. For instance, it may be
argued that the future success or failure of the initiative to establish a separate Football
League of champions, following the example of USA major leagues, does not depend on
ideology or sport-intrinsic values, but strictly on financial calculations. To be more specific,
on the interests of the most important UEFA partners (national associations and partner
corporations) with a special attention to broadcasting and new media reaction. This is
politics as well, but now political power is not manifested within nation-states or their
legislative and executive bodies, but in corporations of which sport associations are the
intersection of one among many. The most important political body to decide who will
win (and thus be in power) is a complex media algorithm, counting virtual attendance, not
elections. Besides that, the ongoing post-bipolar struggle seems to be developing into
a continuous fight, to decide which of the most powerful states and corporations will
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
7
stabilize their global influence after the former bipolar world disappeared. This turbulent
situation creates an extremely instable theatre of powerplay, and sport is willy-nilly
included into this global fight. But how?
This growing tension also shows in the political agency of athletes and sport organizations in the case of Black Lives Matter, and in the fast IOC response on Russian attack on
Ukraine. While sixty years ago those who demonstrated for equality and human rights of
black people, were persecuted in the name of the separation of sport and politics,
nowadays this divide provokes ‘taking the knee’ at the start of sport competitions by all
athletes, and strong political support of the audience. Those who did not want to consent
to such practice had to face contempt of other athletes and public. No sanctions were
applied against those who did bring politics in sport, even directly on the pitch. Quite to
the contrary, all sport leading bodies hurried to share this fight against racism. Thus, the
massive support for Kaepernick’s iconic gesture seems to represent an important actual
turning point in global sport. However, the IOC banned the slogan appearing at athletes’
apparel, because race was not among general principles allowed by the Olympic Charter.
Those allowed are peace, respect, solidarity, inclusion, and equality; universal values
validated by the dominant tradition in sport ethics.
This IOC intervention also sent a clear message: anything goes, but on the Olympic
Games only the most abstract and meaningless political declaration may be expressed by
the Olympic Charter and approved by the Olympic authorities, being the IOC. Thus, the
split changed from the one between sport and politics in general, to a new divide, namely
between the Olympic political authority and individual athletes’ rights to express their
political positions. Quite ambiguous; there’s politics ruling sport to exclude politics. So,
what did change over the years is the common political agenda against racism, and what
did not change is that political declarations only come from the IOC-supremacy down and
not the other way around. Consequently, the politics of sport still seems to be the politics
of authoritarian power, which can give in to political demands and positions arbitrarily, if
it only keeps the subordinates of sport subordinated, and strengthens the grip of leadership over athletes.
Furthermore: how did the world of sport respond to the Russian invasion of Ukraine?
Global public opinion clearly supported the Ukrainian people. The IOC had an example
from the case of former Yugoslavia during the nineties, allowing athletes of ‘new countries’ to compete as individuals, while introducing the ban on Serbian teams, appearing at
international championships, even if they qualified beforehand. But there was also
another example: the abundant use of doping among Russian athletes, under political
pressure from Russia, culminating at Olympic games. The IOC allowed some of these
athletes, if clean of doping, to appear as representatives of the Russian Olympic
Committee, yet without the formal Russian State insignia. If the IOC now, in the case of
this aggressive Russian war against Ukraine, wanted to act, they might be expected to
introduce something much stronger. So, they did. Olympic truce (ékécheiria) in ancient
Greece was an agreement between states not to attack Elis as a host city state during the
Olympic Games, and to provide a safe journey to and from Olympia to all athletes and
their entourage. Yet it was never meant to provide that all wars should stop, or that new
wars were not started during the Olympics. In 1992, the IOC decided to renew this
tradition, and got support from the United Nations, including the Russian Federation.
Since then, the Russian Federation violated this Olympic truce three times: in 2008, when
8
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
it was engaged in Russian-Georgian war, in 2014, when it occupied Crimea, and in 2022,
when it started the aggressive war against Ukraine. While there were some minor reactions to 2008 and 2014, the last is the first time IOC and sport associations came with
a general reply. The use of the Olympic truce to introduce measures against Russian
athletes, sounds a bit strange, not for its purpose, but because of its ritual and conservative pretext. But is it keeping a position of neutrality as sport’s political position? What
makes IOC and other bodies’ position is exactly the multipolar global situation, which is
not important from the point of view of aggression of Russia against Ukraine but must be
considered because of another war—the cold war between Russia and the West. For
neutrality, the declaration for peace would be very abstract, but with a multipolar world
where the Western view of globality is not accepted by many other global or local powers,
it would be understandable from an inherited position of a split between sport and
politics. The declaration of the IOC from February 28, International Olympic Commitee
(2022), states first that ‘The current war in Ukraine, however, puts the Olympic Movement
in a dilemma’, and concludes in the next paragraph ‘This is a dilemma which cannot be
solved’.4 Now what was this dilemma and why could not it be solved, but was still cut
through? One side of dilemma was that ‘. . . the Olympic Movement is united in its sense of
fairness not to punish athletes for the decisions of their government if they are not
actively participating in them . . .’. Another side is that ‘. . . athletes from Russia and
Belarus would be able to continue to participate in sports events . . . ’, but ‘. . . many
athletes from Ukraine are prevented from doing so because of the attack on their
country’. 5
These are not ethical criteria to overcome a (supposed moral) dilemma, they are
political criteria. One side of the dilemma is dubious: many Ukrainian athletes decided
to join the armed forces, but those who keep appearing in sport competitions are
numerous as well and keep repeating that their presence encourages Ukrainian soldiers
and Ukrainian people to resist. But this is not decisive point of critical approach to IOS’s
dilemmatic attitude. Also, it is not decisive that the IOC did not keep neutrality as its main
principle because the post-bipolar world does not allow for the point of neutrality.
Neutrality becomes a realistic position, only when all vectors of power produce
a balanced resultant, or, if there is just one dominant source of global power. In the
contemporary world, we are not there. The IOC’s dilemma is caused by this situation, and
they decided to follow just one source of power. They created a political explanation for
such resultant, insisting that this position is not politics and is not taking sides in the cold
war between aspiring empires. It is the IOC’s problem, how to survive as a dominant
global manager of sport, after taking sides in the cold war. The challenge for a future
political philosophy of sport is to analyse the prevailing sport governance system as one
of global political powers engaged in the cold war.
To a Political Philosophy of Sport
Both contemporary cases illustrate another disturbing phenomenon. Modern sport is not
only ‘capitalism at play’ (Collins 2013, p. 13); this economic game-playing is enabled,
exploited, and even governed by an expanding global political system. How come and
what are its implications? Giorgio Agamben (1946 -) unveiled western politics as a process
of the politically validated encapsulation of persons, activities, and domains, turning
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
9
democracy and state politics into repressive biopolitical regimes (Agamben 1998, 2016).
The global political community represents an autarchic mode of government, ruling all
forms of life, even those considered insufficient or inappropriate. The birth of modern
sport is constituted on the prohibition and exclusion of inappropriate drives and attitudes,
facilitated by specific regulation and sport ethics. In return, sporting governing bodies
were ‘allowed’ to create their own internal politics, the much-appraised autonomy of
sport governance. So following Agamben, what is still considered to be a unique achievement, ruling sport autonomously with specific regulations, disciplinary law, and intrinsic
values, should be reframed as a deceiving veil for a brutal biopolitical takeover. Sport as
that precious social practice in which intimate communities are born, where bodies
mature and excellence is cultivated, seems to be a field par excellence to be politicized.
Biopolitics is involved for the purpose of an enormous controlled and coordinated activity,
manifesting at the same time a global commodity production of tremendous economic
proportions. To conclude, the package deal at the start of modern sport, between mainstream state-politics and the first generation of sports executives, to grant sport its own
autonomy in terms of governance and regulation, created in return a situation of ‘free
play’, exploiting the precious field of modern sport to strengthen political economy in
a global political world.6
Now how to proceed from here? The aim of this article is not to put together proposals
for the reform of sport’s internal politics, addressed to sport governing bodies. What
needs to be developed in the first place, is a critical conceptual framework as a starting
point for a complementary political philosophy of sport. This framework should enable
the debunking of sport’s ethical ideology, mapping the field of sport as a place where
individual and collective actors consider their positions from an apolitical, ‘universal’ point
of view, distinguishing right from wrong. To do so, we should take into consideration the
field of in- and external politics, ruling sport. As such, we enter the field of powerplay,
where those without power try to find a way to survive and function without being totally
subdued to power(s). And sport has become an eminent field of power, struggles
between powers, and tactical conduct of those with less or no power to manage sport
—namely, athletes.7 The mapping of power in sport generally exposes the fact that power
is concentrated in IOC and specific sport bodies, with more power in those associations
which represent big sport business. On the other side, it marks the position of ‘everyday
athletes’ as subjected to the power hierarchy. This distribution of power is a political
activity and must be studied and eventually criticized as such. It has its ethical consequences, including that of the existence of two ethical universes, that of power and that of
lack of power to decide.
In completing the conceptual framework presented here, built from relevant insights
by Aristotle, Badiou, Rancière and Agamben, we will now add the position of Michel de
Certeau (1925 – 1986) in The Practice of Everyday Life: ‘I call a “strategy” the calculus of
force-relationships which becomes possible when a subject of will and power (a proprietor, an enterprise, a city, a scientific institution) can be isolated from an “environment”.
A strategy assumes a place that can be circumscribed as proper (propre in French, meaning “être propriétaire de” – “to be the owner of”) and thus serve as the basis for generating
relations with an exterior distinct from it (competitors, adversaries, “clientèles”, “targets”,
or “objects” of research). Political, economic, and scientific rationality has been constructed on this strategic model’.8 The governance model imposed by IOC or FIFA, with
10
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
abundant power of associations to manage most popular sports, should be qualified as an
enterprise, representing a hegemonic source of power politics in modern sport. The split
between sport and politics was needed to establish the independence of this political
power, creating an institutional dependency to all other carriers of external political
power (international organizations, nation-state governments, global media nets, global
corporations . . .). And then there are those ‘targets’ (athletes and players), who need to be
owned by proprietors (subjects of power), if they want to be an active part of the field.
Their activities mean devotion to sport in their everyday life under rules and conditions
established and managed by ‘subjects of will and power’. As stated earlier, those are the
very features of a biopolitical regime of power, ruling modern sport. The devotion is not
just limited to the game, its rules and values, but also affects other components of their
everyday life. This was revealed without reservation and concealment after the introduction of anti-doping control out of competition which, instead of oppressive discipline,
introduced a system of continuous surveillance.9
Still, the relationship between subjects of power (proprietors) and those subjected to
power is much more complex, because it entails the tactics of everyday life under subjects
of power. Whatever this power relation wins, it does not keep. It must constantly
manipulate events in order to turn them into ‘opportunities’. The weak must continually
turn forces alien to them to their own end and benefit. Those who are objects of power
produce invisible forms of resistance; invisible until the power’s inability to continue to
manage the field is exposed as unmanageable, clearing in the heart of power. This
invisibility conditions everyday tactics as non-political, merely conditioned by moral
concepts, like duty and virtue. Its precondition is that power is unsophisticated, primitive
and in love with its own perception of the reality as something mastered and under
control. Modern sport, with its own governance, regulations and values, seems to fit
perfectly in this understanding of global power politics.
However, to get at the emergence of the political, a political subject must be
produced, not given by the institutionalized framework of politics. Even Aristotle’s
major premise on the ontological reciprocity between morality and ‘the political’,
might convince us to develop a proper political philosophy of sports, complementary
to modern sports’ dominant moral discourse. ‘the political’ in late modernity is a result
of a battle for political recognition and comes from involvement in fight when it
becomes clear that some politics has to be developed for the sake of a successful
outcome. The political together with the political subject emerges when those demanding better conditions become aware that without being recognized and included as
political subjects, they can win a few and lose a few battles, but will never overturn the
absence of their political power.
Why not analyse what’s currently happening in Qatar during the World Cup Football?
Our struggle with this bizarre event derives from the continuous tension between
a football regime (FIFA) that pretends to be outside politics, but at the same time plays
plenty of politics by bowing to Qatari rulers. This tension becomes more and more visible
and unbearable, resulting in a growing number of incidents that debunk the current
relation between sport and politics. To cite just a few examples, what about the ‘JFK’
speech by FIFA president Infantino, in which he presents himself as gay, migrant and all
those other identities at odds with both football culture and the political preferences in
Qatar? This Kafkaesque speech was immediately followed by the FIFA-ban on wearing
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
11
‘One Love’ bracelets or shirts that refer to diversity and inclusion. Here, we see FIFA taking
credit for the political mores of the Qatari regime, enacting a sporting punishment: the
yellow card.
And there is more. Even Sepp Blatter recently distanced himself from the 2010 decision
to keep the World Cup 2022 in Qatar. In doing so, the former FIFA president once again
embarrassed us. If this man now turns away from Qatar, how can anyone else defend
innocent consumption of this World Cup? Blatter demonstrates the double standard in
football; on the one hand, the promise of connection and world peace, on the other the
reality of corruption and self-interest. Because Blatter et al. at the time did not heed Kant’s
‘categorical imperative’ (moral duty) surrounding the allocation of the World Cup to Qatar,
this vacuum has travelled with our perception of this event. In other words, where the
Kantian moral law is not respected, a debt arises that must be repaid sometime. This debt
is now surfacing in the present, as players, coaches, and all of us struggle with the
question of whether it is morally acceptable to enjoy this World Cup. This collective
guilt unveils the shame that Blatter et al. did not feel in 2010.
The lesson we learn from this: athletes have no political rights in sport. The second is
that if they address their grievances to the general public, they will be punished by the
sporting regime. This is a point where athletes must start to think about their status and
rights, which they do more and more often. Athletes and players compare the damage
done by opening Pandora’s box of the fight against internal sport politics, if compared to
the peaceful continuation of their sport lives, or, perhaps, leaving sport forever. Up to
now, the emergence of the political in sport was rare, and when it happened, it was either
punished as in cases mentioned above, or ‘accepted’ by sport authorities in a way which
put athletes again under command of sport authorities—as in the recent case of Colin
Kaepernicks’ gesture and ‘black lives matter’ in sport, which emerged as a spontaneous
reaction but was very quickly put under rules given by highest sport authorities. This
ability to depoliticize new political demands, like those for equal treatment of women of
farewell to false amateurism, of taking the ecological side of sport events, sport transportation, or building of grandiose sport architecture—they were all turned from sincere
political engagement of athletes, into accepted politics, not decided upon to regulate
equality, but to keep inequality of political power untouched. But some of today’s
problems in modern sport are grave and demand fundamental change of institutionalized
structure of decision-making for many reasons. Two of the most visible are the concentration of enormous capital in hands of few who do not submit to democratic control, and
the growing appetite for cooperation of sport authorities with the most authoritarian and
totalitarian regimes. In the last decade we experienced too many repetitions of the Berlin
Olympics trauma. These conflicting issues call for a stronger political status of athletes
themselves, and for converting toothless ‘democratization’ of sport into a resilient and
functional sport democracy.
Political philosophy of sport should not choose a specific position in these deliberations, but clarify some basic concepts like already mentioned difference between strategy
and tactics, and between ‘dirty’ politics and the political. As the first one is taken from de
Certeau, this second duality was developed by Jacques Rancière. His ‘Theses on Politics’
start with a decisive distinction: ‘Politics is not the exercise of power. Politics ought to be
defined on its own terms, as a mode of acting put into practice by a specific kind of
subject and deriving from a particular form of reason. It is the political relationship that
12
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
allows one to think the possibility of a political subject(ivity) [in French: “le sujet politique”], not the other way around’.10 This is clarified further by Thesis 7: ‘Politics is
specifically opposed to the police. The police is a “distribution of the sensible” [le partage
du sensible] whose principle is the absence of a void and of a supplement’.11 The political
emerges from the immanent truth that ‘. . .. equality is not a common measure between
individuals, it is a capacity through which individuals act as the holders of a common
power, a power belonging to anyone. Equality does not arise from the tertium comparationis between individuals, it is already there before any comparison. And the promise to
be “free” is just like the proposition “equal”: it does not designate a property of individuals’. (Rancière 1998, 2017, 2022). The so-called ‘police order’ of society which is
colloquially called politics, divides between those who belong and those who do not,
yet ‘another community’ is always imposed over the police of our social order. Sport
philosophy is involved in defining the conditions to (not) belong to the field of sport, and
thus the ‘distribution of the sensible’, creating inequality. If we are ready to accept this
uneasy truth, we should critically reconsider our power in this ‘police order’ to express
sport’s political potential.
When we add the difference between police and the political to the difference
between the strategy of power and the tactics of the powerless, we can conclude that
under contemporary circumstances of communication it becomes even harder to proceed from complaining and demanding to politicization. The embrace between subjection and subjectivation, and—especially in sport—demand of total depoliticization of the
field, using the assumption that anything political is dirty and unhealthy for sport, keeps
the sport field safe from open and direct politicization. But this will sustain the outburst of
the political in sport until all things proceed as usual. In troubled times (and we are in
troubled times, be it in global disbalance of imperial powers, which is developing into
more and more bloody wars: be it in consequences of ruining nature; be it in growing,
socially and politically unbearable precipice between growing extreme poverty and an
elite of super rich, an economic power most nation states do not possess), these developments are harmful for sport as it is, a domain of big corporations and authoritarian
leadership, but also of extreme nationalism which promoted sport (especially but not
exclusively football) into a cradle of organized extreme right violent activism—proving
that similar attracts similar.
As stated earlier, we believe that a new, critical political philosophy of sport should not
become a kind of politics to substitute what only the emergence of the political in sport
can do. But under contemporary global circumstances, it will argue against the false
principle of that sacred divide between sport and politics which is not respected by
authorities anyway, it will warn against the use of sport ethics for gaining more political
power over modern sport, and it will debunk the so-called ‘sport-economic-trinity’. In
order to do so, we will introduce recent and contemporary philosophies of the political
into sport philosophical considerations, debates and dialogues.
Notes
1. The bipolar stability that ruled global politics: the American hemisphere, ruled by liberal
democracy and capitalism, versus the Russian hemisphere, autocratic regimes and state
SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
13
controlled economic surveillance. This bipolar stability was shattered during the Post-Cold
War period.
Goldmann (1978), p. 42.
Horne and Whannel (2012), p. 128.
International Olympic Commitee (2022).
Ibid..
Those who are familiair with Judith Butler’s thought, might see similarities with her concept
of politics as a ‘constitutive outside’ (Butler and Athanasiou 2013). Yet, seen from the side of
politics, the domain of sport also represents the Agambean ‘reincluded outside’ (Agamben
1998, 15–30), legitimizing modern politics.
Against the military practice to understand tactics as use of strategy in the field of combat,
this difference between strategy and tactics is defined very subversively by.
de Certeau (1984), p. 17.
In Discipline and Punishment, Michel Foucault speaks about subordinate bodies that obey the
regulations and rules of power: ‘Generally speaking, all the authorities exercising individual
control function according to a double mode; that of binary division and branding (mad/
sane; dangerous/harmless; normal/abnormal); and that of coercive assignment of differential
distribution (who he is; where he must be; how he is to be characterized; how he is to be
recognized; how a constant surveillance is to be exercised over him in an individual way, etc.).
On the one hand, the lepers are treated as plague victims; the tactics of individualizing
disciplines are imposed on the excluded; and, on the other hand, the universality of disciplinary controls makes it possible to brand the “leper” and to bring into play against him the
dualistic mechanisms of exclusion. The constant division between the normal and the
abnormal, to which every individual is subjected, brings us back to our own time, by applying
the binary branding and exile of the leper to quite different objects; the existence of a whole
set of techniques and institutions for measuring, supervising and correcting the abnormal
brings into play the disciplinary mechanisms to which the fear of the plague gave rise. All the
mechanisms of power which, even today, are disposed around the abnormal individual, to
brand him and to alter him, are composed of those two forms from which they distantly
derive’. (Foucault 1977).
Rancière (2001).
Ibid..
Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
References
1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford California: Stanford University
Press.
AGAMBEN, G. 2016. The Use of Bodies. Stanford California: Stanford University Press.
Aristotle. 1986. Nicomachean Ethics. London: Penguin.
Aristotle. 1986. Politics. London: Penguin.
BADIOU, A. 1993. L’Éthique: Essai sur la conscience du mal. Paris: Hatier.
BUTLER, J. and A. ATHANASIOU. 2013. Dispossession: The Performative in the Political. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
COLLINS, T. 2013. Sport in Capitalist Society. London: Routledge.
DE CERTEAU, M 1984. The practice of everyday life, edited by S.F. Rendail). Berkeley: University of
California Press.
DE COUBERTIN, P. 19671929. Olympie. In L’idée olympique: Discours et essais edited by Carl Diem Institute.
Schondorf bei Stutgart. Verlag Karl Hoffmann.
AGAMBEN, G.
14
S. MEEUWSEN AND L. KREFT
1943. L’idée olympique dans la Nouvelle Europe. Berlin: Institut Terramare.
1977. Discipline and Punishment: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Pantheon.
GOLDMANN, L. 1978. Sciences humaines et philosophie: Pour un structuralisme génétique suivi de
Structuralisme génétique et création littéraire. Paris: Gonthier.
HORNE, J. and G. WHANNEL. 2012. Understanding the Olympics. London: Routledge.
International Olympic Commitee, 2021. ‘Olympic Charter’, available at: https://olympics.com/ioc/
olympic-charter (1.6.2022).
International Olympic Commitee. 2022. ‘IOC EB recommends no participation of Russian and
Belarusian athletes and officials’, published 28 February. Available at https://olympics.com/ioc/
news/ioc-eb-recommends-no-participation-of-russian-and-belarusian-athletes-and-officials
(accessed 1 June 2022).
MCNAMEE, M. 2008. Sports, virtues and vices. Morality plays. London: Routledge.
MORGAN, W. 2001. Ethics in Sport. Champaign: Human Kinetics.
MORGAN, W. 2020. Sport and Moral Conflict. A Conventionalist Theory. Philadelphia: Temple University
Press.
RANCIÈRE, J. 1998. Aux bords du politique. Paris: Gallimard.
RANCIÈRE, J. 2001. Ten Theses on Politics. Available at http://www.after1968.org/app/webroot/
uploads/RanciereTHESESONPOLITICS.pdf (accessed 1 October 2022).
RANCIÈRE, J. 2017. Reflections on equality and emancipation. Speech held at the International
Antiauthoritarian Festival of Babylonia Journal, 27 May. Available at https://autonomies.org/
2017/08/jacques-ranciere-reflections-on-equality-and-emancipation/ (accessed 1 June 2022).
RANCIÈRE, J. 2022. Les trente ingloriouses. Scènes politiques. Paris: La Fabrique éditions.
DIEM, C.
FOUCAULT, M.