Angelaki
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities
ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20
FORGIVENESS, EMPATHY AND VULNERABILITY
an unfinished conversation with pamela sue anderson
Paul S. Fiddes
To cite this article: Paul S. Fiddes (2020) FORGIVENESS, EMPATHY AND VULNERABILITY,
Angelaki, 25:1-2, 109-125, DOI: 10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717790
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717790
Published online: 26 Feb 2020.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 19
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 25 numbers 1–2 feb–apr 2020
W
hen, in May 2001, Pamela Sue Anderson came to Regent’s Park College,
Oxford for interview as a candidate for a Fellowship in Philosophy and Christian Ethics, she
chose to give her “sample lecture” on the
theme of forgiveness. I later discovered that
she had recently written a chapter on “A Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness” for a book titled Forgiveness and Truth, which was to be published
later in that same year.1 I had myself written on
the Christian approach to forgiveness in a book
on the idea of Atonement in 1998,2 and had
recently published a development of my argument in a book on experience of God as
Trinity.3 As a theologian, as well as Principal
of the college, I was naturally interested to discover what Pamela had to say about the
subject from the distinct perspective of a feminist philosopher of religion.
From that time onwards, indeed for the
sixteen years remaining of her too-short life,
Pamela and I held a sustained conversation
about the nature and practice of forgiveness.
Our talking together, in the Senior Common
Room and over meals, marked our friendship,
and seeped into print, both explicitly and
implicitly. Perhaps the climax of the conversation came in the participation of both of us in a
symposium on the place of forgiveness in the
practice of Restorative Justice (RJ), organized
by another Fellow of Regent’s Park College
(Myra B. Blyth) as part of her research
project, held in June 2014. Both our contributions, suitably revised, were published in
the Oxford Journal of Law and Religion in
2016, and there we took the occasion to enter
into more public debate. Then, in the last
year of Pamela’s life, the theme of forgiveness
took a slightly new form in the context of her
paul s. fiddes
FORGIVENESS,
EMPATHY AND
VULNERABILITY
an unfinished conversation
with pamela sue anderson
developing ideas on the place of vulnerability
in love.
In this paper I briefly want to re-trace the
stages of her thought on forgiveness, through
a series of six articles or book chapters that
she wrote, beginning with the piece from 2001
and ending with her final unpublished work.
At the same time, I intend to hold a dialogue
between her ideas on forgiveness and my own,
thus re-creating our conversation and finding
new insights within it that were not apparent
at the time. It is an exercise in that kind of
memory which – as she emphasized – can
“enact every situation anew” and “forge new
links with the future.”4 My only regret and
deep sadness is that she is not here to share in
ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/20/01–20109-17 © 2020 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717790
109
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
the conversation, and with her quicksilver critique to point up the “ethics of memory” and
so prevent any manipulation of my memories
of her to my own advantage. I am grateful for
the continuation of our warm and close friendship that this exercise offers, as well as the
opportunity to honour her pioneering thought
from which I have learned so much. Inevitably,
however, the conversation remains unfinished.
1 forgiveness as a struggle
The first emphasis that Pamela Sue Anderson5
wanted to make is that forgiveness is a struggle
that cannot be short-circuited. Here, I begin
with the book chapter that she had written
just as she came to Regent’s Park College in
2001, titled “A Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness.”
Her point of departure is a critique of what she
regards as a traditional Christian notion of forgiveness, and while it is not the only approach
it is admittedly widespread. Her “hermeneutic
of suspicion” involves a two-fold objection:
first, forgiveness of wrongdoing is expected,
even required, from people, especially women
and marginalized others; and second, it is
assumed that forgiveness is always possible
since it comes as a divine gift. Thus, she protested, forgiveness is used to reinforce the lack
of self-respect suffered by oppressed persons,
while the sense of self-respect is a rational good.6
In contrast to this Christian account (as she
sees it), she insists that forgiveness is always a
struggle. The experience of enslaved persons
in African-American history suggests that if a
wronged person is no longer to feel resentment
then there needs to be a painful emotional transformation. She writes that it is difficult to create
“stories recounting forgiveness that do not
involve the lack or loss of rational selfrespect,” and so “there is a struggle to create
new narratives of forgiveness and promise.”7
The conflict is between forgiveness and justice,
since justice entails the development of selfrespect, and this in turn requires a righteous
resentment against certain forms of wrongdoing
such as sexual abuse. Anderson sees the
dilemma thus: “how can the soul and its
emotions be transformed to achieve forgiveness
without a loss of self-worth in the face of
massive wrong-doing?”8
Anderson’s insistence on forgiveness as a difficult process of emotional transformation in the
victim seemed to me at the time to have affinities with the idea I had been developing,
that forgiveness is a costly journey. Forgiveness
can never be demanded of a victim, but the one
who wants to forgive, I had written, needs to
embark on a voyage of experience with two
stages to it. First, there is a journey of discovery
as the forgiver has to expose the truth of what
has been done to her, rather than forget about
it, and second there is a journey of endurance
as the forgiver absorbs the hostility and
anxiety of the offender.9 The aim of this twofold journey of empathy is to create a response
in the offender, who needs to face up to the
truth of his actions and to be won to the forgiveness which is being offered. The one who has
offended is more likely to come to self-realization and reconciliation if he or she experiences
the one forgiving as an accepting rather than a
judgemental person. From a Christian perspective, the victim who aims to forgive participates
in the journey of forgiveness which God has
taken universally through the life and death of
Christ. The forgiver takes an initiative which
relies upon the initiative taken by God in
making the deepest journey of empathy into
human lives.
As I talked this over with Anderson during
the years to come, the question which always
arose was whether my idea of forgiveness as a
journey of empathy with the offender allowed
sufficiently for expression of the righteous
resentment which the victim rightly felt. Did
it sufficiently reflect the struggle between forgiveness and justice? Yet in this early piece on
the theme, Anderson felt that oppressed
persons do want to let go of the resentment
they feel, however righteous it is, because of
the toll it takes on them. Forgiveness, she
believed, was characterized by “overcoming
certain potentially destructive emotions like
resentment.”10
Expanding her second critique of a Christian
approach, Anderson asks in this paper why
some enslaved persons were able to exemplify
110
fiddes
the virtue of forgiveness, and comments that
“Personally I do not see how a mere reference
to […] Christian forgiveness or grace, could
be a sufficient explanation.”11 The struggle
could not, and cannot, be short-circuited by an
easy divine gift, and so she makes the challenge
that it is necessary to develop what she calls a
“secular” understanding of forgiveness in
which self-worth is retained within a difficult
process. There is, she writes, “something
about emotional transformation that […]
[a Christian] perspective on forgiveness” cannot
achieve.12 In response, I would (and did) say
that when Christians receive the gift of entering
into the journey of God’s own forgiveness,13
this is indeed sharing in a struggle of feelings
and responses and is no superficial view of grace.
Forgiveness, Anderson urges, involves a
process of emotional and rational transformation of the person in order to achieve release
from resentment without loss of self-respect.
Here, she appeals to a number of witnesses
who were important to her thought during
the course of her writing. First, there is the
narrative account developed by bell hooks,
expressing her struggle with the stereotypes
which restricted the possibilities for black
women’s identities in African-American contexts; hooks, noted Anderson, came to an
inner transformation in a “gradual release
from these stereotypes” which became part
of “a redemptive process of ‘a writing
life.’”14 This painful process of “refiguring
the past” and creating “an imaginary
domain” in which persons can relocate themselves in relation to a past of pain and oppression, means that “forgetting is not the same as
forgiveness.”15 This is an insight that is also
central to my own model of a journey of forgiveness,16 and it raises the place of memory
in a feminist ethics of forgiveness which
Anderson was to explore more thoroughly in
her next piece on the theme.
Another witness for Anderson to the need for
transformation through emotional and rational
struggle is Gillian Rose, who points to the
“intense work of the soul, that gradual rearrangement of its boundaries” that is involved
in the process of mourning; in the paradigmatic
111
Greek stories of Phocion and Antigone, this is a
mourning which makes experiences of past
injustice “visible and speakable,” so that
“mourning draws on transcendent but representable justice.”17 Anderson suggests that
there is a similar process going on in forgiveness, where “release from resentment” occurs
as the person grieving over a transgression
against her “recognizes justice […] in representations (and new acts) of justice.”18 Yet a further
witness here is Paul Ricoeur, whom Anderson
makes a conversation-partner throughout her
work. Anderson proposes that “re-enacting”
narratives of the past anew in relation to
justice here and now can reshape the identity
of a culture or individual when there is a deliberate “struggle” with the difference of others
from oneself. She sees Ricoeur as explaining
this “shaping of narrative identity” in terms of
“the ‘entanglement’ of an individual’s story
with the story of others.”19 A feminist ethics
of forgiveness, she concludes, will take responsibility for the life stories of the other, “through
the exchange of narratives in imagination and
empathy.”20
Again, this seems close to my understanding
of forgiveness as a journey of empathy into the
life of another, but we must not miss that the
empathy Anderson had in mind was between
victims and others who are oppressed, not
between victim and oppressor. She might say,
if she were here: why should empathy include
the transgressor? And I would reply – that it
depends on whether one wants to achieve reconciliation with the other as well as freedom from
one’s own resentment.
2 forgiveness as making a new
future
Anderson’s next paper that reflected on forgiveness, titled “An Ethics of Memory: Promising,
Forgiving, Yearning” (2005), took its point of
departure from the question of how a person’s
identity might be retained in face of the challenge of the postmodern view of the “death”
of the self. It was in fact written for the Blackwell Companion to Postmodern Theology.
Drawing on the thought of Ricoeur and
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
Hannah Arendt, she proposed that our identity
through time consists in the making and
keeping of promises. It is through this that we
are the same person. Forgiveness thus
becomes necessary as a way of dealing with the
broken promises of others, opening up a
shared future.
The paper repeats the presentation of forgiveness from the 2001 piece as a difficult process of
emotional and rational transformation, but
there is no direct statement of a struggle
between forgiveness and justice. Elaborating
the theme of memory from the earlier book
chapter, the struggle is now portrayed as being
between the past and the future, and it takes
the form of a yearning to create just memories
which will move beyond the past to forge new
links with the future. She writes: “The struggle
leads to personal and social transformation only
insofar as the response to the injustice of broken
promises involves forgiving others and yearning
for the transformation of life’s narratives.”21
The process or struggle is defined here as a
“yearning,” including the “mourning” which
appeared in the earlier piece.22 Anderson proposes that we make “narrative sense of life”
through three acts which involve memory in
one way or another: there is the making and
keeping of promises, the forgiveness of broken
promises and yearning (for love and justice)
which holds together promise-keeping and forgiveness.23 Again she writes, “The ultimate
aim of my project is to apply an ethics of
memory to the feminist problematic of philosophy of religion,” explaining that “What needs
to be retrieved are the shattered promises, the
ability to forgive and the yearning which leads
to transforming melancholia into love and
justice.”24 In fact, the triumvirate of forgiveness, promising and yearning was not to play a
substantial part in Anderson’s future working
out of her “project,” though it merits a page
or so in her later Re-visioning Gender.25 In
that study she is interested in the “moral force
of love” in constructing a feminist epistemology
and ethics, in which “yearning” for love plays a
substantial part, and promise-keeping is
replaced by the “commitment” of love,
without the same reflection on forgiveness.26 If
she were here now I would want to ask her
why forgiveness was apparently downplayed in
what she intended as a major book on the gendering of philosophy of religion: it seems that
it no longer had the significance in the making
of human identity that she had given it earlier.
In this book chapter, forgiveness is still
closely bound to the elements of promising
and yearning, in making a story of the self
with an openness to the future grounded in
memory. Promise-making and promisekeeping achieve self-constancy in their continuing through the changes of time. This, Anderson stresses, is not just an individual act but a
communal act of commitment, a mutual
promise as the basis for shared convictions,
rules, norms, customs and beliefs.27 Forgiving
is linked with this phenomenon in freeing us
from a past of broken promises. Admittedly,
the forgiveness here relates to broken promises,
not explicitly to the abuse, violence or oppression that is in view in the first paper.
However, Anderson probably thinks that the
principles of forgiveness are the same in all
instances, since this piece develops the “ethics
of memory” she had proposed in the paper of
2001. After all, the breaking of a communal
promise, or a social contract, often does
involve oppression of particular groups, and
she suggests in Re-visioning Gender that the
breaking of personal promises can be emotional
abuse and involve a threat to self-respect.28 In
the 2005 book chapter, the yearning for justice
and lost love is also inseparable from forgiveness, since it is in “forgetting or forgiving”
that the yearning which is bound up with promising finds the freedom to be “unbound” from
promises that have failed to deliver.29 Anderson’s associating of “forgetting” and “forgiving”
in this context need not mean, of course, that
she has neglected the difference between them
that she registered previously.
The significance of forgiveness to both promising and yearning seems here to derive from
Anderson’s debt to Arendt, who proposes in
The Human Condition that we gain our narrative identity as agents who promise and
forgive. Promise-keeping and forgiveness
respectively “bind” and “unbind” us in time.
112
fiddes
Promising offers a remedy for the unpredictability of behaviour, and forgiveness offers the
remedy for “the predicament of irreversibility,”
i.e., being unable to undo what one has done.30
Anderson also gains from Arendt the perception
that the disclosure of “who” we are takes place
when a new beginning – natality – is established
through an action such as promising or forgiving which “falls into an already existing web of
relationships.”31 Thus, a single life story
affects the life stories of all. Anderson goes on
to find similar themes in Ricoeur who, like
Arendt, considers promise-keeping to be an
example of “the highest expression of selfhood.”32 Anderson notes his obligation to
Arendt’s idea of “natality,” and points out that
for Ricoeur such “births,” together with
memory, establish coherence between past,
present and future in the narrative of the self,
and that acts of promising always take place
“within a web of relationships.”33
In this piece Anderson does not consider
Ricoeur’s own handling of forgiveness, as she
will do in a later one. She does reflect on
Ricoeur’s understanding of involvement in the
“web of relationships,” and here draws attention
to Ricoeur’s caveat that this does not mean we
can actually relive the life of others: she
quotes him to the effect that “It is a matter of
exchanging memories at the narrative level
where they are present for comprehension.”34
This process is portrayed in somewhat cognitive
terms as “an ability to think from the standpoint
of others,” and the influence of Ricoeur here
may account for Anderson’s tendency to establish boundaries to empathy in forgiveness, and
her suspicion of my own model of forgiveness
as a journey of identity into the life of
another. Nevertheless, she repeats from the
2001 paper that an ethics of memory takes
responsibility for the life stories of the other,
“through the exchange of narratives in imagination and empathy.”35
Anderson’s ethical concern for the opening
up of the future in a changed life narrative has
parallels with the aims of RJ, a process which
brings together offender and victim in a conversation either inside or outside the criminal
justice system, in which the victim can confront
113
the perpetrator with the effects of his or her
offence.36 In this meeting, a key aim is to find
a way forward together into the future on
which all the stakeholders are agreed, and
which will involve some kind of change in all
who are involved. Later, as we shall see, Anderson did comment on RJ, but this was not part of
her thinking in 2005.
In my own conversation with her, I raised the
question of the place of a loving God within any
process in which restoration and the making of a
new future is in view. Oddly, contributing as she
was in 2005 to a volume on postmodern theology, she does not say anything about God. But
I wanted to urge that in shaping the future
God is also open to change as a participant in
the healing of broken relations. God, as a
divine forgiver, must be vulnerable, open to suffering and mutable. This is the corollary of a
process of forgiveness which is a journey of
identification with the other, and which in
God’s own story is a voyage into all human
lives, reaching the most intense pitch in the
life and death of Jesus Christ.37 There can, of
course, be no alteration in God’s character of
goodness and faithfulness, or we would no
longer be talking about “God” at all, and
neither is the change any movement from reluctance to forgive into being forgiving. Instead, we
can conceive of God’s taking new experience
into the divine life through the death of Christ
for the sake of creation, enabling God through
empathy to win offenders into reconciliation
and achieve transformation.
3 forgiveness as exceeding justice
In a paper by Anderson of the following year,
titled “Unselfing in Love: A Contradiction in
Terms?” (2006),38 my own stress on the passibility of God does appear in her dialogue with me.
However, this is not where she begins. The
point of departure is the idea of “unselfing,” a
term that Anderson takes and converts from
Iris Murdoch’s notion of unselfing.39 Forgiveness then becomes relevant in several ways.
First, an unhealthy kind of unselfing would
be the “loss of self” in the sense of “self-emptying,” loss of self-worth and self-dignity. She
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
maintains that, whatever ambiguities there
might be in the idea of “unselfing,” the very
idea “presupposes a self capable of loving
relationships: that is, a self who can decreate
in order to find herself in loving another.”40
What Anderson had learnt from Kant’s ethics
of autonomy remained with her throughout
her life as a defence of a woman’s power of
self-determination. Picking up the theme of
her first paper, the demand that someone
should forgive seemed to her to foster this
kind of destructive unselfing. It ignored the
necessary struggle between forgiveness and
justice.41
But forgiveness appears again in Anderson’s
view of a healthy kind of unselfing, which is
marked by a de-centring of the self in giving
“attention” to the other. She writes: “I see the
essence of love simply in an arresting attention
to […] [a person’s] particular existence.”42
Here, she is indebted to Murdoch, and
through her to Simone Weil, for the idea of
unselfing as turning from mere absorption in
the self to attend to another, citing Murdoch’s
acknowledgement that she has borrowed the
word “attention” from Weil “to express the
idea of a just and loving gaze directed upon an
individual reality.”43 Such attention requires a
self “capable of intimate relations,” and the
result in turn of attending to the other is the creation of enriched relations.44 In this context she
approves bell hooks’s notion of awareness of the
reality of ourselves,45 and thinks that a proper
self-love might be best expressed as “oneself
inasmuch as another.”46 The essence of love
remains “in the quality of the self’s attending
to another, including oneself as another.”47
Now, while the main theme of this paper is
“love” in the widest sense as unselfing, Anderson focuses the discussion on one particular
loving act of attention to the other, namely forgiveness: “forgiveness becomes the crucial
example of an ethical act done in order to
sustain loving relationships.” It is crucial, she
will go on to explain, because “today the act
done for the sake of love alone which raises
serious questions about love’s capability is forgiveness.”48 We shall come in due course to
these “serious questions.”
Again following Murdoch, Anderson suggests
that a further aspect of healthy “unselfing” is
the loss of illusions cultivated by the self.49
“Unselfing” means seeking to rid oneself of
self-deceptions concerning the reality of selflove and other-love. One of these illusions, she
suggests, is that love is merely benevolence, an
altruistic “doing good” to others which neglects
the reality of the desires of the self. While benevolence to others is a proper human disposition
to be encouraged, it can become distorted into
“acts of charity” which mask the unjust discrepancy between the situations of rich and poor
in society. It can cease to be a specific act of
goodwill towards another, and become “a nonspecific act of charity in giving to the personally
unknown, less well-off as a duty.”50 In line with
Kant, Anderson finds “a duty to love” to be an
absurdity, since love is a “feeling,” so that if
love is regarded as mere benevolence it undermines itself. At this point, Anderson’s discussion takes a theological turn, detecting a
sanctioning of this human distortion of benevolence in the religious image of an omnibenevolent God.
This is also the point where Anderson
appeals to my own insistence on the mutability and passibility of God. A healthy theology
of unselfing, she argued, will challenge the
view of a God whose love is reducible to benevolence to all; in traditional terms, this is
the image of a God of pure agape or selfgiving love, with no aspect of eros or desire.
Appealing to my own theology, she suggests
that proper human unselfing will be prompted
by the view of a God who “unselfs” by ridding
God’s self of the illusion of invulnerability
and impassibility that is pervasive in classical
theology:
What emerges in Fiddes’ case is the relational
capacity of love. He argues that since human
beings are the objects or subjects of the
searching love of God, relationship […]
with them must satisfy the desire of God
and complete divine joy. Fiddes moves a
great distance from both the classical view
of divine love as the ideal of invulnerable
gift and the human ideal of disinterested
self-giving.51
114
fiddes
Thus (with some theological originality) she
proposes that the image of a God who rids
God’s self of the illusion of disinterested benevolence will challenge our own distortions of
benevolence, and awaken us to our proper
desires. For God and human beings, unselfing
and maintaining the self are to be held in
tension: here she approves my claim that “we
become more truly ourselves when we give ourselves away […] self-giving love is in the end a
self-realization.”52 Anderson does not here – as
I do – explicitly relate this vulnerability of
God to the process of forgiving, even in the
form of a religious image that might motivate
human forgiveness. There is an implicit connection in so far as Anderson has already taken forgiveness as the paradigm example of “the
relational capacity of love,” but it is in another
example of ridding oneself of illusions that she
brings a discussion of forgiveness to the fore.
According to Anderson, another illusion to
be discarded in “unselfing” is that love is a
kind of distributive justice, in which love is to
be given to everyone impartially. Love cannot
be required on the grounds of justice, she
writes, to be distributed equally, to intimates
and strangers alike. Woman especially cannot
distribute love equally, since this destroys a
sense of self, and “historically women and marginalized men have not been allowed to create a
sense of self in the first place.”53 Making love a
form of distributive justice fails to create a
proper self-love which is essential for making
relationships. It is here that the act of forgiveness, as a paradigm of loving relations, raises
the “serious questions” to which Anderson
referred earlier. It is clear that “forgiveness
[…] must be done out of love, not duty or distributive justice”:54
For forgiveness to remain different from forgetting or reparation, it would have to be
incompatible with the rules of distributive
justice which seek reparation in the form of
punishment for crimes or injustices committed. In other words, one forgives precisely
because the injustice cannot be repaired.
Forgiveness is the key example of the tension
between love and distributive justice: in the
115
case of an offence committed, justice requires
reparation, and yet no injustice can be fully
“repaired” and so calls for forgiveness. “One
forgives the unforgivable for the sake of love,”
she asserts, “not distributive justice.” The
implication is that forgiveness exceeds justice,
as she had written earlier in her 2005 book
chapter: “the cemetery of past promises can be
transformed by a love that goes beyond morality
in forgiveness.”55 Yet, at the same time, Anderson insists that if a victim of injustice denies her
own self in forgiving the one who has hurt her,
she has little sense of the reality of love.56 We
are back with the struggle between love and
justice in the act of forgiveness that occupied
Anderson in the first paper above. The development in this piece is to illuminate that struggle
by placing it in the tension (even the apparent
“contradiction”) between “selfing” and “unselfing” in love, but Anderson does not attempt to
supply any easy resolution.
Putting forgiveness in the larger context of
“unselfing in love” does, however, make it a
practice of the “wise lover” who attempts to
“confront the egoistic enemy of the good life
without neutralizing or denuding the self.”57
The two “egoistic enemies” Anderson has identified in this paper, or “the fat relentless ego[s] in
modern ethical theory,”58 have been an overconfidence in benevolence and distributive
justice, but it has been easier to name them
than to resolve the tension of which they are
symptoms. Rather as she had earlier discerned
the need for a slow process of emotional and
rational transformation in the process of forgiveness, here she admits that “one may not
be able to single out accurately any examples
of the wise lover”59 and that the “perfection of
love […] remains humanly impossible.” In the
face of a tension that “verges on contradictions”
one can only hold a “vision of sheer delight in an
arresting attention to the reality of oneself,
other selves, and our world.”60
Anderson’s phrases about “forgiving the
unforgivable” and perfected love as “impossible” have overtones of the treatment of forgiveness by Jacques Derrida, and in her first paper
above Anderson does refer to Derrida in a footnote, recording that he rejects any notion of
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
forgiveness as a duty.61 He formulates the act of
forgiveness in terms of its sheer unconditionality.62 For Derrida the whole point of forgiveness
is that it rises above all mechanisms of reciprocation and the market-place. Forgiveness is not
about calculation, or balancing the accounts:
There is in forgiveness a force, a desire, an
impetus, a movement […] that demands
that forgiveness be granted even to someone
who does not ask for it, who does not
repent or confess or improve or redeem
himself.63
Forgiveness, he stresses, is always of the unforgivable.64 For Derrida, unconditional forgiveness is “impossible,” but there can be no other
kind, or we buy into a mere economy of
exchange. I myself also stress that forgiveness
itself is unconditional; it does not require repentance or remorse in the offender, since that
would undermine the dynamic nature of forgiveness as initiating a response in those who
are reluctant to accept pardon. Above all, the
forgiveness of God expressed in the death of
Christ is unconditional.65 However, in Derrida’s
view, forgiveness to be pure must be offered
without any hope, expectation or intention
that the offender will in due time face up to
his or her crime, be repentant, seek reconciliation, offer reparation and be transformed.
Even holding hope for the offender is, in Derrida’s view, entering an economy of exchange. In
my approach, while forgiveness is unconditional, the completing of forgiveness in reconciliation between those who are alienated (whether
between people or between human persons and
God) is conditional upon an appropriate
response.66 It does not deny unconditional forgiveness to hope for this response, though it
can never be demanded. Derrida’s view seems
to arise from associating forgiveness radically
with forgetting,67 rather than with an empathy
that relies on memory.
Despite an apparent echo of Derrida’s
language, in this piece Anderson appears to
reject unconditional forgiveness, remarking
that “the moral theologian’s insistence on
unconditional, spontaneous and selfless love
becomes self-contradictory.”68 Certainly, to
the end of our conversations, Anderson was
unhappy about the idea. It seemed to her to
undermine justice and self-worth, and especially
to put the woman back in the position of victim.
I urged that forgiveness was not the end of the
process of healing broken relations. I suggested
that reconciliation between victim and oppressor must be conditional on the repentance of
the offender and his making of reparation; forgiveness, as unconditional, has the power to
create such an ethical response. I wonder
whether in this paper, with her urging of the
“forgiving of the unforgivable” there is just
the seed of a possible agreement. She would
have to say.
4 forgiveness as a hope
Some five years later, in a short paper titled “A
Feminist on Forgiveness” (2011), Anderson
returned to the conflict between forgiveness
and justice, as flagged up in the first and third
papers considered here. Indeed, this is the
point of departure for her piece, which is the
transcript of an oral presentation.69 She says,
“Love might say, forgive! But justice may
not!”70 She asks, “Can forgiveness be
unjust?”71 and maintains that “The feminist
argues that in the case of an abused woman
with a weak sense of self-respect, the danger of
forgiveness is to condone injustice.”72 In
short, she is sketching out the situation indicated by the subtitle of the piece: “When
(Where?) Love and Justice Come Apart.”
In the light of this struggle between love and
justice it is appropriate that the talk, published
in a book designed to honour Paul Ricoeur,
takes as its repeated motif Ricoeur’s phrase
about “difficult forgiveness.” Indeed, Anderson
judges that “one half-century of philosophical
reflections on evil were simply a prelude” to
Ricoeur’s account of forgiveness in the epilogue
to his Memory, History, Forgetting, titled “Difficult Forgiveness.”73 As previously, she proposes that the dilemma of forgiveness can be
resolved only through a process of transformation in which the struggle is fully recognized
and worked through. She refers to a “long
process” with forgiveness “a long way down
116
fiddes
the line,”74 and cites bell hooks as writing that
“confronting myself with compassion, I learn
to practice the art of forgiveness.”75 She also
gives at least qualified approval to the particular
Christian view that the pronouncement “I
forgive you” is “not an act at all, but is a description of a process; that is, forgiveness involves a
process of changing one’s emotion.” As in her
first paper above, she certainly rejects an
alternative Christian view that “forgiveness is
both necessary and possible as a miraculous
gift from God,” deriving from a forensic understanding of atonement in Christ as paying an
offender’s debt.76
In exploring the difficult “process” of forgiveness, she finds it to be characterized by
both memory and hope. For the aspect of
memory she is indebted to Ricoeur’s discussion
of “recognition” as “a small miracle of
memory,” when someone suddenly exclaims
“That is her! That is him!”77 Forgiveness,
suggests Anderson, is characterized by the
same recognition of the truth of what has actually happened in a past act of offence, so that
forgiveness depends on “seeing and remembering.”78 It is in memory that the wrong done is
recognized, but through memory also that the
necessary encounter with someone can happen.
Anderson affirms that “in the place where the
person is recognized, the spirit of forgiveness
becomes manifest.”79 Such a “spirit of forgiveness” only becomes possible through a “fundamental premise” that, as she gladly
acknowledges, both she and Ricoeur have
gleaned from Immanuel Kant: that innocence
is more original than guilt, and goodness more
original than evil.80
Here, Anderson (in a footnote)81 makes what
she calls a “detour” to describe “how it is I have
arrived as a moral philosopher – and a philosopher of religion – to my view of forgiveness.”
She explains that she is following Ricoeur in
his own debt to Kant on the nature of good
and evil: that while evil is radical as a propensity
of human action, innocence is more original
than evil or guilt.82 Thus there is what
Ricoeur calls a “spirit of forgiveness” inscribed
in human willing, within the very capability of
humans to act both to do right and wrong, and
117
“a capability not only to do wrong but for that
wrong doing to be undone.” It is this
Kantian–Ricoeurian insight that gives Anderson the hope that, despite the struggle
between love and justice that cannot be easily
resolved, forgiveness is still possible. Ricoeur,
she continues, draws the conclusion that the
act of forgiving is “an unbinding of evil from
the guilty agent” so that the act of evil can be
distinguished from the agent who is “potentially
restored to his or her original innocence.” While
Anderson appears to approve this account, we
are bound to notice that it leads Ricoeur to
equate forgiving with forgetting, as the fault is
separated from the agent and sent into oblivion,
while the agent is remembered only as an innocent person. Ricoeur believes that this kind of
forgetting of faults in the past, or what
Ricoeur calls an “unbinding of debt from
fault,”83 can promote the healing of relations;
it can, he thinks, prevent an obsessive repetition
or commemoration of the past, unblock a situation of conflict in memory, remove melancholia
and so make forgiveness possible.84 Unfortunately, it can also undermine the very process
of “transformation” of the person that Anderson herself is commending, in which person
and act are bound up in one reality that has to
be faced openly by both forgiver and offender.
The Kantian insight into original innocence
need not inevitably lead to the conclusion that
agent and act can be separated, and if forgiveness is to be unconditional (as Derrida perceives),85 they cannot be. The offence done
does not derive from a kind of parcel of evil
that can be detached from an agent but from
destructive attitudes that have to be changed
in the person through a painful voyage of
experience.
In this piece Anderson does in fact link my
own conception of a journey of forgiveness to
her concern for a process of rational and
emotional transformation. In a long footnote
attached to a comment about forgiveness as a
“complex process” she writes:
Roughly, a Christian moral theologian would
probably introduce an account of the stages
of atonement – or, as Paul Fiddes describes,
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
the journeys of forgiveness. Elsewhere I have
given attention to the intriguing work done
by Fiddes on forgiveness – he has an interesting take on […] the process of repairing
broken relationships in the journey of forgiveness: of discovery and endurance.86
Anderson is correct here that I relate the
journey of forgiveness to atonement – in the
sense that God in the death of Christ takes the
furthest voyage into human desolation and isolation in order to awaken human persons to
their situation, and to create response to God’s
forgiving love.87 However, I do not, as she
implies, follow the sequence of the particular
stages of atonement she goes on to outline – recognition of wrong, repentance, forgiveness and
penance. The whole point of the empathetic
journey taken by the Creator into creation is
that unconditional forgiveness has the power
to prompt repentance and reparation, and that
this issues in reconciliation.88
I venture to suggest that this kind of pattern,
in which human beings participate through their
own acts of forgiveness, may offer an answer to
another problem that Anderson raises. Alongside
the struggle between justice and love in forgiveness, Anderson sets what she finds to be a
rational or logical conundrum. On the one
hand, forgiveness would be “unjustified” if the
wrongdoer has not made reparation. On the
other, the act of forgiveness is “pointless” if the
wrongdoer has already made adequate reparation.89 While she offers the slow process of transformation, taking the issue of justice seriously, as
the only way through the struggle, she does not
appear to have any solution to the conundrum.
It ceases to be so acute, however, if we distinguish between unconditional forgiveness and
conditional reconciliation as I have done earlier:
forgiveness prompts reparation rather than following it, and lack of reparation would make
unjustified not forgiveness but reconciliation.
The second major characteristic of the
process of forgiveness which Anderson discusses in this piece (the first being memory) is
that of hope – grounded, as we have seen, in a
conviction that innocence and goodness have
priority over evil. Here, Anderson expands an
idea that she first mentioned in her 2001 paper
on forgiveness, prompted by the writing of Drucilla Cornell, that we should conceive a new imaginative space of freedom, an “imaginary
domain” in which exploited peoples can
recover and relocate themselves in relation to a
past of pain and oppression.90 Beyond Cornell’s
exposition, she asserts that forgiveness can
create that space through love, and, as before,
she sees bell hooks as “working to conceive a
space […] where forgiveness breaks down the
divisions between our private and public lives
in order to open up both to love and
justice.”91 But here she goes a step further in
seeing the hope for this space as meeting a set
of questions about forgiveness which she
herself poses, such as: how can forgiveness be
justified when victims are no longer alive?
When injustice is still taking place against a
people, a race, a sex? When the victim cannot
forgive?92 When the victim is not conscious,
or gone away, or estranged?93 Her answer is
that at times when forgiveness is impossible,
there remains “hope for the place where love
and justice will be able to create a new future.”94
I myself raise almost exactly the same questions about forgiveness, and also offer hope for
a “future space” of reconciliation where forgiveness can be practised.95 However, my account is
deliberately theological in a way that hers is not.
The image of a journey of empathy directed
towards the creation of response to the offer of
forgiveness seems especially problematic when
someone refuses to be reconciled, or is not
present to be reconciled because they have
died, or the situation is such as to make it
unsafe for someone who has been abused to
make any contact with the abuser at all. In
such cases, I urge, the one who wants to
forgive can still set out in imagination on a
path of empathy towards the other, so becoming
the kind of person who is freed from the chains
of the past. A Christian hope is based not only in
a Kantian positive view of human nature but
also in an eschatology where all will experience
the judgement of having to face the truth
about themselves, and have the opportunity to
be reconciled with Love.96
118
fiddes
Belief in a God who is engaged in the same
kind of journey as human beings means that
our own journey becomes part of the journey
of a God in whom all persons “live and move
and have their being.”97 Our hopeful imagination thus has persuasive power in creating
reconciliation in the world as our created love
is added to the uncreated love of God which is
a constant pressure towards human flourishing.
We cannot know what this will achieve, either in
the one with whom we desire to be reconciled or
in others who need to be reconciled and of
whom we are quite unaware.
5 forgiveness and restorative
justice
A paper published by Anderson in 2016, and
originally written for a colloquium on Restorative Justice in 2014, has a similar title to the previous one, being “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart.”98 The departure point here is the
practice of RJ, and the highly contested question, among practitioners of RJ, as to whether
forgiveness should play any part in the
process. Along the lines of previous pieces,
this essay continues to assert a conflict
between forgiveness and justice – or between
love and justice in the act of forgiveness – and
to underline the “difficult” nature of
forgiveness.
The article develops the argument, however,
by making explicit that the process of forgiveness may, and will in the case of women suffering abuse and “intimate violence,” call for a
withholding of forgiveness at least for a
period, not least during the practice of RJ.99
Time will be needed to cultivate emotions of
righteous anger. This “withholding” may well
be implied in the “process of transformation”
set out in earlier papers, but is not so stated
there.100 In dialogue here with Martha Nussbaum, she maintains that anger, in the form of
resentment and contempt, is a cognitive
emotion which plays a positive role in withholding forgiveness from the offender, so creating
both distance (with space for ethical accountability) and time for the injuries to be
119
recognized. Withholding also allows for the suitability of the positive affective emotion of love,
motivating forgiveness, to be assessed.101
Forgiveness is to be withheld in the name of
self-respect. Resentment and contempt need to
be acknowledged if a victim is to be able to
know what and how to forgive, or to express
any just emotion. Forgiveness, she stresses, is
a vice when it maintains injustice. In this circumstance love can be a negative cognitive
emotion,
setting
up
“unethical
love
relations.”102 Women can be “too forgiving or
too loving to be ethical or just,” and “unquestioning trust in a personal religion of love is a
deeply-embedded obstacle to justice in the
lives of oppressed subjects under patriarchy.”103
Anderson’s hesitations about the practice of
RJ is that it might not allow for this exercise
of the proper cognitive emotions of anger, and
this failure would be exacerbated if acts of forgiveness were included within the process.
These would make RJ prone to misunderstanding the cognitive role of human emotions, in the
form of both love and anger, which motivate our
interactions. Thus RJ might exploit the forgiving nature of those women (and men) who are
vulnerable to being treated unjustly precisely
because of being too loving.104 Taking up an
earlier theme, Anderson stresses that unconditional forgiveness is not an ethical requirement
in every situation for every person, since it is
necessary to take time to address cognitive
emotions.105
In my own approach to the place of forgiveness within RJ, I agree strongly with Anderson106 that the survivor of intimate violence
has no duty to forgive. Rather, in line with my
model of a “journey of forgiveness,” I suggest
that the exercise of forgiveness can be encouraged in the process of RJ, with the effect of
creating a response in the offender, without
either requiring or expecting it.107 Using the
language of John Braithwaite, forgiveness can
be regarded as one of the “standards” that can
be “maximized” as appropriate in the process
of RJ.108 Braithwaite himself prefers to regard
forgiveness as an “emergent value,” developing
out of the process, but in his discussion with me
he admits that the issue might be really about
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
the definition of “maximizing.”109 By contrast,
Anderson remains apprehensive about introducing forgiveness into practices of RJ at all. In
RJ, she affirms, we can learn how to recognize
when cognitive emotions such as contempt
have a salient role in alerting us to injustice.
We must begin the process of restoring trust
in oneself in the face of self-denigration before
we can hope to restore justice. Forgiveness,
she admits, is often the decisive step needed to
generate the possibility of repairing ethical
accountability, but it is not an easy step to
take, and it will probably need to be withheld
initially.
Anderson is also apprehensive about certain
practices of “caring” relationships. Like RJ,
these can run the danger of ignoring ethical vulnerability and accountability in the name of
“caring about” the other’s reparation more
than one’s own.110 She notes that twentiethcentury feminist debates have sometimes distinguished between an “ethics of justice” supposedly typical of men, and an “ethics of care,”
supposedly typical of women.111 She judges
that the debate has been right to suspect that
these two types of ethics have been assigned to
the public and private spheres respectively,
with the result that an ethics of justice in the
public sphere has failed to achieve the restoration of personal relations, while an ethics of
care has promoted loving and forgiving relations
only in private life.112 Anderson affirms that it
has been a good thing to unearth an ethics of
care in the decision making of women, but she
agrees with more recent feminist philosophers
in disputing any sharp gender distinction
between care and justice, writing that “we
have many new understandings of gender, transgender and other sexual relations.”113 Stereotypes which divide ethics into men (justice)
and women (care) have to be challenged. She
also warns against slipping into a sharp distinction between public and private life, since the
separation of two spheres of life is highly problematic for forgiveness. Women who suffer intimate violence – within family life – have been
taught to forgive immediately and unconditionally. There is decisive risk of injustice in regarding forgiveness as unproblematic within the
private sphere of life, and she finds this to be
typical of the traditional Christian (premodern) community.
The article shows that at this advanced stage
of our conversation on forgiveness there is convergence between Anderson and myself in so far
as Anderson increasingly associates my understanding of the “journey” of forgiveness with
the “process” of transformation she envisages
herself. Here, she deliberately links her own
account of “taking time to address cognitive
emotions” with what she calls my own
“dynamic process of forgiveness,” and thinks
that both can be related to a proper process of
RJ.114 In fact she makes a point of preferring
what she identifies as my “late modern Christian
theology of forgiveness as a dynamic process” to
Braithwaite’s suspicion that modernity (and the
autonomy it cultivates) is a hindrance to RJ,
opposing his desire to return to what she
regards as dangerous “ancient traditions” of
relationships.115 Her difference from me is
about the stage in the “journey of forgiveness”
where forgiveness becomes appropriate, at
least in the case of women suffering intimate
violence.
For my part, in the paper I contribute to the
colloquium, I try to place her advocacy of withholding forgiveness within my own image of forgiveness as a journey of empathy. I have learned
to take seriously her insistence that withholding
may be necessary, especially in extreme cases of
harm such as abuse, to preserve the integrity,
well-being and freedom of the victim as well as
to make clear to the abuser the terrible depths
of the harm inflicted. So I suggest that persons
who cannot forgive at a particular moment,
and yet who do not have a fixed unforgiving attitude, might begin the journey of forgiveness
and so escape being trapped in resentment by
imagining conditions in which they might take
a first unconditional movement of forgiveness.
They might envisage a situation in which they
themselves were in a better position to take
this move, or in which the offender were in a
different frame of mind or attitude. The very
willingness to imagine that forgiveness might
be possible, though it is impossible at present,
is – I suggest – taking one’s place in the
120
fiddes
empathetic journey of God which can in proper
time enable further steps to be taken.116
A similar step in imagination is commended
by the philosopher Charles Griswold, who
suggests that when forgiveness seems inappropriate we can nevertheless construct in our minds an
“imaginative and credible narrative” about an
offender, finding reasons to think that conditions
for forgiveness such as remorse might have been
or might be fulfilled in a different situation than
obtains at present.117 The advantage I see in the
theological context I propose is that the “imaginative narrative” participates in the story of a
God who is actually moving in the world to
create love and justice ahead of us.
6 forgiveness and vulnerability: in
conclusion
The final paper I am considering118 appeared
posthumously in a publication of the Enhancing
Life Project at the University of Chicago (2017).
Some of the same themes are repeated from the
2016 article – in fact about seven pages119 are
close transcriptions of it – especially the need
to withhold forgiveness120 and to cultivate cognitive emotions of righteous anger in order to
achieve just relations. However, this piece triangulates forgiveness with an ethics of care and an
ethics of vulnerability, where the latter two
themes made only a slight appearance in the
former article.
The need to demolish barriers between
private and public spheres is taken further, in
the light of a situation where offences against
women are often relegated to the private or
family realm, creating a demand on women to
forgive their intimate abusers. Anderson
insists on a “politics of care,” or care in the
public space, characterized by the development
of reciprocal accountability,121 a note already
sounded in the fourth of the papers I have gathered together.122 But the most significant expansion from her previous article on forgiveness is
her treatment of vulnerability, prompted (it
seems) by a dialogue with the notion of universal human “precarious life and corporal vulnerability” in the work of Judith Butler.123
121
The “ethical vulnerability” which Anderson
had briefly mentioned in the former paper is
“clarified” as existing on two levels. First,
there is a “phenomenological level” of experiencing vulnerability, prior to taking any ethical
action. This is “a primary capacity for being
wounded, or a potential wounding,” and
includes “a range of positive to negative vulnerable experiences,” from loving affection in
sexual intimacy to injurious violence that
occurs in intimate relations.124 Anderson also
describes this phenomenology as presenting
“specific, lived experiences of intimacy, as an
openness to love and affection, while admitting
affection could generate negative effects of fear,
shame or rage.”125 In her previous article she
had urged the need for time to come to terms
with cognitive emotions arising from these
experiences of vulnerability before forgiveness
becomes possible.126 Second, there is an
“ethical level” of vulnerability, where “wounding” or the potential for being “wounded” is
not something to be eliminated or thought of
as a mere liability but adopted as a basis for relational accountability which has within it an
openness to change, “of calling one another to
account for immoral, non-moral or ethical
wounds.” Ethical vulnerability opens up an
opportunity to restore justice or to repair the
horrendous pain of wounds, and such “ethical
repair” will need to work with the just emotions
of resentment and contempt.127
As she makes clear in a coda of deliberate
engagement with Butler, Anderson’s desire is
to shift the experience of vulnerability away
from issues of violence, where it often belongs.
The human response to vulnerability usually
takes the form of a social mythology where violence is either to be avoided or imposed on
others. But rather, we should allow vulnerability
to lead us into an “openness to loving affection”128 and accountability in relations. This
project was to take initial form in her proposal
for a new “social imaginary” of vulnerability
in two final, unpublished papers which are
now published in this journal.129 But forgiveness does not feature explicitly in her outline
of this imaginary, any more than it takes
centre stage in the paper of 2017.
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
Through six papers we have traced Pamela
Sue Anderson’s understanding of the impasse,
and yet the possibility, of forgiveness. A constant feature has been her urging, in face of
the struggle between forgiveness and justice,
or between love and justice in forgiveness, to
give time and space for a process of cognitive
and emotional transformation to happen in
which forgiveness can gradually emerge.
Though in increasing convergence with my
own view of the process of forgiveness, she has
remained suspicious of accounts of the
“journey” that make forgiveness too much of
an initiating action, out of concern that this
imposes demands upon women who are
abused and oppressed. Her account seems to
belong, in terms of this final paper, to what
she calls a “phenomenological level” of vulnerability. If Pamela were here, I would ask her
what place she finds for forgiveness in the
active, “ethical level” of vulnerability within
her social imaginary. And I would like to
know whether, as a philosopher of religion,
she sees a place for a vulnerable
God within a new narrative by
which we can live. The conversation must now remain openended, but then the best conversations always are.
disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by
the author.
notes
1 Pamela Sue Anderson, “A Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness” in Forgiveness and Truth, eds. Alistair
McFadyen and Marcel Sarot (Edinburgh: Clark,
2001) 145–56.
2 Paul S. Fiddes, Past Event and Present Salvation:
The Christian Idea of Atonement (London: Darton,
1989) 171–89.
3 Paul S. Fiddes, Participating in God: A Pastoral Doctrine of the Trinity (London: Darton, 2000) 191–223.
4 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness” 154.
5 Following my personal introduction about
“Pamela” I will henceforth refer to her in a more
academic way.
6 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness” 145,
147.
7 Ibid. 148–49.
8 Ibid. 152.
9 Fiddes, Past Event and Present Salvation 173–75;
Fiddes, Participating in God 192–97.
10 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
151, cf. 152.
11 Ibid. 152.
12 Ibid. 155.
13 For an account of this shared journey, see
Fiddes, Participating in God 206–10.
14 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
149, citing bell hooks, Wounds of Passion: A
Writing Life (New York: Holt, 1997) v.
15 Ibid. 151, 150.
16 Paul S. Fiddes, “Memory, Forgetting and the
Problem of Forgiveness. Reflecting on Volf,
Derrida and Ricoeur” in Forgiving and Forgetting,
eds. Hartmut Von Sass and Johannes Zachhuber
(Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2015) 130–33.
17 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
152–53, citing Gillian Rose, Mourning Becomes the
Law: Philosophy and Representation (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1997) 35–36, 104.
18 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
153.
19 Ibid. 155, citing Ricoeur, “Reflections on a New
Ethos for Europe” in Paul Ricoeur: The Hermeneutics
of Action, ed. Richard Kearney (London: Sage, 1996)
6–7.
20 Anderson, “Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
155.
21 “An Ethics of Memory: Promising, Forgiving,
Yearning” in The Blackwell Companion to Postmodern
Theology, ed. Graham Ward (Oxford: Blackwell,
2005) 243.
22 Ibid. 239–40. Women’s “yearning” was
already a prominent theme in Pamela Sue Anderson, A Feminist Philosophy of Religion: The Rationality and Myths of Religious Belief (Oxford:
122
fiddes
Blackwell, 1998): see, for example, 171–75, 213–
15, 225–26.
23 Ibid. 233.
24 Ibid. 234, 235. She notes (239) that Julia Kristeva
affirms forgiveness as a “solution to the inertia of
melancholia”: see Kristeva, Black Sun: Depression
and Melancholia, trans. Leon S. Roudiez
(New York: Columbia UP, 1989) 189–90.
25 Pamela Sue Anderson, Re-visioning Gender in
Philosophy of Religion: Reason, Love and Epistemic
Locatedness (London: Ashgate, 2012) 104–05.
42 Ibid. 246.
43 Ibid. 255, citing Murdoch, Sovereignty of Good
34.
44 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 258.
45 Ibid. 255, citing bell hooks, Yearning: Race, Gender
and Cultural Politics (Boston: South End, 1990) 111.
46 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 257, referring to
Ricoeur’s phrase “oneself inasmuch as being other”
in Ricoeur, Oneself as Another 3.
47 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 255.
26 Ibid. 106–10, 142–46.
48 Ibid. 253.
27 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 234.
49 Ibid. 248.
28 Anderson, Re-visioning Gender 105.
50 Ibid. 251–52.
29 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 234.
51 Ibid 257. Cf. Fiddes, Creative Suffering of God
71–76.
30 Ibid. 237, citing Hannah Arendt, The Human
Condition, 2nd ed. (Chicago: U of Chicago P,
1998) 236–37.
31 Ibid. 236, citing Arendt, ibid. 183.
52 Paul S. Fiddes, Freedom and Limit: A Dialogue
between Literature and Christian Doctrine (Macon,
GA: Mercer UP, 1999) 160–61, cited by Anderson,
“Unselfing in Love” 255–56, 255 n.
32 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 237–38. See
Paul Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, trans. Kathleen
Blamey (Chicago: Chicago UP, 1992) 266–68.
54 Ibid. 261.
33 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 238.
55 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 236.
34 Ricoeur, “Reflections on a New Ethos” 7.
56 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 260.
35 Anderson, “An Ethics of Memory” 242.
57 Ibid. 264.
36 See John Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and
Responsive Regulation (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2002)
3–28.
58 Ibid. 260.
37 Paul S. Fiddes, The Creative Suffering of God
(Oxford: Oxford UP, 1988) 157–63.
60 Ibid. 265.
38 Pamela Sue Anderson, “Unselfing in Love: A
Contradiction in Terms?” in Faith in the Enlightenment? The Critique of the Enlightenment Revisited,
eds. Lieven Boeve, Joeri Schrijvers, Wessel
Stoker, and Hendrik M. Vroom (Amsterdam:
Rodopi, 2006) 257–61.
39 Iris Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good (London:
Routledge, 1970) 84; cf. “the long task of unselfing”
in Iris Murdoch’s novel Henry and Cato (London:
Chatto, 1976) 143. Anderson, “Unselfing in Love”
247–49.
40 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 249.
41 Ibid. 253, 260–61.
123
53 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 260.
59 Ibid. 264.
61 Anderson, “A Feminist Ethics of Forgiveness”
152 n.
62 Jacques Derrida, “To Forgive: The Unforgivable
and the Imprescriptible” in Questioning God, eds.
J.D. Caputo, M. Dooley, and M.J. Scanlon (Bloomington: Indiana UP, 2001) 25–30.
63 Ibid. 28, cf. 8.
64 Jacques Derrida, On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness (New York: Columbia UP, 2001) 32.
65 Fiddes, Participating in God 217–19; for an insistence on conditionality in forgiveness, see Richard
Swinburne, Responsibility and Atonement (Oxford:
Clarendon, 1989) 83–85, 148–52, 160–62.
forgiveness, empathy, vulnerability
66 Fiddes, “Memory, Forgetting and the Problem
of Forgiveness” 126–27, 132–33. Nigel Biggar, In
Defence of War (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2013) 61–
69, similarly identifies an unconditional “compassion-forgiveness” and a conditional “absolution-forgiveness.”
83 The narrator always owes an “unpaid debt” to
the past, the need to render past events their due
by rendering them truthfully: Ricoeur, Memory,
History and Forgetting 363–64; see also Paul
Ricoeur, The Reality of the Historical Past (Milwaukee: Marquette UP, 1984) 25–27.
67 Compare Miroslav Volf, who argues for
eschatological forgetting: Volf, The End of
Memory: Remembering Rightly in a Violent World
(Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006) 203. For a
criticism of Volf, see S. Hauerwas, “Why Time
Cannot and Should Not Heal the Wounds of
History But Time Has Been and Can Be
Redeemed,” Scottish Journal of Theology 53
(2000): 42–43.
84 Ricoeur, Memory, History and Forgetting 502–03.
85 Derrida, On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness
34–39.
86 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 116.
87 Fiddes, Past Event and Present Salvation 178–79.
88 For more detail, see Fiddes, Participating in God
216–19.
68 Anderson, “Unselfing in Love” 260.
89 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 110.
69 The address was given at Mansfield College,
Oxford, in a series whose theme was Getting it
Right: Moral Issues of Today.
90 Ibid. 109; cf. Anderson, “A Feminist Ethics
of Forgiveness” 151. See Drucilla Cornell,
At the Heart of Freedom: Feminism, Sex and
Equality (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1998) 8–
17, 182–86.
70 Pamela Sue Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness. When (Where?) Love and Justice Come
Apart” in Paul Ricoeur: Honoring and Continuing the
Work, ed. Farhang Erfani (Lanham, MD: Lexington,
2011) 107.
91 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 109.
92 Ibid. 110.
71 Ibid. 108, 112.
93 Ibid. 111.
72 Ibid. 109.
94 Ibid. 113.
73 Ibid. 114 n., referring to Paul Ricoeur, Memory,
History, Forgetting, trans. Katherine Blamey and
David Pellauer (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2004)
457–506.
95 Fiddes, “Restorative Justice and the Theological
Dynamic of Forgiveness,” Oxford Journal of Law and
Religion 5.1 (2016): 64–65; Fiddes, Participating in
God 209–10.
74 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 109.
96 Fiddes, Participating in God 210.
75 Ibid. 112; my emphasis. See bell hooks, Remembered Rapture: The Writer at Work (London:
Women’s P, 1999) 119.
97 Acts 17.28.
76 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 115–
16 n.
77 Ibid. 108; Ricoeur, Memory, History, Forgetting
495.
78 Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness” 107.
79 Ibid. 112.
80 Ibid. 108.
81 Ibid. 114–15 n.
82 See also Pamela Sue Anderson and Jordan Bell,
Kant and Theology (London: Clark, 2010) 62–65.
98 Pamela Sue Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness Come Apart: A Feminist Perspective on
Restorative Justice and Intimate Violence,” Oxford
Journal of Law and Religion 5.1 (2016): 113–34.
99 Ibid. 116–18.
100 See Anderson’s acknowledgement, in ibid.
118 n., of the similar idea in Joram Graf Haber,
“Feminism and Forgiveness” in Norms and Values:
Essays on the Work of Virginia Held, eds. Joran
Graf Haber and Mark S. Halfon (Lanham, MD:
Rowman, 1998) 146–47.
101 Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart” 114–16. She references (114 n.)
Martha Nussbaum’s John Locke Lectures on
124
fiddes
“Anger and Forgiveness” at the time (2014) in
Oxford.
124 Anderson, “Arguing for ‘Ethical’ Vulnerability”
153.
102 Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart” 117.
125 Ibid. 147–48.
103 Ibid 123.
104 Ibid 134.
105 Ibid. 123.
106 Ibid. 116.
107 Fiddes, “Restorative Justice” 56.
108 Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive
Regulation 14–16.
109 John Braithwaite, “Redeeming the ‘F’ Word in
Restorative Justice,” Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 5.1 (2016) 84–86.
110 Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart” 130.
111 Ibid. 118, referencing Carol Gilligan, In a
Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1982).
126 Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart” 115.
127 Anderson, “Arguing for ‘Ethical’ Vulnerability”
154, cf. 147–48.
128 Ibid. 150.
129 Pamela Sue Anderson, “Towards a New Philosophical Imaginary,” eds. Sabina Lovibond and
A.W. Moore, in Love and Vulnerability: Thinking
with Pamela Sue Anderson, ed. Pelagia Goulimari,
Spec. issue of Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical
Humanities 25.1–2 (2020): 8–22; Anderson,
“Creating a New Imaginary for Love in Religion,”
ed. Paul S. Fiddes, in Love and Vulnerability: Thinking
with Pamela Sue Anderson, ed. Pelagia Goulimari,
Spec. issue of Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical
Humanities 25.1–2 (2020): 46–53.
112 Anderson, “When Justice and Forgiveness
Come Apart” 128.
113 Ibid. 129.
114 Ibid. 116 n., 131 n.
115 Ibid. 121.
116 Fiddes, “Restorative Justice” 64.
117 Charles Griswold, Forgiveness: A Philosophical
Exploration (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2007) 124.
118 Pamela Sue Anderson, “Arguing for ‘Ethical’
Vulnerability: Towards a Politics of Care?” in
Exploring Vulnerability, eds. Heike Springhart and
Günter Thomas (Göttingen and Bristol, CT: Vandenhoeck, 2017) 147–62.
119 Ibid. 154–61.
120 Ibid. 158.
121 Ibid. 148–51.
122 See Anderson, “A Feminist on Forgiveness”
106.
123 Anderson, “Arguing for ‘Ethical’ Vulnerability”
161, citing (for example) Judith Butler, Precarious
Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence (London:
Verso, 2004).
Paul S. Fiddes
Regent’s Park College Oxford
Pusey Street
Oxford OX1 2LB
UK
E-mail: paul.fi
[email protected]