View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk
brought to you by
CORE
Volume XIX
provided by OAR@UM
Id-Dritt 2006
Just Problems?
Dr. Alan Xuereb
M.Phil. (Jur.), LL.D.
Preservative Justice
Justice is normally the language of complaint, and sometimes of
revenge. Justice is often, therefore, analysed as a negative virtue
whose demands can be met simply by doing nothing beyond
correcting the wrongs inflicted on others. 544
However, most worked-out views as to what constitutes injustice
involve at least an outline image of justice in a positive sense
which goes beyond correcting the wrongs that have been done and
include an impression of a "just" human relationship. The idea of
injustice is closely associated with reactions to the disappointment
of existing expectations. 545
Hence justice, at least in its negative expressions, can have strong
conservative implications in that it seeks to sustain the status quo in
society against destructive and disorderly intrusions.
544
Shklar for example argues that we cannot set rigid rules to distinguish instances of
misfortune from injustice, as most theories of justice would have us do, for such definitions
would not take into account historical variability and differences in perception and interest
between victims and spectators. From the victim's point of view . . . the full definition of
injustice must include not only the immediate cause of disaster but also our refusal to
prevent and then to mitigate the damage, or what Shklar calls passive injustice. With this
broader definition comes a call for greater responsibility from both citizens and public
servants. When we attempt to make political decisions about what to do in specific instances
of injustice, says Shklar, we must give the victim's voice its full weight." The Faces of
Injustice - Shklar, J. N. - Yale University Press Pub. : July 1992.
545
Vide also: Kuklin, Bailey H. - The Justification for Protecting Reasonable Expectations
www.hofstra.edu/pdf/law_Iawrev_kuklin.pdf.
- 397
Id-Dritt 2006
Volume XIX
Disputes between Individuals
When disputes between individuals or groups are considered and
settled under private law, the intention is to protect an existing
system of rights. If one man encroaches on the rights of another,
he is liable to be required to restore the balance, (i) by making good
for the damage he has caused or (ii) by paying compensation and/
(iii) or at least undertaking to respect the rights of the injured party
in future.
This concept clearly stated in the Maltese Civil Code namely under
Article 1047 (1)
"The damage which consists in depriving a person of the use of his
own money, shall be made good by the payment of interest at the
rate of eight per cent a year.
(2) If, however, the party causing the damage has acted
maliciously, the court may, according to circumstances, grant also
to the injured party compensation for any other damage sustained
by him, including every loss of earnings, if it is shown that the
party causing the damage, by depriving the party injured of the use
of his own money, had particularly the intention of causing him
such other damage, or if such damage is the immediate and direct
consequence of the injured party having been so deprived of the
use of his own money."
The Concept of Restitutio in Integrum
The procedures of legal justice, in these types of instance, are
conservative, protecting and restoring an established order thus a
form of restitutio in integrum. In the Roman empire, where Ticius
did wrong to Caius, the former had to compensate the latter by a
restitutio in integrum. That meant, and still means to this day,
placing the victim of a breach of contract or a tortious act in the
same position they were before the event. The Romans clearly
understood the principle that a claimant must be put back to where
they were before the damage was done to them, and this would be
- 398
Dr. Alan Xuereb
ld-Dritt 2006- Volume XIX
never achieved unless the victim was fully compensated (in
integrum). Roman law, then, conceived restitutio in integrum to be
accomplished where the claimant received the principal sum due,
interests at a certain rate from a certain date, compensation for their
economic losses and the costs incurred by them in seekingjustice.
Restitutio in integrum has since been fundamental rule of law in the
countries that follow civil law. Traditionally, in the civil law
system, it includes loss of profits or economic loss in both contract
and tort (e.g. Article 1149 of the French Civil Code; Article 1106
of the Spanish Civil Code; Article 1995 of the Louisiana Code
1985). Damages in contract are deemed to be, except in cases of
fraud, those which are direct and foreseeable at the time of the
contract (Article 1150 France; Article 1107 Spain); damages in tort
are those which are direct and immediate including loss of profit,
so foreseeability is not necessary.
In civil law, interest is always awarded as part of the economic loss
to which claimants are entitled. Interest is payable unquestionably
where the debtor has delayed in performing their obligation to pay
a sum of money (Article 1153 France; Article 1108 Spain). Pre
judgment interest is awarded as an integral part of damages, in all
cases, in the currency of the loss, in both contract and tort,
compounded at the average prime rate of the currency in which that
loss or damage was sustained, from the date of the breach or the
loss to the date of judgment. Post-judgment interest is awarded at
the average prime bank rate (so to reflect the monetary value) for
the period from the date ofjudgement until final payment.
In the common law countries, the courts often refuse to award
complete compensation (restitution in integrum). Most of them
have been unwilling to award damages for pure economic loss (i.e.
damages in tort when there is no physical damage) even if the
damages were direct and foreseeable. 546 Also, almost regularly,
damages in foreign currency were refused (until Miliangos [1975]
in England and The Amoco Cadiz [1992] in the US 7th Circuit).
546
The Mineral Transporter [1986] AC I; [1985] 2 LI R 303.
- 399
Just Problems?
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
For example, the common law courts refused pre-judgment interest
and interest above a certain rate, although in Admiralty
jurisdictions, equity has been recognised and damages have been
awarded in a way close to restitutio in integrum.
The courts in the UK, US and Australia have very rarely granted
economic loss where the claimant did not sustain direct physical
damage. Also, common law jurisdictions have been more
restrictive regarding interest, though they are opening up gradually
(S.35A The Supreme Court Act 1981) so as to render it a matter of
the discretion of the court, as opposed to a right of the claimant
successful in the judgment.547
The discrepancies between civil law and common law over the
application of the rule of restitutio in integrum have given rise to
conflict of laws and to somewhat irrational solutions to the
assessment of damages. The laws applicable to damages differ
among themselves because some jurisdictions and the practices of
certain courts depart from the Roman rule to adopt rules of thumb
and unsubstantiated criteria for special circumstances. In Maltese
law the restitutio in integrum concept is explicitly mentioned in the
Commercial Code (Chapter 13) Article 541,548 regarding the
prescription and inadmissibility of action in certain commercial
matters, and also in the Civil Code, more precisely under Article
1765549 relating to the form and effects of donations550 and also in
the Patents Act (Chapter 417) under Article 46 concerning the re
establishment of rights.551
Progressive Justice
However, law has a progressive or reformative aspect as well.
Laws promulgated by the legislature from time to time change the
547
Making it a discretionary remedy only: House of Lords in President Of India vs La
Pintada Cia Navegacion [1984] 2 Ll.R 9 at p23.
Title I
549
Restitutio in integrum. Amended by: XLVI.1973.92.
550
Sub-title II
551
PART XIII
548
-400 -
Dr. Alan Xuereb
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
rules in accordance with new conceptions of what is fair and
proper. Such as Human Rights legislation, changes in the Maltese
Civil Code promoting parental authority instead of paternal
authority, changes concerning the promotion of equality between
man and woman, the granting of parental leave for both parents, a
better distribution of children's allowance benefits, the recognition
of the housewife's work through a bonus, there have been new laws
about protection at work, requiring safety precautions in
industries, forbidding unfair dismissal, limiting the power of
employers to make workpeople redundant; and internationally the
promulgation of the United Nations' Convention on the Rights of
Children, the recognition by the International Community of the
principles of Common Heritage of Mankind, of The Rights of
Future Generations, and of Common Concern about the planet's
climate and so on.
In social deontology, as in law, the preservative aspect of justice
upholds the established order of things. Persons are entitled to
keep what they have, their rights and property. Many feel that it is
unjust to upset the existing differentials in pay for different jobs. At
the same time nearly everybody also attributes to justice a
reformative role, allowing "new" (or should one say newly
recognised) rights to be set up on the basis of (a) need or (b) merit.
The idea is that justice, in the sense of retaining differentials for
different jobs does not require any class of persons to stay where
they are in the established hierarchy, on the contrary, if they are
especially talented or especially hard-working, it is just for them to
be rewarded and to move up the social scale. What we have up till
now called preservative justice tries to keep things as they are, on
the assumption that everyone benefits from a stable society, despite
the defects of any actual social order.
Reformative Justice
Reformative justice tries to remedy the defects, to redistribute
rights in such a way as to make a fairer society. But what is fair?
There have been two different, and apparently incompatible, ideas
- 401 -
Id-Tuitt 2006 - Volume XIX
Just Problems?
about this. First there is the idea of justice as depending on merit
or desert. It can be seen in criminal justice as well as in ideas of
fairness in social ethics. For example, criminal justice is a matter
of punishing people who have been found guilty of breaching the
law; it would be seriously unjust to punish people who have done
nothing to deserve it.
Likewise, just desert has to do with merit - this means that a reward
or honour, should go to the person who earns it, who deserves it.
To pass over the candidate or contestant who deserved the reward
and to hand it to somebody who did not deserve it would be unjust,
unfair. Why?
The problem in practice lies in how do you assess who is more
meritorious than whom. In other words, how should we classify
who is the best candidate? What criteria should we use to assert
that "A" is for example, more intelligent than "B" in order to
reward him? For now suffice it to say that something which is not
due to someone and which is given to him, makes that donation, an
unfair and unjust act.
However, there is another idea of justice, based on equality and
need. According to this view, justice requires us to treat all human
beings as equal worth and as having equal claims. According to
this view it is unjust to discriminate in favour of some and against
others - except in order to meet special needs - what we call
positive discrimination.
And what is discrimination?
Discrimination may be descriptively summarised as treating people
unequally and therefore that is often unjust (according an
egalitarian concept of justice), discrimination in favour of need has
an egalitarian purpose. It gives more to the needy because they
have less - it is an attempt to reduce inequality, to approach that
ideal of equality for all which according to this view, would be
perfect justice.
Other kinds of discrimination, however, are inegalitarian in effect
as well as in method - they increase the existing inequalities. The
idea behind this conception of justice is that the particularly
-402-
Dr. Alan Xuereb
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
talented individual already has an advantage over ordinary people.
If he is given special rewards, or special prizes, or a specially good
job, you will increase his advantage. It may well be advantageous
to the community to do this - in that the person with special talents
for a particular job, such as running a business or running a school,
will no doubt bring more benefit to the community in doing that
job than would someone else of less talent.
So it makes sense, it is reasonable to train the talented individual,
put him in the responsible job, and pay him well as an incentive. It
is socially useful, and right for that reason but if this view is
adopted one cannot conclude that this is necessarily just or
equitable. Strict justice, according to this view, requires us to treat
everybody alike, apart from helping underdogs to approach
equality with the rest.
Each of these theories of justice appears to have an intuitive appeal
for our moral consciousness. They both make a persuasive case.
Professor John Rawls has produced an ingenious suggestion for
settling the principles of justice in a rational way. It is intended to
be a method of avoiding appeals to intuition with the consequent
risk of inconsistent answers. 552
Rawls uses the device · of a hypothetical social contract, a notion
familiar in earlier political philosophy but employed for a different
purpose. Rawls asks us to imagine a number of people who know
the general laws of social science but are ignorant of all particular
facts, including their own abilities, their won history, their own
position in society, or indeed the time and place of that society.
They are asked to agree upon principles for the distribution of
benefits and burdens. We can suppose, Rawls adds, that they will
think about the matter in terms of self-interest, trying to maximise
benefits and minimise burdens for themselves. They do not know
where they themselves will be in the ordering of affairs. They
might be at the top of the social scale or they might be at the
bottom. So, says Rawls, they will take care to make conditions as
552
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Oxford University Press, 1973, especially chapter III.
-403 -
Just Problems?
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
good as possible for the person at the bottom of the scale, in case
they tum out to be there themselves. Their decisions will be
motivated by self-interest but will have the effect of serving the
interest of everyone impartially, because of "the veil of ignorance".
In Rawls's view, that is what constitutes the idea of justice as
fairness. Justice then is an institutional arrangement which will, in
Rawls's view benefit everyone impartially, and we can reach an
understanding of it by imagining a social contract made in
ignorance of one's personal situation.
Rawls is not here suggesting that the concept of justice can be
identified with an idea of self-interest. Justice is essentially
impartial between one person and another. This reminds us of
Finnis's requirements of practical reason.553 The third requirement
in Finnis's list refers to the fundamental impartiality among the
human subjects who are or may be partakers of those goods. So,
the only reason for me to prefer my well-being is that it is through
my self-determined and self-realising participation in the basic
goods that one can do what reasonableness suggests and requires,
i.e. favour and realise the forms of human good indicated in the
first principles of practical reason; and so add or contribute to the
common good which insures justice for all. As Rawls puts it, if
you ask yourself in any situation what would be the just or fair
solution of a problem, you should not think in terms of self-interest,
giving yourself priority over others. The difficulty is that if people
are simply told to think intuitively in terms of justice, they will
come up with different and inconsistent answers.554
A rational calculation in terms of self-interest will avoid the bare
reference to intuitions of justice, but in the ordinary way such a
calculation would not give us the impartiality that we need.
Moreover, the hypothesis of making the calculation under a veil of
553
Coherent life plan; No arbitrary preferences amongst the basic values; No arbitrary
preferences amongst persons; Proper sense of detachment; Proper sense of commitment;
limited relevance of efficient means; Respect for every basic value in every act; Common
good of one's community; Follow one's conscience;
554
Raphael, D.D. Moral Philosophy, pp.72.
-404-
Id-Dritt 2006- Volume XIX
Dr. Alan Xuereb
ignorance about one's personal situation is a method of adding
impartiality. If one have to provide for my own interests in any
and every possible contingency, one am providing for the interests
of any everyone, not just for my own. This should remind us of the
Kantian Categorical Imperative in the form of "act as if you were
legislating for everyone", Rawls would add, starting from the poor.
Kant's "Categorical Imperative" reveals the injustice of "excepting"
ourselves
from conventional social practices like promise
keeping. But can it equally reveal the injustice of "complying" with
socially entrenched unjust maxims, e.g., slave-holding maxims in
colonial America? Standard Kantian arguments against slavery
depend on overly narrow definitions of slavery and by requiring
universalisation across all rational beings, beg the moral question
of whether differences ever warrant different treatment.555
To get back to Rawls, behind the veil of ignorance though you
might think self-interestedly, you are really constrained reasonably
to act as if you were legislating for everyone. This point about
legislating for everyone compels us to analyse what would be the
result of such a hypothetical contract made under a veil of
ignorance about particular facts? According to Rawls, people in
this system would go first for a maximum of equal liberty, and then
secondly they would agree to such departures from equality as
would improve life for everyone, including the least fortunate.
The point of the second principle is to make a distinction between
just and unjust inequalities. If the giving of special rewards or
special opportunities to talented people not only produces
substantial benefit for those few, with consequent inequality, but
also has the result of improving the general standard of life of the
whole community, including the standard of its poorest members,
then the inequality is justified.
555
Calhoun, Cheshire, Kant and Compliance With Conventionalised Injustice - SJ Phil,
32(2), 135-159, Sum 94
- 405
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
Just Problems?
However, we have a condition imposed by Rawls: if the benefit
accrues only to the privileged group and does nothing to improve
the situation of the poor, of those least advantaged, then it is not
justified. This is the main argument against factionism. But this is
not just a justice argument in favour of charity.556 There is an
economical aspect to it as well; after all a wealthier lower class
enhances the general good of the whole society. This conclusion
gives priority to an equality concept of justice. It also makes some
provision for the alternative concept of differential reward, though
not in terms of merit, strictly speaking. It says that differential
rewards are justified, not because they are deserved by the
individuals who get them, but because they benefit the whole
community and especially its poorest members. Inequality is
supported on the grounds of social utility557 and helping the needy.
So Rawls' s idea of justice maintains priority for the equality-needs
concept, including in it a hint of common utility, but really without
any valuation of merit or desert as such.
The conclusion will not be to everyone's liking, but at least it is
quite definite in settling the dilemma of choosing between the two
traditional concepts.
Furthermore, if the conclusion really has been reached by a rational
process of thought instead of appealing to intuitive conviction, we
ought to accept it. In fact, Rawls's conclusions do not rest purely
on rational calculations which would seem obvious to anyone.
556
Stressing the point that charity and justice are in fact two very distinct concepts.
'Social utility' arguments have a strong political impetus, however they might create
aberrations. Consider Sottomayor-Cardia, a Portugese-speaking philosopher, his ideas
departs from classical utilitarianism in many ways. In the first place emphasis is laid on the
concept of "interest" rather than in "happiness". At the same time there is a vindication of a
certain sort of preference for our own interest when confronted with the maximizing
principle in its most radical form, as this radical maximizing principle could lead to a sort of
"pathological Kantianism". Exception is made in cases of "negative" utilitarianism, that is,
when great greatest common "evil". In such cases the author would even allow for some
"unjust acts", so that suffering, and every sort of evil for the greatest number could be
avoided.
557
-406 -
Id-Dritt 2006- Volume XIX
Dr. Alan Xuereb
The general idea of equality in the absence of special
considerations is rational enough. So is a departure from equality
for the sake ofbenefit for all.
Why should there be special emphasis on benefit for the poor?
Intuitively, of course, this appeals to our sense ofjustice, or at any
rate to our sense of morality. Does Rawls succeed in showing that
it would appeal to our sense ofself-interest ifwe were clothed in a
veil ofignorance concerning our personal situation?
Rawls assumes that a rational self-interested man will always play
safe, will think most ofcushioning his position ifhe should turn out
to be unlucky. Suppose this hypothetical contractor contemplates
two alternative forms of society. One follows the policy of a
radical Welfare State, always providing quite a soft cushion for the
people at the bottom of the social scale but inevitably at the
expense of high taxation for the rest, so that nobody is excessively
well off.
The second society still has a cushion for its poorer members, but a
less comfortable cushion, and therefore it can leave scope for a few
people to gain glittering prizes as the result ofspecial talent, special
effort, or simple luck. Ifwe are asked which ofthe two is the more
just society, we may well say the first, but that is an intuitive
judgement. Ifwe are asked which ofthe two would be chosen by a
purely self-interested individual who did not know what his
personal abilities and fortunes would tum out to be, is it clear that
he would go for the first alternative? Why should he necessarily
play safe and think mainly of what will happen to him if he is
unlucky? Why should he not take a bit ofa gamble? In the second
society, he will not be so badly off even if he lands up at the
bottom of the pile, and there is always the chance that he might
tum out to be one ofthe fortunate few.
-407
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
Just Problems?
The idea of self-interest itself does not imply any preference
between timidity and boldness in making this choice. Rawls is not
justified in assuming that a self-interested man will be timid rather
than bold. This is obvious from the fact that Rawls' s first principle
of justice assumes the opposite, namely that a self-interested man
will prefer boldness to timidity. The first principle requires a
maximum of equal liberty. 558 This means that the people taking part
in this hypothetical social contract, and choosing from a self
interested point of view, will give priority to maximum of liberty
for all.
Rawls makes it quite clear that his specification of equal liberty,
rather than some other kind of equality,559 is deliberate. Is it clear
that a self-interested person, dissociating himself from the kind of
society he lives in, would necessarily give the highest priority to
freedom? Presuming that it makes sense at all to think of self
interested persons making choices in genuine ignorance of their
own situation and unaffected by the experience of a particular
society, why should we say that their choice would be intrepid
rather than insecure in selecting their first principle of justice, and
fainthearted rather than resolute in selecting their second principle?
Rawls' s artifice of a social contract, then, does not give us a
rational method of deciding between two rival concepts ofjustice.
The purpose of the device is to reach impartiality. But that can be
done in a simpler way. To get away from a self-interested to an
impartial judgement, all one needs to do is to imagine oneself in the
shoes of someone else. Is not this in fact the psychological basis of
the needs concept of justice? If one says that justice requires
special attention to the needs of the poor, the idea of self-interested
is quite irrelevant.
558
First Principle: Liberty - Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total
system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all. Second
Principle: Wealth - Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are
both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings
principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair
equality of opportunity.
559
Such as equality of equal goods, for instance.
-408
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
Dr. Alan Xuereb
It is not a question of making sure that there will be help for
yourself if you ever find yourself landed among the poor.
It is a
question of a sort of self-identification with the poor, an empathic
bondage between your present "self' and the Poor' s condition.
One can only appreciate what the poor feel if you imagine what
you would feel if you were one of them.
But this is not supposing that you really are one of them, and the
moral judgement which it produces is an altruistic one, not a self
interested insurance policy. The question that does need to be
raised is whether the moral obligation which arises from sympathy
for the disadvantaged is an obligation ofjustice.
Those who have a predilection for the merit-concept of justice will
not dispute that there is a moral obligation to succour the needy,
but they will deny that it is an obligation of justice. It is the duty
of charity, they will say, a finer thing than justice but not to be
confused with it.
Justice has to do with entitlements or rights. There is no right to
charity, as there is a right to what you have earned for yourself.
Charity is a matter of grace and favour. By all means, a
conscientious person will feel that he has a duty to be charitable; if
he thinks of himself merely as doing a favour, he may be tarnishing
the sheen of charity as a virtue. But for the recipient it is a favour,
not a right. As a duty, charity is a 'duty of supererogation', 560 it
goes beyond what is absolutely required of us by duties of 'perfect
obligation', by the demands ofjustice.
In referring to Rawls's definition of justice as a sort of ethical
yardstick hardly propounds a novel concept.
5
60
Raphael, D.D. Prof. Op. Cit. Pp. 75.
-409
I
I
Just Problems?
Id-Dritt 2006 - Volume XIX
Aristotle considered in his Nicomachean Ethics what it means to be
unjust and it is submitted approached that word as a symbol in the
Jungian sense of the word. 561 One ends up asking the question
whether these are just problems or problems of the just?
Alan Xuereb
September 2006
561
Thomson, J.A.K., translator of The Ethics of Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics,
Markham, Penguin Books Canada Ltd., (1980), p.172.
"the word is considered to
describe both one who breaks the law and one who takes advantage of another, i.e. acts
unfairly.... just means lawful and fair; and unjust means both unlawful and unfair."
-410-