Glenn Rikowski
Alien Life: Marx and the Future of the Human
Introduction
The ‘human’ appears to be in crisis. There is a
practical challenge to the constitution of humans.
This challenge is diverse but comes from four main
elds of contemporary science: biotechnology
(especially genetic modication of human DNA);
cybernetics, in particular, the connection of microchips
to the human brain or central nervous system;
microchip technology, articial intelligence (AI) and
robotics; and nanotechnology.1
With this new science and technology, the ‘future
of the human’ appears to become open to a world of
possibilities. It seems to offer powerful techniques
for generating articial – rather than natural –
selection. Evolution is subsumed under ‘human’
control and possibilities for redesigning the species
yield ‘transhuman’ or ‘posthuman’ futures. In this
scenario, the technological redenition of what the
‘human’ is becomes reality. Designer humans, the
downloading of consciousness into computers, bodies
without organs and cyborgs (a range of humancomputer fusions) are some of the options on the
1
Nanotechnology engineers structures at extreme microlevels. A nanometre is a
billionth of a metre: about 1/80,000 of the diameter of a human hair, or 10 times the
diameter of a hydrogen atom.
Historical Materialism, volume 11:2 (121–164)
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2003
Also available online – www.brill.nl
122 Glenn Rikowski
horizon. Some, such as the transhumanists, posthumanists and extropians
welcome these posthuman futures.
This article argues that the posthumanists have misunderstood history.
They have ignored capitalist development and missed the essential point: we
are already not-human. We are capital. Furthermore, the posthumanists rely
on technological determinism and capricious ‘choice’ regarding what we can
become in the future, and a disarming optimism concerning our capacity to
generate a world worth living in on the back of new science and its applications
to design of the species.
The unfolding of the new sciences and technologies so lauded by the
posthumanists does not proceed in a social vacuum. They are developing
within the social universe of capital. These technologies are an expression of
the deepening of capitalist social relations and capital as social force, and so
they are not innocent. The horror is not that we shall be invaded by new
technologies that have the capacity to recongure us as a species, a denite
life-form. There is a deeper horror; the horror of humanity already possessed
by an alien social force: capital. The new ‘inhuman’ technologies are a practical
manifestation of this deep possession of the human by capital. The concept
of human capital, on this account, is not some inadequate notion drawn from
bourgeois labour economics but expresses our real predicament.
The rst section notes some impending scientic and technological
discoveries and applications that are reconguring human life. The second
section shows how these developments hold promises for life beyond the
‘human’ – as post/trans-human life-forms. Section III contains a critique of
post/transhumanism as development of the human based on ‘autonomous’
technology. The rest of the paper explores how we are already situated
posthumanly as capitalised life-forms.
Our social existence as human capital is a contradictory one. It is the form
of everyday life as the experience of living contradictions that provides the
dynamic (and hence the explanation) for us to seek to become posthuman
capital: to enable humanism – as an open future for the species. Humanism, on
this basis, is our collective freedom to decide what the ‘human’ is to become,
free of the fetters of capital. In toto, capital limits what we can become. For
our becoming – as a species – is an expression of the ‘becoming of capital’ that
Marx wrote about in the Manuscripts,2 capital as a ‘force we must submit to’.3
2
3
Marx 1977a.
Marx 1992, p. 269.
Marx and the Future of the Human 123
Humanism becomes possible only on the abolition of capital as social force,
and this presupposes the destruction of capitalist social relations and the
social universe of capital, whose substance is value.
On this account of humanism, there is no ‘essence’ of the ‘human’, no
‘getting back to where we once belonged’. Today, humanism is the struggle
for an open future. The social universe of capital must be imploded in order
to set in train the project of humanism as social reality.
I. The appliance of science
The appliance of new science and technologies to human frailties and limitations
appears to be on the threshold of a new era. The Human Genome Project has
caused most optimism for big breakthroughs in the near future. As Matt
Ridley has dramatically put it:
On 26th June 2000, the world changed. On that day, for the rst time, a
species of living creature announced that it had grown sufciently complex,
biologically and culturally, to have read its own genetic recipe. It now
had the complete instructions for building and running the body of one of
its kind. 4
For Ridley, the ‘secret of life is out’.5 The Human Genome Project (HGP) has
provided a map of the human genome. It was only seventeen years ago that
two Californian scientists spliced DNA and successfully transferred genetic
material from one life-form to another,6 giving rise to a new applied science
that spawned a new industry: genetic engineering. Yet this is only the beginning;
the whole biotechnology sector has a capitalisation of only $150 billion, far
less than that of the internet. Mark Williams has argued that, by the midtwenty-rst century, the internet ‘may seem a side-show to the main event
in IT – the explosion of bioinformatics’.7
Matt Ridley stresses the dangers as well as the benets inherent in mining
the human genome for practical applications. He lists germ warfare, genetic
engineering of human beings and social and economic division (between
those who can/not afford the benets owing from biotechnology) as some
of the dangers at issue. Steve Jones argues that the prot drive may dampen
4
5
6
7
Ridley 2000.
Ridley 2000.
Bruno 2000, p. 262.
Williams 2000.
124 Glenn Rikowski
enthusiasm for the whole HGP, as corporations attempt to patent sequences
of DNA ‘without knowing what they do’.8 Ayala Ochert notes that, in the
US, ‘there is serious talk of genetically modifying people’ and that scientists
‘have begun to talk openly about the possibility’ of GM people.9
More sinister is that scientists are also considering possibilities for the ‘direct
control of our evolution through so-called “germline” gene therapy’.10 Somatic
gene therapy – which has no consequences for offspring – was rst carried
out fourteen years ago. However, Ayala Ochert predicts that, in next twenty
years, human genetic modication – ‘germline’ modication of inherited
characteristics – is on the cards. The consequences of this are that, if you
‘change the germline . . . you change evolution’.11 Ochert stresses that this
work is not being carried out by a group of ‘mad professor’ types trying to
produce a master race. Rather, it is growing out of mainstream scientic
research being undertaken in fertility clinics, in medicine, in biology and in
pharmaceutical companies.12 If these trends continue, and the applications
owing from the HGP are anywhere near as signicant as many scientists
are predicting, then, argues Kat Arney, the development of ‘cloning techniques,
brain-cell transplants and micro-computers could allow people to “upgrade”
both themselves and their cloned progeny’.13
Ochert’s reassurance that twenty-three European countries signed a Council
of Europe declaration prohibiting ‘germline’ gene therapy may not be worth
much when commentators point towards the European biotechnology sector
being hamstrung by strict regulations on the industry.14 The European biotech
sector has also received far less state funding for development than its American
counterpart, where tax breaks for biotech start-ups tempt venture capitalists
into the eld. With no global regulation, European germline enterprises may
set up in countries outside Council of Europe jurisdiction. For now, it may
well be the practical difculties of translating new knowledge about the
human genome into hard products are prohibitive. For example, 95–99.9 per
cent of all ‘engineered’ embryos is damaged or defective.15
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
Jones, in Cartwright et al. 2000, p. 24.
Ochert 2000, p. 22.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Arney 1998.
Commentators such as Guerrera and Firn 2000.
Ochert 2000, p. 22.
Marx and the Future of the Human 125
The other technology where applications directly affecting the human body
seem on the horizon is cybernetics. In the last few years, it has come off the
science ction shelves and into the body of real humans, or proto-cyborgs.
Jeremy Campbell notes work at the University of Southern California on
growing neurones on microchips ‘that are made to emigrate into the brain’16
and communicate with it. Experiments at Reading University, led by Kevin
Warwick, involve implanting chips into his own arm.17 An experiment undertaken in August 1998 involved a computer programmed to respond to
Warwick’s actions, and further self-experimentation is planned. 18 According
to Theodore Burger, the capability exists for building computer chips that act
just like nerve cells.19 From this, argues Jeremy Campbell, computer chips in
the brain to boost memory become a feasible step.20 These chips would allow
‘people to “download” large quantities of information instantly, as a computer
does from the Internet’, according to neuroscience writer Ray Kurzweil.21
Whilst this technological invasion appears to recongure the ‘human’,
this is nothing as compared with its opposite; the ‘downloading’ of our
consciousness into a computer lodged within a robot. Though much further
off, this leaves any conception of what it is to be ‘human’ in limbo. As Bill
Joy, cofounder and Chief Scientist at Sun Microsystems, ponders:
But if we are downloaded into our technology, what are the chances that
we will thereafter be ourselves or even human? It seems to me far more
likely that a robotic existence would not be like a human one . . . [and] . . . the
robots would in no sense be our children, [and] . . . on this path our humanity
may well be lost.22
Charles Platt argues that, if we downloaded our consciousness into a computer,
then the resulting entities would be ‘isomorphs’ – minds without organs.23
Nanotechnology is the design and manufacture of devices to atomic-scale
precision. The potential of the technology appears to be gigantic. As Natasha
Vita-More notes, nanomachines could repair aged tissues and organs. They
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
Campbell 1999.
See Alesky 2000.
In Alesky 2000.
In Campbell 1999.
Campbell 1999.
In Campbell 1999.
Joy 2000, p. 244.
Platt 2000, p. 208.
126 Glenn Rikowski
could, in theory, reanimate people who have been frozen in cryonic
suspension.24 With nanotechnology, argues Paul Virilio, the ‘inner core of the
living’ is to be equipped with micromachines that can ‘effectively stimulate
our faculties’ – including enhanced cognitive capabilities.25 Nanobots – tiny
machines we could swallow – could be launched into our blood streams.
They would ‘supplement our natural immune system and seek out and destroy
pathogens, cancer cells, arterial plaque, and other disease agents’, notes Ray
Kurzweil.26 Nick Bostrom predicts the creation of a ‘superintelligence’ within
the next forty years: a cognitive system that ‘drastically outperforms the top
present-day humans in every way’. 27 Such a system would fuse human
cognitive capability with:
. . . hardware neural networks, simulated neural networks, classical AI,
extracranially cultured tissue, quantum computers, large interconnected
computer networks, evolutionary chips, nootropic treatment of the human
brain, biological-electronic symbiosis systems or what have you.28
Wired up in this way, we could shut down all our schools and universities.
In this section, I have listed key scientic developments that could shape
the ‘future of the human’. Human life appears to be subject to re-design. Paul
Virilio argues that, for our species, the situation has been reached where
classical evolution as natural selection no longer applies. For Virilio, we are
on the verge of a ‘techno-scientic phase’ of evolution where articial selection,
selection based on conscious choice, prevails.29 Some do not mourn this
‘passing of the human’, but look to a transhuman future that holds great
promise for liberation of all kinds, and it is to this trans/posthumanism that
we now turn.
II. Advancing a trans/posthuman future
The previous section pointed towards scientic applications that have the
potential to radically alter humankind. Some welcome this, and actively strive
to speed up its development. Nick Bostrom summarises this outlook:
24
25
26
27
28
29
Vita-More und., p. 14.
Virilio 1995, p. 101.
Kurzweil 1999, p. 176.
Bostrom 1998, p. 13.
Ibid.
Virilio 1995, p. 117.
Marx and the Future of the Human 127
Over the past few years, a new paradigm for thinking about humankind’s
future has begun to take shape among some leading computer scientists,
neuroscientists, nanotechnologists and researchers at the forefront of
technological development. The new paradigm rejects . . . the assumption
that the ‘human condition’ is at root a constant. . . . This assumption no
longer holds true.30
The ‘human’, it seems, is headed for history. However, for transhumanists,
it is more complex than this, as the following discussion makes clear.
Transhumanist politics, ethics and philosophy supplement technological
wonders.
A useful starting point is the notion of the ‘transhuman’. This concept posits
the contemporary constitution of the ‘human’ as being in a state of radical
transition. According to Max More:
We are transhuman to the extent that we seek to become posthuman and
take action to prepare for a posthuman future. This involves learning about
and making use of new technologies that can increase our capacities and
life expectancy, questioning common assumptions, and transforming ourselves
ready for the future, rising above outmoded human beliefs and behaviors. 31
This denition begs the question of what the ‘posthuman’ is, and this
is addressed later. The ‘transhuman’ is a practical process of leaving
currently constituted humanity behind. It implies a transition beyond the
human condition and human ‘nature’. Transhumanism carries with it a moral
and political spark: we ought to try to overcome the ‘human’ limitations
resulting from our physiology and biological foundations. For Ouroboros,
‘transhumanism’ is
the belief that we can, and should, try to overcome our biological limits by
means of reason, science and technology. Transhumanists seek things like
intelligence, augmentation, increased strength and beauty, extreme life
extension, sustainable mood enhancement and the capability to get offplanet
and explore the universe. These goals are to be achieved with the aid
of contemporary and future technologies such as genetic engineering,
nanotechnology, cryonics, megascale and space-time engineering, AI, and
mind uploading.32
30
31
32
Bostrom 1998, p. 24.
More undated.
Ouroboros 1999, p. 4.
128 Glenn Rikowski
Max More has described transhumanism as related to philosophies of life
that ‘seek the continuation and acceleration of the evolution of intelligent life
beyond its currently human form and limits’.33 Science and technology are
the principal means to these goals, although, for More, ‘life-promoting principles
and values’ also play a role34 – however, transhumanism is no religious cult,
argues More. Rather, it is founded on the belief that ‘it is good to improve
oneself, physically and mentally’, and to dissolve existing biological and social
limits to processes of self-improvement.35 These limits can be overcome through
the utilisation of ‘rational’ methods (technology and science).36 Transhumanists
advocate the ‘progressive transformation of the human condition’; there is
no end point.37
The core goal, then, is the transcendence of ‘human nature’, implying
the practical redenition of the human. The ‘posthuman’ is the realisation of the
transhumanist project. Transhumanism is therefore a ‘politics of/for the
posthuman’; humans actively striving to become posthumans.38 Max More
denes the ‘posthuman’ in the following way:
Posthumans have overcome the biological, neurological, and psychological
constraints evolved into humans. Posthumans may be partly or mostly
biological in form, but will likely be or partly or wholly postbiological –
our personalities having been transferred ‘into’ more durable, modiable,
and faster, and more powerful bodies and thinking hardware. Some of the
technologies that we currently expect to play a role in allowing us to become
posthuman include genetic engineering , neural-computer integration,
molecular nanotechnology, and cognitive science.39
Following More, Greg Burch argues that the ‘posthuman’ refers to what we
have changed so much that our condition no longer can be accurately called
‘human’.40
Another signicant term in this lexicon is ‘posthumanism’. Posthumanism
is an ‘attitude on [sic] how to deal with the limitations of the human form’,
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
More undated.
More undated.
More undated.
Transcedo 1998, p. 1.
Burch 1998, p. 1.
Rikowski 1999b, p. 56.
More undated.
Burch, in Burch and Toth-Fejel 1999, p. 1.
Marx and the Future of the Human 129
according to Daniel Ust.41 It is a tragic feeling or attitude, focusing on the
frustrations of life as merely ‘human’. It is the negative side of the positive
vision of transhumanism.
Two nal concepts are required – extropy and extropian – though there
are many others that could be added in a comprehensive rendering. The
signicance of these two concepts is that they dene the position of the world’s
leading transhumanist, Max More, cofounder of the Extropy Institute. The
Extropian Movement was started by Max More and Tom Morrow (not their
real names) in the late 1980s. They launched the journal Extropy in 1988, and
there is now Extropy Online. There is also the Extropy Institute (with annual
conferences), a bimonthly newsletter, an electronic email list, a boarding
house – Nextropia – and parties and lunches.42 According to Beatrice Gibson,
membership of the Extropy Institute is increasing.43 The annual conference is
particularly important. At the Extro4 conference in 2000, the gap between
extropians and mainstream scientists visibly narrowed as several scientists
from a range of elds got together formally for the rst time with leading
extropians at a major venue.44
So what are the extropians about? According to Brian Alexander, they are
‘techno-believers with boundless faith in science’s power to amp up human
potential’.45 Life extension is a major goal, with ‘deathism’ scorned. Beatrice
Gibson characterises the extropians as ‘a Californian group of hardcore
technological believers, who aspire one day to be able to download the
informational essence of their minds onto computer databases and achieve
cyber-immortality’.46
Max More denes the key terms: extropy is the extent of a system’s
intelligence, information, order, vitality, and capacity for improvement.47 It is
the opposite of entropy, which is based on the second law of thermodynamics
that states everything in the universe is inevitably subject to death and decay.
Entropy dictates that life is subject to mortality,48 but extropians seek to extend
41
Ust undated, p. 1.
See Ust undated, p. 1.
43
Gibson 2000, p. 27.
44
Alexander 2000, p. 180.
45
Alexander 2000, p. 179.
46
Gibson 2000, p. 26. For more on the Californian roots of transhumanism and
cyberideology, see Barbrook and Cameron 1996, and Barbrook 2002.
47
More 1999, p. 1.
48
Gibson 2000, p. 26 and p. 29.
42
130 Glenn Rikowski
and enrich life for ‘humans’.49 They believe the best strategy for attaining
posthumanity to be a combination of technology and determination, rather
than looking for it through psychic contacts, or extraterrestrial or divine gift.50
More outlines the core extropian principles as: perpetual progress, selftransformation, practical optimism, intelligent technology, the open society,
self-direction, and rational thinking.51
Although a techno-ideology, transhumanism cannot be reduced to any
single technology. Furthermore, it has nothing to do with developing a ‘master
race’, argues Greg Burch.52 This becomes more apparent when some of the
positive claims for transhumanism are stated. These include the dissolution
of hierarchies based on gender, ‘race’ or any other ascriptive characteristic –
especially age. The goal is individual choice of skin colour and texture, choice
of the range of sexual organs and decision on overall body design. No single
body design is deemed superior; it is just a personal preference or fashion
statement – which can be altered. Natasha Vita-More speaks of a future with
multiple sex organs, polymer skin that changes colour and virtual reality
eyeball implants.53 Shaun Jones raises the stakes as he talks about ‘the
manipulation of the rewalls that exist between species’, so that we may have
fur instead of mere skin for part or all of our bodies.54 Why buy mink fur,
with all the cruelty inherent in its production, when it can be grown on our
own arms?
Dramatic claims have been made for the cyborg as harbinger of a new
equality. As our ‘evolutionary descendent’, it is the ‘solution to gender ’ and
the solution to power differentiation.55 Thus, ‘the cyborg may appear animal
and material, invincible and perishable, utopian and mythical, corporeal and
opaque, male and female, historical and subversive’, notes Jeff Lewis.56 For
Donna Haraway, the cyborg as a fused human-machine entity breaks down
hierarchy:
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
More 1999, p. 1. See also More in Olson 2002, p. 2.
More undated.
More 1999, p. 2.
In Burch and Toth-Fejel 1999, p. 1.
In Alexander 2000, p. 179.
In Alexander 2000, p. 186.
Lewis 1998, p. 377.
Ibid.
Marx and the Future of the Human 131
The cyborg is resolutely committed to partiality, irony, intimacy, and perversity.
It is oppositional, utopian and completely without innocence . . . The
relationships for forming polarity and hierarchical domination are at issue
in the cyborg world.57
The cyborg promises an ‘informatics of liberation’ that would ‘seek to advance
semblation beyond the entertainment perimeters of arcade games and
capitalistic processes generally’.58 A posthuman future would not maintain
current hierarchies. And it would be more fun. Ed Regis argues that the ‘toilet,
as we know it, would be a thing of the past’; however, the transhuman’s
sexual capacity would increase ‘in variety, intensity, duration, and just about
every other imaginable way’, enhanced by our new sex organs and new
sexes.59 This transhuman equality, choice and difference ts cosily with some
liberal-left visions, although, in terms of its politics and economics, the
transhumanist outlook tends generally to support neoliberal nostrums.60
At the terminus of some transhuman futures resides the ‘body without
organs’.61 A consciousness swirling around in chips inside a robot sounds like
a practical case of annihilation of the ‘human’. Ian Tattersall questions whether
a species can survive as a set of ‘disembodied attributes’.62 This last point
opens up the general question of the relationship between humanism and
transhumanism.
According to Nick Bostrom, transhumanism ‘agrees with humanism on
many points but shoots beyond it by emphasising that we can and should
transcend our biological limitations’.63 Indeed, argues Greg Burch:
The word ‘transhumanism’ consciously evokes the tradition of humanism,
i.e. the secular view of man as the ‘center ’ of the moral universe. However,
transhumanism goes beyond humanism, because it does not accept some
immutable, fundamental ‘human nature’ as a given, but rather looks to
continuing – and accelerating – the process of expanding and improving
the very nature of human beings themselves. 64
57
Haraway 1991, p. 151 in Lewis 1998, p. 377.
Ibid.
59
Regis 1990, p. 168.
60
See Rikowski 2000c. See also Barbrook and Cameron 1996, and Barbrook 2002 –
on the cyber-politics underpinning the Californian Ideology that spawned such movements as transhumanism.
61
Bukatman 1999, p. 325.
62
Tattersall 2000, p. 75.
63
Bostrom 1998, p. 25.
64
Burch 1998, p. 1.
58
132 Glenn Rikowski
Max More argues that, like humanists, transhumanists ‘favour reason, progress,
and values centered on our well being’ rather than on an external religious
authority.65 However, transhumanists take humanism further by challenging
human limits by means of science and technology combined with critical and
creative thinking. Thus, transhumanists
see humanity as a transitory stage in the evolutionary development of
intelligence. We advocate using science to accelerate our move from human
to transhuman or posthuman condition.66
As we have seen, for Burch, ‘transhumanism’ evokes the tradition of humanism:
humankind at the ‘centre’ of the moral universe, the ‘measure of all things’.67
Transhumanism, however, does not accept some immutable ‘human nature’
as a xed item. There is no ‘essence’ to the human – xed by genetic,
psychological, social or any other dimension of existence. Transhumanism
seeks to continue and accelerate the ‘process of expanding and improving
the very nature of human beings themselves’, argues Burch.68 Thus: ‘transhumanism is the modern heir to the humanist tradition, in fact transhumanism
carries on the torch of the “humane” culture into an era of ultratechnology’.69
As Daniel Ust, notes, labelling posthumanism as inhuman merely begs the
question regarding what the ‘human’ is.70 Ust argues that there is no necessary
conict between posthuman existence and some of the ner qualities we
associate with humans. Indeed, argues Ust, the posthuman will extend virtues
and qualities such as intelligence, courage and inventiveness, which, with
much greater physical capacity and longevity, should promote increased
tenderness and compassion.71
Together with the scientic, medical and technological developments of
the previous section, this section raises serious questions concerning the future
of the ‘human’. The ‘human’ appears to be at risk. The following section puts
this risk into perspective through a critique of transhumanism.
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
More 1999, p. 1.
Ibid.
Burch 1998, p. 1.
Ibid.
Burch in Burch and Toth-Fejel 1999, p. 1.
Ust undated, p. 3.
Ibid.
Marx and the Future of the Human 133
III. An alien critique of transhumanism
Of course, different conceptions of the human subject have been proposed
throughout the centuries,72 and ideas of human nature have changed substantially throughout history, from Plato to Wittgenstein and beyond,73 but
the posthuman points towards a fundamental surpassing of the ‘human’
itself.74 This has consequences for any project of locating the ‘human’ in some
behavioural traits such as in the capacity to ‘make ourselves’,75 or to ‘care
for the things precious to us’.76 These take on new meanings within post/
transhumanist discourses that exceed old notions of the ‘human’. Neither
will denitions of the ‘human’ based on general capabilities hold up (such
as the ‘learning animal’ or the ‘toolmaker’): these are being redened as we
forge ever-closer relationships with machines and computers. Furthermore,
the ‘human’ is seriously at risk on some genetic bottom-line denition (for
example, the exact chemical composition of the DNA making up genes); 77
this is dissolving with genetic engineering possibilities.
What is meant by ‘inhuman’ becomes unclear too. Keith Tester’s assertion
that the inhuman is everything which forces the individual to ‘subscribe to a
determined being’ (after Ortega y Gasset) is problematised by possibilities for
the posthuman.78 The degree of determination by the ‘social’ is downgraded by
virtue of the apparent dynamism of possibilities opened up by the posthuman.
It appears that posthuman innovation supersedes not just classical Darwinian
evolution but also mainstream sociological conceptions on the efcacy of
social structures, norms and values as fetters and shapers of the social life of
individuals. The posthuman crashes through social a well as biological limits.79
Tester’s claim that the ‘inhuman is everything which gives the already written
script of the novel she or he is going to be able to write’, trades on old
sociological verities that have no currency within the posthuman.80 The notion
of posthuman sociality is a reconguration of all previously known forms of
social life, on the accounts of the post/transhuman theorists.
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
See Morris 1991, and Smith 2002.
See Trigg 1988.
Rikowski 1999b.
Tester 1995, p. xi.
Joy 2000, p. 262.
Lewontin 1995, p. 43.
Tester 1995, p. xi.
As in Transcedo 1998.
Tester 1995, p. xi.
134 Glenn Rikowski
The notion of ‘dehumanisation’ also undergoes radical transformation
within posthuman discourse. For Tester, dehumanisation ‘is the processual
tendency of circumstance to foreclose on the possibilities which the individual
experiences him or her self as having in relation to the situations she or he
is thrown into’.81 Yet Tester realises ‘the profound difculty is that precisely
without these circumstances and experiential determinations, the world could
scarcely be a place of and for human being’.82 The posthuman changes these
circumstances, radically. The posthuman condition offers a degree of malleability
to the entity in question that makes prognostications about sociality difcult.
What kind of social life does a consciousness downloaded into a computer
lodged within a robot have? If the transhuman is a trajectory for the ‘human’,
then all bets concerning the relevance of contemporary sociological concepts
are, at best, hedged.
Finally, Tester ’s claim that the ‘human and the inhuman can never
be separated’ rests upon an anthropomorphism that is challenged by the
posthuman.83 For, as Keith Ansell-Pearson argues:
To maintain that technology is making us ‘less human’ is to suppose that
there exists some xed nature of the human by which one could measure
the excesses of technology, and so appraise its inventions in terms of some
metaphysical cost-benets analysis.84
The posthuman problematises the ‘human’ and technology drives this problem
on ever more intensely. It demands continual rethinking of our relationship
with machines.85 The posthuman also apparently generates the drive for
‘technology’s invention of the human animal’.86 Of course, as Martin Parker
has noted, social organisation always involves some relation between humans
and non-human materials,87 but the movement towards the posthuman
incrementally blurs the distinction. Set on this trajectory, as Bill Joy urges,
the question is: ‘Which is to be the master? Will we survive our own technologies?’88 From a posthumanist perspective, however, these questions are
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ansell-Pearson 1997a, p. 153.
Hayles 1997a, p. 153.
Ansell-Pearson 1997a, p. 153.
Parker 1998, p. 504.
Joy 2000, p. 256.
Marx and the Future of the Human 135
redundant; the invasiveness of technology into the becoming-posthuman
is not a threat but rather a solution to the future of the ‘human’. But, as Paul
Saffo argues, technologies mirror the cultures that create them, and the ‘coming
world of electronic lifeforms is likely to be no different’,89 and on this point
rests part of the critique of the posthuman promise, as developed later.
The crisis of the ‘human’ is simultaneously a crisis of humanism.90 If humanism
is ‘an account that centres human beings as the measure of all other things’,91
then the posthuman trajectory continually recongures the standard of
measurement. Max More argues that the real issue is a humanist courage
decit:
Should we ‘play God’? We might expect Humanists, having accepted that
there is no divine creator, shepherd, and purpose-giver, to resp ond
afrmatively. However, I contend that many humanists, though pro-reason,
science, and technology . . . still fear their own Promethean urge to challenge
the gods.92
Alternatively, transhumanists ‘anticipate our future as posthumans’ and adjust
their view of their lives accordingly.93
Taking the argument one stage further, according to Judith Halberstam and
Ira Livingstone, ‘if the human is dead, the alien, the other goes with it’.94 For
these analysts, however, the alien is the posthuman; they are therefore closet
humanists at heart, mourning the ‘death of the human’. Katherine Hayles,
meanwhile, looks forward to the excitement of the posthuman as it ‘evokes
the exhilarating prospect of getting out of some of the old boxes and opening
new ways of thinking about what being human means’.95 For Hayles, the
posthuman does not signify the end of humanity; rather, it ‘signals instead
the end of a certain conception of the human’.96 This conception itself applied
only to a small number of people – those with the ‘wealth, power, and leisure
to conceptualise themselves as autonomous beings exercising their will through
individual agency and choice’. 97 Thus, ‘old humanism’ is a class-based
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
Saffo 1998, pp. 2–3.
Halberstam and Livingstone 1995, p. 9.
Parker 1998, p. 504.
More 1994, p. 1.
Ibid.
Halberstam and Livingstone 1995, p. 13.
Hayles 1999, p. 285.
Hayles 1999, p. 286.
Ibid.
136 Glenn Rikowski
perspective on the human, despite protests for its universality from those
supporters of the ‘liberal humanist view of the self’.98 Hayles argues that the
posthuman ‘need not be recuperated back into liberal humanism, nor need
it be construed as anti-human’: it has its own future.99
Others point towards the human/transhuman as continuum. Transcedo
argues that both humanism and transhumanism revere rationalism and are
concerned for the fate of humanity.100 They both eschew the relevance of the
supernatural as guide to life. Transhumanism only parts company with
humanism when the former urges on development of the ‘human’ beyond
current biological constitution and human evolution. However, the shift
towards the posthuman is not just a matter of us subjecting ourselves to new
science and technology. Max More makes this clear:
The transition from human to posthuman can be dened physically or
memetically. Physically, we will have become posthuman only when we
have made such fundamental and sweeping modications to our inherited
genetics, physiology, neurophysiology and neurochemistry, that we can no
longer be usefully classied with Homo Sapiens. Memetically, we might expect
posthumans to have a different motivational structure from humans, or at
least the ability to make modications if they choose. For example . . . complete
control over emotional responses through manipulation of neurochemistry.101
More leaves something out in his list of ‘things for change’: the nature of
posthuman society. What he – and almost all trans/posthumanist writers –
forgets is that the spectre of posthuman capitalism lurks within the future for
the post/human.102 There are real social limits to posthumanisation, limits set
by capital. The trans/posthumanists avoid the problem of capital in their
projections. On the constitution of post/human society, the silence of the
trans/posthumanists signies their real techtopianism: their ungrounded
belief that technology will cut through all problems and limits for the post/
human. This is where Marx enters.
The problem is how to introduce Marx into the debate on the future of the
human. Felicity Callard and Donald Lowe have attempted to bring Marx in
98
99
100
101
102
Hayles 1999, pp. 186–7.
Hayles 1999, p. 187.
Transcedo 1998, p. 1.
More 1994, p. 2.
Ansell-Pearson 1997a-b, and Callard 1998 are exceptions.
Marx and the Future of the Human 137
through analyses of the body.103 However, this neatly skips around some of
the phenomena that take us deeply into an exploration of the ‘human’ through
Marx, principally labour-power and capital. Thus, the search is on for better
ways of approaching post/transhumanism through Marx.
Marx and the post/transhuman
There are a few texts that bring Marx and Marxism into direct contact with
the problem of the post/transhuman. Keith Ansell-Pearson’s work makes
some attempt to do this. However, Ansell-Pearson only discerns Marx’s
relevance for subjecting post/trans-human theory to critique in the nal pages
of the Conclusion to his Germinal Life.104 He also addressed briey the
capitalism/transhuman relation in his earlier Viroid Life.105
Ansell-Pearson argues we should be sceptical about ‘depictions of evolution
as moving increasingly in the direction of a posthuman phase’, as these theories
biologise and hypostatise developments within capitalism.106 Secondly, post/
transhuman theories give no account of the changing relation between humans
and machines – an account that Marxism has a signicant stake in.107 AnsellPearson argues that it was ‘Marx’s tremendous insight that it is capital itself
which develops as a metaphysics of energy’, and he hails the following quote
from Marx:
It [political economy/private property] develops a cosmopolitan, universal
energy which breaks through every limit and every bond and posits itself
as the only policy, the only universality, the only limit and the only bond.108
From this exciting beginning, Ansell-Pearson’s attempt to bring Marx into
contact with post/transhumanism tails off. First, he debunks Guy Debord’s
view that it is the destiny of the working class to ‘humanise the inhuman’
by gaining control over it. He dismisses Debord (on post/transhuman grounds)
as an essentialist.109 In Viroid Life, he conates capital and Nietzsche’s eternal
103
As demonstrated in Rikowski 2000c. Callard 1998 and Lowe 1995 provide a ‘false
start’ for understanding transhumanism through Marx by their focus on the body
rather than exploring capitalist socialist relations and capital as a social force.
104
Ansell-Pearson 1999.
105
Ansell-Pearson 1997a.
106
Ansell-Pearson 1999, p. 214.
107
Ansell-Pearson 1999, p. 215.
108
Marx 1977a, in Ansell-Pearson 1999, p. 218.
109
Ansell-Pearson 1999, p. 160.
138 Glenn Rikowski
return by arguing that ‘Capital operates as a virtual machine trapped within
a productionist logic of eternal repetition’.110 Thus: if the posthuman happens,
it develops as a distinctly capitalist social form of life. Furthermore, it is an
aspect of capital’s eternal life as eternal return of the Same. Yet this does not
square with Ansell-Pearson’s contention that the ‘evolution of the system of
capitalism can be de-reied by exposing, through a machinic analysis, the
illusion of total control it inevitably gives rise to’.111 He seeks to justify this
by referring to ‘structural pressures’ that compel groups to move in opposite
directions at the same time.112 Whether there is capital’s eternal return or
capital’s lack of total control due to ‘structural pressures’ forcing groups into
conict, is never followed through by Ansell-Pearson in either Germinal Life
or Viroid Life.
Nick Land’s brief posthumanist critique of Marxism is more interesting
than Ansell-Pearson’s meandering.113 Land argues that Marx’s value theory
of labour is anthropomorphic. Thus, ‘surplus-value is not analytically extricable
from transhuman machineries’.114 The post/transhuman spells the death not
just of the ‘human’ but also of the social universe of capital with its substance:
value. On this account, ‘virtual capital-extinction is immanent to production’.115
Capitalism is the ‘economic base of nal-phase human security’ that engenders
the posthuman – its real gravedigger.116 Here, Land has raised a substantial
problem for Marxism.
Donald Lowe seconds Nick Land’s projection on the end of surplus-value
production. He argues that ‘robotic, labor-less, non-human machines do not
produce surplus-value’.117 Unlike Land, Lowe explains why this is the case;
surplus-value is extracted from production to satisfy bodily needs, but, with
the posthuman, those needs diminish radically as we become at one with
machines. The problem with this analysis is that it runs counter to the variegated
posthuman futures offered by post/transhumanists. Those posthumans who
choose to remain in esh-covered bodies still have needs, and are therefore
potentially capable of value production.
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
Ansell-Pearson 1997a, p. 174.
Ansell-Pearson 1997a, p. 176.
Ansell-Pearson 1997a, p. 177.
Land 1998.
Land 1998, p. 78.
Ibid.
Land 1998, p. 81.
Lowe 1995, p. 175.
Marx and the Future of the Human 139
In these circumstances, Lowe’s call for us to resist a posthuman future falls
into the trap of seeming to want to retain value production. Abstract resistance
against a posthuman future falls back on itself; we end up saving the very
social conditions and arrangements – capitalism – that, if post/transhumanists
are correct, are generating a particular (capitalist) form of posthuman future.
However, Lowe redeems the situation by arguing for resistance to capital:
real resistance is the negation of, and active opposition to, capital. But this
misses the other target: resistance to a form of human life. With another attempt
(but taking the previous two points on board too), Lowe hits both targets:
Resistance is critical in the sense that it seeks to reverse the means/ends
relations in the late-capitalist opposition between bodily needs and capital
accumulation.118
In essence, this becomes human resistance: our resistance to the capitalisation of
the human, the capitalisation of humanity – resistance to ourselves becoming truly
human capital, capital as a life-form within the ‘human’. This is the real horror
that the post/transhumanists hide, a horror uncovered later in this article.
Having outlined key post/transhumanist concepts, and indicated through
the work of Lowe how we can engage Marx with a critique of the transhuman,
the following sub section pinpoints some of the basic weaknesses of the
post/transhumanist outlook.
An alien critique of trans/posthumanism
As an old-fashioned ‘human’, I am alien to the posthuman of the future. As
such an alien, a relic of future’s past, I present this sub section as a spoiler
for a posthuman future. I bring the posthuman down to earth (and Earth)
by posing some points of critique for my potential superior.
(i) When is post?
Ironically, the concept of ‘posthuman’ appears to be premised upon some
naturalistic conception of the ‘human’ which implies an unwarranted essentialism. The posthuman points towards a fundamental surpassing of the
‘human’: as ‘humans’ are technologised, invaded, taken over and shaped by
biochemical manipulation, computer-tech implants and human-computer
118
Ibid.
140 Glenn Rikowski
interaction, then they become something else – posthuman. However, unless the
‘human’ has been xed beforehand – perhaps resting on some biological or
genetic bottom-line – then the posthuman theorists are never ever in a position
to say whether the post- has really arrived: that the ‘human’ is history.119
(ii) Technological determinism, demon technology
A further problem is technological determinism. The ‘new technologies’ appear
to oat free of social relations in post/transhumanist discourse. Technology
and biochemical inventions, innovations and products invade human bodies
for consumption (or consumption aids), or for enhancing the productivity of
labour, or for the basic functioning of the organism. These technological
developments, abstracted from capitalist social relations and the structuring
elements of capitalist society (value, abstract labour, capital etc.),120 form the
backdrop to potentially horric vistas or post/transhuman techtopias. It seems
then that:
Technologies have their own increasingly alien agenda, and human concerns
will survive and prosper only when we learn to treat them, not as slaves
or simple extensions of ourselves, but as unknown constructs with whom
we make creative alliances and wary pacts.121
We must make our peace with technology, otherwise technology invades the
body, argues Stelarc.122 The machine preys upon humanity, which heralds
the end of (human) history, accompanied by new Luddite calls to ‘control
the machine’. Post/transhuman theorists who terrorise today’s humanity with
prognoses of genetically designed bodies, microchips in the brain and the
rest typically lack an explanatory dynamic which underpins such developments
and projections. If free-oating technology was a reality, if it really had a ‘life
of its own’, then it would not be the powerful enemy it appears to be. Its
externality to humans would herald our ability to halt its entry into our
bodies. But technology is an expression of capitalist social relations, and these
cannot just be sent to the breaker’s yard; they require fundamental forms of
social destruction, a mass dismantling on a global scale. Technology, therefore,
is not something external to the world of the human.
119
120
121
122
Rikowski 1999b, pp. 56–7.
After Postone 1996.
Davis 1998, p. 335.
Stelarc 1998, p. 117.
Marx and the Future of the Human 141
(iii) No dynamic for techno-evolution
Yet another problem for post/transhuman theory is its incorporation of articial
rather than natural selection. As UCLA’s Gregory Stock argues, ‘Evolution
is being superceded by technology. . . . Humans are becoming objects of
conscious design’.123 Kat Arney argues that ‘As we near the end of the twentieth
century, it feels as if mankind has ceased to evolve in the biological sense’
for ‘technological evolution has won hands-down over biological evolution’.124
Thus, the ‘survival of the ttest no longer applies’ as ‘disadvantageous genes
are passed on’.125 We are gradually removing the selective pressures that lie
at the heart of classic Darwinian evolution.
Ray Kurzweil argues that, in the present century, humans will have ‘vastly
beaten evolution’ therefore ‘achieving in a matter of only thousands of
years as much or more than evolution achieved in billions of years’.126 Paul
Virilio views the posthuman through post-Darwinism. 127 For a future of
human-machine integration, symbiosis and fusion, it is articial – not
natural – selection that will determine the selection of types. However,
there is the problem of specifying the dynamic, the mechanism for articial
selection. Given the posthuman hype about diversity and choice, Virilio’s
articial selection takes on a chilling note. Posthumans shall decide which
posthumans are ‘selected’; thus, against apparent posthuman-liberalism, a
‘master posthuman’ is the outcome of Virilio’s ‘articial selection’ – unless
some non-interventionist mode of articial selection is applied. But this move
merely makes articial selection as random as natural selection, when its
main advantage was that it was under rational control.
But where is the dynamic for articial selection? Virilio has an answer:
science will exert its own ‘will to power’ to attack ‘certain peculiarities of the
species’, and scientists will decide, on some criteria or other, the future shape
of the posthuman.128 From the post/human choice of selection of types, Virilio
shifts to ‘the will to power of science’ for determining survival of types. Virilio
reies science and awards it strange (and ominous) power over human
survival. We have a scientistic determinism here: science free from social
123
124
125
126
127
128
In Ochert 2000, p. 23.
Arney 1998.
Arney 1998.
Kurzweil 1999, p. 59.
Virilio 1995.
Virilio 1995, p. 20.
142 Glenn Rikowski
relations and social forms. Yet, if Virilio ‘personies’ the force of science, then
scientists call the shots; we arrive back at post/human selection by post/
humans.
(iv) Social limits to trans/posthumanism
Those trans/posthumanists that call for the body to break through social
barriers need to address the problem of capital, of capitalism. FM-2030’s
assumption that the end of the industrial age signies the end of capital/ism
leads her/him to fail to take capitalism seriously.129 Stelarc screams at us that:
‘THE BODY MUST BURST FROM ITS BIOLOGICAL, CULTURAL, AND
PLANETARY CONTAINMENT’, without enquiring how we are being contained
by capital as social relation and social force.130 In effect, the social relations of the
movement towards trans/posthumanism are untheorised. This stunts
posthuman politics, for there is no realisation that technology cannot ‘burst
from its cultural integument’ without a critique of the form of that containment,
and a political programme for smashing through it. Without this critique, the
spectre of capital haunts the posthuman condition.
(v) Motivation of cybernation
This point is connected to the previous one. Why should posthumans want
to smash the social domination of capital when they can adjust to it? Using
mood-altering drugs and other technologies, posthumans could simply redesign
themselves to cope with its demands. However, the social drive to produce
(surplus-) value is innite in volume, speed and intensity.131 Against an innite
social drive, humans, posthumans or superhumans necessarily fall short.
‘Humans drop like ies’ in relation to the innitude of capital’s social drives,
and posthumans would too; their performance in labour (however good)
always susceptible to improvement. But, as the question of motivation to
terminate capital could be suppressed by technological means, then the tensions
involved in producing against an innite social drive for posthumans may
also be subsumed.
This subsection has provided criticisms of trans/posthuman theory/
prophecies that collectively pose problems for the contemporary transhumanist
129
130
131
FM-2030 undated.
Stelarc 1998, p. 116 – original capitalisation.
See Rikowski 2000c.
Marx and the Future of the Human 143
movement. The rest of the paper argues that the whole basis of transhuman
theory and prophecy is founded on a serious misreading of history. We are
already transhuman in a very specic sense: we are capital, human capital,
humanity capitalised.
IV. Karl Marx’s social universe
And even if we scatter to the stars, isn’t it likely that we may take our
problems with us or nd, later, that they have followed us?132
Today, we exist within the capital’s social universe. This is Karl Marx’s social
universe, as analysed in Capital. The substance of this social universe is value.133
Capital is value in motion.134 Value is not a ‘thing’. In its rst incarnation in
the capitalist labour process, it inheres within some material ‘things’, in
commodities; though it can also be created within immaterial commodities
too.135 Thus, value, as the substance of the social universe of capital should
not be thought of as some kind of ‘stuff’, some material substratum. It is,
after all, a social substance. Value can be viewed as being social energy that
undergoes transformations: its rst metamorphosis being its constitution as
capital in the form of surplus-value. It is the matter and anti-matter of Marx’s
social universe. 136
Social phenomena within capital’s social universe are neither self-maintaining
nor constitute stable entities. These phenomena, indeed the whole social
universe is constantly at risk of implosion. Through labour, we ensure its
maintenance. Value is not self-generating, it cannot create itself, nor can it
morph into capital on its own accord. It is labour that creates value and
mediates its various transformations and forms of movement, rstly into capital
on the basis of surplus-value, and then the myriad forms of capital springing
from surplus-value.137 As Karl Marx indicated in the Grundrisse:
Labour is the living, form-giving re; it is the transitoriness of things, their
temporality, as their formation by living time. 138
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
Joy 2000, p. 254.
As argued in Neary 2002, Neary and Rikowski 2000, 2002, and in Rikowski 2002.
See Kay and Mott 1982, and Neary 2002.
See Lazzarato 1996.
See Neary and Rikowski 2000.
See Marx 1977b, and Postone 1996.
Marx 1973a, p. 361.
144 Glenn Rikowski
Thus: the existence of the substance (value as social energy) that constitutes
the social universe depends upon our labour. Labour, in turn, is dependent
upon our capacity to labour, our labour-power: the energy, skills, knowledge,
physical and personal qualities that we, as labourers, posses. Marx dened
labour-power in the following way, as
the aggregate of those mental and physical capabilities existing in a
human being, which he exercises whenever he produces a use-value of any
description. 139
Labour-power here has real existence: it exists as it is transformed into labour.
Within the labour market, it has virtual existence within the body of the
potential labourer. Labour-power is fuel for the living re (labour). In the
labour process, labour-power (potential, capacity to labour) is transformed
into labour (activity, actuality). The personal and physical qualities, powers,
skills and so on of labourers are activated by the will of the labourer for the
performance of labour.
On the basis of Marx’s denition of labour-power, we can dene labourpower as including not just ‘skills’ and knowledge, the foundation of much
mainstream education research.140 It also incorporates the attitudes and
personality traits essential for effective performance within the labour process.
It depends, therefore, on what is included within ‘mental capabilities’. Empirical
research on the recruitment process, where employers assess labour-powers,141
suggests ‘mental capabilities’ must include work attitudes, social attitudes
and personality traits – aspects of our ‘personalities’. These, too, are incorporated
within labour-power as it transforms itself into labour.
In contemporary capitalist society, education and training are elements
within denite forms of labour-power’s social production. Empirically, these
forms show wide variation. The signicant point is that the substance of the
social universe of capital (value) rests upon our labour, which in turn hinges
on labour-power being transformed into labour in the labour process for the
production of (im/material) commodities which incorporate value in its ‘cell
form’.142 Labour-power (its formation and quality), rests (though not exclusively)
upon education and training in contemporary capitalism. This is the real
139
140
141
142
Marx 1977b, p. 164.
See Rikowski 1990.
For example, in studies cited in Rikowski 1990.
Marx 1977c.
Marx and the Future of the Human 145
signicance of education and training in capitalism today. What constitutes
‘capitalist’ schooling and training as precisely capitalist is that it is implicated
in generating the substance of the social universe of capital: value. We have
come full circle. It appears that we are trapped within a labyrinth bounded
by the margins of capital’s universe. Thus, it seems that, to destroy this social
universe for human liberation, it must be imploded. The best place to begin
this project is with a critique of the strange, living commodity, labour-power.143
Labour-power (that other great class of commodities)144
It is well known that Karl Marx opened his rst volume of Capital with the
commodity, and not with capital. Marx rst of all draws our attention to the
fact that
the wealth of those societies in which the capitalist mode of production
prevails, presents itself as ‘an immense accumulation of commodities,’ its
unit being a single commodity. Our investigation must therefore begin with
the analysis of a commodity.145
For Marx, analysis of capitalist society begins with the commodity, as it is
the ‘economic cell-form’ of that society.146 It is the most basic element that
can inform us about the more complex phenomena springing from it. The
commodity was the perfect starting point for Marx as it incorporates the
fundamental structuring elements of capitalist society: value, use-value and
exchange-value posited on the basis of abstract labour as measured by labourtime.147 It is the condensed ‘general form of the product’ in capitalist society,148
the ‘most elementary form of bourgeois wealth’,149 and hence the ‘formation
and premise of capitalist production’.150 Commodities are also ‘the rst result
of the immediate process of capitalist production, its product’.151
Less well known is that, in Theories of Surplus-Value – Part I, Marx makes
it clear that there are two classes or categories of commodities within capital’s
social universe. For
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
As argued in Rikowski 1999a and 2000b.
This sub section draws from Rikowski 2000a.
Marx 1977b, p. 43. Marx had made this point previously in Marx 1973a, p. 881.
Marx 1977c, p. 19.
Postone 1996, pp. 127–8.
Postone 1996, p. 148.
Marx 1969, p. 173.
Marx 1979, p. 1004.
Marx 1979, p. 974.
146 Glenn Rikowski
the whole world of ‘commodities’ can be divided into two great parts. First,
labour-power; second, commodities as distinct from labour-power itself. 152
These commodities are distinguished essentially on the following consideration:
A commodity – as distinguished from labour-power itself – is a material thing
confronting man, a thing of a certain utility for him, in which a denite
quantity of labour is xed or materialised. 153
Later, in Theories of Surplus-Value – Part I, Marx criticises Adam Smith for
holding that the commodity, in order to incorporate value, has to be a physical,
material thing. Value is a social substance; it has, therefore, a social mode of
existence.154 However, the examples Marx uses in Capital to illustrate his
arguments related mainly to material commodities: coats, iron, paper and so
on. In the rst volume of Capital, Marx states that: ‘A commodity is, in the
rst place, an object outside us, a thing that by its properties satises human
wants of some sort or another’.155 Here, he appears to be ruling out immaterial
products such as health and education. Yet a radical interpretation of Marx
would start out from the commodity as inclusive of material and immaterial
forms. Indeed, the distinction between material and immaterial commodities
is practically dissolving on a daily basis.156 The commodity-form is taking
hold of all spheres of social existence.
Marx’s original distinction between labour-power and the ‘general class’
of commodities was that the latter were external to the person of the labourer,
whereas labour-power was incorporated within personhood itself. However,
with people buying cosmetic surgery, the market in spare body parts and the
future beckoning big business in human re/design, the physical externality
of the ‘general class’ of commodities to human beings is no longer what it
was in Marx’s day. These developments herald the breakdown of this aspect
of Marx’s original distinction between the two great classes of commodities.
What, then, is the distinction between the two categories of commodities if
the externality criterion is no longer what it was?
A distinction may still exist on the following considerations. First, labourpower is an aspect of the person; it is internal to personhood, in a special
152
153
154
155
156
Marx 1969, p. 167.
Marx 1969, p. 164 – original emphasis.
Marx 1969, p. 171.
Marx 1977b, p. 43 – emphasis added.
Hardt and Negri, 2000.
Marx and the Future of the Human 147
sense. It is a unied force owing throughout the person. The installation of
a new heart – an object originally external to the person in question – does
not alter this. Labour-power has no specic location within personhood; it
is a force owing throughout the totality of the person. Labour-power has
reality only within the person, whereas general commodities have existence
external to the person and can also become elements of persons, as increasing
numbers of medical products become incorporated within the human. Labourpower, as a human force, cannot leave humans and act as the same force
within bricks. As Marx noted, labour-power does ‘not exist apart from him
[the labourer] at all’.157 It cannot be external to the person. Marx notes the
‘uniqueness’ of labour-power in this respect.158 Secondly, labour-power (unlike
a brick) is under the sway of a potentially hostile will. Internality and
consciousness distinguish labour-power from the general class of commodities.
Labour-power on this account is the special commodity that generates
value and surplus-value (the substance of capital) through its transformation
into labour. Without human labour-power, there is no capital – no matter
what the level of technological development.159 In contemporary capitalist
society, labour-power takes on added signicance. Its quality enhancement
is increasingly being viewed by representatives of capital as a new strategy
for increasing relative surplus-value.
Relative surplus-value: on the basis of labour-power enhancement
There are two main ways of producing surplus-value. The rst is to extend
the length of the working day. This effectively extends the labour-time that
labourers are engaged in producing surplus-value. Marx called this absolute
surplus-value production. This form of surplus-value production has absolute
limits: there are only twenty-four hours in a day and workers have to sleep,
eat and reproduce. Attempts to break through the latter limits (as in the
Industrial Revolution) result in the physical and mental deterioration of
workers – thus ultimately affecting the quality of their labour-powers.
The second method of surplus-value creation Marx called relative surplusvalue production. Here, the labour-time it takes to produce value equal to
the value of labour-power (necessary labour) is reduced. The main way that
157
158
159
Marx 1973a, p. 267.
Marx 1969, p. 45.
Rikowski 2001a.
148 Glenn Rikowski
this has occurred historically is through the application of machinery and
automation to production. Application of new technology has the effect of
reducing the labour-time necessary for generating value equivalent to the
value of labour-power. It increases labour productivity, and also de-values
the goods labourers need to maintain their labour-powers. On a global scale,
this effectively reduces the value of labour-power across the board, as the
value of each of the ‘necessities’ constituting the value of labour-power, falls.
This process increases the labour-time devoted to surplus-value production,
as a proportion of total labour-time (whilst this remains constant). The point
at which surplus-value arises from labouring in the labour process is reached
earlier as compared with before the new technology was introduced. The
working day is re-divided on the basis of necessary labour-time, yielding more
surplus-value in the process. But this is only one way of producing relative
surplus-value.
In an era of the intensication of capitalist globalisation, where technological
innovation spreads more quickly than ever before, capitals have been seeking
new ways of generating relative surplus-value. One of these has gained
increasing sponsorship in recent years: the strategy of enhancing the quality of
labour-power itself. It has the effect of reducing necessary labour. The technicist
point regarding whether ‘really existing’ education and training policies
actually have this effect is not the issue – though it is a key concern for mainstream education and training researchers. The essential point to grasp is that
in contemporary capitalism there is a social drive to enhance the quality of human
labour-power. This social drive, like all of capital’s social drives is innite. It
would not make logical sense within the perverted social universe of capital
to suggest any absolute limit on the basis of the functioning of the system.160
However, in similar fashion to absolute surplus-value production, the innite
social drive to enhance the quality of human labour-power clashes with a
number of practical considerations. First, labour-power development depends
on co-operation – which expresses itself in the ‘problem of motivation’, an
individual willingness to aid development of one’s own labour-power. Secondly,
when pushed too far, we witness the phenomenon of ‘humans dropping like
ies’: humans buckling under as they are subjected to concrete (and hence
160
Just as there are no logical limits to value production, a moral limit on what
constitutes a ‘fair wage’ or ‘a good day’s work’ has no social validity within capital’s
social universe.
Marx and the Future of the Human 149
necessarily limited) manifestations of an innite social drive. Thus: depression
(with no terminal point to ‘improvement’); various forms of stress and ill
health; and so on. Thirdly, people may protest and effectively revolt against
an impersonal social drive ‘manifesting’ itself as concrete social practice.
Fourthly, those generating these social practices are themselves all too human,
and hence also ‘capitalised’.161 As capitalised life-forms, the designers of
concrete schemes that seek to nurture a social drive that is innite can do
this precisely because they have some afnity with these social practices that
express capital’s social drives. Fifthly, as ‘we’ are capital too, it is possible for
us to aesthetically and logically appreciate attempted concrete expressions of
innite social drives, whilst also being able to see the contradiction involved.162
This contradiction is the notion that an innite social drive can be concretely
expressed. The prospect is absurd, as it assumes innite resources, time, labour
(of a quality that is ‘innitely good’) and effort to activate and effect the innite
social drive.
The analysis of labour-power is a necessary step for viewing our
development: the human as capital. By this token, this section is also a resource
for the alien theses on the future of the human outlined in the next section.
V. Alien theses
There is . . . no need to search for alien intelligent life since it is already deep
within us.163
This section outlines some theses that generate our future as human capital,
which is an unstable future masquerading as never-ending story. This instability
at the heart of capital’s social universe – the human as capital – is an optimistic
outcome. Because we are forms of capital, we also incorporate its contradictions.
It is our attempts to solve these contradictions – as they ow through our
everyday lives – that provides the dynamic for leading us to conclude that
the only real solution to these problems is to implode the social universe of
capital through collective social force.164 On this basis, capital’s social universe
can never be in ‘steady-state’ mode. As Harry Cleaver notes:
161
162
163
164
See Rikowski 1999a.
See Rikowski 1999b.
Ansell-Pearson 1997b, p. 182.
See Rikowski 1999b.
150 Glenn Rikowski
Capital can never win, totally once and for all. It must tolerate the continued
existence of an alien subjectivity which constantly threatens to destroy it.165
Thus, human liberation from capital does not depend on an ethic that rests
on arguing things could be otherwise (and better),166 and that people ought
to want the alternative – though this helps. Rather, we are driven (individually,
socially and collectively), as capitalised life-forms, to seek solutions to our
predicament. This is the social form of ‘agency’ in capitalist society – the attempt
to break free of the social force that deeply possesses us: capital.
The irony is that, as we are capital, then this enables us to think as and
through capital – all the better to grasp its workings and its madness, and all
the better to locate the weaknesses in its social domination. We use capital’s
existence within us as a basis for its critique and dissolution. We turn ourselves
against our selves.
This way of envisioning capital’s social universe has important consequences
for Marxist humanism. First, the struggle to be ‘human’ has been lost within
capitalist society; we are becoming capital on an incremental (generation-bygeneration) scale. Secondly, Marxist humanism is a struggle against what we
have become, and also against where we are headed: the posthuman as capitalised
life-form. On the above account, we are driven into this struggle. Thus: Marxist
humanism has real social existence as this struggle. It is not primarily a
philosophy or ethic of the liberation of mankind (though it is also this); it is
much more important. It expresses a necessary struggle. Thirdly, Marxist
humanism holds out a promise: our collective and individual capacity (if not
right) to dene the ‘human’, and also posthuman futures.
What is the social form of the human? The following alien theses have been
developed with this question in view.
(i)
If social energy (or force) constitutes the social universe of capital and value
is its substance, then there is no externality. There is no ‘outside’ of this social
universe. Our creation constitutes itself by its extension through our labour.
Neither does an ‘inside’ pertain; the social universe of capital is all that there
165
166
Cleaver in Neary 1997, p. 25.
As in Postone 1996.
Marx and the Future of the Human 151
is, as the sum of ‘the social’. Hence, every social phenomenon is already
situated as an element within this social universe and assumes a particular
social form on this basis. This applies to the ‘human’ too. There can be no exceptions,
as this implies either externality beyond the social eld of force (i.e. existence
within another social universe), or a vacuum within the eld (the mythical
‘spaces between the margins’ of postmodern folk law). The ‘human’ as a form
of capital can be conveniently called human capital; the critique of human
capital, therefore, becomes a critique of the form of the ‘human’ as given by
capitalist society.
(ii)
The development of capitalism coincides with the capitalisation of humanity.167
Humans increasingly become something Other than human: a new life-form,
a ‘new species’.168 This is because capital is a progressive movement towards
totality. Its development on this basis ‘consists precisely in subordinating all
elements of society to itself’ for ‘this is historically how it becomes a totality’.169
This includes the ‘human’ – there are no exceptions. With the deepening and
strengthening of capital as social force within its own social energy domain,
we evolve as capitalist life-form: human capital.
(iii)
Labour-power’s transformation into labour within the labour process generates
(surplus-)value. Labour-power ows throughout personhood; it is a unitary
force. Labour-power’s social form in capitalist society is as human capital.
Labour-power is the ip-side of human capital. Human capital has a double
form: as the social form that labour-power assumes in capitalist society, and
as the form of the ‘human’. The reduction of humanity to labour-power
simultaneously expresses the practical reduction of the ‘human’ to capital.
Labour-power ows throughout personhood, hence the person is capital.170
I am capital.
167
168
169
170
Rikowski 1999b, p. 50.
Marx 1977a.
Marx 1973a.
See Rikowski 1999b.
152 Glenn Rikowski
(iv)
Marx provides a further thesis for the capitalisation of the ‘human’. In the
capitalist labour process, labour-power becomes part of capital: it is capitalised.
As Marx notes, in the labour process
the worker functions here as a special natural form of this capital, as distinct
from the elements of capital that exist in the natural form of means of
production.171
Furthermore, labourers develop themselves as labour-power within the labour
process, but as labour-power of a specic kind: human capital. There is a
two-fold process going on when labourers labour within the capitalist labour
process:
the individu al not only develops his abilities in production but also
expends them, uses them up in the act of production.172 . . . [And hence] . . .
Universal prostitution appears as a necessary phase in the development of
the social character of personal talents, capacities, abilities, activities . . .173
As labour-power is inseparable from the person (and ows throughout
personhood), then we have personhood capitalised, humans capitalised, human
capital.174
Taking these theses together, then:
Capital becomes a living social force within the human . . . and this is the
basis of the transhuman; it is this that makes us ‘extra-human’. Capital is not
just ‘out there’; we are it, it is us.175
We are already transhuman as a life-form within the social universe of capital.
Human capital, then, can be viewed as the social form that labour-power
assumes in capitalist society. Human capital acts as a virus on labour-power
in contemporary society. On the analysis owing from the above theses,
contradictions of capital course through our personhoods. The contradictions
between value, use-value and exchange-value, are aspects of our personhoods
as they are aspects of labour-power that are expressed through corresponding
171
172
173
174
175
Marx 1973b, pp. 455–6.
Marx 1973b, p. 90.
Marx 1973a, p. 163.
Rikowski 1999b, pp. 70–1.
Rikowski 1999b, p. 71.
Marx and the Future of the Human 153
aspects of labour.176 Hence, we are ‘screwed up’ by capital as we organise
our skills, capacities, abilities and personal characteristics and attitudes and
other labour-power attributes to meet the contradictory demands (such as
quantitative/speed imperatives clashing against qualitative drives) inherent
in value creation. To the extent that we think through these categories, we
are doubly confused: for example, as in attempts to frame education and
training policies that are ‘coherent’ – when no such coherence is possible.177
Our social constitution (or social being) is founded on a contradiction that
plays even more havoc within our individual and collective existences than
those founded on the basis of labour-power as human capital. This is the
contradiction between our selves as labour and as capital. The ‘class relation’
is internal to personhood, as well as external to it. Our social existence as
labour clashes daily with our social existence (our constitution) as capital. We
have a double life, two ways of existing (with their related and antagonistic
emotions, drives, desires etc.) that clash within our personhoods. This practical
dialectic blights our lives, whilst simultaneously driving us on individually
and collectively to deal with the everyday problems generated by it. The only
solution is to dissolve the relation, but the forces that it conjures up within
our personhoods provides a dynamic, exceeding any ‘moral’ arguments for
socialism, that indicates why such a dramatic dissolution through collective
action is urgent for us.
Class, on the analysis advanced here is:
the capital relation: the dynamic, contradictory, antagonistic relation that
generates and maintains the social universe of capital.178
Social class is the capital-labour relation that is internal to personhood, as
well as structuring relations between people. We are divided against ourselves,
and within our selves. What is required to articulate all this is a psychology
of capital, a psychology of the human condition in a society dominated by
capital.
176
Rikowski 2002, pp. 187–93. Basically, the value aspect of labour-power refers to
the capacity to labour in relation to its quantitative element (i.e. speed and intensity).
The use value aspect of labour-power pinpoints the qualitative element (consideration
to the quality of labour and product). The exchange aspect of labour-power rests on
the formal equality of labour, and this is established on the basis of abstract labour that
is the substance of value.
177
See Rikowski 2001b.
178
Rikowski 2001c, p. 14.
154 Glenn Rikowski
Finally, as labour in capital, we incorporate two further labour-power aspects
within our selves: the subjective and the collective.179 The former is labourpower in its will-determined moment, the labourer’s relative willingness to
transform her labour-power into actual labour in the labour process. To the
extent that this subordination occurs, the labourer becomes capital and the other
labour-power aspects and attributes are developed as capital in their rst
moments of social existence within the person.180 Yet our social constitution
as labour against capital forms a social limit to our becoming capital, as we
strive to better our lives (individually and collectively) on the basis of antithetical
drives whose realisation implies practical challenges to capital (for example,
higher wages, better working conditions etc.). It also forms a limit to the
subordination of our wills under capital.
The collective aspect of labour-power can be viewed as an ‘agglomeration
and amalgamation of the individual labour-powers of workers set in motion
for capital’.181 As Marx indicated, this:
collective power of labour, its characteristic as a social force, is therefore the
collective power of capital.182
As labour can be viewed as a collective force, so can labour-power, notes
Marx. It can be viewed as an ‘accumulation of labour-powers’.183 This is where
the quality of co-operation between labourers and their labour-powers is to
the fore. Empirically, this is reected in recruitment studies that point towards
worker co-operation, people ‘tting-in’ with other workers – which are held
to impact positively on productivity.
The focus on the capital relation, labour-power and labour-power aspects
through the work of Marx has the potential to tell us more about the ‘future
of the human’ than any whiz-bang transhumanist theses based on scientic
and technological developments. Consideration of the former group of
phenomena opens up the possibilities for a ‘real psychology’ of the ‘human’,
which is also a psychology of capital. Such a psychology has yet to be written.
Exclusive focus on the technologies and science that seemingly generate the
‘transhuman condition’ avoids the social forces that set limits to what ‘the
179
180
181
182
183
Rikowski 1996, and 2002.
Rikowski 1996, p. 8.
Ibid.
Marx 1973a, p. 585.
Ibid.
Marx and the Future of the Human 155
human’ can become. Thus, the fantasies of those such a Natasha Vita-More
(multiple sex organs, leopard fur on our arms etc.) are abstracted from the
social universe in which we nd ourselves: the social universe of capital. Whilst
choice, self-expression and fun are emphasised by some transhumanists, they
hide their heads in sand when it comes to the social form of the human in
capitalist society, and what implications such a society and such a human
form might hold for the ‘future of the human’.
Some critics of transhumanism such as Bill Joy point to certain dangers
of realising the mainstream transhuman future.184 There is the likely high
percentage of cloned humans that would die early or have defects, the
possibilities that nanobots might run amok and turn everything into ‘grey
goo’, or the introduction of new mental illnesses through inserting computer
chips in our brains, and many more frightening possibilities. Francis Fukuyama,
meanwhile, worries about the ethical status of the ‘posthuman’, our claims
to rights and dignity when we attain such a state and the possibilities for
authoritarian politics that the new technologies open up (such as selective
breeding, life prolongation and so on).185 Of course, there may be other sorts
of limits to the realisation of the posthuman – scientic, technical, and economic
(some human ‘improvements’ might just cost too much) – as well as those
grounded in the nature of capital’s social universe. However, an exclusive
focus on the feasibility of the relevant scientic and technological generators
of the posthuman would severely limit the critique of transhumanism. Such
an analysis, by itself, would mirror the technological determinism that is one
of the weaknesses of transhumanist theory. In avoiding a social analysis of
the form of the ‘human’ in contemporary society, such an analysis would
give succour to the closure of the ‘future of the human’. It would forestall and
cloud the uncovering of the dynamic that can offer us possibilities for a way
out of capital’s universe and hence possibilities for a form of the human that
is not-capitalised. This dynamic is the interplay of social forces, drives and
contradictions that constitute the human in contemporary society, a dynamic
that can at least point towards a ‘human’ condition beyond capital, as well as
indicating how we labour in and against capital. This dynamic, or dialectic,
that is internal to personhood, does not just imply that resistance to capital
is dened into social being. It implies that conformity to capital’s imperatives
184
185
See Joy 2000.
Fukuyama 2002.
156 Glenn Rikowski
(through the value, use-value and exchange-value aspects of labour-power)
is also incorporated within personhood. The class struggle is within us, as
well as everywhere else where our labour has any effectivity – that is, everywhere we know. This is the openness at the heart of the perspective on the
‘human’ outlined in this article: resistance or conformity to capital’s imperatives?
The choice is there every microsecond.
On the other hand, it might appear that my rendering of the ‘human’ (or
transhuman) condition is more horric, more gloomy and doom-ridden than
anything the transhumanists throw up. Some readers may nd the suggestion
‘we are capital’ offensive and repugnant, and retreat into notions of dignity,
autonomy or some ‘rock-solid’ values, or into beliefs in the sanctity of Humanity.
Others might think the suggestion simply in bad taste. But one of the strengths
of transhumanist writings is that they pinpoint many of the weaknesses of
our current situation as humans: death, disease, and gender and race inequality
(these are redundant if we choose sexes, skin colours and other physical
features) are key examples. It is also possible to develop transhuman principles,
as Max More has done.186 However, within the social universe of capital,
all moral principles – including More’s – have no social validity.187 Values
have virtual existence, as ‘justice’, ‘dignity’ and other values cannot have any
substance in capital’s realm, and so they exist only as the struggles to establish
their possibility. It is value that determines our ‘social worth’ in capital’s
universe; the value of the labour-time that goes into the social production of
our labour-powers xes our real ‘worth’ as individuals. This point indicates
the signicance of education and training in contemporary capitalism, and
other institutions involved in the social production of labour-power. The
labour of teachers, trainers and developers of labour-power determines our
individual worth qua individuals. So, people do not have equal social worth
in capitalist society, though in theory it is possible.188 But this point may
horrify some even more than the notion that ‘we are capital’!
The horror works both ways, fortunately. The horror that is our social
existence nurtures sickening dreams for ourselves as capital, especially those
of us that push the ‘capital’ aspect of ourselves to the forefront of our lives.
That is, for those that can be readily recognised as ‘representatives’ of capital
in their everyday identications. For:
186
187
188
As in More 1999.
See Rikowski 2000a; and Rikowski in McLaren and Rikowski 2001.
This theoretical possibility is discussed in Rikowski 2000a.
Marx and the Future of the Human 157
[The] oppositional forces within personhood ensure openness within the
social universe of capital; a universe that moves and expands on the
foundation of the clashing of drives and forces within its totality. This
openness does not exist within postmodernist aporias, or in some social
spaces ‘in the margins’, or in the borders of this social universe. There are
no such spaces, in my view. There is nowhere to hide. The social universe
of capital is all that there is. Rather, the openness results from the clash of
social forces and drives. . . . [And] there is one [social force] that has the
capacity to destroy the whole basis of the social universe of capital. This is
the collective social force of the working class acting on a global scale to
destroy capitalist social relations, to annihilate capital itself, and this is the
communist impulse at its most vital, when there is a massive movement of
social force and energy. The capitalist social universe, whose substance is
value, implodes when this social force to move human history on from prehistory generates sufcient pressure. In the routine running and expansion
of the social universe of capital, this force is suppressed – it only has virtual
existence. But it is our hope for the future.189
Conclusion: the future of the human
Marx’s writings open up the future of the human. Within the closed (but
ever-expanding) social universe of capital, the future of the human is already
cast – pregured on the basis of existing social relations. This future (and this
present) rst appears as horror; the ‘human’ possessed by capital – with no
escape possible, as capital is everywhere. However, the horror works both ways;
the potential for awareness of our predicament as capital also increases
historically. In this awareness, hope resides, for the potentiality to loathe what
we are becoming increases the more we become un-human.
But hope is not enough. We may hope that critical analyses of society can
expose the gap between what is and what might be. 190 We can hope that the
obvious social inequalities and poverty throughout global capital re enough
anger to burn up the source of those inequalities and impoverishment. We
may hope that some emerging cyborg entity pregures the socialist being of
the future. However, unless there are possibilities for pinpointing a dynamic
189
190
Rikowski, in McLaren and Rikowski 2001, p. 14.
As in Postone 1996.
158 Glenn Rikowski
incorporated within our own personhoods that drives us towards breaking
out of the labyrinth of capital towards socialism, then these hopes may be
all that we are left with. This article makes inroads into uncovering such a
dynamic through and exploration of the ‘human’ and the transhuman in the
context of the writings of Marx. Our social constitution as both capital and
labour (which also incorporates the contradictions within and between these)
drives us on to seek solutions to our own condition – but with no guarantee
of success. The invasive social force within us – capital – could win out.
This article has explored the social form of the ‘human’ in capitalist society.
Capital is an invasive social force that ‘possesses’ the human, and the intensity
of this non-human force to permeate our lives, our souls, increases historically.
We are becoming capitalised, which is the becoming of capital within us.
Secondly, the argument shows that labour-power – that unique, living, yet
most abominable of commodities – is the primary conduit through which
capital ows into our personhoods. The form that labour-power takes in
capitalist society is human capital, and as labour-power ows throughout
our personhoods, so too does capital in its ‘human’ form. Thirdly, in this
sense, the ‘transhuman’ already exists; we are already transhuman as human
capital. Fourthly, as social entities, we are therefore constituted in such a way
that we incorporate the contradictions internal to capital and the violent
dialectic between capital and labour within our being. We are inherently
unstable, messed-up social beings. The only real solution to our condition
is the collective dissolution of that social force which powers our sickness:
capital and its social universe based on value. Fifthly, our instability and our
experiences as living contradiction-ridden lives in a world where only value,
rather than values, has social validity, means that we are driven to constantly
seek all kinds of ‘solutions’ to our condition and the problems of everyday
life. We may also nurture hopes and fantasies that fall well short of what is
required to truly make us the ‘new species’, a form of human life where selfcreation is unfettered by the iron cage of capital. For humans, notes Cyril
Smith:
create themselves by simultaneously creating not only the physical conditions
of their own life, but also the social forms within which this creation occurs.191
191
Smith 2002, p. 14 – emphasis added.
Marx and the Future of the Human 159
In capitalist society, the social form of the human erects barriers to human
self-creation and development. The development of the ‘human’ as capital
intensies with capitalist social development, and this process becomes
increasingly obvious, if we have the courage to see and act on it. Finally, in
acting on this realisation and effectively setting about changing both society
and ourselves as currently constituted we open up ‘the future of the human’.
We open up what we can become, and possibilities for what Cyril Smith calls
‘living humanly’ with each other.192
Transhumanists might hold this article has treated them very badly.
Transhumanism and posthuman thought has been a vehicle for thinking
through problems of the ‘human’. Furthermore, it has been argued that
transhumanism avoids analysis of the social force that invades the human
whilst also setting limits to what the trans/human is and can become; it
avoids capital and the constitution of the ‘human’ in capitalist society. Thus,
as a result, transhumanism engenders dreams and fantasies. Posthuman
politics remains abstract. These apparently bold thinkers shy away from the
impossibility of many of the futures they envisage, whilst under-analysing
a transhuman future dominated by capital. In the event, they misread
history and fail to adequately ground their own project. Perhaps what the
transhumanist movement really needs, therefore, is a project based on Marxist
theory that can open up the future in ways that excite transhumanists. A
Marxist transhumanism suggests itself here, together with a posthuman politics
based on destroying the social force that blocks the emergence of cuddly
forms of the posthuman: capital. Perhaps this article, therefore, has done some
service to the transhumanist movement, but the ball is now in the transhumanist
court.
The style and forms of argumentation of this article have not conformed
to standard Marxist exposition and writing. But I would argue that the messy
twists and turns of the text were necessary to unfold the ‘horror within’. For
me, taking such risks is part of what research in critical Marxist theory is all
about.
Meanwhile, the potential horrors presented by the trans/posthumanists as
compared with us as capital seem like Dr. Who as compared with The Exorcist.
Gnat-sized robots, microscopic gyroscopes, television beamed directly onto
your retina. This may sound like a grocery list for a crazed sci- visionary.
192
Smith 1996, p. 100.
160 Glenn Rikowski
But all these projects are in the works today, thanks to an emerging chip
technology known as microelectromechanical systems (MEMS).193
Be afraid, be very afraid – but not of this!
References
Alesky, Mark 2000, ‘Cyborg 1.0: Kevin Warwick Outlines His Plan to Become One
with His Computer’, Wired, February: 145–8.
Alexander, Brian 2000, ‘Don’t Die, Stay Pretty: Introducing the Ultrahuman Makeover’,
Wired, January: 178–88.
Ansell-Pearson, Keith 1997a, Viroid Life: Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Transhuman
Condition, London: Routledge.
Ansell-Pearson, Keith 1997b, ‘Viroid Life: On Machines, Technics and Evolution’, in
Deleuze and Philosophy: The Difference Engineer, edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson,
London: Routledge.
Ansell-Pearson, Keith 1999, Germinal Life: The Difference and Repetition of Deleuze,
London: Routledge.
Arney, Kat 1998, ‘Feeling Chipper?’ The Guardian (Higher Education), 22 September.
Barbrook, Richard 2002, ‘The Regulation of Liberty: Free Speech, Free Trade and
Free Gifts on the Net’, The Commoner, May, no. 4, at: www.commoner.org.uk/
04barbrook.pdf
Barbrook, Richard and Andy Cameron 1996, ‘The Californian Ideology’, Science As
Culture, 26, 6 (Part 1): 44–72.
Bostrom, Nick 1998, Predictions from Philosophy? How Philosophers Could Make Themselves
Useful. Last updated 19th September at: www.hedweb.com/nickb/predict.htm
Bruno, Lee 2000, ‘Biotech Redux’, Red Herring (Biotech Brieng), April, 77: 262–4.
Bukatman, Scott 1993, Terminal Identity: The Virtual Subject in Postmodern Science Fiction,
Durham, NC.: Duke University Press.
Burch, Greg 1998, ‘Transhumanism’, June (506 E.E.), at: http://users.aol.com/
gburch3/thext.html
Burch, Greg and Tihamer Toth-Fejel 1999, ‘A Dialogue Concerning Transhumanist and
Extroprian Ethics (Dialogue 1)’ at: www.extropy.org/eo/articles/dialog1.jsp
Callard, Felicity 1998, ‘The Body in Theory’, Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space, 16: 387–400.
Campbell, Jeremy 1999 ‘Computer Chips in the Brain Will Make You Smarter’, London
Evening Standard, 7 December: 17.
Cartwright, Nancy and Peter Goodfellow, Steve Jones, Geoff Mulgan, Robert Plomin,
Steven Rose, and James D. Watson 2000, ‘Round Table: The Meaning of the Genome’,
Prospect, October: 24–30.
193
Leonard 2000, p. 162.
Marx and the Future of the Human 161
Davis, Erik 1998, Techgnosis: Myth, Magic and Mysticism in the Age of Information, London:
Serpent’s Tail.
FM-2030 undated, ‘What Are Some Highlights of New Ideological Directions in the
Coming Years?’ (6 pages), at: www.aleph.se/Trans/Intro/transhuman.txt
Fukuyama, Francis 2002, Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology
Revolution, London: Prole Books.
Gibson, Beatrice 2000, ‘Download Your Brain’, limb by limb, March/April, Issue 3:
26–30.
Guerrera, Francesco and David Firn 2000, ‘European Biotechnology Caught in a Trap’,
Financial Times, 27 September: 29.
Halberstam, Judith and Ira Livingstone 1995, ‘Introduction: Posthuman Bodies’, in
Posthuman Bodies, edited by Judith Halberstam and Ira Livingstone, Bloomington:
University of Indianapolis Press.
Haraway, Donna 1991, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, New
York: Routledge.
Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri 2000, Empire, Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University
Press.
Hayles, Katherine 1999, How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature
and Informatics, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Joy, Bill 2000, ‘Why the Future Doesn’t Need Us’, Wired, April: 238–62.
Kay, Geoff and James Mott 1982, Political Order and the Law of Labour, London: Macmillan.
Kurzweil, Ray 1999, The Age of the Spiritual Machines: How We Will Live, Work and Think
in the New Age of Intelligent Machines, London: Phoenix.
Land, Nick 1998, ‘Cybergothic’, in Virtual Futures: Cyberotics, Technology and Posthuman
Pragmatism, edited by Joan Broadhurst Dixon and Eric Cassidy, London: Routledge.
Lazzarato, Maurizio 1996, ‘Immaterial Labor’, in Radical Thought in Italy: A Potential
Politics, edited by Paolo Virno and Michael Hardt, Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Leonard, Andrew 2000, ‘As the MEMS Revolution Takes Off, Small Is Getting Bigger
Every Day’, Wired, January: 162–4.
Lewis, Jeff 1998, ‘Digitopians: Transculturalism, Computers and the Politics of Hope’,
International Journal of Cultural Studies, 1, 3: 373–89.
Lewontin, Richard 1995, ‘The Dream of the Human Genome’, in Politics and the Human
Body: Assault on Dignity, edited by Jean Elshtain and J. Timothy Cloyd, Nashville:
Vanderbilt University Press.
Lowe, Donald 1995, The Body in Late-Capitalist USA, Durham, NC.: Duke University
Press.
Marx, Karl 1969 [1863], Theories of Surplus-Value – Part I, London: Lawrence &
Wishart.
Marx, Karl 1973a [1858], Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy,
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1973b [1857], ‘General Introduction’ (to the Grundrisse). Translated by
Martin Nicolaus, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1977a [1844b], Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
162 Glenn Rikowski
Marx, Karl 1977b [1867a], Capital: A Critique of Political Economy – Volume I, London:
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, Karl 1977c [1867b], Preface to the First German Edition of Capital – Volume I,
London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, Karl 1978 [1878], Capital: A Critique of Political Economy – Volume II, Harmondsworth: Penguin & New Left Review.
Marx, Karl 1979 [1866], Results of the Immediate Process of Production, Addendum to
Capital, Vol. 1, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1992 [1844a], ‘Excerpts from James Mill’s Elements of Political Economy’, in
Karl Marx: Early Writings, translated by Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton,
London: Penguin Classics & New Left Review.
McLaren, Peter and Glenn Rikowski 2001, ‘Pedagogy for Revolution Against Education
for Capital: An E-Dialogue on Education in Capitalism Today’, Cultural Logic: An
Electronic Journal of Marxist Theory & Practice, 4, 1: http://eserver.org/clogic/4–1/
mclaren&rikowski.html
More, Max 1994, ‘On Becoming Posthuman’ at: www.maxmore.com/becoming.htm
More, Max 1999, ‘The Extropian Principles (Version 3.0): A Transhumanist Declaration’
at: www.extropy.org/extprn3.htm
More, Max undated, ‘What Do “Transhu man” and “Posthuman” Mean?’ at:
www.idom.com/~arkuat/exi/faq/transpost.html
Morris, Brian 1991, Western Conceptions of the Individual, Oxford: Berg.
Neary, Michael 1997, Youth, Training and the Training State: The Real History of Youth
Training in the Twentieth Century, London: Macmillan.
Neary, Michael 2002, ‘Labour Moves: A Critique of Social Movement Unionism’, in
The Labour Debate: An Investigation into the Theory and Reality of Capitalist Work, edited
by Ana Dinerstein and Michael Neary, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Neary, Michael and Glenn Rikowski 2000, ‘The Speed of Life: The Signicance of Karl
Marx’s Concept of Socially Necessary Labour-Time’, paper presented at the British
Sociological Association Annual Conference, University of York, 17–20 April.
Neary, Michael and Glenn Rikowski 2002, ‘Time and Speed in the Social Universe of
Capital’, in Social Constructions of Time: Structure and Process in Work and Everyday
Life, edited by Graham Crow and Sue Heath, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Ochert, Ayala 2000, ‘A Germ of an Idea Leads to GM People’, Times Higher Education
Supplement, 28 January: 22–3.
Olson, Sander 2002, ‘Interview with Max More’, Extropy: Journal of Transhumanist
Solutions, July, at: www.extropy.org/ideas/journal/current/2002–07–04.html
Ouroboros 1999, ‘The Transtopian Principles, Version 2.2’, 18 November at:
http://members.wbs.net/homepages/c/r/y/cryogenic4life/index2.html
Parker, Martin 1998, ‘Judgement Day: Cyborganization, Humanism and Postmodern
Ethics’, Organization, 5, 4: 503–18.
Platt, Charles 2000, ‘Clear the Line, I’m Sending Myself Right Now’, Wired, January:
205–10.
Postone, Moishe 1996, Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s
Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Regis, Ed 1990, Great Mambo Chicken and the Transhuman Condition: Science Slightly Over
the Edge, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx and the Future of the Human 163
Ridley, Matt 2000, ‘The Genome on CD’, a CD by Prospect, October.
Rikowski, Glenn 1990, ‘The Recruitment Process and Labour-Power’, unpublished
paper, Division of Humanities & Modern Languages, Epping Forest College,
Loughton, Essex, July.
Rikowski, Glenn 1996, ‘Apprenticeship and the Use-Value Aspect of Labour-Power’,
paper prepared for the ESRC Seminar Series on Apprenticeship, Nene College,
Northampton, 31 May.
Rikowski, Glenn 1999a, ‘Nietzsche, Marx and Mastery: The Learning Unto Death’, in
Apprenticeship: Towards a New Paradigm of Learning, edited by Patrick Ainley and
Helen Rainbird, London: Kogan Page.
Rikowski, Glenn 1999b, ‘Education, Capital and the Transhuman’, in Postmodernism
in Educational Theory: Education and the Politics of Human Resistance, edited by Dave
Hill, Peter McLaren, Mike Cole and Glenn Rikowski, London: Tufnell Press.
Rikowski, Glenn 2000a, ‘Education and Social Justice within the Social Universe of
Capital’, paper presented at the British Educational Research Association Day
Conference on ‘Approaching Social Justice: Theoretical Frameworks for Practical
Purposes’, Faculty of Education, Nottingham Trent University, Clifton Hall, 10 April.
Rikowski, Glenn 2000b, ‘That Other Great Class of Commodities: Repositioning Marxist
Educational Theory’, paper presented at the British Educational Research Association
Conference, Cardiff University, 9 September, Session 10.21.
Rikowski, Glenn 2000c, ‘Messing with the Explosive Commodity: School Improvement,
Educational Research and Labour-Power in the Era of Global Capitalism’, paper
presented at the British Educational Research Association Conference, Cardiff
University, 7 September, Session 3.4.
Rikowski, Glenn 2001a, The Battle in Seattle: Its Signicance for Education London: Tufnell
Press.
Rikowski, Glenn 2001b, ‘Education for Industry: A Complex Technicism’, Journal of
Education and Work, 14, 1: 29–49.
Rikowski, Glenn 2001c, ‘After the Manuscript Broke Off: Thoughts on Marx, Social
Class and Education’, paper presented at the British Sociological Association Education
Study Group Meeting, King’s College London, 23 June.
Rikowski, Glenn 2002, ‘Fuel for the Living Fire: Labour-Power!’, in The Labour Debate:
An Investigation into the Theory and Reality of Capitalist Work, edited by Ana Dinerstein
and Michael Neary, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Saffo, Paul 1998, The Lifeform Generation at: www.saffo.org/elife.html
Smith, Cyril 1996, Marx at the Millennium, London: Pluto Press.
Smith, Cyril 2002, ‘Karl Marx and Human Self-Creation’, in The Cyril Smith Internet
Archive, at: www.marxists.org/reference/archive/smithcyril/works/alteration/
index.htm
Stelarc 1998, ‘From Psycho-Body to Cyber-Systems: Images of Posthuman Entities’,
in Virtual Futures: Cyberotics, Technology and Posthuman Pragmatism, edited by Joan
Broadhurst Dixon and Eric Cassidy, London: Routledge.
Tattersall, Ian 2000, ‘Will We Keep Evolving?’, Time, 155, 14: 73–5.
Tester, Keith 1995, The Inhuman Condition, London: Routledge.
Transcedo 1998, ‘What Is Transhumanism?’, Dutch Transhumanist Society, 20 June
at: www.educa.com/transcedo/etrans.htm
Trigg, Roger 1988, Ideas of Human Nature: An Historical Introduction, Oxford: Blackwell.
164 Glenn Rikowski
Ust, Daniel undated, ‘What Is Posthumanism?’ at: www.teleport.com/~jaheriot/
posthum.htm
Virilio, Paul 1995, The Art of the Motor, translated by Julie Rose, Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Vita-More, Natasha undated, ‘Ageless Thinking: Creating Positive Transhuman Attitude’
at: www.aleph.se/Trans/Individual/Life/ageless.html
Williams, Mark 2000, ‘Exploring the Nature Within Us in the Century of Biology’, Red
Herring, September, 82: 106–8.