Metafísica y Persona
Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Metafísica y Persona, Año 15, No. 30, Julio-Diciembre 2023, es una publicación semestral, coeditada por la Universidad de Málaga y la Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla A.C., a través de la Academia de Filosofía, por la
Facultad de Filosofía y Humanidades y el Departamento de Investigación. Calle 21 Sur No. 1103, Col. Santiago, Puebla-Puebla, C.P. 72410, tel. (222) 229.94.00,
www.upaep.mx,
[email protected],
[email protected]. Editor responsable: Roberto Casales García. Reservas de Derecho al Uso Exclusivo 04-2014061317185400-102, ISSN: 2007-9699 ambos otorgados por el Instituto Nacional del
Derecho de Autor. Licitud de Título y contenido No. (en trámite), otorgados por
la Comisión Calificadora de Publicaciones y Revistas Ilustradas de la Secretaría de
Gobernación. Impresa por Mónica Lobatón Díaz, Servicios editoriales y de impresión, Enrique Rébsamen 124, colonia Narvarte Poniente, 03020, Ciudad de
México, este número se terminó de imprimir en julio de 2023, con un tiraje
de 250 ejemplares.
Metafísica y Persona está presente en los siguientes índices: Latindex, ÍnDICEs-CSIC,
REDIB, SERIUNAM, The Philosopher’s Index, ERIH PLUS, Dialnet, Fuente Académica.
Las opiniones expresadas por los autores no necesariamente reflejan la postura
de los editores de la publicación.
Queda estrictamente prohibida la reproducción total o parcial de los contenidos
e imágenes de la publicación sin previa autorización de los editores.
ISSN: 2007-9699
Metafísica y Persona
Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15 — Número 30
Julio-Diciembre 2023
Información general
Objetivos científicos
Metafísica y Persona es una revista de difusión internacional y carácter académico, cuyo
objetivo principal es la transmisión y discusión de los resultados de las últimas investigaciones en el ámbito que reflejan su título y subtítulo, mediante la publicación de Artículos
y Notas inéditos y de contrastado valor científico.
Pretende ser un lugar de encuentro y difusión de estudios que ahonden en las relaciones entre filosofía, conocimiento y vida, y que, por su calidad, originalidad y rigor, representen un claro avance en el saber y una contribución de relieve en el campo científico de
las materias que abarca.
Cobertura temática
El eje central de la revista es la realidad de la persona. Los artículos publicados en
ella abordarán el estudio de la persona desde los distintos puntos de vista que permiten
conocerla mejor. El lector encontrará, por tanto, trabajos de Filosofía, Teología, Sociología,
Psicología, Psiquiatría, Neurociencia, Medicina y otros saberes centrados en el hombre.
No obstante, la revista otorga una especial atención a la Antropología filosófica y, muy
en particular, a la Metafísica de la persona, pues son ellas las que dan sentido y sirven de
fundamento al resto de saberes sobre el ser humano.
Público al que se dirige
Metafísica y Persona se dirige especialmente a la comunidad científica y académica y, más
en concreto, a aquellos investigadores de Instituciones Universitarias y otros Centros afines
que, sobre todo desde una perspectiva filosófica, dedican todo o parte de sus trabajos a
mejorar el conocimiento de la persona, necesitado de una constante revisión y puesta al día.
No obstante, por las múltiples orientaciones que acoge, la Revista está también abierta
a un público más amplio: a todos aquellos que, dotados de una base filosófica y de cierta
formación en los saberes acerca de la existencia humana, desean profundizar en el conocimiento de la persona.
Carácter de las contribuciones
Las contribuciones enviadas a Metafísica y Persona han de ser inéditas en cualquier
idioma y no estar sujetas a revisión para ser publicadas en ninguna otra revista o publicación, ni digital ni impresa. En principio, los artículos se publicarán en la lengua en que
hayan sido redactados, aunque en ocasiones, de acuerdo con el autor, podrán ser traducidos al castellano o al inglés.
Los artículos y las notas son sometidos a un arbitraje doble-ciego. Para ser publicados,
los artículos han de obtener dos dictámenes favorables. Las notas, sin embargo, podrán
ser admitidas con un solo dictamen positivo y rechazadas con un solo dictamen negativo.
Más detalles en relación a este extremo figuran en las Normas editoriales.
Datos generales (edición, difusión, identificación y contacto)
Metafísica y Persona es coeditada entre la Universidad de Málaga (UMA) y la Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla (UPAEP). Nació como revista electrónica,
pero hoy se ofrece a los lectores tanto en formato digital como en papel.
En su versión impresa, la revista se distribuye, con alcance internacional, mediante
intercambio, donaciones e inscripciones (ver Suscripciones).
Identificación esencial
Título: Metafísica y Persona
Subtítulo: Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Carácter: Revista filosófica
Periodicidad: Semestral
Difusión: Internacional
ISSN en línea: 1989-4996
ISSN impreso: 2007-9699
Lugar de edición, año de edición y entidad editora
• Málaga (España), Universidad de Málaga (Grupo PAI, Junta de Andalucía, HUM-495)
• Puebla (México), Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla (Facultad de
Filosofía y Humanidades, y Departamento de Investigación)
Año de fundación: 2009
Dirección postal y electrónica
• Livia Bastos Andrade
Facultad de Filosofía
Decanato de Artes y Humanidades
Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla
Calle 21 Sur No. 1103, Col. Santiago
72410 PUEBLA (México)
[email protected]
• Gabriel Martí Andrés
Departamento de Filosofía
Facultad de Filosofía y Letras
Universidad de Málaga
Campus de Teatinos
E-29071 MÁLAGA (España)
[email protected]
Consejo Directivo
Director emérito:
Directora:
Subdirector:
Secretarios:
Melendo Granados, Tomás, Universidad de Málaga, España
Bastos Andrade, Livia, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado
de Puebla, México
Martí Andrés, Gabriel, Universidad de Málaga, España
García Martín, José, Universidad de Granada, España
Castro Manzano, José Martín, Universidad Popular Autónoma del
Estado de Puebla, México
Consejo de Redacción
Blancas Blancas, Noé, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla, México
García González, Juan A., Universidad de Málaga, España
Jiménez, Pablo, Australian National University, Australia
Lynch, Sandra (emérito), University of Notre Dame, Australia
Porras Torres, Antonio, Universidad de Málaga, España
Rojas Jiménez, Alejandro, Universidad de Málaga, España
Villagrán Mora, Abigail, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla, México
Consejo Científico Asesor
Arana Cañedo, Juan, Universidad de Sevilla, España
Brock, Stephen L., Università della Santa Croce, Italia
Caldera, Rafael T., Universidad Simón Bolívar, Venezuela
Casales García, Roberto, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla, México
Clavell, Lluís (emérito), Università della Santa Croce, Italia
D’Agostino, Francesco, Università Tor Vergata, Italia
Donati, Pierpaolo, Università di Bologna, Italia
Falgueras Salinas, Ignacio, Universidad de Málaga, España
González García, Ángel L. (†), Universidad de Navarra, España
Grimaldi, Nicolás, Université de Paris-Sorbonne, Francia
Hittinger, Russell, University of Tulsa, Oklahoma
Jaulent, Esteve, Instituto Brasileiro de Filosofia e Ciência “Raimundo Lúlio”, Brasil
Livi, Antonio (†), Università Lateranense, Italia
Llano Cifuentes, Carlos (†), Instituto Panamericano de Alta Dirección de Empresa, México
Medina Delgadillo, Jorge, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla, México
Morán y Castellanos, Jorge (†), Universidad Panamericana, México
Pithod, Abelardo, Centro de Investigaciones Cuyo, Argentina
Pizzutti, Giuseppe M., Università della Basilicata, Italia
Peña Vial, Jorge, Universidad de los Andes, Chile
Ramsey, Hayden, Australian Catholic University, Australia
Redmond, Walter, University of Texas, U.S.A.
Sánchez Muñoz, Rubén, Universidad Popular Autónoma del Estado de Puebla, México
Sánchez Sorondo, Marcelo, Pontificia Accademia delle Scienze, Italia
Vigo, Alejandro, Universidad de los Andes, Chile
Wippel, John F., Catholic University of America, U.S.A.
Zagal, Héctor, Universidad Panamericana, México
Contenido
Artículos
The “razón de fuerza mayor” and barbarism. Eduardo Nicol and Michel
Henry on the Technique
Stefano Santasilia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
A critical reflection on the Antikythera Mechanism from an idealist
perspective and its implications on technological development as a means
of understanding our Cosmos
Carlos Alberto Carbajal Constantine . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
A natural artificial intelligence? Some notes on the computational biomimicry
of human intelligence
Héctor Velázquez . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31
What kind of “intelligence” is Artificial Intelligence?
Paniel Reyes Cárdenas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
Some remarks on Leibniz’s criticisms to mechanics
Roberto Casales García. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
Del simbolismo a la alimentación: el nacimiento de una nueva identidad
bajo las virtudes teologales, la Virgen de Guadalupe, la trigarancia y los
chiles en nogada
David Sánchez Sánchez . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
Notas críticas
La primera propuesta de Martin Seligman acerca de la felicidad
Livia Bastos Andrade . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
Reseñas
Tappolet, C., Philosophy of Emotion. A contemporary Introduction,
New York: Routledge, 2022, 255p.
María Soledad Paladino . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
7
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
Panikkar, R., Ecosofía. La sabiduría de la Tierra, Barcelona: Fragmenta
Editorial, 2021, 93p.
Paulina Michelle Romero Tenorio, Iñigo Sánchez Trujillo,
Rubén Sánchez Muñoz. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121
Normas editoriales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125
8
Artículos
Metafísica y Persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
Some remarks on Leibniz’s criticisms to mechanics
Algunas observaciones sobre las críticas de Leibniz a la mecánica
Abstract
Roberto Casales García1
UPAEP, Universidad
[email protected]
The main purpose of this paper is to analyze some of Leibniz’s critics of mechanics in
order to understand its limitations, particularly those that help to clarify the distinction
between the machines made by human beings and machines of nature. To understand
Leibniz’s critics of mechanics, we divided them into three kinds: 1. critics of the Cartesian
conception of extension; 2. Leibniz´s mill argument; and 3. the irreducibility of living being too simple machines or artifacts.
Keywords: force, mechanics, machine of nature, perception, body.
Resumen
El objetivo principal de este artículo es analizar algunas de las críticas de Leibniz al
mecanicismo, con la intención de comprender sus limitaciones, particularmente aquellas
que nos ayudan a esclarecer la distinción entre las máquinas fabricadas por los seres humanos y las máquinas de la naturaleza. Para entender las críticas de Leibniz al mecanicismo, las hemos dividido en tres: 1. las críticas a la concepción cartesiana de extensión; 2.
el argumento leibniziano del molino; y 3. la irreductibilidad de los seres vivos a simples
máquinas o artefactos.
Palabras clave: fuerza, mecanicismo, máquina de la naturaleza, percepción, cuerpo.
Introduction
In a famous letter to Nicolas Remond, dated on January 10th of 1714,
Leibniz mentioned that, after studying some modern philosophers and
1
ORCID: https://orcid.org/0000-0003-4189-7961
Recepción del original: 01/06/2023
Aceptación definitiva: 07/07/2023
49
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
thinkers at the age of fifteen, he went to the Rosetal to deliberate whether
to preserve substantial forms or not. Even when he chooses mechanics
over metaphysics at that moment, his further investigations on the ultimate grounds of mechanics and the laws of motion lead him to conclude
that “they could not be found in mathematics but that I should have to
return to metaphysics”.2 A statement that can also be found in his New
System of the Nature and the Communication of Substances of 1695, where he
argues that
after trying to explore the principles of mechanics itself in order to account
for the laws of nature which we learn from experience, I perceived that the
sole consideration of extended mass was not enough but that it was necessary,
in addition, to use the concept of force […] althought it falls within the sphere
of metaphysics.3
These biographical notes let us see that his adscription to mechanics was
ambiguous since he, on one side, state that every natural phenomena could
be explained mechanically, at the same time that he, on the other side, affirms
that “the principles of mechanics themselves cannot be explained geometrically, since they depend on more sublime principles which show the wisdom
of the Author in the order and perfection of his work”.4
Even when Leibniz is considered as a relevant precursor for computing
and artificial intelligence,5 especially for his improvements in mathematics and logic, his developments for the mines of Harz, and his calculator,
his ambiguous adscription to mechanics reveals some of the limits not only
of this account of nature but also of our technological improvements. The
main purpose of this paper is to analyze some of Leibniz’s critics of mechanics in order to understand these limitations, particularly those that
help to clarify the distinction between the machines made by human beings
and machines of nature. To understand Leibniz’s critics of mechanics, we
divided these into three kinds: 1. critics of the Cartesian conception of extension; 2. Leibniz´s mill argument; and 3. the irreducibility of living being
too simple machines or artifacts.
2
3
4
5
Loemker, 655. All references from Leibniz and Descartes will be quoted according to the
canonical style of citation.
Loemker, 454; GP IV, 478.
Tentamen anagogicum, Loemecker, 478; GP VII, 272; see also: Extrait d’une letter de M. de Leibniz
sur la question, si l’essence du corps consiste dans l’Etendue, Lamarra 204-205.
Camacho Naranjo, L. (2019). “H. Dreyfus, R. Smullyan y G.W. Leibniz: sobre los límites de
sistemas formales”, en Carvajal Villaplana, A., Leibniz. Máquinas inteligentes, multiculturalismo y ética de la vida, Granada: Comares (Nova Leibniz Latina 2), pp. 5-28.
50
Some remarks about Leibniz’s critics to mechanics
The insufficiency of the Cartesian conception of extension
Descartes notion of extension is quite relevant for mechanics not only because he sustains that extension constitutes the true nature or essence of all
bodies,6 but also because, as Gilson noticed, it allows him to develop a form of
“mathematicism”, according to which all human knowledge can be molded in
conformity “with the pattern of mathematical evidence”.7 If the essence of all
bodies consists in extension, then we can measure and describe every natural
phenomena through the lengths of a mathematical equation. Even when Leibniz accepts that every natural phenomena can be explained mechanically, and
thus by mathematical means, he clearly sustain in a brief text of 1677 that this
account of nature only correspond to our cognitive limitations:
First of all, I take it to be certain that all things come about through certain
intelligible causes, or causes which we could perceive if some angel wished
to reveal them to us. And since we may perceive nothing accurately except
magnitude, figure, motion, and perception itself, it follows that everything is
to be explained through these four. But because we are now speaking of those
things which seem to take place without perception, such as the reactions of
liquids, the precipitations of salts, etc., we have no means of explaining them
except through magnitude, figure, and motion, that is, through mechanism.8
According to Leibniz, extension and mechanics only correspond to how
we can represent the external and phenomenical world through perception:
every natural phenomena can be explained mechanically, through mathematical means, only because, as we can see in his correspondence with De
Volder, “matter or extender mass is nothing but a phenomenon grounded
in things, like the rainbow or the mock-sun, and all reality belongs only to
unities”.9 By giving a phenomenical character to all bodies, Leibniz is not
saying that they lack of reality, but only that it is grounded in something
else and, therefore, that the true essence or nature of bodies cannot consist
only in extension. What Leibniz is denying is the substantial character of extension. One reason to sustain this is that extension is only a relative and incomplete concept, “an analyzable and relative concept, for it can be resolved
into plurality, continuity and coexistence or the existence of parts at one and
the same time”.10 As a property of things, according to Leibniz, extension is
not an absolute predicate but only an attribute relatively of what is extended
6
7
8
9
10
Treatise on light, Ariew 37; AT XI, 36.
Gilson, E., The Unity of Philosophical Experience, New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1950, p. 133.
De modo perveniendi ad veram corporum analysin et resum naturalium causas, Loemker,
173; GP VII, 265.
Letter from Leibniz to De Volder from June 30th of 1704, Loemker, 536; GP II, 270.
Letter from Leibniz to De Volder from march 24th of 1699, Loemker, 516; GP II, 169.
51
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
or diffused, which means that it cannot be separated from the thing that is
extended or diffused.11
In a second argument to deny the substantiality of extension, as we can see
in a brief text from 1691, Leibniz state that if the true essence of bodies consists
in extension, extension alone should be enough to explain every property of
bodies.12 Extension, as Laura Herrera noticed,13 is not enough to explain the
transmission of movement that happens in the collision of two or more bodies,
where the extension is completely indifferent, and the results of this collision
would be, at most, explained by the mere geometric composition of movements, without explaining the ultimate causes of movement.14 Another reason
to say that extension is insufficient to explain every property of bodies, specifically the ultimate causes of motion, is that “extension is an attribute which
cannot make up a complete entity, no action or change can be deduced from it,
it expresses only a present state, not at all the future and past as the concept of a
substance must do”.15 According to Leibniz, on the contrary, “even by the laws
of motion, a body is never affected by the impact of another except by virtue of
its own elasticity, which comes from a motion which already exists within it”.16
Both reasons to deny the substantial character of extension aim to the
same place, as Juan Arana notice: extension and mechanics insufficiency implies that if we need to
change the point of view from foronomics to dynamics. Alternatively, if desired, to pass from describing movement with exactitude to explain it. The
distinction between describing and explaining seem unequivocal, as it can
be seen when we confront rough descriptions and explanations that lead us
to the ultimate causes.17
Even when we can explain everything mechanically, mechanics only represents one form to approach to nature, especially when we want to understand the realm of living beings, as we will see in Leibniz’s mill argument
against mechanical materialism.
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
“Nullum quidem librum contra philosohpian Cartesianam…”, GP IV, 394.
Extrait d’une letter de M. de Leibniz sur la question, si l’essence du corps consiste dans l’Etendue,
Lamarra, 203.
Herrera, L., “En torno a la concepción leibniziana del cuerpo”, en Rodero-Cilleros, S. &
Sánchez-Rodríguez, M. (Eds.), Leibniz en la filosofía y la ciencia modernas, Granada: Comares,
2010, p. 284.
Extrait d’une letter de M. de Leibniz sur la question, si l’essence du corps consiste dans l’Etendue,
Lamarra, 203.
Draft of a letter from Leibniz to Arnauld, Mason, 88; Finster, 186.
Draft of ‘New System for the Explaining the Nature of Substances and the Communication between
them, as well as the Union of the Soul with the Body, Woolhouse, 25; GP IV, 476.
Juan Arana 2013: 63.
52
Some remarks about Leibniz’s critics to mechanics
Leibniz’s mill argument against mechanical materialism
Beyond the Cartesian conception of extension and its applications to natural sciences, mechanics not only affirms that everything in nature can be
measured and, therefore, described through a mathematical equation, but
also that we can explain every single natural change by understanding two
things: the parts that constitute the machine, i.e., the gears that make this machine work, and the way that these parts interact.18 Leibniz believes that we
can only apply this mechanical criterion to explain the interaction of bodies,
so “a body never receives a change in motion except through another body in
motion which pushes it”,19 since bodies, according to §79 of his Monadology,
“act according to the laws of efficient causes or the laws of motion”.20 However, he also states that we cannot apply the same criterion to explain the inner
activity of those simple substances that “enters into compounds”,21 since their
inner actions, as he states in §2 of his Principles of Nature and of Grace, Based on
Reason, “can only be its perceptions –that is to say, the representations of the
compound, or of that which is without, in the simple– and its appetitions –that
is to say, its tendencies from one perception to another– which are the principles of change”.22 By grounding mechanics in his dynamics and not only in
extension, Leibniz not only states that “there is never a body without movement”, as he states in the Preface of his New Essays in Human Understanding
of 1710, but also “that in the natural course of things no substance can lack
activity”23 or, as he claims in the §1 of his Principles of Nature and of Grace,
Based on Reason, “substance is a being capable of action”:24 while in bodies or
compounds their activity consist in motion, the activity of monads consist in
perception and appetite, two inner activities of this soul-like entities.
When Leibniz state that each body or compound is not one substance but
an aggregate of substances,25 he is also saying that the force that explains motion, considered as a derivative force, proceeds from an inner primitive force
of these monads: “derivative forces are in fact nothing but the modifications
and echoes of primitive forces”.26 According to this approach, as we can see
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
Velázquez Fernández, H., ¿Qué es la naturaleza? Introducción filosófica a la historia de la
ciencia, México: Porrúa, 2007, p. 87.
Considerations on vital Principles and Plastic Natures, Loemker, 587; GP VI, 541.
Loemker, 651; GP VI, 620.
Monadology, Loemker, 643; GP VI, 607.
Loemker, 636; Robinet I, 29.
AA VI, 6, 53.
Loemker, 636; Robinet I, 27.
Communicata ex disputationibus cum Fardella, de serie rerum, corporibus et substantiis, et de praedeterminatione, AA VI, 4B, 1668.
Letter from Leibniz to De Volder from June 20th of 1703, Loemker, 530; GP II, 251.
53
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
in §11 of his On Nature Itself of 1698, we can only say that “bodies in themselves are inert” since “extension, or the geometric nature of a body, taken
alone contains nothing from which action and motion can arise,” a passive
force of resistance that he locates in prime matter or mass, “which is everywhere proportional in a body to its magnitude”.27 Since action and motion
are not something that can be derived from this prime matter or mass, Leibniz
concludes that we need to presuppose something else in bodies that explain
all these activities and, therefore, “that there must be found in corporeal substance a primary entelechy or first recipient (prôton dektikòn) of activity, that is,
a primitive motive force which, superadded to extension, or what is merely
geometrical, and mass, or what is merely material, always acts indeed and
yet is modified in various ways by the concourse of bodies”.28 As we can see
in §11 of his New System, these primary entelechies constitute the
real unities absolutely devoid of parts, that can be the sources of actions, and
the absolute first principle of the composition of things, and as it were the
ultimate elements in the analysis of sunstances…they have something of the
nature of life and a kind of perception.29
Even when we can explain every corporal movement by mechanical means,
as the result of the impact of another body, this movement can be described,
in Leibniz’s opinion, as an external expression of the inner force of things,
something that depends on the existence of monads. This soul-like entities,
as primary forces, also are subject to change, a change that “is continuous in
each one” and that comes from “an internal principle”.30 The inner action of
monads, as we already state, consist in perception and appetite: while perceptions are the “detail in that which changes,” i.e., “the passing state”31 which
express or represent what is outside (the external world) from the inside,32 as
a mental state; appetites are “the action of the internal principle which brings
about change or passage from one perception to another”.33 Since monads are
always acting, we can infer that they are always perceiving and passing from
one perception to another, even when they are not aware of their own perceptions, as we can see in the Preface of his New Essays, when he introduced
his theory of minute perceptions: “besides, there is in us an infinity of perceptions, unaccompanied by awareness or reflection; that is, of alterations in the
soul itself, of which we are unaware because these impressions are either too
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
Loemker, 503; GP IV, 510.
On Nature Itself, Loemker, 503; GP IV, 511.
Woolhouse, 16; GP IV, 482-483.
Monadology, Loemker, 643-644; GP VI, 608.
Monadology, Loemker, 644; GP VI, 608.
Letter to R.C. Wagner from June 4th of 1710, GP VII, 329-330.
Monadology, Loemker, 644; GP VI, 609.
54
Some remarks about Leibniz’s critics to mechanics
minute and too numerous, or else too unvarying, so that they are not sufficiently distinctive on their own”.34 Monads always perceive something, even
when they lack of any kind of consciousness or reflection, as we can see in
those monads whose perceptions cannot reach the level of sensation.35 All of
this allow us to understand the ontological background of his mill argument
against mechanical materialism, as we can see in §17 of his Monadology:
It must be confessed, moreover, that perception and what depends on it are
inexplicable by mechanical reasons, that is, by figures and motions. If we pretend that there is a machine whose structure enables it to think, feel, and
have perception, one could think of it as enlarged yet preserving its same
proportions, so that one could enter it as one does a mill. If we did this, we
should find nothing within but parts which push upon each other; we should
never see anything which would explain a perception. So it is in the simple
substance, and not in the composite substance or machine, that perception
must be sought. Furthermore, this is the only thing –namely, perceptions
and their changes- that can be found in simple substance. It is in this alone
that the internal actions of simple substances can consist.36
As Paul Lodge noticed, the key to understand Leibniz’s mill argument is
to recognize its target are mechanical materialists that affirm that every corporeal being is a mechanical system and, therefore, that material things are
entities whose behavior can be accurately and exhaustively explained by adverting to nothing other than the sizes and shapes of impenetrable particles
that have the power to receive motion from other particles through impact or
as a result of the direct activity of immaterial entities upon them.37
If we pay attention to the ontological backgrounds of this argument, we
will see that Leibniz agrees with mechanical materialists in saying that every
corporeal natural phenomenon is prone to a mechanical explanation, something that, however, cannot apply to perception and appetite, the inner activity of monads, since they do not depend on any corporeal or geometrical
thing. Mental states like perception and appetite, even when they could be
related with sensation and, in this way, with the impressions that we receive
through some of our organs, cannot be explained in mechanical terms since
“they are not properties of mechanical material things”.38 By understanding
the parts that constitute our body, conceived as a natural machine, and the
34
35
36
37
38
AA VI, 6, 53.
Monadology, Loemker, 644; GP VI, 610.
Monadology, Loemker, 644; GP VI, 609.
Lodge, P., “Leibniz’s Mill Argument Against Mechanical Materialism Revisited”, Ergo, vol. 1,
num. 3, 2014, p. 81.
Lodge, P., “Leibniz’s Mill Argument…”, p. 82.
55
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
way they interact, i.e., the way that they behave, we would never see something that explains our mental states:
sentient or thinking being is not a mechanical thing like a watch or a mill: one
cannot conceive of sizes and shapes and motions combining mechanically to
produce something which thinks, and senses too, in a mass where [formerly]
there was nothing of the kind.39
Machines of nature vs artifacts
As we can see at the end of §2 of his New System, Leibniz’s concerns about
mechanics are not only related to the Cartesian notion of extension but also
with the opinion “of those who transform or demote animals into mere machines,” something that he considers implausible and “contrary to the order
of things”.40 Leibniz also makes this critic to Descartes when he explains, in
§2 of his Principles of Nature and of Grace, Based on Reason, the distinction between perception and the reflective knowledge that only spirits can reach: by
stating that all our perceptions are apperceived, i.e., that every mental state
is conscious,41 “these same Cartesians think that only spirits are monads and
that there is no soul in beast, still less other principles of life”.42 In this way,
Leibniz not only recognize that animals have souls but also that every living
being have one, including plants, since they have perceptions and appetites:
“the great analogy which exists between plants and animals inclines me to
believe that there is some perception and appetite even in plants”.43 All of
this means that even when Leibniz accepts a mechanical account of bodies,
including the bodies of all living beings, “he strongly resists the Cartesian
attempt to describe natural machines in terms of artificial ones”.44 The reason
to sustain the irreducibility of living beings to artificial machines, however, is
not only that living beings have a soul that guarantees the unity of the entire
organism, since bodies without a soul can only be considered as mere aggregates of beings without any further vinculum45 –while living beings are still
the same being even when their body experiences some changes or modifi-
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
New Essays, AA VI, 6, 66-67.
Woolhouse, 11; GP IV, 478.
AT, VIII, 160.
Loemker, 637; Robinet I, 37.
New Essays, AA VI, 6, 139.
Nachtomy, O., “Leibniz on Artifical and Natural Machines: Or What It Means to Remain a
Machine to the Least of its Parts”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O. (Eds.), Machines of Nature and
Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer, 2011, p. 65.
“Nullum quidem librum contra philosohpian Cartesianam…”, GP IV, 395-396.
56
Some remarks about Leibniz’s critics to mechanics
cations–,46 but also because their complex structure, which make them quite
different from artifacts, as we can see in §64 of his Monadology:
So each organic body belonging to a living being is a kind of divine machine
or natural automaton infinitely surpassing all artificial automata. For machine made by human art is not a machine in each of its parts; for example,
the tooth of a brass wheel has parts or fragments which are not artificial so
far as we are concerned, and which do not have the character of a machine,
in that they fit the use for which the wheel was intended. But machines of
nature, living bodies, are still machines in their smallest parts, into infinity. It
is this that makes the difference between nature and art, that is between the
divine art and ours.47
Even when Leibniz describes the structure of an organism in terms of a
mechanism, as he asserts in his New Essays about the bodies of plants and
animals,48 he also elaborates “his own program to characterize living beings
not as inert mechanisms but as animate active creatures”.49 This program can
be resumed in two aspects: first, that these machines of nature, contrary to artifacts, consist of an infinity of nested organs or parts involved in each other;50
second, that “a natural machine is still a machine even in its smallest parts”.51
According to Nachtomy’s approach to the first aspect, this infinity “is not the
number of organs or machines but rather the very structure of a natural machine which involves machines within machines,” a structure that “develops
ad infinitum”,52 something that helps us to understand in which sense Leibniz
affirms, on one side, that “the soul only changes its body little by little and by
degrees, so that it is never deprived of all its organs at once”,53 and, on the
other side, “that not only the soul, as mirror of an indestructible universe, is
itself indestructible but also the animal itself, although its machine may often
perish in part and cast off or take on particular organic coverings”.54 In this
way, as he states in his correspondence with De Volder,
when I Say that even if it is corporeal, a substance contains an infinity of machines, I think it must be added at the same time that it forms one machine
Leibniz a Foucher, GP I, 391.
Loemker, 649; GP VI, 618.
48
AA VI, 6, 139.
49
Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O., “Introduction”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O. (Eds.), Machines of
Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer, 2011, p. 2.
50
“Nullum quidem librum contra philosohpian Cartesianam…”, GP IV, 396.
51
New System, Woolhouse, 16; GP IV, 482.
52
Nachtomy, O., “Leibniz on Artificial…”, p. 73.
53
Monadology, Loemker, 650; GP VI, 619.
54
Monadology, Loemker, 651; GP VI, 620.
46
47
57
Metafísica y persona. Filosofía, conocimiento y vida
Año 15, Núm. 30, Julio-Diciembre, 2023, ISSN: 2007-9699
composed of these machines and that it is actuated, besides, by one entelechy, without which it would contain no principle of true unity.55
Machines of nature, finally, not only differ from artifacts because they
have an organic structure that suffer a number of develops that extend to infinity; they also differ by virtue of theirs parts: while artifacts are aggregates
of things that are not always artifacts at the same time, smaller machines or
artifacts, each machine of nature “is an aggregate of smaller corporeal substances”, organic bodies that “are in turn aggregates of even smaller corporeal substances, and so on to infinity”.56 Each part of a living being, in this
sense, is a smaller living being that is also composed of other even smaller
living beings, conforming an aggregate of machines of nature that are integrated by virtue of an intrinsic teleological organization.57
References
Camacho Naranjo, L. (2019). “H. Dreyfus, R. Smullyan y G.W. Leibniz: sobre los
límites de sistemas formales”, en Carvajal Villaplana, A., Leibniz. Máquinas
inteligentes, multiculturalismo y ética de la vida, Granada: Comares (Nova Leibniz Latina 2), pp. 5-28.
Descartes, R., Oeuvres de Descartes, Adam, Ch. & Tannery, P. (Eds.), Paris: J. Vrin,
11 vols, 1964-1986.
Descartes, R., Philosophical Essays and Correspondence, Ariew, R. (ed.), Indianapolis-Cambridge: Hackett Publishing, 2000.
Gilson, E., The Unity of Philosophical Experience, New York: Charles Scribner’s
Sons, 1950.
Herrera, L., “En torno a la concepción leibniziana del cuerpo”, en Rodero-Cilleros, S. & Sánchez-Rodríguez, M. (Eds.), Leibniz en la filosofía y la ciencia modernas, Granada: Comares, 2010, pp. 281-296.
Leibniz, G.W., Der Briefwechsel mit Antoine Arnauld (Franzosisch-deutsch), Finster, R. (Ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1997.
Leibniz, G.W., Die Philosophischen Schriften, herausgegeben von C.I. Gerhardt,
Hildesheim, 1965.
Leibniz, G.W., Essais scientifiques et philosophiques. Les articles publiés dans les journaux savants, Lamarra, A. & Palaia, R. (Eds.), 3 vols., Hildesheim: Olms, 2005.
55
56
57
Letter from Leibniz to De Volder from June 20th of 1703, Loemker, 529; GP II, 250.
Phemister, P., “Monads and Machines”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O. (Eds.), Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer,
2011, p. 41.
Animadversiones, Dutens II-2, 144.
58
Some remarks about Leibniz’s critics to mechanics
Leibniz, G.W., Gothofredi Guillelmi Leibnitii… Opera Omnia, Dutens, L. (Ed.), 6
vols. Geneva: De Tournes, 1768.
Leibniz, G.W., Leibniz’s ‘New System’ and Associated Contemporary Texts, Woolhouse,
R.S. & Francks, R. (Eds.), Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.
Leibniz, G.W., New Essays on Human Understanding. Remnant, P. & Bennett, J.
(Eds.). Glasgow: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Leibniz, G.W., Philosophical Papers and Letters, Loemker, L.E. (Ed.), Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989.
Leibniz, G.W., Principes de la nature et de la grâce fondés en raison. Principles de la
philosophie ou monadologie, publiés intégralement d’après des lettres inédites
par Robinet, A., París, 1954.
Leibniz, G.W., Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Von der Deutschen Akademie der
Wissenschaften zu Berlin, Darmstadt (1923 y ss.), Leipzig (1938 y ss.), Berlín
(1950 y ss.).
Leibniz, G.W., The Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence, Mason, H.T. (Ed.), New York:
Manchester University Press, 1967.
Lodge, P., “Leibniz’s Mill Argument Against Mechanical Materialism Revisited”,
Ergo, vol. 1, num. 3, 2014, pp. 79-99.
Nachtomy, O., “Leibniz on Artificial and Natural Machines: Or What It Means
to Remain a Machine to the Least of its Parts”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O.
(Eds.), Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer, 2011, pp. 61-80.
Phemister, P., “Monads and Machines”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O. (Eds.),
Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer, 2011, pp. 39-60.
Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O., “Introduction”, en Smith, J.E. & Nachtomy, O.
(Eds.), Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York: Springer, 2011, pp. 1-9.
Velázquez Fernández, H., ¿Qué es la naturaleza? Introducción filosófica a la historia de la ciencia, México: Porrúa, 2007.
59