Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Paraconsistent vagueness: a positive argument

2010, Synthese

Paraconsistent approaches have received little attention in the literature on vagueness (at least compared to other proposals). The reason seems to be that many philosophers have found the idea that a contradiction might be true (or that a sentence and its negation might both be true) hard to swallow. Even advocates of paraconsistency on vagueness do not look very convinced when they consider this fact; since they seem to have spent more time arguing that paraconsistent theories are at least as good as their paracomplete counterparts, than giving positive reasons to believe on a particular paraconsistent proposal. But it sometimes happens that the weakness of a theory turns out to be its mayor ally, and this is what (I claim) happens in a particular paraconsistent proposal known as subvaluationism. In order to make room for truth-value gluts subvaluationism needs to endorse a notion of logical consequence that is, in some sense, weaker than standard notions of consequence. But this weakness allows the subvaluationist theory to accommodate higher-order vagueness in a way that it is not available to other theories of vagueness (such as, for example, its paracomplete counterpart, supervaluationism).

Synthese (2011) 183:211–227 DOI 10.1007/s11229-010-9760-0 Paraconsistent vagueness: a positive argument Pablo Cobreros Received: 23 December 2009 / Accepted: 29 June 2010 / Published online: 3 August 2010 © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 Abstract Paraconsistent approaches have received little attention in the literature on vagueness (at least compared to other proposals). The reason seems to be that many philosophers have found the idea that a contradiction might be true (or that a sentence and its negation might both be true) hard to swallow. Even advocates of paraconsistency on vagueness do not look very convinced when they consider this fact; since they seem to have spent more time arguing that paraconsistent theories are at least as good as their paracomplete counterparts, than giving positive reasons to believe on a particular paraconsistent proposal. But it sometimes happens that the weakness of a theory turns out to be its mayor ally, and this is what (I claim) happens in a particular paraconsistent proposal known as subvaluationism. In order to make room for truth-value gluts subvaluationism needs to endorse a notion of logical consequence that is, in some sense, weaker than standard notions of consequence. But this weakness allows the subvaluationist theory to accommodate higher-order vagueness in a way that it is not available to other theories of vagueness (such as, for example, its paracomplete counterpart, supervaluationism). Keywords Logical consequence · Paraconsistency · Vagueness · Subvaluationism The subvaluationist theory of vagueness is the dual theory of the well-known supervaluationist theory. Where the supervaluationist reads ‘truth’ as ‘supertruth’ (truth in every precisification) the subvaluationist reads ‘truth’ as ‘subtruth’ (truth in some precisification). This dual reading of the notion of truth leads to a theory P. Cobreros (B) University of Navarra, Pamplona, Spain e-mail: [email protected] 123 212 Synthese (2011) 183:211–227 of vagueness in which borderline sentences give raise to gluts of truth-value (by contrast to supervaluationism in which borderline sentences give raise to gaps in truth-value). Subvaluationism is a paraconsistent theory in the sense that a sentence might both be true and false without triviality (i.e., the set of sentences { p, ¬ p} is subvaluationist-satisfiable); it is weakly paraconsistent in the sense that classical contradictions are not subvaluationist-satisfiable (the analogous dual remarks apply to supervaluationism). The subvaluationist theory has been defended by Dominic Hyde (in Hyde 1997 and in the more recent Hyde and Colyvan 2008) who exploits the duality between subvaluationism and supervaluationism to argue that the first is at least as good as the second and, consequently, the neglect of paraconsistent theories in the literature lacks a justification. Commenting on Hyde’s 1997 paper Beall and Colyvan (2001) point out that Hyde could have gone further arguing that truth-value gluts seem to have the upper hand in the case of paradoxes other than the sorites, such as the paradoxes of self-reference in which truth-value gluts, unlike truth-value gaps, do not succumb to strengthened versions. Even if truth-value glut theories have the upper hand in the case of self-referential paradoxes, this might not constitute enough justification for a glut solution in the case of vagueness. There are other phenomena that suggest a gappy treatment and there’s no argument for the claim that gluts solve things everywhere. It seems to me that paraconsistent proposals on vagueness, subvaluationism in particular, deserve a positive argument, a justification on its own not parasitic on a paracomplete dual. This paper provides such an argument based on Fara’s (so-called) paradox of higher-order vagueness. Fara (2003) shows that if the supervaluationist is committed to a rule of inference known as D-introduction, then she/he cannot endorse the complete hierarchy of gap-principles needed to explain the seeming absence of sharp transitions in sorites series. This paper argues that these gap-principles are equally compelling to other theories of vagueness in which the notion of a borderline case plays a key role. Then it shows that these theories, if committed to a notion of logical consequence as strong as local consequence, cannot avoid a strengthened version of the paradox. But the subvaluationist can. The paper is divided into three sections. The first one describes in a general way what it is understood by a borderline-based theory of vagueness and proposes a general setting to define a notion of definiteness for this sort of theories. Different informal readings of the general setting will deliver different notions of truth for each theory and, consequently, different notions of logical consequence. The paper considers three alternatives: supervaluationist, local and subvaluationist consequence. The second section presents Fara’s paradox of higher-order vagueness as applied to the supervaluationist theory. The last section considers a strengthened version of Fara’s paradox and explains why theories committed to a notion of logical consequence as strong as local consequence cannot handle this version of the paradox while the subvaluationist theory can. 123