Richard Duus
Related Authors
Faye Antoniou
National & Kapodistrian University of Athens
Grant J Rich
Walden University
Evangelia Galanaki
National & Kapodistrian University of Athens
Konstantinos Malafantis
National & Kapodistrian University of Athens
Sanem Soyarslan
North Carolina State University
Virginia Thomas
Middlebury College
InterestsView All (15)
Uploads
Papers by Richard Duus
A routine supports a privacy that, in turn, supports focused reflective thinking cycle in the context of a shared we-relation of a marriage, that if satisfactory, can continue for an extended time. It provides both an experiential base for an outward-directed meaning to one’s life, and subjective inward-directed experiences that is one’s inward unfolding and growth of knowledge and concurrent range of affect, perceptual sensitivities, rationality, imagination, general ability, and ethical openness of one’s subjective breadth and depth being.
eBook 74,89 € | £63.99 | $84.99 74,89 € (D) | 74,89 € (A) | CHF [2] 85,00 Available from your library or springer.com/shop MyCopy [3]
Duus, R. (2020). Constituting Selves: Psychology’s Pragmatic Horizon. Switzerland AG: Springer Nature. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/978–3–030–39017–4
tension experienced between psychological science, ‘experimental psychology,’
and applied consulting psychological practice, ‘clinical psychology.’ This is an
exploration of that ‘gap’ and its resulting tension. First-person perspective is
proposed as an important aspect of psychological reality in conjunction with the
related perspectival aspects of second- and third-person perspectives. These 3
aspects taken ‘wholistically’ constitute a perspectival diffusion grate through which
psychological reality is discerned. The reductionistic naturalism of scientifically
apprehended reality is examined for the powerful resistances that impedite utilizing
perspective in psychological investigations with consequences for our understanding
of psychological reality. The impediments constructed by Quine, Sellars,
Dennett, Metzinger, and cognitive psychology are all examined for their robust
intractability to first-person perspective or anything that might seem similar. The
conclusion suggested is that they all result from a ‘scientific near-sightedness’ of a
strict naturalism. The result is that any intentionally dependent objects that are real
in the lives of persons are eliminated as not real with no ontological significance.
The assertion is that ordinary things such as car keys and employment are real and
are ontologically significant.
Keywords: first-person, hard naturalism, liberal naturalism, personhood, third-person
with The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (1999), and
further developed by Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (2003). These books
are meant to be accessible to the general public, but are also useful to those professionals and
researchers, who are not neuroscientists, seeking a review of recent neuroscientific empirical
developments and thinking concerning self and consciousness. These books summarizing one person's
effort to capture the complex phenomena of self, consciousness and mind totally within the
neurological processes of the central nervous system take their place in a large corpus of literature
concerning self that is complex and sometimes difficult. “Few ideas are as weighty and as slippery as
the notion of self,” to borrow Jerrold Seigel’s apt characterization in the introduction to his account of
the western intellectual discussion of its varied and changing ideas of self, The Idea of the Self (Seigel,
2005, p. 3).
Drafts by Richard Duus
members jointly engage a shared project second-person engagement is joined. The purpose of this
paper is to present an account of intersubjective space as second-person perspective. A joint
engagement of a project by members of a community, that could be a simple conversation, gives rise
to a unitary we-relation that is a second-person engagement. The structure of second-person
encounter is described by four properties of an interdefinable circle that consists of the
authority to confront an other person of one’s community with a claim of a transgression which
becomes a practical reason for the person confronted to direct their conduct for which she is
unconditionally responsible. Direct first-person experience of a we-relation is the empathic
connection of a unitary property of a second-person engagement while reactive attitudes are the
emotional context of moral conduct. Second-person engagement is inherently moral that derives from
the properties of the interdefinable circle and the social infrastructure of the community an
engagement is embedded. Moral autonomy derives from the imperative nature of the principles
derived from a social infrastructure. Such a principle can be recognized as a categorical
imperative. Conduct is moral and responsible only if autonomous.
Keywords: intersubjectivity, we-experience, morality, second-person stand, practical
reasons, autonomy, reactive attitudes
subsequently, undeveloped. Subjectivity processes include evolving experience episodes and its
unifying thinking core. This inquiry presented in this paper targeted the structure of experience,
its relation to an I, its relation to thinking, and its intersubjective nature. A proposed outline of
the processes of subjectivity are presented derived from William James, Hector Neri Castañeda,
and Lynne Rudder Baker. The resulting subjectivity structure is empirically developed from
linguistic indexical references which are used to map processes with which a person receives
experience and intersubjectively shares it. Experience and thinking are shown to be entwined in
a stream of experience by an internal reflexivity of first-person perspective which constitutes a
person and a corresponding system of I-strands. Experience is tied to a doxastic matrix, mind in
an other vocabulary, in a relation that integrates an experience-thinking episode to the accretions
of past experiences and beliefs which prepares for continuing thinking and action. It is proposed
that a noumenal I outside the world constructs the world from internal experience to counter
Cartesian radical doubt which makes the sensory world uncertain and in which only one’s
experience is reliably one’s own.
Keywords: subjectivity, first-person perspective, indexical referents, doxastic pedestal, I-strands,
reflexivity, self-consciousness
Keywords: subjectivity, first-person perspective, indexical referents, doxastic pedestal, I-strands,
There is a gap between the first-person and third-person perspectives resulting in a tension experienced between psychological science, ‘experimental psychology’, and applied consulting psychological practice, ‘clinical psychology’. This is an exploration of that ‘gap’ and its resulting tension. First-person perspective is proposed as an important aspect of psychological reality in conjunction with the related perspectival aspects of second- and third-person perspectives. These three aspects taken ‘wholistically’ constitute a perspectival diffusion grate through which psychological reality is discerned. The reductionistic naturalism of scientifically apprehended reality is examined for the powerful resistances that impedite utilizing perspective in psychological investigations with consequences for our understanding of psychological reality. The impediments constructed by Quine, Sellars, Dennett, Metzinger, and cognitive psychology are all examined for their robust intractability to first-person perspective or anything that might seem similar. The conclusion suggested is that they all result from a ‘scientific near-sightedness’ of a strict naturalism. The result is that any intentionally dependent objects that are real in the lives of persons are eliminated as not real with no ontological significance. The assertion is that ordinary things such as car keys and employment are real and are ontologically significant.
A routine supports a privacy that, in turn, supports focused reflective thinking cycle in the context of a shared we-relation of a marriage, that if satisfactory, can continue for an extended time. It provides both an experiential base for an outward-directed meaning to one’s life, and subjective inward-directed experiences that is one’s inward unfolding and growth of knowledge and concurrent range of affect, perceptual sensitivities, rationality, imagination, general ability, and ethical openness of one’s subjective breadth and depth being.
eBook 74,89 € | £63.99 | $84.99 74,89 € (D) | 74,89 € (A) | CHF [2] 85,00 Available from your library or springer.com/shop MyCopy [3]
Duus, R. (2020). Constituting Selves: Psychology’s Pragmatic Horizon. Switzerland AG: Springer Nature. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/978–3–030–39017–4
tension experienced between psychological science, ‘experimental psychology,’
and applied consulting psychological practice, ‘clinical psychology.’ This is an
exploration of that ‘gap’ and its resulting tension. First-person perspective is
proposed as an important aspect of psychological reality in conjunction with the
related perspectival aspects of second- and third-person perspectives. These 3
aspects taken ‘wholistically’ constitute a perspectival diffusion grate through which
psychological reality is discerned. The reductionistic naturalism of scientifically
apprehended reality is examined for the powerful resistances that impedite utilizing
perspective in psychological investigations with consequences for our understanding
of psychological reality. The impediments constructed by Quine, Sellars,
Dennett, Metzinger, and cognitive psychology are all examined for their robust
intractability to first-person perspective or anything that might seem similar. The
conclusion suggested is that they all result from a ‘scientific near-sightedness’ of a
strict naturalism. The result is that any intentionally dependent objects that are real
in the lives of persons are eliminated as not real with no ontological significance.
The assertion is that ordinary things such as car keys and employment are real and
are ontologically significant.
Keywords: first-person, hard naturalism, liberal naturalism, personhood, third-person
with The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (1999), and
further developed by Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (2003). These books
are meant to be accessible to the general public, but are also useful to those professionals and
researchers, who are not neuroscientists, seeking a review of recent neuroscientific empirical
developments and thinking concerning self and consciousness. These books summarizing one person's
effort to capture the complex phenomena of self, consciousness and mind totally within the
neurological processes of the central nervous system take their place in a large corpus of literature
concerning self that is complex and sometimes difficult. “Few ideas are as weighty and as slippery as
the notion of self,” to borrow Jerrold Seigel’s apt characterization in the introduction to his account of
the western intellectual discussion of its varied and changing ideas of self, The Idea of the Self (Seigel,
2005, p. 3).
members jointly engage a shared project second-person engagement is joined. The purpose of this
paper is to present an account of intersubjective space as second-person perspective. A joint
engagement of a project by members of a community, that could be a simple conversation, gives rise
to a unitary we-relation that is a second-person engagement. The structure of second-person
encounter is described by four properties of an interdefinable circle that consists of the
authority to confront an other person of one’s community with a claim of a transgression which
becomes a practical reason for the person confronted to direct their conduct for which she is
unconditionally responsible. Direct first-person experience of a we-relation is the empathic
connection of a unitary property of a second-person engagement while reactive attitudes are the
emotional context of moral conduct. Second-person engagement is inherently moral that derives from
the properties of the interdefinable circle and the social infrastructure of the community an
engagement is embedded. Moral autonomy derives from the imperative nature of the principles
derived from a social infrastructure. Such a principle can be recognized as a categorical
imperative. Conduct is moral and responsible only if autonomous.
Keywords: intersubjectivity, we-experience, morality, second-person stand, practical
reasons, autonomy, reactive attitudes
subsequently, undeveloped. Subjectivity processes include evolving experience episodes and its
unifying thinking core. This inquiry presented in this paper targeted the structure of experience,
its relation to an I, its relation to thinking, and its intersubjective nature. A proposed outline of
the processes of subjectivity are presented derived from William James, Hector Neri Castañeda,
and Lynne Rudder Baker. The resulting subjectivity structure is empirically developed from
linguistic indexical references which are used to map processes with which a person receives
experience and intersubjectively shares it. Experience and thinking are shown to be entwined in
a stream of experience by an internal reflexivity of first-person perspective which constitutes a
person and a corresponding system of I-strands. Experience is tied to a doxastic matrix, mind in
an other vocabulary, in a relation that integrates an experience-thinking episode to the accretions
of past experiences and beliefs which prepares for continuing thinking and action. It is proposed
that a noumenal I outside the world constructs the world from internal experience to counter
Cartesian radical doubt which makes the sensory world uncertain and in which only one’s
experience is reliably one’s own.
Keywords: subjectivity, first-person perspective, indexical referents, doxastic pedestal, I-strands,
reflexivity, self-consciousness
Keywords: subjectivity, first-person perspective, indexical referents, doxastic pedestal, I-strands,
There is a gap between the first-person and third-person perspectives resulting in a tension experienced between psychological science, ‘experimental psychology’, and applied consulting psychological practice, ‘clinical psychology’. This is an exploration of that ‘gap’ and its resulting tension. First-person perspective is proposed as an important aspect of psychological reality in conjunction with the related perspectival aspects of second- and third-person perspectives. These three aspects taken ‘wholistically’ constitute a perspectival diffusion grate through which psychological reality is discerned. The reductionistic naturalism of scientifically apprehended reality is examined for the powerful resistances that impedite utilizing perspective in psychological investigations with consequences for our understanding of psychological reality. The impediments constructed by Quine, Sellars, Dennett, Metzinger, and cognitive psychology are all examined for their robust intractability to first-person perspective or anything that might seem similar. The conclusion suggested is that they all result from a ‘scientific near-sightedness’ of a strict naturalism. The result is that any intentionally dependent objects that are real in the lives of persons are eliminated as not real with no ontological significance. The assertion is that ordinary things such as car keys and employment are real and are ontologically significant.