History of gravitational theory: Difference between revisions
→Aristotle: Anaxagoras, Empedocles |
m brackets fixed |
||
(28 intermediate revisions by 13 users not shown) | |||
Line 17: | Line 17: | ||
In [[physics]], theories of [[gravitation]] postulate mechanisms of interaction governing the movements of bodies with mass. There have been numerous theories of gravitation since ancient times. The first extant sources discussing such theories are found in [[ancient Greek philosophy]]. This work was furthered through the [[Science in the Middle Ages|Middle Ages]] by [[History of science and technology in the Indian subcontinent|Indian]], [[Physics in the medieval Islamic world|Islamic]], and [[European science in the Middle Ages|European scientists]], before gaining great strides [[History of science in the Renaissance|during the Renaissance]] and [[Scientific Revolution]]—culminating in the formulation of [[Newton's law of gravity]]. This was superseded by [[Albert Einstein]]'s [[theory of relativity]] in the early 20th century. |
In [[physics]], theories of [[gravitation]] postulate mechanisms of interaction governing the movements of bodies with mass. There have been numerous theories of gravitation since ancient times. The first extant sources discussing such theories are found in [[ancient Greek philosophy]]. This work was furthered through the [[Science in the Middle Ages|Middle Ages]] by [[History of science and technology in the Indian subcontinent|Indian]], [[Physics in the medieval Islamic world|Islamic]], and [[European science in the Middle Ages|European scientists]], before gaining great strides [[History of science in the Renaissance|during the Renaissance]] and [[Scientific Revolution]]—culminating in the formulation of [[Newton's law of gravity]]. This was superseded by [[Albert Einstein]]'s [[theory of relativity]] in the early 20th century. |
||
Greek philosopher [[Aristotle]] ({{fl.|4th century |
Greek philosopher [[Aristotle]] ({{fl.|4th century BC}}) found that objects immersed in a medium tend to fall at speeds proportional to their weight. [[Vitruvius]] ({{Floruit|1st century BC|lk=no}}) understood that objects fall based on their [[specific gravity]]. In the 6th century AD, Byzantine [[Alexandria]]n scholar [[John Philoponus]] modified the [[Aristotelian physics#Natural place|Aristotelian concept of gravity]] with the [[theory of impetus]]. In the 7th century, Indian astronomer [[Brahmagupta]] spoke of gravity as an attractive force. In the 14th century, European philosophers [[Jean Buridan]] and [[Albert of Saxony (philosopher)|Albert of Saxony]]—who were influenced by Islamic scholars such as [[Ibn Sina]] and [[Abu'l-Barakat]] respectively<ref name="Sayili1987" /><ref name="Gutman2003" />—developed the theory of impetus and linked it to the acceleration and mass of objects. Albert also developed a law of proportion regarding the relationship between the speed of an object in [[free fall]] and the time elapsed. |
||
Italians of the 16th century found that objects in free fall tend to accelerate equally. In 1632, [[Galileo Galilei]] put forth [[Galilean invariance|the basic principle of relativity]]. The existence of the [[gravitational constant]] was explored by various researchers from the mid-17th century, helping [[Isaac Newton]] formulate his law of universal gravitation. Newton's [[classical mechanics]] were superseded in the early 20th century, when Einstein developed the [[Special relativity|special]] and [[General relativity|general]] theories of relativity. An elemental [[Graviton|force carrier of gravity]] is hypothesized in [[quantum gravity]] approaches such as [[string theory]], in a potentially unified [[theory of everything]]. |
Italians of the 16th century found that objects in free fall tend to accelerate equally. In 1632, [[Galileo Galilei]] put forth [[Galilean invariance|the basic principle of relativity]]. The existence of the [[gravitational constant]] was explored by various researchers from the mid-17th century, helping [[Isaac Newton]] formulate his law of universal gravitation. Newton's [[classical mechanics]] were superseded in the early 20th century, when Einstein developed the [[Special relativity|special]] and [[General relativity|general]] theories of relativity. An elemental [[Graviton|force carrier of gravity]] is hypothesized in [[quantum gravity]] approaches such as [[string theory]], in a potentially unified [[theory of everything]]. |
||
==Antiquity== |
== Antiquity == |
||
{{See also|Archimedes' principle|Aristotelian physics|Epicureanism|Principle of inertia}} |
{{See also|Archimedes' principle|Aristotelian physics|Epicureanism|Principle of inertia}} |
||
=== Classical antiquity === |
=== Classical antiquity === |
||
==== Heraclitus, Anaxagoras, Empedocles and Leucippus ==== |
==== Heraclitus, Anaxagoras, Empedocles and Leucippus ==== |
||
[[File:Ca' Rezzonico - Eraclito 1705 - Giuseppe Torretti (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright|Heraclitus]] |
[[File:Ca' Rezzonico - Eraclito 1705 - Giuseppe Torretti (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright|Heraclitus]] |
||
[[File:Leucippus. |
[[File:Leucippus. Line engraving by S. Beyssent after Mlle C. Reyde Wellcome V0003528.jpg|alt=A line engraving of Leucippus|thumb|Leucippus|upright=1.2]] |
||
The [[ |
The [[pre-Socratic]] Greek philosopher [[Heraclitus]] ({{circa|535|475 BC}}) of the [[Ionian School (philosophy)|Ionian School]] used the word ''[[logos]]'' ('word') to describe a kind of law which keeps the [[cosmos]] in harmony, moving all objects, including the stars, winds, and waves.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Smith |first=Homer W. |author-link=Homer W. Smith |url=https://archive.org/details/manhisgods00smit |title=Man and His Gods |publisher=[[Grosset & Dunlap]] |year=1952 |location=New York |page=[https://archive.org/details/manhisgods00smit/page/144 144] |url-access=registration}}</ref> [[Anaxagoras]] ({{circa|500|428 BC|lk=no}}), another Ionian philosopher, introduced the concept of ''[[nous]]'' ('[[Cosmos|cosmic]] mind') as an ordering force.<ref>{{Cite IEP|url-id=anaxagoras|title=Anaxagoras (c.500—428 B.C.E.)|first=Michael|last=Patzia}}</ref> |
||
In the |
In the cosmogony of the Greek philosopher [[Empedocles]] ({{circa|494|434/443 BC|lk=no}}), there were two opposing [[Fundamental forces|fundamental cosmic forces]] of "attraction" and "repulsion", which Empedocles personified as "[[Love]]" and "Strife" (''[[Philotes]]'' and ''[[Neikea|Neikos]]'').<ref>{{Cite IEP|url-id=empedocles|title=Empedocles (c. 492—432 B.C.E.)|first=Gordon|last=Campbell}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Preston |first=David |year=2020 |title=Empedocles' Big Break: Pre-Socratic Cosmology and The Big Bounce |url=https://ojs.bibl.u-szeged.hu/index.php/suc/article/view/34717 |journal=Sapiens Ubique Civis |volume=1 |pages=11–28 |doi=10.14232/suc.2020.1.11-28 |issn=2786-2984 |quote=Empedocles also posits two opposing forces in an eternal tug-of-war as the energy which causes the roots to move about in the first place. These are 'Love' (also referred to as Aphrodite, Cypris, or Harmony) and 'Strife' (also referred to as Anger, Wrath, or Discord), the former named so for its unifying nature, the latter for its destructive. Under the influence of Love, the roots are ‘glued’ and ‘fitted’ together, while under Strife they are torn apart. To equate this to something more relatable, here we might think about the roles of gravity and dark energy in modern physical cosmology.}}</ref> |
||
The ancient |
The ancient atomist [[Leucippus]] (5th century BC) proposed the cosmos was created when a large group of [[atom]]s came together and swirled as a [[vortex]]. The smaller atoms became the celestial bodies of the cosmos. The larger atoms in the center came together as a membrane from which the [[Earth]] was formed.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Furley |first=David |url=https://archive.org/details/greekcosmologist0001furl |title=The Greek Cosmologists: Volume 1, The Formation of the Atomic Theory and its Earliest Critics |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1987 |isbn=0-521-33328-8 |pages=140–141 |doi=10.1017/CBO9780511552540 |url-access=registration}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=McKirahan |first=Richard D. |author-link=Richard McKirahan |url=https://archive.org/details/philosophybefore00mcki |title=Philosophy Before Socrates |publisher=Hackett |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-60384-182-5 |edition=2nd |pages=411–412 |orig-date=1994 |url-access=registration}}</ref> |
||
==== Aristotle ==== |
==== Aristotle ==== |
||
[[File:Statue at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki (cropped).jpg|left|thumb|upright|Aristotle]] |
[[File:Statue at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki (cropped).jpg|left|thumb|upright|Aristotle]] |
||
[[File:Aristotle's laws of motion.svg|thumb|upright=1. |
[[File:Aristotle's laws of motion.svg|thumb|upright=1.2|Aristotle found that objects immersed in a medium tend to fall at speeds proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the medium.<ref name="Relativity of Gravity">{{Cite web |title=Aristotle's Theory of Free-Fall |url=https://relativityofgravity.com/part1-b/ |access-date=2023-06-09 |website=Relativity of Gravity}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Drabkin |first=Israel E. |year=1938 |title=Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle |journal=The American Journal of Philology |volume=59 |issue=1 |pages=60–84 |jstor=90584}}</ref><ref name="Rovelli2015">{{Cite journal |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |year=2015 |title=Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look |journal=Journal of the American Philosophical Association |volume=1 |issue=1 |pages=23–40 |arxiv=1312.4057 |doi=10.1017/apa.2014.11 |issn=2053-4477 |s2cid=44193681}}</ref>]] |
||
In the 4th century |
In the 4th century BC, Greek philosopher Aristotle taught that there is no [[Causality|effect]] or [[motion]] without a cause. The cause of the downward natural motion of heavy bodies, such as the [[classical element]]s of [[earth (classical element)|earth]] and [[Water (classical element)|water]], was related to their [[Nature (philosophy)|nature]] (''gravity''), which caused them to move downward toward the center of the ([[geocentric]]) universe. For this reason Aristotle supported a [[spherical Earth]], since "every portion of earth has weight until it reaches the centre, and the jostling of parts greater and smaller would bring about not a waved surface, but rather compression and convergence of part and part until the centre is reached".<ref>{{Cite web |title=On the Heavens by Aristotle, Book 2, Part 14 |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/heavens.2.ii.html |access-date=2023-08-23 |website=classics.mit.edu |publisher=MIT |via=The Internet Classics Archive}}</ref> On the other hand, light bodies such as the element [[Fire (classical element)|fire]] and [[Air (classical element)|air]], were moved by their nature (''levity'') upward toward the [[Celestial spheres|celestial sphere]] of the [[Moon]] (see [[sublunary sphere]]). [[Astronomical object]]s near the [[fixed stars]] are composed of [[Aether (classical element)|aether]], whose natural motion is circular. Beyond them is the [[Unmoved mover|prime mover]], the [[final cause]] of all motion in the cosmos.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Grant |first=Edward |url=http://archive.org/details/foundationsofmod0000gran |title=The foundations of modern science in the Middle Ages: their religious, institutional, and intellectual contexts |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1996 |isbn=978-0-521-56137-2 |pages=60–61 |via=the Internet Archive}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Pedersen |first=Olaf |url=http://archive.org/details/earlyphysicsastr0000pede |title=Early physics and astronomy: a historical introduction |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1993 |isbn=978-0-521-40340-5 |page=130 |via=the Internet Archive}}</ref> In his ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'', Aristotle correctly asserted that objects immersed in a medium tend to fall at speeds proportional to their [[weight]] and inversely proportional to the [[density]] of the medium.<ref name="Relativity of Gravity" /><ref name="Rovelli2015" /> |
||
==== Strato of Lampsacus, Epicurus and Aristarchus of Samos ==== |
==== Strato of Lampsacus, Epicurus and Aristarchus of Samos ==== |
||
Greek philosopher [[Strato of Lampsacus]] ( |
Greek philosopher [[Strato of Lampsacus]] ({{circa|335|269 BC|lk=no}}) rejected the Aristotelian belief of "natural places" in exchange for a [[Mechanism (philosophy)|mechanical]] view in which objects do not gain [[weight]] as they fall, instead arguing that the greater impact was due to an increase in speed.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Carrier |first=Richard |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Qu07DwAAQBAJ&q=For+example%2C+in+his+lost+books+On+Lightness+and+Heaviness+and+On+Motion%2C+Strato+abandoned+the+doctrine+of+%27natural+places%27+in+exchange+for+a+more+mechanical+view+of+why+some+objects+rise+and+others+fall&pg=PT142 |title=The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire |publisher=Pitchstone |year=2017 |isbn=978-1-63431-107-6 |location=United States and Canada |page=333 |quote=For example, in his lost books On Lightness and Heaviness and On Motion, Strato abandoned the doctrine of 'natural places' in exchange for a more mechanical view of why some objects rise and others fall}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Fortenbaugh |first=William |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=N8s3DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA103 |title=Strato of Lampsacus: Text, Translation and Discussion |publisher=Routledge |year=2017 |isbn=978-1-351-48792-4 |quote=If someone drops a rock [from] a finger's height above the ground, it certainly won't make a visible impact on the ground, but if someone drops it holding it a hundred feet or more, it will have a strong impact. And there is no other reason for that impact. Because it does not have greater weight, nor is it impelled by greater force; but it moves faster.}}</ref> |
||
[[Epicurus]] ( |
[[Epicurus]] ({{circa|341|lk=no}}{{snd}}270 BC) viewed weight as an inherent property of [[atom]]s which influences their movement.<ref>{{Cite journal |year=2015 |title=Weight in Greek Atomism |url=https://philarchive.org/archive/AUGWIG-3 |journal=[[Philosophia]] |volume=45 |pages=85}}</ref> These atoms move downward in constant [[free fall]] within an infinite vacuum without [[friction]] at equal speed, regardless of their mass. On the other hand, upward motion is due to [[Collision theory|atomic collisions]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Laertius |first=Diogenes |title=Letter of Epicurus to Herodotus, (61) |url=https://www.attalus.org/old/diogenes10b.html |access-date=2024-02-26 |website=Attalus}}</ref> [[Epicureans]] deviated from older [[atomist]] theories like that of [[Democritus]] ({{circa|460|370 BC|lk=no}}) by proposing the idea that atoms may randomly deviate from their expected course.<ref>{{Citation |last=Berryman |first=Sylvia |title=Ancient Atomism |year=2022 |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |editor-last2=Nodelman |editor-first2=Uri |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/atomism-ancient/ |access-date=2024-02-11 |edition=Winter 2022 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}</ref> |
||
Greek astronomer [[Aristarchus of Samos]] ( |
Greek astronomer [[Aristarchus of Samos]] ({{circa|310|230 BC|lk=no}}) theorized [[Earth's rotation]] around its own axis, as well as [[Earth's orbit]] around the [[Sun]] in a [[heliocentric]] cosmology.<ref name="perseus.tufts.edu">{{Cite web |title=Plutarch, Platonicae quaestiones, Question VIII, section 1 |url=http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:2008.01.0384:chapter=8:section=1 |access-date=2023-08-27 |website=perseus.tufts.edu}}</ref> [[Seleucus of Seleucia]] ({{circa|190|150 BC|lk=no}}) supported his cosmology<ref name="perseus.tufts.edu" /> and also described [[Gravitation of the Moon|gravitational effects of the Moon]] on the [[tidal range]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Strabo |author-link=Strabo |title=Geography — III, 5, 9. |url=https://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/E/Roman/Texts/Strabo/3E*.html |access-date=2023-08-27 |website=penelope.uchicago.edu |publisher=University of Chicago}}</ref> |
||
==== Archimedes ==== |
==== Archimedes ==== |
||
The 3rd-century |
The 3rd-century BC Greek physicist [[Archimedes]] ({{circa|287|212 BC|lk=no}}}) discovered the [[centre of mass]] of a triangle.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Neitz |first=Reviel |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZC1MOaAkKnsC&pg=PT125 |title=The Archimedes Codex: Revealing The Secrets Of The World's Greatest Palimpsest |last2=Noel |first2=William |publisher=Hachette |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-78022-198-4}}</ref> He also postulated that if the [[Centre of gravity|centres of gravity]] of two equal weights was not the same, it would be located in the middle of the line that joins them.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Tuplin |first=C. J. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ajGkvOo0egwC&q=ancient+greeks+gravity&pg=PR11 |title=Science and Mathematics in Ancient Greek Culture |last2=Wolpert |first2=Lewis |publisher=Hachette |year=2002 |isbn=978-0-19-815248-4 |page=xi}}</ref> In ''[[On Floating Bodies]]'', Archimedes claimed that for any object submerged in a fluid there is an equivalent upward [[buoyant force]] to the weight of the fluid displaced by the object's volume.<ref>{{Cite web |year=1897 |title=The works of Archimedes |url=https://archive.org/stream/worksofarchimede00arch#page/256/mode/2up |publisher=Cambridge University Press |page=257 |quote=Any solid lighter than a fluid will, if placed in the fluid, be so far immersed that the weight of the solid will be equal to the weight of the fluid displaced.}}</ref> The fluids described by Archimedes are not self-gravitating, since he assumes that "any fluid at rest is the surface of a sphere whose centre is the same as that of the Earth".<ref>{{Cite book |url=https://archive.org/stream/worksofarchimede00arch#page/254/mode/2up |title=The works of Archimedes |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1897 |page=254 |translator-last=Heath |translator-first=T. L. |access-date=13 November 2017 |translator-link=Thomas L. Heath}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Ceccarelli |first=Marco |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UmBnVMA5ri4C&pg=PA13 |title=Distinguished Figures in Mechanism and Machine Science: Their Contributions and Legacies |publisher=Springer |year=2007 |isbn=978-1-4020-6366-4 |page=13}}</ref> |
||
==== Hipparchus of Nicaea, Lucretius and Vitruvius ==== |
==== Hipparchus of Nicaea, Lucretius and Vitruvius ==== |
||
Greek astronomer [[Hipparchus of Nicaea]] ( |
Greek astronomer [[Hipparchus of Nicaea]] ({{circa|190|120 BC|lk=no}}) also rejected [[Aristotelian physics]] and followed Strato in adopting some form of [[theory of impetus]] to explain motion.<ref>{{Cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YAEsAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA87 |title=Simplicius: On Aristotle On the Heavens 1.5-9 |publisher=Bloomsbury |year=2014 |isbn=978-1-4725-0111-0 |editor-last=Sorabji |editor-first=Richard |page=87 |translator-last=Hankinson |translator-first=R. J.}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Carrier |first=Richard |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Qu07DwAAQBAJ&q=Hipparchus+rejected+the+Aristotlian+physics+of+motion+and+followed+Strato+in+embracing+an+early+impetus+theory |title=The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire |publisher=Pitchstone |year=2017 |isbn=978-1-63431-107-6 |quote=Hipparchus rejected the Aristotlian physics of motion and followed Strato in embracing an early impetus theory}}</ref> The poem ''{{lang|la|[[De rerum natura]]}}'' by [[Lucretius]] ({{circa|99|55 BC|lk=no}}}) asserts that more massive bodies fall faster in a medium because the latter resists less, but in a [[vacuum]] fall with equal speed.<ref>{{Cite web |editor-last=Leonard |editor-first=William Ellery |title=Lucretius, De Rerum Natura, BOOK II, line 216 |url=http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:1999.02.0131:book=2:card=216 |access-date=2023-08-20 |website=[[Perseus Digital Library]] |via=[[Tufts University]]}}</ref> Roman engineer and architect [[Vitruvius]] ({{circa|85|15 BC|lk=no}}) contends in his ''{{lang|la|[[De architectura]]}}'' that gravity is not dependent on a substance's weight but rather on its 'nature' ({{cf.}}[[specific gravity]]): |
||
<blockquote>If the [[Mercury (element)|quicksilver]] is poured into a vessel, and a stone weighing one hundred pounds is laid upon it, the stone swims on the surface, and cannot depress the liquid, nor break through, nor separate it. If we remove the hundred pound weight, and put on a scruple of gold, it will not swim, but will sink to the bottom of its own accord. Hence, it is undeniable that the gravity of a substance depends not on the amount of its weight, but on its nature.<ref> |
<blockquote>If the [[Mercury (element)|quicksilver]] is poured into a vessel, and a stone weighing one hundred pounds is laid upon it, the stone swims on the surface, and cannot depress the liquid, nor break through, nor separate it. If we remove the hundred pound weight, and put on a scruple of gold, it will not swim, but will sink to the bottom of its own accord. Hence, it is undeniable that the gravity of a substance depends not on the amount of its weight, but on its nature.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Vitruvius |first=Marcus Pollio |author-link=Marcus Vitruvius Pollio |title=De Architectura libri decem |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=1914 |editor-last=Howard |editor-first=Alfred A. |location=Cambridge, MA |page=215 |trans-title=Ten Books on Architecture |chapter=VII |chapter-url=http://www.gutenberg.org/files/20239/20239-h/29239-h.htm#Page_215 |lang=la}}</ref><ref>For another English translation see:{{Cite book |url=https://archive.org/details/bim_eighteenth-century_de-architectura-englis_vitruvius_1791_2/page/168/mode/2up |title=The architecture of M. Vitruvius Pollio |year=1791 |volume=2 |page=168}}</ref> (translated from the original Latin by W. Newton)</blockquote> |
||
{{Cite book |last=Vitruvius |first=Marcus Pollio |title=De Architectura libri decem |date=1914 |publisher=Harvard University Press |others=Herbert Langford Warren, Nelson Robinson (illus), Morris Hicky Morgan |editor=Howard |editor-first=Alfred A. |place=Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts |page=215 |language=en-us |trans-title=Ten Books on Architecture |chapter=VII |author-link=Marcus Vitruvius Pollio |chapter-url=http://www.gutenberg.org/files/20239/20239-h/29239-h.htm#Page_215}}</ref><ref>For another English translation see:{{cite book | url = https://archive.org/details/bim_eighteenth-century_de-architectura-englis_vitruvius_1791_2/page/168/mode/2up | title = The architecture of M. Vitruvius Pollio: translated from the original Latin by W. Newton | page = 168 | volume = 2 | year = 1791}}</ref></blockquote> |
|||
==== Plutarch, Pliny the Elder, and Claudius Ptolemy ==== |
==== Plutarch, Pliny the Elder, and Claudius Ptolemy ==== |
||
[[File:Pliny the Elder, Loggia del Consiglio, Piazza dei Signori, Verona (37520060770) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Pliny the Elder]] |
[[File:Pliny the Elder, Loggia del Consiglio, Piazza dei Signori, Verona (37520060770) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Pliny the Elder]] |
||
Greek philosopher [[Plutarch]] ({{ |
Greek philosopher [[Plutarch]] ({{circa|46|120 AD|lk=no}}) attested the existence of Roman astronomers who rejected Aristotelian physics, "even contemplating theories of [[inertia]] and [[universal gravitation]]",<ref>{{Cite book |last=Carrier |first=Richard |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Qu07DwAAQBAJ&dq=Plutarch+also+attests+to+the+existence+of+Roman+philosophers+and+astronomers+who+rejected+Aristotelian+dynamics+and+were+engaging+sophisticated+debates+on+the+subject%2C+even+contemplating+theories+of+inertia+and+universal+gravitation&pg=PT185 |title=The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire |publisher=Pitchstone |year=2017 |isbn=978-1-63431-107-6 |quote=Plutarch also attests to the existence of Roman philosophers and astronomers who rejected Aristotelian dynamics and were engaging sophisticated debates on the subject, even contemplating theories of inertia and universal gravitation}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Taub |first=Liba Chaia |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4inhAAAAMAAJ |title=Aetna and the Moon: Explaining Nature in Ancient Greece and Rome |publisher=Oregon State University Press |year=2008 |isbn=978-0-87071-196-1}}</ref> and suggested that gravitational attraction was not unique to the Earth.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bakker |first=Frederik |last2=Palmerino |first2=Carla Rita |date=2020-06-01 |title=Motion to the Center or Motion to the Whole? Plutarch's Views on Gravity and Their Influence on Galileo |url=https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/709138 |journal=Isis |volume=111 |issue=2 |pages=217–238 |doi=10.1086/709138 |issn=0021-1753 |s2cid=219925047 |hdl-access=free |hdl=2066/219256}}</ref> The gravitational effects of the Moon on the tides were noticed by [[Pliny the Elder]] (23–79 AD) in his ''{{lang|la|[[Naturalis Historia]]}}''<ref>{{Cite book |last=Pliny the Elder |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=aVMMAAAAIAAJ&pg=PA128 |title=The Natural History of Pliny |publisher=H. G. Bohn |year=1893 |isbn=978-0-598-91073-8 |page=128}}</ref> and [[Claudius Ptolemy]] ({{circa|100|170 AD|lk=no}}) in his ''[[Tetrabiblos]]''.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Ptolemy |title=Tetrabiblos |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]] |year=1940 |volume=1 |location=Cambridge, MA |translator-last=Robbins |translator-first=Frank E. |chapter=2}}</ref> |
||
=== Byzantine era === |
=== Byzantine era === |
||
==== John Philoponus ==== |
==== John Philoponus ==== |
||
In the 6th century |
In the 6th century AD, the Byzantine [[Alexandria]]n scholar [[John Philoponus]] proposed the theory of impetus, which modifies Aristotle's theory that "continuation of motion depends on continued action of a force" by incorporating a causative force which diminishes over time. In his [[Commentaries on Aristotle|commentary on Aristotle's ''Physics'']] that "if one lets fall simultaneously from the same height two bodies differing greatly in weight, one will find that the ratio of the times of their motion does not correspond to the ratios of their weights, but the difference in time is a very small one".<ref>{{Cite web |title=John Philoponus |url=https://www.eoht.info/page/John%20Philoponus |access-date=2023-06-09 |website=eoht.info}}<!-- auto-translated by Module:CS1 translator --></ref> |
||
== Indian subcontinent == |
== Indian subcontinent == |
||
Line 71: | Line 69: | ||
=== Brahmagupta === |
=== Brahmagupta === |
||
[[File:Ujjain, Ram Ghat (9840921865).jpg|thumb|Ujjain, Ram Ghat, home to Brahmagupta and Bhaskaracharya]] |
[[File:Ujjain, Ram Ghat (9840921865).jpg|thumb|Ujjain, Ram Ghat, home to Brahmagupta and Bhaskaracharya]] |
||
[[Brahmagupta]] ( |
[[Brahmagupta]] ({{circa|598|668 AD|lk=no}}) was the first Indian scholar to describe gravity as an attractive force:<ref>{{Cite book |last=Pickover |first=Clifford |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SQXcpvjcJBUC&pg=PA105 |title=Archimedes to Hawking: Laws of Science and the Great Minds Behind Them |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2008 |isbn=978-0-19-979268-9 |page=105}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Bose |first=Mainak Kumar |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nbItAAAAMAAJ |title=Late classical India |publisher=A. Mukherjee & Company |year=1988}}{{page needed|date=March 2020}}</ref>{{failed verification|date=July 2024}}<ref>{{Cite book |last=Sen |first=Amartya |title=The Argumentative Indian |publisher=Allen Lane |year=2005 |isbn=978-0-7139-9687-6 |page=29}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Thurston |first=Hugh |title=Early Astronomy |publisher=Springer |year=1993 |isbn=978-0-387-94107-3 |location=New York}}{{page needed|date=March 2020}}</ref>{{failed verification|date=July 2024}} |
||
<blockquote>The earth on all its sides is the same; all people on the earth stand upright, and all heavy things fall down to the earth by a law of nature, for it is the nature of the earth to attract and to keep things, as it is the nature of water to flow ... If a thing wants to go deeper down than the earth, let it try. The earth is the only ''low'' thing, and seeds always return to it, in whatever direction you may throw them away, and never rise upwards from the earth.<ref name=" |
<blockquote>The earth on all its sides is the same; all people on the earth stand upright, and all heavy things fall down to the earth by a law of nature, for it is the nature of the earth to attract and to keep things, as it is the nature of water to flow ... If a thing wants to go deeper down than the earth, let it try. The earth is the only ''low'' thing, and seeds always return to it, in whatever direction you may throw them away, and never rise upwards from the earth.<ref name="Kegan Paul">{{Cite book |url=http://www.columbia.edu/cu/lweb/digital/collections/cul/texts/ldpd_5949073_001/pages/ldpd_5949073_001_00000328.html?toggle=image&menu=maximize&top=&left= |title=Alberuni's India |publisher=Kegan Paul |page=272 |access-date=3 June 2014}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |title=Kitāb al-Jawharatayn al-'atīqatayn al-mā'i'atayn min al-ṣafrā' wa-al-bayḍā': al-dhahab wa-al-fiḍḍah |publisher=Maṭba'at Dār al-Kutub wa-al-Wathā'iq al-Qawmīyah bi-al-Qāhirah |year=2004 |location=Cairo |pages=43–44, 87 |language=ar |script-title=ar:كتاب الجوهرتين العتيقتين المائعتين من الصفراء والبيضاء : الذهب والفضة |oclc=607846741}}</ref>{{efn|The source of this quote is ''[[Al-Biruni]]'s India'' ({{circa|1030|lk=no}}).<ref name="Kegan Paul" />}}</blockquote> |
||
=== |
=== Bhāskara II === |
||
[[Bhāskara II]] ({{circa|1114|1185|lk=no}}), another Indian mathematician and astronomer, describes gravity as an inherent attractive property of Earth in the section "{{tlitn|sa|Golādhyāyah}}" ("On Spherics") of his treatise {{tlit|sa|[[Siddhānta Shiromani]]}}: |
|||
<blockquote>The property of attraction is inherent in the Earth. By this property the Earth attracts any unsupported heavy thing towards it: The thing appears to be falling but it is in a state of being drawn to Earth. ... It is manifest from this that ... people situated at distances of a fourth part of the circumference [of earth] from us or in the opposite hemisphere, cannot by any means fall downwards [in space].<ref>{{Cite book | |
<blockquote>The property of attraction is inherent in the Earth. By this property the Earth attracts any unsupported heavy thing towards it: The thing appears to be falling but it is in a state of being drawn to Earth. ... It is manifest from this that ... people situated at distances of a fourth part of the circumference [of earth] from us or in the opposite hemisphere, cannot by any means fall downwards [in space].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Áryabhat́t́a |author-link=Aryabhata |url=https://archive.org/details/ancientsystemhi00wilkgoog/mode/1up |title=Súrya Siddhánta and Siddhánta Shiromańi |last2=Bháskarácárya |author-link2=Bhāskara II |publisher=C. B. Lewis, Baptist Mission Press |year=1150 |location=Calcutta |publication-date=1860 |page=113 |language=sa |translator-last=Deva Sástri |translator-first=Bápú |chapter=Chapter III ─ Called Bhuvana-kośa or Cosmograghy |orig-date=505, 1150 |translator-last2=Wilkinson |translator-first2=Lancelot |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/ancientsystemhi00wilkgoog/page/n24/mode/2up}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Bháskarácárya |author-link=Bhāskara II |url=https://ia804707.us.archive.org/31/items/in.ernet.dli.2015.340209/2015.340209.Goladhaya_text.pdf |title=Siddhánta Shiromańi: Goládhyáyah |year=1150 |location=Calcutta |language=sa |chapter=ভুবনকোষ}}</ref></blockquote> |
||
==Islamic world== |
== Islamic world == |
||
{{See also|Physics in the medieval Islamic world|Astronomy in the medieval Islamic world}} |
{{See also|Physics in the medieval Islamic world|Astronomy in the medieval Islamic world}} |
||
⚫ | |||
Ancient Greeks like [[Posidonius]] had associated the tides in the sea with to be influenced by moonlight. Around 850, [[Abu Ma'shar al-Balkhi]] recorded the tides and the moon position and noticed high-tides when the Moon was below the horizon. Abu Ma'shar considered an alternative explanation where the Moon and the sea had to share some astrological virtue that attracted each other. This work was translated into Latin and became one of the two main theories for tides for European scholars.<ref>{{Citation |last=Deparis |first=Vincent |title=Investigations of Tides from the Antiquity to Laplace |work=Tides in Astronomy and Astrophysics |volume=861 |pages=31–82 |year=2013 |editor-last=Souchay |editor-first=Jean |editor-last2=Mathis |editor-first2=Stéphane |editor-last3=Tokieda |editor-first3=Tadashi |location=Berlin |publisher=Springer |doi=10.1007/978-3-642-32961-6_2 |isbn=978-3-642-32960-9}}</ref> |
|||
=== Ibn Sina === |
=== Ibn Sina === |
||
[[File:1950 "Avicenna" stamp of Iran (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Ibn Sina]] |
[[File:1950 "Avicenna" stamp of Iran (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Ibn Sina]] |
||
In the 11th century |
In the 11th century, Persian polymath [[Ibn Sina]] (Avicenna) agreed with Philoponus' theory that "the moved object acquires an inclination from the mover" as an explanation for [[projectile motion]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=McGinnis |first=Jon |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=V9ITPVoGjsoC&pg=PA147 |title=Classical Arabic philosophy: an anthology of sources |last2=Reisman |first2=David C. |publisher=Hackett |year=2007 |isbn=978-0-87220-871-1 |page=174 |access-date=16 June 2010}}</ref> Ibn Sina then published [[Theory of impetus#Arabic theories|his own theory of impetus]] in ''[[The Book of Healing]]'' ({{circa|1020|lk=no}}). Unlike Philoponus, who believed that it was a temporary virtue that would decline even in a vacuum, Ibn Sina viewed it as a persistent, requiring external forces such as [[air resistance]] to dissipate it.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Espinoza |first=Fernando |year=2005 |title=An analysis of the historical development of ideas about motion and its implications for teaching |journal=Physics Education |volume=40 |issue=2 |page=141 |bibcode=2005PhyEd..40..139E |doi=10.1088/0031-9120/40/2/002 |s2cid=250809354}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Nasr |first=Seyyed Hossein |title=The Islamic intellectual tradition in Persia |last2=Mehdi Amin |first2=Razavi |publisher=Routledge |year=1996 |isbn=978-0-7007-0314-2 |page=72}}</ref><ref name="Sayili1987">{{Cite journal |last=Sayili |first=Aydin |author-link=Aydin Sayili |title=Ibn Sīnā and Buridan on the Motion of the Projectile |journal=Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences |volume=500 |issue=1 |pages=477–482 |bibcode=1987NYASA.500..477S |doi=10.1111/j.1749-6632.1987.tb37219.x |s2cid=84784804 |year=1987}}</ref> Ibn Sina made distinction between force and inclination ({{tlit|ar|mayl}}), and argued that an object gained inclination when the object is in opposition to its natural motion. He concluded that continuation of motion is attributed to the inclination that is transferred to the object, and that object will be in motion until the inclination is spent.<ref>Espinoza, Fernando. "An Analysis of the Historical Development of Ideas About Motion and its Implications for Teaching". Physics Education. Vol. 40 (2).</ref> The Iraqi polymath [[Ibn al-Haytham]] describes gravity as a force in which heavier body moves towards the centre of the earth. He also describes the force of gravity will only move towards the direction of the centre of the earth not in different directions.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Clagett |first=Marshall |url=https://archive.org/details/scienceofmechani0000unse/page/57/mode/1up |title=The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages |publisher=University of Wisconsin Press |year=1961 |volume=1 |page=58 |via=the Internet Archive |issue=58}}</ref> |
||
=== Al-Biruni === |
=== Al-Biruni === |
||
[[File:Persian Scholar pavilion in Vienna UN (Biruni) (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright|Al-Biruni]] |
[[File:Persian Scholar pavilion in Vienna UN (Biruni) (cropped)2.jpg|thumb|upright|Al-Biruni]] |
||
Another 11th-century Persian polymath, [[Al-Biruni]], proposed that [[ |
Another 11th-century Persian polymath, [[Al-Biruni]], proposed that [[heavenly bodies]] have [[mass]], weight, and gravity, just like the Earth. He criticized both Aristotle and Ibn Sina for holding the view that only the Earth has these properties.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Starr |first=S. Frederick |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hWyYDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA260 |title=Lost Enlightenment: Central Asia's Golden Age from the Arab Conquest to Tamerlane |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=2015 |isbn=978-0-691-16585-1 |page=260}}</ref> The 12th-century scholar [[Al-Khazini]] suggested that the gravity an object contains varies depending on its distance from the centre of the universe (referring to the centre of the Earth). Al-Biruni and Al-Khazini studied the theory of the centre of gravity, and generalized and applied it to three-dimensional bodies. Fine experimental methods were also developed for determining the specific gravity or [[specific weight]] of objects, based the theory of [[Balance (device for weighing)|balances]] and [[weighing]].<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia |year=1996 |title=Statics |encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science |publisher=Psychology Press |editor-last=Rushdī |editor-first=Rāshid |volume=2 |pages=614–642 |isbn=978-0-415-12411-9 |quote=Using a whole body of mathematical methods (not only those inherited from the antique theory of ratios and infinitesimal techniques, but also the methods of the contemporary algebra and fine calculation techniques), Muslim scientists raised statics to a new, higher level. The classical results of Archimedes in the theory of the centre of gravity were generalized and applied to three-dimensional bodies, the theory of ponderable lever was founded and the 'science of gravity' was created and later further developed in medieval Europe. The phenomena of statics were studied by using the dynamic approach so that two trends – statics and dynamics – turned out to be inter-related within a single science, mechanics. The combination of the dynamic approach with Archimedean hydrostatics gave birth to a direction in science which may be called medieval hydrodynamics. ... Numerous fine experimental methods were developed for determining the specific weight, which were based, in particular, on the theory of balances and weighing. The classical works of al-Biruni and al-Khazini can by right be considered as the beginning of the application of experimental methods in medieval science. |last2=Levinova |first2=I. S. |first1=Mariam |last1=Rozhanskaya}}</ref> |
||
=== Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī === |
=== Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī === |
||
In the 12th century, [[ |
In the 12th century, [[Ibn Malka al-Baghdadi]] adopted and modified Ibn Sina's theory on [[projectile motion]]. In his ''Kitab al-Mu'tabar'', Abu'l-Barakat stated that the mover imparts a violent inclination ({{tlit|ar|mayl qasri}}) on the moved and that this diminishes as the moving object distances itself from the mover.<ref name="Gutman2003" /> According to [[Shlomo Pines]], al-Baghdādī's theory of motion was "the oldest negation of Aristotle's fundamental dynamic law [namely, that a constant force produces a uniform motion], [and is thus an] anticipation in a vague fashion of the fundamental law of [[classical mechanics]] [namely, that a force applied continuously produces [[acceleration]]]."<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia |year=1970 |title=Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī, Hibat Allah |encyclopedia=[[Dictionary of Scientific Biography]] |publisher=Charles Scribner's Sons |location=New York |last=Pines |first=Shlomo |volume=1 |pages=26–28 |isbn=0-684-10114-9}} <br /> ([[cf.]] Abel B. Franco (October 2003). "Avempace, Projectile Motion, and Impetus Theory", ''Journal of the History of Ideas'' '''64''' (4), pp. 521–546 [528].)</ref> |
||
==European Renaissance== |
== European Renaissance == |
||
{{See also|Science in the Renaissance}} |
{{See also|Science in the Renaissance}} |
||
=== 14th century === |
=== 14th century === |
||
[[File: |
[[File:Démonstration de la gravité, Image du monde.jpg|link=[[:es:Archivo:Démonstration de la gravité, Image du monde]].jpg|thumb|A 14th century illustration from [[Gautier de Metz]]'s ''[[Gautier de Metz|L'Image du monde]]'' showing the gravitational attraction of the Earth at its [[antipodes]].]] |
||
==== Jean Buridan, the Oxford Calculators, Albert of Saxony ==== |
==== Jean Buridan, the Oxford Calculators, Albert of Saxony ==== |
||
In the 14th century, both the French philosopher [[Jean Buridan]] and the [[Oxford Calculators]] (the Merton School) of the [[Merton College]] of [[University of Oxford|Oxford]] rejected the [[Aristotelian physics#Natural place|Aristotelian concept of gravity]].{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}}{{efn|This was interpreted as deriving the weight of objects from the [[Atmospheric pressure|pressure of the air]] below them.{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}}}} They attributed the motion of objects to an impetus (akin to [[momentum]]), which varies according to velocity and mass;{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}} Buridan was influenced in this by Ibn Sina's ''Book of Healing''.<ref name=" |
In the 14th century, both the French philosopher [[Jean Buridan]] and the [[Oxford Calculators]] (the Merton School) of the [[Merton College]] of [[University of Oxford|Oxford]] rejected the [[Aristotelian physics#Natural place|Aristotelian concept of gravity]].{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}}{{efn|This was interpreted as deriving the weight of objects from the [[Atmospheric pressure|pressure of the air]] below them.{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}}}} They attributed the motion of objects to an impetus (akin to [[momentum]]), which varies according to velocity and mass;{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}} Buridan was influenced in this by Ibn Sina's ''Book of Healing''.<ref name="Sayili1987" /> Buridan and the philosopher [[Albert of Saxony (philosopher)|Albert of Saxony]] ({{circa|1320|1390|lk=no}}) adopted Abu'l-Barakat's theory that the acceleration of a falling body is a result of its increasing impetus.<ref name="Gutman2003">{{Cite book |last=Gutman |first=Oliver |title=Pseudo-Avicenna, Liber Celi Et Mundi: A Critical Edition |publisher=Brill |year=2003 |isbn=90-04-13228-7 |page=193}}</ref> Influenced by Buridan, Albert developed a law of proportion regarding the relationship between the speed of an object in [[free fall]] and the time elapsed.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Drake |first=Stillman |author-link=Stillman Drake |year=1975 |title=Free fall from Albert of Saxony to Honoré Fabri |url=https://www.academia.edu/7082532 |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A |volume=5 |issue=4 |pages=347–366 |bibcode=1975SHPSA...5..347D |doi=10.1016/0039-3681(75)90007-2 |issn=0039-3681 |via=[[Academia.edu]]}}</ref> He also theorized that mountains and valleys are caused by [[erosion]]{{efn|[[Leonardo da Vinci]] tested this theory by observing [[trace fossil]]s,<ref name="Knight2017" /> which he used to argue against the [[Flood myth|myth of a universal flood]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Da Vinci |first=Leonardo |title=The Notebooks of Leonardo da Vinci |publisher=New American Library |year=1971 |editor-last=Taylor |editor-first=Pamela |pages=136–138, 142–148}}</ref>}}—displacing the Earth's centre of gravity.<ref name="Knight2017">{{Cite web |last=Knight |first=Kevin |year=2017 |title=Albert of Saxony |url=http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/13504a.htm |access-date=10 July 2019 |website=New Advent}}</ref>{{efn|Furthermore, he hypothesized that the planet is in equilibrium when its centre of gravity coincides with that of its mass.<ref name="Knight2017" />}} |
||
==== Uniform and difform motion ==== |
==== Uniform and difform motion ==== |
||
The roots of Domingo de Soto's expression |
The roots of Domingo de Soto's expression {{lang|la|uniform difform}} motion [uniformly accelerated motion] lies in the Oxford Calculators terms "uniform" and "difform" motion:{{Sfn|Wallace|2004a|p=386}} "uniform motion" was used differently then than it would be by later writers, and might have referred both to constant speed and to motion in which all parts of a body are moving at equal speed. The Calculators did not illustrate the different types of motion with real-world examples.{{sfn|Wallace|2004a|p=386}} John of Holland at the University of Prague, illustrated uniform motion with what would later be called uniform velocity, but also with a falling stone (all parts moving at the same speed), and with a sphere in uniform rotation. He did, however, make distinctions between different kinds of "uniform" motion. Difform motion was exemplified by walking at increasing speed.{{sfn|Wallace|2004a|p=386}} |
||
==== Mean speed theorem ==== |
==== Mean speed theorem ==== |
||
{{Main|Mean speed theorem}}{{See also|Equations of motion#History}} |
{{Main|Mean speed theorem}}{{See also|Equations of motion#History}} |
||
[[File:First page of the book "Traité de l'espère" containing a miniature portraying Nicole Oresme (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright|Nicole Oresme]] |
[[File:First page of the book "Traité de l'espère" containing a miniature portraying Nicole Oresme (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright|Nicole Oresme]] |
||
Also in the 14th century, the Merton School developed the [[mean speed theorem]]; a uniformly accelerated body starting from rest travels the same distance as a body with [[Speed|uniform speed]] whose speed is half the final velocity of the accelerated body. The mean speed theorem was proved by [[Nicole Oresme]] ( |
Also in the 14th century, the Merton School developed the [[mean speed theorem]]; a uniformly accelerated body starting from rest travels the same distance as a body with [[Speed|uniform speed]] whose speed is half the final velocity of the accelerated body. The mean speed theorem was proved by [[Nicole Oresme]] ({{circa|1323|lk=no}}{{snd}}1382) and would be influential in later [[Equations for a falling body|gravitational equations]].{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}} Written as a modern equation: |
||
<math>\ s=\frac{1}{2}v_ft </math> |
<math>\ s=\frac{1}{2}v_ft </math> |
||
Line 115: | Line 115: | ||
However, since small time intervals could not be measured, the relationship between time and distance was not so evident as the equation suggests. More generally; equations, which were not widely used until after Galileo's time, imply a clarity that was not there. |
However, since small time intervals could not be measured, the relationship between time and distance was not so evident as the equation suggests. More generally; equations, which were not widely used until after Galileo's time, imply a clarity that was not there. |
||
=== 15th–17th |
=== 15th–17th centuries === |
||
==== Leonardo da Vinci ==== |
==== Leonardo da Vinci ==== |
||
[[File:Statue of Leonardo da Vinci (Uffizi) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Leonardo da Vinci]] |
[[File:Statue of Leonardo da Vinci (Uffizi) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Leonardo da Vinci]] |
||
[[Leonardo da Vinci]] (1452–1519) made drawings recording the acceleration of falling objects.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Ouellette |first=Jennifer |date=2023-02-10 |title=Leonardo noted link between gravity and acceleration centuries before Einstein |url=https://arstechnica.com/science/2023/02/leonardo-noted-link-between-gravity-and-acceleration-centuries-before-einstein/ |access-date=2023-02-11 |website=[[Ars Technica]] |
[[Leonardo da Vinci]] (1452–1519) made drawings recording the acceleration of falling objects.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Ouellette |first=Jennifer |date=2023-02-10 |title=Leonardo noted link between gravity and acceleration centuries before Einstein |url=https://arstechnica.com/science/2023/02/leonardo-noted-link-between-gravity-and-acceleration-centuries-before-einstein/ |access-date=2023-02-11 |website=[[Ars Technica]]}}</ref> He wrote that the "mother and origin of gravity" is [[kinetic energy|energy]]. He describes two pairs of physical powers which stem from a [[metaphysical]] origin and have an effect on everything: [[potential energy|abundance of force]] and motion, and gravity and resistance. He associates gravity with the 'cold' [[classical element]]s, [[Water (classical element)|water]] and earth, and calls its energy infinite.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Da Vinci |first=Leonardo |title=The Notebooks of Leonardo da Vinci |publisher=New American Library |year=1971 |editor-last=Taylor |editor-first=Pamela |page=124 |quote=Force arises from dearth or abundance; it is the child of physical motion, and the grandchild of spiritual motion, and the mother and origin of gravity. Gravity is limited to the elements of water and earth; but his force is unlimited, and by it infinite worlds might be moved if instruments could be made by which the force be generated.<br />Force, with physical motion, and gravity, with resistance, are the four external powers on which all actions of mortals depend.}}</ref>{{efn|Leonardo did not publish his manuscripts and they had no direct influence on subsequent science.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Capra |first=Fritjof |author-link=Fritjof Capra |url=https://archive.org/details/scienceofleonard00capr/page/5 |title=The Science of Leonardo |publisher=Doubleday |year=2007 |isbn=978-0-385-51390-6 |pages=[https://archive.org/details/scienceofleonard00capr/page/5 5–6]}}</ref>}} In [[Codex Arundel]], Leonardo recorded that if a water-pouring vase moves transversally (sideways), simulating the trajectory of a vertically falling object, it produces a [[right triangle]] with equal leg length, composed of falling material that forms the [[hypotenuse]] and the vase trajectory forming one of the legs.<ref name="Gharib2023">{{Cite journal |last=Gharib |first=Morteza |last2=Roh |first2=Chris |last3=Noca |first3=Flavio |date=1 February 2023 |title=Leonardo da Vinci's Visualization of Gravity as a Form of Acceleration |url=https://direct.mit.edu/leon/article-abstract/56/1/21/113863/Leonardo-da-Vinci-s-Visualization-of-Gravity-as-a |journal=Leonardo |volume=56 |pages=21–27 |doi=10.1162/leon_a_02322 |s2cid=254299572 |access-date=16 February 2023}}</ref> On the hypotenuse, Leonardo noted the equivalence of the two orthogonal motions, one effected by gravity and the other proposed by the experimenter.<ref name="Gharib2023" /> |
||
==== Nicolaus Copernicus, Petrus Apianus ==== |
==== Nicolaus Copernicus, Petrus Apianus ==== |
||
[[File:Nicolaus Copernicus Monument in Toruń (Thorn) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Nicolaus Copernicus]] |
[[File:Nicolaus Copernicus Monument in Toruń (Thorn) (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Nicolaus Copernicus]] |
||
By 1514, [[Nicolaus Copernicus]] had written [[Little Commentary|an outline]] of [[Copernican heliocentrism|his heliocentric model]], in which he stated that Earth's centre is the centre of both [[Earth's rotation|its rotation]] and the [[orbit of the Moon]].<ref>{{ |
By 1514, [[Nicolaus Copernicus]] had written [[Little Commentary|an outline]] of [[Copernican heliocentrism|his heliocentric model]], in which he stated that Earth's centre is the centre of both [[Earth's rotation|its rotation]] and the [[orbit of the Moon]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Durant |first=Will |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yWa7JBDirUYC |title=The Story of Civilization: Volume VI – The Reformation |publisher=Simon & Schuster |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-4516-4763-1 |page=823 |orig-year=1957}}</ref>{{efn|He accounted for these movements by explaining, "Rotation is natural to a sphere, and by that very act is its shape expressed."{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=27}}}} In 1533, German humanist [[Petrus Apianus]] described the [[exertion]] of gravity:{{efn|Physicist [[Pierre Duhem]] erroneously attributes this to [[Jordanus Nemorarius]], whom he calls the "precursor of Leonardo". Leonardo alludes to Jordanus in his notebooks, but not to any of his theories.<ref name="Ginzburg1936">{{Cite journal |last=Ginzburg |first=Benjamin |date=September 1936 |title=Duhem and Jordanus Nemorarius |journal=Isis |publisher=The University of Chicago Press |volume=25 |issue=2 |pages=341–362 |doi=10.1086/347085 |jstor=225373 |s2cid=145152521}}</ref>}} |
||
<blockquote>Since it is apparent that in the descent [along the arc] there is more impediment acquired, it is clear that gravity is diminished on this account. But because this comes about by reason of the position of heavy bodies, let it be called a [[Gravitational potential|positional gravity]] [i.e. |
<blockquote>Since it is apparent that in the descent [along the arc] there is more impediment acquired, it is clear that gravity is diminished on this account. But because this comes about by reason of the position of heavy bodies, let it be called a [[Gravitational potential|positional gravity]] [i.e. {{lang|la|gravitas secundum situm}}]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Duhem |first=Pierre |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Lcf-CAAAQBAJ&pg=PR24 |title=The Origins of Statics: The Sources of Physical Theory Volume 1 |publisher=Springer |year=2012 |isbn=9789401137300 |page=xxiv |translator-last=Leneaux |translator-first=G. F. |translator-last2=Vagliente |translator-first2=V. N. |translator-last3=Wagener |translator-first3=G. H.}}</ref></blockquote> |
||
==== Francesco Beato and Luca Ghini ==== |
==== Francesco Beato and Luca Ghini ==== |
||
Line 133: | Line 133: | ||
==== Domingo de Soto ==== |
==== Domingo de Soto ==== |
||
[[File:DOMINGO DE SOTO016 (cropped).JPG|thumb|upright|Domingo de Soto]] |
[[File:DOMINGO DE SOTO016 (cropped).JPG|thumb|upright|Domingo de Soto]] |
||
In 1551, [[Domingo de Soto]] theorized that objects in free fall accelerate uniformly in his book ''Physicorum Aristotelis quaestiones''.<ref name=" |
In 1551, [[Domingo de Soto]] theorized that objects in free fall accelerate uniformly in his book ''Physicorum Aristotelis quaestiones''.<ref name="Wallace2018">{{Cite book |last=Wallace |first=William A. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8GxQDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR21 |title=Domingo de Soto and the Early Galileo: Essays on Intellectual History |publisher=Routledge |year=2018 |isbn=978-1-351-15959-3 |location=Abingdon, UK |pages=119, 121–122 |orig-date=2004}}</ref> This idea was subsequently explored in more detail by Galileo Galilei, who derived his [[kinematics]] from the 14th-century Merton College and Jean Buridan,{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=41}} and possibly De Soto as well.<ref name="Wallace2018" /> |
||
==== Simon Stevin ==== |
==== Simon Stevin ==== |
||
{{Main|Delft tower experiment}} |
{{Main|Delft tower experiment}} |
||
[[File:Standbeeld van Simon Stevin door Louis Eugène Simonis (1810-1893) - Simon Stevinplein, Brugge.jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Simon Stevin]] |
[[File:Standbeeld van Simon Stevin door Louis Eugène Simonis (1810-1893) - Simon Stevinplein, Brugge.jpg|thumb|upright=0.8|Simon Stevin]] |
||
In 1585, Flemish polymath [[Simon Stevin]] performed a demonstration for [[Jan Cornets de Groot]], a local politician in the Dutch city of [[Delft]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Icke |first=V. |url=http://archive.org/details/gravitydoesnotex0000icke |title=Gravity does not exist: A puzzle for the 21st century |date=2014 |publisher=Amsterdam University Press |pages=9|bibcode=2014gdne.book.....I |
In 1585, Flemish polymath [[Simon Stevin]] performed a demonstration for [[Jan Cornets de Groot]], a local politician in the Dutch city of [[Delft]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Icke |first=V. |url=http://archive.org/details/gravitydoesnotex0000icke |title=Gravity does not exist: A puzzle for the 21st century |date=2014 |publisher=Amsterdam University Press |pages=9 |bibcode=2014gdne.book.....I}}</ref> Stevin dropped two lead balls from the [[Nieuwe Kerk (Delft)|Nieuwe Kerk]] in that city. From the sound of the impacts, Stevin deduced that the balls had fallen at the same speed. The result was published in 1586.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Drake |first=S |url=http://archive.org/details/galileoatwork00stil |title=Galileo at work: His scientific biography |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1978 |isbn=978-0-226-16226-3 |pages=20}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Stevin |first=S. |url=https://dwc.knaw.nl/pub/bronnen/Simon_Stevin-%5bI%5d_The_Principal_Works_of_Simon_Stevin,_Mechanics.pdf |title=The Principal Works of Simon Stevin |publisher=C. V. Swets & Zeitlinger |year=1955 |editor-last=Dijksterhuis |editor-first=E. J. |volume=1 |pages=509, 511 |language=nl, en |orig-date=1586}}</ref> |
||
{{Blockquote|text=Let us take (as ... Jan Cornets de Groot ... and I have done) two balls of lead, the one ten times larger and heavier than the other, and drop them together from a height of 30 feet on to a board or something on which they give a perceptible sound. Then it will be found that the lighter will not be ten times longer on its way than the heavier, but that they fall together on to the board so simultaneously that their two sounds seem to be one and the same. ... Therefore Aristotle ... is wrong.|author=Simon Stevin|title=De Beghinselen der Weeghconst}} |
{{Blockquote|text=Let us take (as ... Jan Cornets de Groot ... and I have done) two balls of lead, the one ten times larger and heavier than the other, and drop them together from a height of 30 feet on to a board or something on which they give a perceptible sound. Then it will be found that the lighter will not be ten times longer on its way than the heavier, but that they fall together on to the board so simultaneously that their two sounds seem to be one and the same. ... Therefore Aristotle ... is wrong.|author=Simon Stevin|title=De Beghinselen der Weeghconst}} |
||
Line 149: | Line 149: | ||
Written with modern symbols: {{math|''s'' ∝ ''t''<sup>2</sup>}} |
Written with modern symbols: {{math|''s'' ∝ ''t''<sup>2</sup>}} |
||
The result was published in ''[[Two New Sciences]]'' in 1638. In the same book, Galileo suggested that the slight variance of speed of falling objects of different mass was due to air resistance, and that objects would fall completely uniformly in a vacuum.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Galilei|first=Galileo|title=Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences|publisher=Martino Fine Books|year=2015|isbn=978- |
The result was published in ''[[Two New Sciences]]'' in 1638. In the same book, Galileo suggested that the slight variance of speed of falling objects of different mass was due to air resistance, and that objects would fall completely uniformly in a vacuum.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Galilei |first=Galileo |author-link=Galileo Galilei |title=Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences |publisher=Martino Fine Books |year=2015 |isbn=978-1-61427-794-1 |location=Eastford, CT |pages=72 |translator-last=Crew |translator-first=Henry |translator-link=Henry Crew}}</ref> The relation of the distance of objects in free fall to the square of the time taken was confirmed by Italian [[Jesuits]] [[Francesco Maria Grimaldi|Grimaldi]] and [[Riccioli]] between 1640 and 1650. They also made a calculation of the [[gravity of Earth]] by recording the oscillations of a pendulum.<ref>J.L. Heilbron, ''Electricity in the 17th and 18th Centuries: A Study of Early Modern Physics'' (Berkeley: the University of California Press, 1979), 180.</ref> |
||
==== Johannes Kepler ==== |
==== Johannes Kepler ==== |
||
[[File:JKepler (cropped).jpg|left|thumb|upright=0.8|Johannes Kepler]] |
[[File:JKepler (cropped).jpg|left|thumb|upright=0.8|Johannes Kepler]] |
||
In his ''[[Astronomia nova]]'' (1609), [[Johannes Kepler]] proposed an attractive force of limited radius between any "kindred" bodies: |
In his ''[[Astronomia nova]]'' (1609), [[Johannes Kepler]] proposed an attractive force of limited radius between any "kindred" bodies: |
||
<blockquote>Gravity is a mutual corporeal disposition among kindred bodies to unite or join together; thus the earth attracts a stone much more than the stone seeks the earth. (The magnetic faculty is another example of this sort).... If two stones were set near one another in some place in the world outside the sphere of influence of a third kindred body, these stones, like two magnetic bodies, would come together in an intermediate place, each approaching the other by a space proportional to the bulk [''moles''] of the other....<ref |
<blockquote>Gravity is a mutual corporeal disposition among kindred bodies to unite or join together; thus the earth attracts a stone much more than the stone seeks the earth. (The magnetic faculty is another example of this sort).... If two stones were set near one another in some place in the world outside the sphere of influence of a third kindred body, these stones, like two magnetic bodies, would come together in an intermediate place, each approaching the other by a space proportional to the bulk [''moles''] of the other....<ref>{{Cite book |last=Kepler |first=Johannes |author-link=Johannes Kepler |title=Selections from Kepler's Astronomia Nova |publisher=Green Lion |year=2004 |isbn=1-888009-28-4 |location=Santa Fe, NM |pages=1 |translator-last=Donahue |translator-first=William H.}}</ref></blockquote> |
||
==== Evangelista Torricelli ==== |
==== Evangelista Torricelli ==== |
||
A disciple of Galileo, [[Evangelista Torricelli]] reiterated Aristotle's model involving a gravitational centre, adding his view that a system can only be in equilibrium when the common centre itself is unable to fall.<ref name=" |
A disciple of Galileo, [[Evangelista Torricelli]] reiterated Aristotle's model involving a gravitational centre, adding his view that a system can only be in equilibrium when the common centre itself is unable to fall.<ref name="Ginzburg1936" /> |
||
==European Enlightenment== |
== European Enlightenment == |
||
{{See also|Scientific Revolution|Science in the Age of Enlightenment}} |
{{See also|Scientific Revolution|Science in the Age of Enlightenment}} |
||
The relation of the distance of objects in free fall to the square of the time taken was confirmed by [[Francesco Maria Grimaldi]] and [[Giovanni Battista Riccioli]] between 1640 and 1650. They also made a calculation of the [[gravity of Earth]] constant by recording the oscillations of a pendulum.<ref>J.L. Heilbron, ''Electricity in the 17th and 18th Centuries: A Study of Early Modern Physics'' (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), 180.</ref> |
The relation of the distance of objects in free fall to the square of the time taken was confirmed by [[Francesco Maria Grimaldi]] and [[Giovanni Battista Riccioli]] between 1640 and 1650. They also made a calculation of the [[gravity of Earth]] constant by recording the oscillations of a pendulum.<ref>J.L. Heilbron, ''Electricity in the 17th and 18th Centuries: A Study of Early Modern Physics'' (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), 180.</ref> |
||
===Mechanical explanations=== |
=== Mechanical explanations === |
||
{{ |
{{Main|Mechanical explanations of gravitation}} |
||
{{See also|Aether theories}} |
{{See also|Aether theories}} |
||
In 1644, [[René Descartes]] proposed that no empty space can exist and that a [[Continuum mechanics|continuum of matter]] causes every motion to be [[curvilinear motion|curvilinear]]. Thus, [[centrifugal force]] thrusts relatively light matter away from the central [[Mechanical explanations of gravitation#Vortex|vortices]] of celestial bodies, lowering density locally and thereby creating [[Centripetal force|centripetal pressure]].{{ |
In 1644, [[René Descartes]] proposed that no empty space can exist and that a [[Continuum mechanics|continuum of matter]] causes every motion to be [[curvilinear motion|curvilinear]]. Thus, [[centrifugal force]] thrusts relatively light matter away from the central [[Mechanical explanations of gravitation#Vortex|vortices]] of celestial bodies, lowering density locally and thereby creating [[Centripetal force|centripetal pressure]].{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=93}}<ref>{{Cite book |last=Descartes |first=René |title=Principles of Philosophy |title-link=Principles of Philosophy |year=1644}}</ref> Using aspects of this theory, between 1669 and 1690, [[Christiaan Huygens]] designed a mathematical vortex model. In one of his proofs, he shows that the distance elapsed by an object dropped from a spinning wheel will increase proportionally to the square of the wheel's rotation time.{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=121}} In 1671, [[Robert Hooke]] speculated that gravitation is the result of bodies emitting waves in the [[aether theories|aether]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Taylor |first=William Bower |year=1876 |title=Kinetic Theories of Gravitation |journal=Smithsonian Report |pages=205–282}}</ref>{{efn|[[James Challis]] repeated this assumption in 1869.}} [[Nicolas Fatio de Duillier]] (1690) and [[Georges-Louis Le Sage]] (1748) proposed [[Le Sage's theory of gravitation|a corpuscular model]] using some sort of screening or shadowing mechanism. In 1784, Le Sage posited that gravity could be a result of the collision of atoms, and in the early 19th century, he expanded [[Daniel Bernoulli]]'s [[Hydrodynamica|theory of corpuscular pressure]] to the universe as a whole.{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=480}} A similar model was later created by [[Hendrik Lorentz]] (1853–1928), who used [[electromagnetic radiation]] instead of corpuscles. |
||
English mathematician Isaac Newton used Descartes' argument that curvilinear motion constrains inertia,{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=120}} and in 1675, argued that aether streams attract all bodies to one another.{{efn|[[Bernhard Riemann]] made a similar argument in 1853.}} Newton (1717) and [[Leonhard Euler]] (1760) proposed a model in which the aether loses density near mass, leading to a net force acting on bodies.{{citation needed|date=October 2019}} Further mechanical explanations of gravitation (including [[Le Sage's theory of gravitation|Le Sage's theory]]) were created between 1650 and 1900 to explain Newton's theory, but mechanistic models eventually fell out of favor because most of them lead to an unacceptable amount of drag (air resistance), which was not observed. Others violate the [[energy conservation law]] and are incompatible with modern [[thermodynamics]].<ref name=" |
English mathematician Isaac Newton used Descartes' argument that curvilinear motion constrains inertia,{{sfn|Gillispie|1960|p=120}} and in 1675, argued that aether streams attract all bodies to one another.{{efn|[[Bernhard Riemann]] made a similar argument in 1853.}} Newton (1717) and [[Leonhard Euler]] (1760) proposed a model in which the aether loses density near mass, leading to a net force acting on bodies.{{citation needed|date=October 2019}} Further mechanical explanations of gravitation (including [[Le Sage's theory of gravitation|Le Sage's theory]]) were created between 1650 and 1900 to explain Newton's theory, but mechanistic models eventually fell out of favor because most of them lead to an unacceptable amount of drag (air resistance), which was not observed. Others violate the [[energy conservation law]] and are incompatible with modern [[thermodynamics]].<ref name="Zenneck1903">{{Cite book |last=Zenneck |first=J. |author-link=Jonathan Zenneck |title=Encyklopädie der Mathematischen Wissenschaften mit Einschluss ihrer Anwendungen |year=1903 |isbn=978-3-663-15445-7 |volume=5 |location=Leipzig |pages=25–67 |language=de |chapter=Gravitation |doi=10.1007/978-3-663-16016-8_2 |issue=1}}</ref> |
||
=== 'Weight' before Newton === |
=== 'Weight' before Newton === |
||
{{Main|Mass#Pre-Newtonian concepts}} |
{{Main|Mass#Pre-Newtonian concepts}} |
||
Before Newton, 'weight' had the double meaning 'amount' and 'heaviness'.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Browne |first=K. M. |year=2018 |title=The pre-Newtonian meaning of the word "weight"; a comment on "Kepler and the origins of pre-Newtonian mass" [Am. J. Phys. 85, 115–123 (2017)] |journal=American Journal of Physics |volume=86 |issue=6 |pages= |
Before Newton, 'weight' had the double meaning 'amount' and 'heaviness'.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Browne |first=K. M. |year=2018 |title=The pre-Newtonian meaning of the word "weight"; a comment on "Kepler and the origins of pre-Newtonian mass" [Am. J. Phys. 85, 115–123 (2017)] |journal=American Journal of Physics |volume=86 |issue=6 |pages=471–474 |bibcode=2018AmJPh..86..471B |doi=10.1119/1.5027490 |s2cid=125953814 |doi-access=free}}</ref>{{Blockquote|text=What we now know as mass was until the time of Newton called "weight." ... A goldsmith believed that an ounce of gold was a quantity of gold. ... But the ancients believed that a beam balance also measured "heaviness" which they recognized through their muscular senses. ... Mass and its associated downward force were believed to be the same thing. |
||
Kepler formed a [distinct] concept of mass ( |
Kepler formed a [distinct] concept of mass ("amount of matter" ({{lang|la|copia materiae}}), but called it "weight" as did everyone at that time.|author=K. M. Browne|title=The pre-Newtonian meaning of the word “weight”}} |
||
=== Mass as distinct from weight === |
=== Mass as distinct from weight === |
||
[[File:Portrait of Sir Isaac Newton, 1689.jpg|thumb|''Portrait of Isaac Newton (1642–1727)'' by [[Godfrey Kneller]] (1689)]] |
[[File:Portrait of Sir Isaac Newton, 1689.jpg|thumb|''Portrait of Isaac Newton (1642–1727)'' by [[Godfrey Kneller]] (1689)]] |
||
In 1686, Newton gave the concept of mass its name. In the first paragraph of ''Principia'', Newton defined quantity of matter as |
In 1686, Newton gave the concept of mass its name. In the first paragraph of ''Principia'', Newton defined quantity of matter as "density and bulk conjunctly", and mass as quantity of matter.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Newton |first=I. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Tm0FAAAAQAAJ&pg=PP13 |title=The mathematical principles of natural philosophy |publisher=Printed for Benjamin Motte |year=1729 |pages=1–2 |translator-last=Motte |translator-first=A. |orig-date=Original work published 1686}}</ref>{{Blockquote|text=The quantity of matter is the measure of the same, arising from its density and bulk conjunctly. ... It is this quantity that I mean hereafter everywhere under the name of body or mass. And the same is known by the weight of each body; for it is proportional to the weight.|author=Isaac Newton|title=Mathematical principles of natural philosophy|source=Definition I.}} |
||
=== Newton's law of universal gravitation === |
=== Newton's law of universal gravitation === |
||
{{See also|Gauss's law for gravity}} |
{{See also|Gauss's law for gravity}} |
||
In 1679, Robert Hooke wrote to Isaac Newton of his hypothesis concerning orbital motion, which partly depends on an [[inverse-square]] force.<ref name= |
In 1679, Robert Hooke wrote to Isaac Newton of his hypothesis concerning orbital motion, which partly depends on an [[inverse-square]] force.<ref name="Cohen2002">{{Cite book |last=Cohen |first=I. Bernard |title=The Cambridge Companion to Newton |last2=Smith |first2=George Edwin |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2002 |isbn=978-0-521-65696-2 |pages=11–12, 96–97}}</ref>{{efn|Newton was almost certainly influenced by this correspondence to do his subsequent work on gravitation,<ref name="Cohen2002" /> although he denied that Hooke had told him of the inverse-square force.<ref>H. W. Turnbull (ed.), ''Correspondence of Isaac Newton, Vol. 2'' (1676–1687), (Cambridge University Press, 1960), pp. 297–314, 431–448.</ref>}} In 1684, both Hooke and Newton told [[Edmond Halley]] that they had proven the inverse-square law of planetary motion, in January and August, respectively.<ref name="Sagan1997">{{Cite book |last=Sagan |first=Carl |author-link=Carl Sagan |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LhkoowKFaTsC |title=Comet |last2=Druyan |first2=Ann |author-link2=Ann Druyan |publisher=Random House |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-307-80105-0 |location=New York |pages=52–58}}</ref> While Hooke refused to produce his proofs, Newton was prompted to compose ''[[De motu corporum in gyrum]]'' ('On the motion of bodies in an orbit'), in which he mathematically derives [[Kepler's laws of planetary motion]].<ref name="Sagan1997" /> In 1687, with Halley's support (and to [[Newton-Hooke priority controversy for the inverse square law|Hooke's dismay]]), Newton published ''[[Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica]]'' (''Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy''), which hypothesizes the inverse-square [[law of universal gravitation]].<ref name="Sagan1997" /> In his own words:<blockquote>I deduced that the forces which keep the planets in their orbs must be reciprocally as the squares of their distances from the centres about which they revolve; and thereby compared the force requisite to keep the moon in her orb with the force of gravity at the surface of the earth; and found them to answer pretty nearly.</blockquote> |
||
Newton's original formula was: |
Newton's original formula was: |
||
Line 191: | Line 191: | ||
where the symbol <math>\propto</math> means "is proportional to". To make this into an equal-sided formula or equation, there needed to be a multiplying factor or constant that would give the correct force of gravity no matter the value of the masses or distance between them – the [[gravitational constant]]. Newton would need an accurate measure of this constant to prove his inverse-square law. Reasonably accurate measurements were not available in until the [[Cavendish experiment]] by [[Henry Cavendish]] in 1797.<ref>[http://ebooks.library.ualberta.ca/local/meandensityofear00poynuoft Poynting 1894]</ref> |
where the symbol <math>\propto</math> means "is proportional to". To make this into an equal-sided formula or equation, there needed to be a multiplying factor or constant that would give the correct force of gravity no matter the value of the masses or distance between them – the [[gravitational constant]]. Newton would need an accurate measure of this constant to prove his inverse-square law. Reasonably accurate measurements were not available in until the [[Cavendish experiment]] by [[Henry Cavendish]] in 1797.<ref>[http://ebooks.library.ualberta.ca/local/meandensityofear00poynuoft Poynting 1894]</ref> |
||
In Newton's theory<ref>{{ |
In Newton's theory<ref>{{Cite book |last=Newton |first=I. |author-link=Isaac Newton |title=[[Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica]] |year=1686 |language=la}}</ref> (rewritten using more modern mathematics) the density of mass <math>\rho\,</math> generates a scalar field, the gravitational potential <math>\varphi\,</math> in joules per kilogram, by |
||
:<math>{\partial^2 \varphi \over \partial x^j \, \partial x^j} = 4 \pi G \rho \,.</math> |
:<math>{\partial^2 \varphi \over \partial x^j \, \partial x^j} = 4 \pi G \rho \,.</math> |
||
Line 203: | Line 203: | ||
:<math>\varphi = -\frac{GM} r \,.</math> |
:<math>\varphi = -\frac{GM} r \,.</math> |
||
The ''Principia'' sold out quickly, inspiring Newton to publish a second edition in 1713.<ref>''The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 4'', Cambridge University Press 1967, at pp. 519, n.2.</ref><ref>[[Richard S. Westfall|Westfall, Richard S.]] (1971), ''Force in Newton's Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth Century''. New York: American Elsevier, p. 750.</ref> |
The ''Principia'' sold out quickly, inspiring Newton to publish a second edition in 1713.<ref>''The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 4'', Cambridge University Press 1967, at pp. 519, n.2.</ref><ref>[[Richard S. Westfall|Westfall, Richard S.]] (1971), ''Force in Newton's Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth Century''. New York: American Elsevier, p. 750.</ref> |
||
However the theory of gravity itself was not accepted quickly. |
However the theory of gravity itself was not accepted quickly. |
||
The theory of gravity faced two barriers. First scientists like [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] complained that it relied on [[action at a distance]], that the mechanism of gravity was "invisible, intangible, and not mechanical".<ref |
The theory of gravity faced two barriers. First scientists like [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] complained that it relied on [[action at a distance]], that the mechanism of gravity was "invisible, intangible, and not mechanical".<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hesse |first=Mary B. |year=1955 |title=Action at a Distance in Classical Physics |journal=Isis |volume=46 |issue=4 |pages=337–353 |doi=10.1086/348429 |issn=0021-1753 |jstor=227576 |s2cid=121166354}}</ref>{{rp|339}}<ref>Gillispie, Charles Coulston. The edge of objectivity: An essay in the history of scientific ideas. Princeton University Press, 2016.</ref>{{rp|144}} The French philosopher [[Voltaire]] countered these concerns, ultimately writing [[Elements of the Philosophy of Newton|his own book]] to explain aspects of it to French readers in 1738, which helped to popularize Newton's theory.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Shank |first=J. B. |year=2009 |title=Voltaire |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/voltaire/ |publisher=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> |
||
Second, detailed comparisons with astronomical data were not initially favorable. Among the most conspicuous issue was the so-called ''great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn''. Comparisons of ancient astronomical observations to those of the early 1700s implied that the orbit of Saturn was increasing in diameter while that of Jupiter was decreasing. Ultimately this meant Saturn would exit the Solar System and Jupiter would collide with other planets or the Sun. The problem was tackled first by [[Leonhard Euler]] in 1748, then [[Joseph-Louis Lagrange]] in 1763, by [[Pierre-Simon Laplace]] in 1773. Each effort improved the mathematical treatment until the issue was resolved by Laplace in 1784 approximately 100 years after Newton's first publication on gravity. Laplace showed that the changes were periodic but with immensely long periods beyond any existing measurements.<ref |
Second, detailed comparisons with astronomical data were not initially favorable. Among the most conspicuous issue was the so-called ''great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn''. Comparisons of ancient astronomical observations to those of the early 1700s implied that the orbit of Saturn was increasing in diameter while that of Jupiter was decreasing. Ultimately this meant Saturn would exit the Solar System and Jupiter would collide with other planets or the Sun. The problem was tackled first by [[Leonhard Euler]] in 1748, then [[Joseph-Louis Lagrange]] in 1763, by [[Pierre-Simon Laplace]] in 1773. Each effort improved the mathematical treatment until the issue was resolved by Laplace in 1784 approximately 100 years after Newton's first publication on gravity. Laplace showed that the changes were periodic but with immensely long periods beyond any existing measurements.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Whittaker |first=Edmund T. |title=A history of the theories of aether & electricity. 2: The Modern Theories 1900–1926 |publisher=Dover |year=1989 |isbn=978-0-486-26126-3 |edition=Repr. |location=New York}}</ref>{{rp|144}} |
||
Successes such the solution to the great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn mystery accumulated. In 1755, Prussian philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]] published [[Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens|a cosmological manuscript]] based on Newtonian principles, in which he develops an early version of the [[nebular hypothesis]].<ref>{{ |
Successes such the solution to the great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn mystery accumulated. In 1755, Prussian philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]] published [[Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens|a cosmological manuscript]] based on Newtonian principles, in which he develops an early version of the [[nebular hypothesis]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Woolfson |first=M. M. |year=1993 |title=Solar System – its origin and evolution |journal=Q. J. R. Astron. Soc. |volume=34 |pages=1–20 |bibcode=1993QJRAS..34....1W}}</ref> [[Edmond Halley]] proposed that similar looking objects appearing every 76 years was in fact a single comet. The appearance of the comet in 1759, now named after him, within a month of predictions based on Newton's gravity greatly improved scientific opinion of the theory.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hughes |first=D. W. |year=1987 |title=The history of Halley's Comet |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Mathematical and Physical Sciences |volume=323 |issue=1572 |pages=349–367 |bibcode=1987RSPTA.323..349H |doi=10.1098/rsta.1987.0091 |issn=0080-4614 |s2cid=123592786}}</ref> Newton's theory enjoyed its greatest success when it was used to predict the existence of [[Neptune]] based on motions of [[Uranus]] that could not be accounted by the actions of the other planets. Calculations by [[John Couch Adams]] and [[Urbain Le Verrier]] both predicted the general position of the planet. In 1846, Le Verrier sent his position to [[Johann Gottfried Galle]], asking him to verify it. The same night, Galle spotted Neptune near the position Le Verrier had predicted.<ref>{{Cite EB1911|wstitle=Adams, John Couch|volume=1|pages=177–178}}</ref> |
||
Not every comparison was successful. By the end of the 19th century, Le Verrier showed that the orbit of [[Mercury (planet)|Mercury]] could not be accounted for entirely under Newtonian gravity, and all searches for another perturbing body (such as a planet orbiting the Sun even closer than Mercury) were fruitless.<ref name=" |
Not every comparison was successful. By the end of the 19th century, Le Verrier showed that the orbit of [[Mercury (planet)|Mercury]] could not be accounted for entirely under Newtonian gravity, and all searches for another perturbing body (such as a planet orbiting the Sun even closer than Mercury) were fruitless.<ref name="Einstein1916">{{Cite journal |last=Einstein |first=Albert |author-link=Albert Einstein |year=1916 |title=The Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity |url=https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/The_Foundation_of_the_Generalised_Theory_of_Relativity |format=PDF |journal=Annalen der Physik |volume=49 |issue=7 |pages=769–822 |bibcode=1916AnP...354..769E |doi=10.1002/andp.19163540702 |access-date=2006-09-03}}</ref> Even so, Newton's theory is thought to be exceptionally accurate in the limit of weak [[gravitational field]]s and low speeds. |
||
At the end of the 19th century, many tried to combine Newton's force law with the established laws of [[Classical electromagnetism|electrodynamics]] (like those of [[Wilhelm Eduard Weber]], [[Carl Friedrich Gauss]], and [[Bernhard Riemann]]) |
At the end of the 19th century, many tried to combine Newton's force law with the established laws of [[Classical electromagnetism|electrodynamics]] (like those of [[Wilhelm Eduard Weber]], [[Carl Friedrich Gauss]], and [[Bernhard Riemann]]) to explain the anomalous [[perihelion precession of Mercury]]. In 1890, [[Maurice Lévy]] succeeded in doing so by combining the laws of Weber and Riemann, whereby the [[speed of gravity]] is equal to the speed of light. In another attempt, [[Paul Gerber]] (1898) succeeded in deriving the correct formula for the perihelion shift (which was identical to the formula later used by Albert Einstein). These hypotheses were rejected because of the outdated laws they were based on, being superseded by those of [[James Clerk Maxwell]].<ref name="Zenneck1903" /> |
||
==Modern era== |
== Modern era == |
||
{{ |
{{See also|Alternatives to general relativity}} |
||
In 1900, [[Hendrik Lorentz]] tried to explain gravity on the basis of [[Lorentz ether theory|his ether theory]] and [[Maxwell's equations]]. He assumed, like [[Ottaviano Fabrizio Mossotti]] and [[Johann Karl Friedrich Zöllner]], that the attraction of opposite charged particles is stronger than the repulsion of equal charged particles. The resulting net force is exactly what is known as universal gravitation, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. Lorentz calculated that the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.<ref>{{ |
In 1900, [[Hendrik Lorentz]] tried to explain gravity on the basis of [[Lorentz ether theory|his ether theory]] and [[Maxwell's equations]]. He assumed, like [[Ottaviano Fabrizio Mossotti]] and [[Johann Karl Friedrich Zöllner]], that the attraction of opposite charged particles is stronger than the repulsion of equal charged particles. The resulting net force is exactly what is known as universal gravitation, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. Lorentz calculated that the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Lorentz |first=H. A. |author-link=Hendrik Lorentz |year=1900 |title=Considerations on Gravitation |url=https://www.dwc.knaw.nl/DL/publications/PU00014433.pdf |journal=Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences (KNAW) |volume=2 |pages=559–574}}</ref> |
||
In the late 19th century, [[Lord Kelvin]] pondered the possibility of a [[theory of everything]].<ref>{{ |
In the late 19th century, [[Lord Kelvin]] pondered the possibility of a [[theory of everything]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Thompson |first=Silvanus P. |year=2019 |title=Lord Kelvin |url=https://www.iec.ch/about/history/figures/lord_kelvin.htm |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190329170841/https://www.iec.ch/about/history/figures/lord_kelvin.htm |archive-date=29 March 2019 |access-date=October 16, 2019 |website=International Electrotechnical Commission}}</ref> He proposed that every body pulsates, which might be an explanation of gravitation and [[electric charge]]s. His ideas were largely mechanistic and required the existence of the aether, which the [[Michelson–Morley experiment]] failed to detect in 1887. This, combined with [[Mach's principle]], led to gravitational models which feature [[action at a distance]]. |
||
Albert Einstein developed his revolutionary [[theory of relativity]] in papers published in 1905 and 1915; these account for the perihelion precession of Mercury.<ref name=" |
Albert Einstein developed his revolutionary [[theory of relativity]] in papers published in 1905 and 1915; these account for the perihelion precession of Mercury.<ref name="Einstein1916" /> In 1914, [[Gunnar Nordström]] attempted to unify gravity and [[electromagnetism]] in [[Nordström's theory of gravitation|his theory]] of [[five-dimensional]] gravitation.{{efn|In [[string theory]], dimensions exceeding four allow for the existence of [[Multiverse|parallel realities]]—which along with the [[anthropic principle]], help to explain the statistical near-impossibility of our [[fine-tuned universe]].}} General relativity was proven in 1919, when [[Arthur Eddington]] observed [[gravitational lens]]ing around a solar eclipse, matching Einstein's equations. This resulted in Einstein's theory superseding Newtonian physics.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Andrzej |first=Stasiak |year=2003 |title=Myths in science |journal=EMBO Reports |volume=4 |issue=3 |page=236 |doi=10.1038/sj.embor.embor779 |pmc=1315907 |doi-access=free}}</ref> Thereafter, German mathematician [[Theodor Kaluza]] promoted the idea of general relativity with a fifth dimension, which in 1921 Swedish physicist [[Oskar Klein]] gave [[Kaluza–Klein theory|a physical interpretation]] of in a prototypical [[string theory]], a possible model of [[quantum gravity]] and potential theory of everything. |
||
[[File:Einstein 1921 by F Schmutzer - restoration.jpg|thumb|upright|Albert Einstein in 1921]] |
[[File:Einstein 1921 by F Schmutzer - restoration.jpg|thumb|upright|Albert Einstein in 1921]] |
||
[[Einstein's field equations]] include a [[cosmological constant]] to account for the alleged [[static universe|staticity of the universe]]. However, [[Edwin Hubble]] observed in 1929 that the universe appears to be expanding. By the 1930s, [[Paul Dirac]] developed the hypothesis that gravitation should slowly and steadily decrease over the course of the history of the universe.<ref>{{ |
[[Einstein's field equations]] include a [[cosmological constant]] to account for the alleged [[static universe|staticity of the universe]]. However, [[Edwin Hubble]] observed in 1929 that the universe appears to be expanding. By the 1930s, [[Paul Dirac]] developed the hypothesis that gravitation should slowly and steadily decrease over the course of the history of the universe.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Haber |first=Heinz |author-link=Heinz Haber |title=Unser blauer Planet |publisher=[[Rowohlt Verlag]] |year=1967 |edition=Rororo Taschenbuch Ausgabe [Rororo pocket edition] |series=Rororo Sachbuch [Rororo nonfiction] |location=Reinbek |page=52 |language=de |trans-title=Our blue planet |chapter=Die Expansion der Erde |trans-chapter=The expansion of the Earth |bibcode=1967ubp..book.....H |quote=Der englische Physiker und Nobelpreisträger Dirac hat ... vor über dreißig Jahren die Vermutung begründet, dass sich das universelle Maß der Schwerkraft im Laufe der Geschichte des Universums außerordentlich langsam, aber stetig verringert." '''English:''' "The English physicist and Nobel laureate Dirac has ..., more than thirty years ago, substantiated the assumption that the universal strength of gravity decreases very slowly, but steadily over the course of the history of the universe. |orig-date=1965}}</ref> [[Alan Guth]] and [[Alexei Starobinsky]] proposed in 1980 that [[cosmic inflation]] in the very early universe could have been driven by a negative [[pressure]] field, a concept later coined '[[dark energy]]'—found in 2013 to have composed around 68.3% of the early universe.<ref name="The Washington Post">{{Cite news |title=Big Bang's afterglow shows universe is 80 million years older than scientists first thought |url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/europe/telescope-that-sees-big-bangs-afterglow-sees-older-universe-in-glimpse-of-first-split-second/2013/03/21/ada16076-920e-11e2-9173-7f87cda73b49_story_1.html |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130322054138/http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/europe/telescope-that-sees-big-bangs-afterglow-sees-older-universe-in-glimpse-of-first-split-second/2013/03/21/ada16076-920e-11e2-9173-7f87cda73b49_story_1.html |archive-date=22 March 2013 |access-date=22 March 2013 |work=The Washington Post}}</ref> |
||
In 1922, [[Jacobus Kapteyn]] proposed the existence of [[dark matter]], an unseen force that moves stars in galaxies at higher velocities than gravity alone accounts for. It was found in 2013 to have comprised 26.8% of the early universe.<ref name="Washington Post"/> Along with dark energy, dark matter is an outlier in Einstein's relativity, and an explanation for its apparent effects is a requirement for a successful theory of everything. |
In 1922, [[Jacobus Kapteyn]] proposed the existence of [[dark matter]], an unseen force that moves stars in galaxies at higher velocities than gravity alone accounts for. It was found in 2013 to have comprised 26.8% of the early universe.<ref name="The Washington Post" /> Along with dark energy, dark matter is an outlier in Einstein's relativity, and an explanation for its apparent effects is a requirement for a successful theory of everything. |
||
In 1957, [[Hermann Bondi]] proposed that [[Negative mass|negative gravitational mass]] (combined with negative inertial mass) would comply with the [[strong equivalence principle]] of general relativity and [[Newton's laws of motion]]. Bondi's proof yielded [[gravitational singularity|singularity]]-free solutions for the relativity equations.<ref |
In 1957, [[Hermann Bondi]] proposed that [[Negative mass|negative gravitational mass]] (combined with negative inertial mass) would comply with the [[strong equivalence principle]] of general relativity and [[Newton's laws of motion]]. Bondi's proof yielded [[gravitational singularity|singularity]]-free solutions for the relativity equations.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bondi |first=H. |year=1957 |title=Negative mass in general relativity |journal=Reviews of Modern Physics |volume=29 |issue=3 |pages=423–428 |bibcode=1957RvMP...29..423B |doi=10.1103/revmodphys.29.423}}</ref> |
||
Early theories of gravity attempted to explain planetary orbits (Newton) and more complicated orbits (e.g. Lagrange). Then came unsuccessful attempts to [[Le Sage's theory of gravitation|combine gravity and either wave or corpuscular theories]] of gravity. The whole landscape of physics was changed with the discovery of [[Lorentz transformation]]s, and this led to attempts to reconcile it with gravity. At the same time, experimental physicists started testing the foundations of gravity and relativity—[[Lorentz covariance|Lorentz invariance]], the [[ |
Early theories of gravity attempted to explain planetary orbits (Newton) and more complicated orbits (e.g. Lagrange). Then came unsuccessful attempts to [[Le Sage's theory of gravitation|combine gravity and either wave or corpuscular theories]] of gravity. The whole landscape of physics was changed with the discovery of [[Lorentz transformation]]s, and this led to attempts to reconcile it with gravity. At the same time, experimental physicists started testing the foundations of gravity and relativity—[[Lorentz covariance|Lorentz invariance]], the [[gravitational deflection of light]], the [[Eötvös experiment]]. These considerations led to and past the development of [[general relativity]]. |
||
===Einstein ( |
=== Einstein (1905–1912) === |
||
In 1905, Albert Einstein published a series of papers in which he established the [[special theory of relativity]] and the fact that [[Mass–energy equivalence|mass and energy are equivalent]]. In 1907, in what he described as "the happiest thought of my life", Einstein realized that someone who is in free fall experiences no gravitational field. In other words, gravitation is exactly equivalent to acceleration. |
In 1905, Albert Einstein published a series of papers in which he established the [[special theory of relativity]] and the fact that [[Mass–energy equivalence|mass and energy are equivalent]]. In 1907, in what he described as "the happiest thought of my life", Einstein realized that someone who is in free fall experiences no gravitational field. In other words, gravitation is exactly equivalent to acceleration. |
||
Einstein's two-part publication in 1912<ref |
Einstein's two-part publication in 1912<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Einstein |first=Albert |author-link=Albert Einstein |year=1912 |title=Lichtgeschwindigkeit und Statik des Gravitationsfeldes |url=https://zenodo.org/record/1424235 |journal=Annalen der Physik |language=de |volume=38 |issue=7 |pages=355–369 |bibcode=1912AnP...343..355E |doi=10.1002/andp.19123430704}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Einstein |first=Albert |author-link=Albert Einstein |year=1912 |title=Zur Theorie des statischen Gravitationsfeldes |url=https://zenodo.org/record/1424241 |journal=Annalen der Physik |language=de |volume=38 |issue=7 |page=443 |bibcode=1912AnP...343..443E |doi=10.1002/andp.19123430709}}</ref> (and before in 1908) is really only important for historical reasons. By then he knew of the gravitational redshift and the deflection of light. He had realized that Lorentz transformations are not generally applicable, but retained them. The theory states that the speed of light is constant in free space but varies in the presence of matter. The theory was only expected to hold when the source of the gravitational field is stationary. It includes the [[principle of least action]]: |
||
:<math>\delta \int d\tau = 0\,</math> |
:<math>\delta \int d\tau = 0\,</math> |
||
Line 246: | Line 246: | ||
where <math>\eta_{\mu \nu} \,</math> is the [[Minkowski space|Minkowski metric]], and there is a summation from 1 to 4 over indices <math>\mu \,</math> and <math>\nu \,</math>. |
where <math>\eta_{\mu \nu} \,</math> is the [[Minkowski space|Minkowski metric]], and there is a summation from 1 to 4 over indices <math>\mu \,</math> and <math>\nu \,</math>. |
||
Einstein and Grossmann<ref name= |
Einstein and Grossmann<ref name="Einstein">Einstein, A. and Grossmann, M. (1913), ''Zeitschrift für Mathematik und Physik'' 62, 225</ref> includes [[Riemannian geometry]] and [[Covariant transformation|tensor calculus]]. |
||
:<math>\delta \int d\tau = 0 \,</math> |
:<math>\delta \int d\tau = 0 \,</math> |
||
Line 258: | Line 258: | ||
is not in general relativity. It expresses the [[stress–energy tensor]] as a function of the matter density. |
is not in general relativity. It expresses the [[stress–energy tensor]] as a function of the matter density. |
||
===Lorentz-invariant models (1905–1910)=== |
=== Lorentz-invariant models (1905–1910) === |
||
Based on the [[principle of relativity]], [[Henri Poincaré]] (1905, 1906), [[Hermann Minkowski]] (1908), and [[Arnold Sommerfeld]] (1910) tried to modify Newton's theory and to establish a [[Lorentz covariance|Lorentz invariant]] gravitational law, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. As in Lorentz's model, the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.<ref>{{ |
Based on the [[principle of relativity]], [[Henri Poincaré]] (1905, 1906), [[Hermann Minkowski]] (1908), and [[Arnold Sommerfeld]] (1910) tried to modify Newton's theory and to establish a [[Lorentz covariance|Lorentz invariant]] gravitational law, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. As in Lorentz's model, the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Walter |first=S. |year=2007 |editor-last=Renn |editor-first=J. |title=Breaking in the 4-vectors: the four-dimensional movement in gravitation, 1905–1910 |url=http://scottwalter.free.fr/papers/breaking2007.pdf |journal=The Genesis of General Relativity |volume=3 |pages=193–252 |bibcode=2007ggr..conf..193W |location=Berlin}}</ref> |
||
===Abraham (1912)=== |
=== Abraham (1912) === |
||
Meanwhile, [[Max Abraham]] developed an alternative model of gravity in which the speed of light depends on the gravitational field strength and so is variable almost everywhere. Abraham's 1914 review of gravitation models is said to be excellent, but his own model was poor. |
Meanwhile, [[Max Abraham]] developed an alternative model of gravity in which the speed of light depends on the gravitational field strength and so is variable almost everywhere. Abraham's 1914 review of gravitation models is said to be excellent, but his own model was poor. |
||
===Nordström (1912)=== |
=== Nordström (1912) === |
||
The first approach of [[Nordström's theory of gravitation|Nordström (1912)]]<ref |
The first approach of [[Nordström's theory of gravitation|Nordström (1912)]]<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Nordström |first=G. |author-link=Gunnar Nordström |year=1912 |title=Relativitätsprinzip und Gravitation |url=https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=mdp.39015023176806&view=1up&seq=1220 |journal=Physikalische Zeitschrift |language=de |volume=13 |page=1126}}</ref> was to retain the Minkowski metric and a constant value of <math>c\,</math> but to let mass depend on the gravitational field strength <math>\varphi\,</math>. Allowing this field strength to satisfy |
||
:<math>\Box \varphi = \rho \,</math> |
:<math>\Box \varphi = \rho \,</math> |
||
Line 279: | Line 279: | ||
where <math>u \,</math> is the four-velocity and the dot is a differential with respect to time. |
where <math>u \,</math> is the four-velocity and the dot is a differential with respect to time. |
||
The second approach of [[Nordström's theory of gravitation|Nordström (1913)]]<ref name="Nordström1913">{{ |
The second approach of [[Nordström's theory of gravitation|Nordström (1913)]]<ref name="Nordström1913">{{Cite journal |last=Nordström |first=G. |year=1913 |title=Zur Theorie der Gravitation vom Standpunkt des Relativitätsprinzips |journal=Annalen der Physik |language=de |volume=42 |issue=13 |page=533 |bibcode=1913AnP...347..533N |doi=10.1002/andp.19133471303}}</ref> is remembered as the first [[logically consistent]] relativistic field theory of gravitation ever formulated. (notation from Pais<ref>{{Cite book |last=Pais |first=Abraham |title=Subtle is the Lord: The Science and Life of Albert Einstein |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2005 |isbn=978-0-19-152402-8 |location=New York}}</ref> not Nordström): |
||
:<math>\delta \int \psi \, d\tau = 0 \,</math> |
:<math>\delta \int \psi \, d\tau = 0 \,</math> |
||
Line 291: | Line 291: | ||
This theory is Lorentz invariant, satisfies the conservation laws, correctly reduces to the Newtonian limit and satisfies the [[Equivalence principle|weak equivalence principle]]. |
This theory is Lorentz invariant, satisfies the conservation laws, correctly reduces to the Newtonian limit and satisfies the [[Equivalence principle|weak equivalence principle]]. |
||
===Einstein and Fokker (1914)=== |
=== Einstein and Fokker (1914) === |
||
This theory<ref |
This theory<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Einstein |first=Albert |last2=Fokker |first2=A. D. |year=1914 |title=Die Nordströmsche Gravitationstheorie vom Standpunkt des absoluten Differentkalküls |journal=Annalen der Physik |language=de |volume=44 |issue=10 |pages=321–328 |bibcode=1914AnP...349..321E |doi=10.1002/andp.19143491009}}</ref> is Einstein's first treatment of gravitation in which general covariance is strictly obeyed. Writing: |
||
:<math>\delta \int ds = 0 \,</math> |
:<math>\delta \int ds = 0 \,</math> |
||
Line 300: | Line 300: | ||
:<math>g_{\mu \nu} = \psi^2 \eta_{\mu \nu} \,</math> |
:<math>g_{\mu \nu} = \psi^2 \eta_{\mu \nu} \,</math> |
||
they relate Einstein–Grossmann<ref name= |
they relate Einstein–Grossmann<ref name="Einstein" /> to Nordström.<ref name="Nordström1913" /> They also state: |
||
:<math>T \, \propto \, R \,.</math> |
:<math>T \, \propto \, R \,.</math> |
||
Line 308: | Line 308: | ||
Between 1911 and 1915, Einstein developed the idea that gravitation is equivalent to acceleration, initially stated as the [[equivalence principle]], into his general theory of relativity, which fuses the [[Three-dimensional space|three dimensions of space]] and the one dimension of [[time]] into the [[four-dimensional]] fabric of [[spacetime]]. However, it does not unify gravity with [[quantum|quanta]]—individual particles of energy, which Einstein himself had postulated the existence of in 1905. |
Between 1911 and 1915, Einstein developed the idea that gravitation is equivalent to acceleration, initially stated as the [[equivalence principle]], into his general theory of relativity, which fuses the [[Three-dimensional space|three dimensions of space]] and the one dimension of [[time]] into the [[four-dimensional]] fabric of [[spacetime]]. However, it does not unify gravity with [[quantum|quanta]]—individual particles of energy, which Einstein himself had postulated the existence of in 1905. |
||
===General relativity=== |
=== General relativity === |
||
{{Main|History of general relativity}} |
{{Main|History of general relativity}} |
||
[[File:1919 Eclipse expedition to test relativity.jpg|thumb|upright=2.2|Illustration explaining the relevance of the total [[solar eclipse of 29 May 1919]], from the 22 November 1919 edition of ''[[The Illustrated London News]]'']] |
[[File:1919 Eclipse expedition to test relativity.jpg|thumb|upright=2.2|Illustration explaining the relevance of the total [[solar eclipse of 29 May 1919]], from the 22 November 1919 edition of ''[[The Illustrated London News]]'']] |
||
In general relativity, the effects of gravitation are ascribed to spacetime curvature instead of to a force. The starting point for general relativity is the equivalence principle, which equates free fall with inertial motion. The issue that this creates is that free-falling objects can accelerate with respect to each other. To deal with this difficulty, Einstein proposed that spacetime is curved by matter, and that free-falling objects are moving along [[Geodesics in general relativity|locally straight paths in curved spacetime]]. More specifically, Einstein and [[David Hilbert]] discovered the [[field equation]]s of general relativity, which relate the presence of matter and the curvature of spacetime. [[Einstein field equations|These field equations]] are a set of 10 [[simultaneous equation|simultaneous]], [[ |
In general relativity, the effects of gravitation are ascribed to spacetime curvature instead of to a force. The starting point for general relativity is the equivalence principle, which equates free fall with inertial motion. The issue that this creates is that free-falling objects can accelerate with respect to each other. To deal with this difficulty, Einstein proposed that spacetime is curved by matter, and that free-falling objects are moving along [[Geodesics in general relativity|locally straight paths in curved spacetime]]. More specifically, Einstein and [[David Hilbert]] discovered the [[field equation]]s of general relativity, which relate the presence of matter and the curvature of spacetime. [[Einstein field equations|These field equations]] are a set of 10 [[simultaneous equation|simultaneous]], [[non-linear]], [[differential equation]]s. The solutions of the field equations are the components of the [[metric tensor (general relativity)|metric tensor]] of spacetime, which describes its geometry. The geodesic paths of spacetime are calculated from the metric tensor. |
||
Notable solutions of the Einstein field equations include: |
Notable solutions of the Einstein field equations include: |
||
* The [[Schwarzschild solution]], which describes spacetime surrounding a [[spherical symmetry|spherically symmetrical]] non-rotating uncharged massive object. For objects with radii smaller than the [[Schwarzschild radius]], this solution generates a [[black hole]] with a central singularity. |
* The [[Schwarzschild solution]], which describes spacetime surrounding a [[spherical symmetry|spherically symmetrical]] non-rotating uncharged massive object. For objects with radii smaller than the [[Schwarzschild radius]], this solution generates a [[black hole]] with a central singularity. |
||
* The [[ |
* The [[Reissner–Nordström solution]], in which the central object has an electrical charge. For charges with a [[geometrized]] length less than the geometrized length of the mass of the object, this solution produces black holes with an [[event horizon]] surrounding a [[Cauchy horizon]]. |
||
* The [[Kerr solution]] for rotating massive objects. This solution also produces black holes with multiple horizons. |
* The [[Kerr solution]] for rotating massive objects. This solution also produces black holes with multiple horizons. |
||
* The [[physical cosmology|cosmological]] [[Robertson–Walker coordinates|Robertson–Walker solution]] (from 1922 and 1924), which predicts the expansion of the universe.{{cn|date=March 2024}} |
* The [[physical cosmology|cosmological]] [[Robertson–Walker coordinates|Robertson–Walker solution]] (from 1922 and 1924), which predicts the expansion of the universe.{{cn|date=March 2024}} |
||
General relativity has enjoyed much success because its predictions (not called for by older theories of gravity) have been regularly confirmed. For example: |
General relativity has enjoyed much success because its predictions (not called for by older theories of gravity) have been regularly confirmed. For example: |
||
* General relativity accounts for the anomalous perihelion precession of Mercury.<ref name=" |
* General relativity accounts for the anomalous perihelion precession of Mercury.<ref name="Einstein1916" /> |
||
* Gravitational lensing was first confirmed in 1919, and has more recently been strongly confirmed through the use of a [[quasar]] which passes behind the Sun as seen from the Earth. |
* Gravitational lensing was first confirmed in 1919, and has more recently been strongly confirmed through the use of a [[quasar]] which passes behind the Sun as seen from the Earth. |
||
* The expansion of the universe (predicted by the [[Robertson–Walker metric]]) was confirmed by Edwin Hubble in 1929. |
* The expansion of the universe (predicted by the [[Robertson–Walker metric]]) was confirmed by Edwin Hubble in 1929. |
||
Line 327: | Line 327: | ||
* The [[time delay of light]] passing close to a massive object was first identified by [[Irwin Shapiro]] in 1964 in interplanetary spacecraft signals. |
* The [[time delay of light]] passing close to a massive object was first identified by [[Irwin Shapiro]] in 1964 in interplanetary spacecraft signals. |
||
* [[Gravitational radiation]] has been indirectly confirmed through studies of binary [[pulsar]]s such as [[PSR 1913+16]]. |
* [[Gravitational radiation]] has been indirectly confirmed through studies of binary [[pulsar]]s such as [[PSR 1913+16]]. |
||
** In 2015, the [[LIGO]] experiments directly [[First observation of gravitational waves|detected gravitational radiation]] from [[Binary black hole|two colliding black holes]], making this the first direct observation of both gravitational waves and black holes.<ref |
** In 2015, the [[LIGO]] experiments directly [[First observation of gravitational waves|detected gravitational radiation]] from [[Binary black hole|two colliding black holes]], making this the first direct observation of both gravitational waves and black holes.<ref>{{cite journal |collaboration=LIGO Scientific Collaboration and Virgo Collaboration |last1=Abbott |first1=Benjamin P. |title=Observation of Gravitational Waves from a Binary Black Hole Merger |journal=Physical Review Letters |volume=116 |issue=6 |pages=061102 |year=2016 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.116.061102 |arxiv=1602.03837 |bibcode = 2016PhRvL.116f1102A |pmid=26918975|s2cid=124959784}} |
||
*{{ |
*{{Cite web |title=Observation of Gravitational Waves from a Binary Black Hole Merger |url=https://www.ligo.caltech.edu/system/media_files/binaries/301/original/detection-science-summary.pdf |website=LIGO Scientific Collaboration}}</ref> |
||
It is believed that [[neutron star]] mergers (since detected in 2017)<ref |
It is believed that [[neutron star]] mergers (since detected in 2017)<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Abbott |first=B. P. |last2=Abbott |first2=R. |last3=Abbott |first3=T. D. |last4=Acernese |first4=F. |last5=Ackley |first5=K. |last6=Adams |first6=C. |last7=Adams |first7=T. |last8=Addesso |first8=P. |last9=Adhikari |first9=R. X. |last10=Adya |first10=V. B. |last11=Affeldt |first11=C. |last12=Afrough |first12=M. |last13=Agarwal |first13=B. |last14=Agathos |first14=M. |last15=Agatsuma |first15=K. |year=2017 |title=Multi-messenger Observations of a Binary Neutron Star Merger |journal=The Astrophysical Journal Letters |volume=848 |issue=2 |pages=L12 |arxiv=1710.05833 |bibcode=2017ApJ...848L..12A |doi=10.3847/2041-8213/aa91c9 |s2cid=217162243 |doi-access=free |last16=Aggarwal |first16=N. |last17=Aguiar |first17=O. D. |last18=Aiello |first18=L. |last19=Ain |first19=A. |last20=Ajith |first20=P. |last21=Allen |first21=B. |last22=Allen |first22=G. |last23=Allocca |first23=A. |last24=Altin |first24=P. A. |last25=Amato |first25=A. |last26=Ananyeva |first26=A. |last27=Anderson |first27=S. B. |last28=Anderson |first28=W. G. |last29=Angelova |first29=S. V. |last30=Antier |first30=S.}}</ref> and black hole formation may also create detectable amounts of gravitational radiation. |
||
===Quantum gravity=== |
=== Quantum gravity === |
||
{{Main|Quantum gravity}} |
{{Main|Quantum gravity}} |
||
Several decades after the discovery of general relativity, it was realized that it cannot be the complete theory of gravity because it is incompatible with [[quantum mechanics]].<ref name=" |
Several decades after the discovery of general relativity, it was realized that it cannot be the complete theory of gravity because it is incompatible with [[quantum mechanics]].<ref name="Randall2005">{{Cite book |last=Randall |first=Lisa |url=https://archive.org/details/warpedpassagesun00rand_1 |title=Warped Passages: Unraveling the Universe's Hidden Dimensions |publisher=Ecco |year=2005 |isbn=978-0-06-053108-9 |url-access=registration}}</ref> Later it was understood that it is possible to describe gravity in the framework of [[quantum field theory]] like the other [[fundamental forces]]. In this framework, the attractive force of gravity arises due to exchange of [[virtual particle|virtual]] [[graviton]]s, in the same way as the electromagnetic force arises from exchange of virtual [[photon]]s.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Feynman |first=Richard |url=https://archive.org/details/feynmanlectureso0000feyn_g4q1 |title=Feynman lectures on gravitation |last2=Morinigo |first2=F. B. |last3=Wagner |first3=W. G. |last4=Hatfield |first4=B. |publisher=Addison-Wesley |year=1995 |isbn=978-0-201-62734-3 |url-access=registration}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Zee |first=A. |title=Quantum Field Theory in a Nutshell |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=2003}}</ref> This reproduces general relativity in the [[classical limit]], but only at the linearized level and postulating that the conditions for the applicability of [[Ehrenfest theorem]] holds, which is not always the case. Moreover, this approach fails at short distances of the order of the [[Planck length]].<ref name="Randall2005" /> |
||
==See also== |
== See also == |
||
* [[Anti-gravity]] |
* [[Anti-gravity]] |
||
* [[History of physics]] |
* [[History of physics]] |
||
== |
== Notes == |
||
{{Notelist}} |
|||
⚫ | |||
{{notelist}} |
|||
== References == |
|||
=== Citations === |
=== Citations === |
||
{{Reflist| |
{{Reflist|30em}} |
||
===Sources=== |
=== Sources === |
||
*{{ |
*{{Cite book |last=Gillispie |first=Charles Coulston |url=https://archive.org/details/edgeofobjectivit00char |title=The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=1960 |isbn=0-691-02350-6}} |
||
*{{Cite book |last=Wallace |first=W. A. |url=https://archive.org/details/domingo-de-soto-and-the-early-galileo/page/n3/mode/1up?view=theater |title=Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history |publisher=Routledge |year=2004a |editor-last=Wallace |editor-first=W. A. |chapter=The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics}} (Reprinted from "The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics". (1968). Isis, 59(4), 384–401). |
*{{Cite book |last=Wallace |first=W. A. |url=https://archive.org/details/domingo-de-soto-and-the-early-galileo/page/n3/mode/1up?view=theater |title=Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history |publisher=Routledge |year=2004a |editor-last=Wallace |editor-first=W. A. |chapter=The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics}} (Reprinted from "The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics". (1968). Isis, 59(4), 384–401). |
||
*{{Cite book |last=Wallace |first=W. A. |url=https://archive.org/details/domingo-de-soto-and-the-early-galileo/page/n3/mode/1up?view=theater |title=Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history |publisher=Routledge |year=2004b |editor-last=Wallace |editor-first=W. A. |chapter=Domingo de Soto and the Iberian roots of |
*{{Cite book |last=Wallace |first=W. A. |url=https://archive.org/details/domingo-de-soto-and-the-early-galileo/page/n3/mode/1up?view=theater |title=Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history |publisher=Routledge |year=2004b |editor-last=Wallace |editor-first=W. A. |chapter=Domingo de Soto and the Iberian roots of Galileo's science}} (Reprinted from White, K. (Ed.). (1997). Hispanic philosophy in the age of discovery. Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 29. Catholic University of America Press). |
||
{{theories of gravitation}} |
{{theories of gravitation}} |
||
{{History of physics}} |
{{History of physics}} |
||
{{DEFAULTSORT:History Of Gravitational Theory}} |
|||
[[Category:Theories of gravity]] |
[[Category:Theories of gravity]] |
||
[[Category:History of physics]]{{#invoke:Check for unknown parameters|check|unknown={{main other|[[Category:Pages using history of gravitational theory with unknown parameters|_VALUE_{{PAGENAME}}]]}}|preview=Page using [[History of gravitational theory]] with unknown parameter "_VALUE_"|ignoreblank=y}} |
|||
[[Category:History of physics]] |
Latest revision as of 17:06, 9 November 2024
In physics, theories of gravitation postulate mechanisms of interaction governing the movements of bodies with mass. There have been numerous theories of gravitation since ancient times. The first extant sources discussing such theories are found in ancient Greek philosophy. This work was furthered through the Middle Ages by Indian, Islamic, and European scientists, before gaining great strides during the Renaissance and Scientific Revolution—culminating in the formulation of Newton's law of gravity. This was superseded by Albert Einstein's theory of relativity in the early 20th century.
Greek philosopher Aristotle (fl. 4th century BC) found that objects immersed in a medium tend to fall at speeds proportional to their weight. Vitruvius (fl. 1st century BC) understood that objects fall based on their specific gravity. In the 6th century AD, Byzantine Alexandrian scholar John Philoponus modified the Aristotelian concept of gravity with the theory of impetus. In the 7th century, Indian astronomer Brahmagupta spoke of gravity as an attractive force. In the 14th century, European philosophers Jean Buridan and Albert of Saxony—who were influenced by Islamic scholars such as Ibn Sina and Abu'l-Barakat respectively[1][2]—developed the theory of impetus and linked it to the acceleration and mass of objects. Albert also developed a law of proportion regarding the relationship between the speed of an object in free fall and the time elapsed.
Italians of the 16th century found that objects in free fall tend to accelerate equally. In 1632, Galileo Galilei put forth the basic principle of relativity. The existence of the gravitational constant was explored by various researchers from the mid-17th century, helping Isaac Newton formulate his law of universal gravitation. Newton's classical mechanics were superseded in the early 20th century, when Einstein developed the special and general theories of relativity. An elemental force carrier of gravity is hypothesized in quantum gravity approaches such as string theory, in a potentially unified theory of everything.
Antiquity
[edit]Classical antiquity
[edit]Heraclitus, Anaxagoras, Empedocles and Leucippus
[edit]The pre-Socratic Greek philosopher Heraclitus (c. 535 – c. 475 BC) of the Ionian School used the word logos ('word') to describe a kind of law which keeps the cosmos in harmony, moving all objects, including the stars, winds, and waves.[3] Anaxagoras (c. 500 – c. 428 BC), another Ionian philosopher, introduced the concept of nous ('cosmic mind') as an ordering force.[4]
In the cosmogony of the Greek philosopher Empedocles (c. 494 – c. 434/443 BC), there were two opposing fundamental cosmic forces of "attraction" and "repulsion", which Empedocles personified as "Love" and "Strife" (Philotes and Neikos).[5][6]
The ancient atomist Leucippus (5th century BC) proposed the cosmos was created when a large group of atoms came together and swirled as a vortex. The smaller atoms became the celestial bodies of the cosmos. The larger atoms in the center came together as a membrane from which the Earth was formed.[7][8]
Aristotle
[edit]In the 4th century BC, Greek philosopher Aristotle taught that there is no effect or motion without a cause. The cause of the downward natural motion of heavy bodies, such as the classical elements of earth and water, was related to their nature (gravity), which caused them to move downward toward the center of the (geocentric) universe. For this reason Aristotle supported a spherical Earth, since "every portion of earth has weight until it reaches the centre, and the jostling of parts greater and smaller would bring about not a waved surface, but rather compression and convergence of part and part until the centre is reached".[12] On the other hand, light bodies such as the element fire and air, were moved by their nature (levity) upward toward the celestial sphere of the Moon (see sublunary sphere). Astronomical objects near the fixed stars are composed of aether, whose natural motion is circular. Beyond them is the prime mover, the final cause of all motion in the cosmos.[13][14] In his Physics, Aristotle correctly asserted that objects immersed in a medium tend to fall at speeds proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the medium.[9][11]
Strato of Lampsacus, Epicurus and Aristarchus of Samos
[edit]Greek philosopher Strato of Lampsacus (c. 335 – c. 269 BC) rejected the Aristotelian belief of "natural places" in exchange for a mechanical view in which objects do not gain weight as they fall, instead arguing that the greater impact was due to an increase in speed.[15][16]
Epicurus (c. 341 – 270 BC) viewed weight as an inherent property of atoms which influences their movement.[17] These atoms move downward in constant free fall within an infinite vacuum without friction at equal speed, regardless of their mass. On the other hand, upward motion is due to atomic collisions.[18] Epicureans deviated from older atomist theories like that of Democritus (c. 460 – c. 370 BC) by proposing the idea that atoms may randomly deviate from their expected course.[19]
Greek astronomer Aristarchus of Samos (c. 310 – c. 230 BC) theorized Earth's rotation around its own axis, as well as Earth's orbit around the Sun in a heliocentric cosmology.[20] Seleucus of Seleucia (c. 190 – c. 150 BC) supported his cosmology[20] and also described gravitational effects of the Moon on the tidal range.[21]
Archimedes
[edit]The 3rd-century BC Greek physicist Archimedes (c. 287 – c. 212 BC}) discovered the centre of mass of a triangle.[22] He also postulated that if the centres of gravity of two equal weights was not the same, it would be located in the middle of the line that joins them.[23] In On Floating Bodies, Archimedes claimed that for any object submerged in a fluid there is an equivalent upward buoyant force to the weight of the fluid displaced by the object's volume.[24] The fluids described by Archimedes are not self-gravitating, since he assumes that "any fluid at rest is the surface of a sphere whose centre is the same as that of the Earth".[25][26]
Hipparchus of Nicaea, Lucretius and Vitruvius
[edit]Greek astronomer Hipparchus of Nicaea (c. 190 – c. 120 BC) also rejected Aristotelian physics and followed Strato in adopting some form of theory of impetus to explain motion.[27][28] The poem De rerum natura by Lucretius (c. 99 – c. 55 BC}) asserts that more massive bodies fall faster in a medium because the latter resists less, but in a vacuum fall with equal speed.[29] Roman engineer and architect Vitruvius (c. 85 – c. 15 BC) contends in his De architectura that gravity is not dependent on a substance's weight but rather on its 'nature' (cf. specific gravity):
If the quicksilver is poured into a vessel, and a stone weighing one hundred pounds is laid upon it, the stone swims on the surface, and cannot depress the liquid, nor break through, nor separate it. If we remove the hundred pound weight, and put on a scruple of gold, it will not swim, but will sink to the bottom of its own accord. Hence, it is undeniable that the gravity of a substance depends not on the amount of its weight, but on its nature.[30][31] (translated from the original Latin by W. Newton)
Plutarch, Pliny the Elder, and Claudius Ptolemy
[edit]Greek philosopher Plutarch (c. 46 – c. 120 AD) attested the existence of Roman astronomers who rejected Aristotelian physics, "even contemplating theories of inertia and universal gravitation",[32][33] and suggested that gravitational attraction was not unique to the Earth.[34] The gravitational effects of the Moon on the tides were noticed by Pliny the Elder (23–79 AD) in his Naturalis Historia[35] and Claudius Ptolemy (c. 100 – c. 170 AD) in his Tetrabiblos.[36]
Byzantine era
[edit]John Philoponus
[edit]In the 6th century AD, the Byzantine Alexandrian scholar John Philoponus proposed the theory of impetus, which modifies Aristotle's theory that "continuation of motion depends on continued action of a force" by incorporating a causative force which diminishes over time. In his commentary on Aristotle's Physics that "if one lets fall simultaneously from the same height two bodies differing greatly in weight, one will find that the ratio of the times of their motion does not correspond to the ratios of their weights, but the difference in time is a very small one".[37]
Indian subcontinent
[edit]Brahmagupta
[edit]Brahmagupta (c. 598 – c. 668 AD) was the first Indian scholar to describe gravity as an attractive force:[38][39][failed verification][40][41][failed verification]
The earth on all its sides is the same; all people on the earth stand upright, and all heavy things fall down to the earth by a law of nature, for it is the nature of the earth to attract and to keep things, as it is the nature of water to flow ... If a thing wants to go deeper down than the earth, let it try. The earth is the only low thing, and seeds always return to it, in whatever direction you may throw them away, and never rise upwards from the earth.[42][43][a]
Bhāskara II
[edit]Bhāskara II (c. 1114 – c. 1185), another Indian mathematician and astronomer, describes gravity as an inherent attractive property of Earth in the section "Golādhyāyah" ("On Spherics") of his treatise Siddhānta Shiromani:
The property of attraction is inherent in the Earth. By this property the Earth attracts any unsupported heavy thing towards it: The thing appears to be falling but it is in a state of being drawn to Earth. ... It is manifest from this that ... people situated at distances of a fourth part of the circumference [of earth] from us or in the opposite hemisphere, cannot by any means fall downwards [in space].[44][45]
Islamic world
[edit]Abu Ma'shar
[edit]Ancient Greeks like Posidonius had associated the tides in the sea with to be influenced by moonlight. Around 850, Abu Ma'shar al-Balkhi recorded the tides and the moon position and noticed high-tides when the Moon was below the horizon. Abu Ma'shar considered an alternative explanation where the Moon and the sea had to share some astrological virtue that attracted each other. This work was translated into Latin and became one of the two main theories for tides for European scholars.[46]
Ibn Sina
[edit]In the 11th century, Persian polymath Ibn Sina (Avicenna) agreed with Philoponus' theory that "the moved object acquires an inclination from the mover" as an explanation for projectile motion.[47] Ibn Sina then published his own theory of impetus in The Book of Healing (c. 1020). Unlike Philoponus, who believed that it was a temporary virtue that would decline even in a vacuum, Ibn Sina viewed it as a persistent, requiring external forces such as air resistance to dissipate it.[48][49][1] Ibn Sina made distinction between force and inclination (mayl), and argued that an object gained inclination when the object is in opposition to its natural motion. He concluded that continuation of motion is attributed to the inclination that is transferred to the object, and that object will be in motion until the inclination is spent.[50] The Iraqi polymath Ibn al-Haytham describes gravity as a force in which heavier body moves towards the centre of the earth. He also describes the force of gravity will only move towards the direction of the centre of the earth not in different directions.[51]
Al-Biruni
[edit]Another 11th-century Persian polymath, Al-Biruni, proposed that heavenly bodies have mass, weight, and gravity, just like the Earth. He criticized both Aristotle and Ibn Sina for holding the view that only the Earth has these properties.[52] The 12th-century scholar Al-Khazini suggested that the gravity an object contains varies depending on its distance from the centre of the universe (referring to the centre of the Earth). Al-Biruni and Al-Khazini studied the theory of the centre of gravity, and generalized and applied it to three-dimensional bodies. Fine experimental methods were also developed for determining the specific gravity or specific weight of objects, based the theory of balances and weighing.[53]
Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī
[edit]In the 12th century, Ibn Malka al-Baghdadi adopted and modified Ibn Sina's theory on projectile motion. In his Kitab al-Mu'tabar, Abu'l-Barakat stated that the mover imparts a violent inclination (mayl qasri) on the moved and that this diminishes as the moving object distances itself from the mover.[2] According to Shlomo Pines, al-Baghdādī's theory of motion was "the oldest negation of Aristotle's fundamental dynamic law [namely, that a constant force produces a uniform motion], [and is thus an] anticipation in a vague fashion of the fundamental law of classical mechanics [namely, that a force applied continuously produces acceleration]."[54]
European Renaissance
[edit]14th century
[edit]Jean Buridan, the Oxford Calculators, Albert of Saxony
[edit]In the 14th century, both the French philosopher Jean Buridan and the Oxford Calculators (the Merton School) of the Merton College of Oxford rejected the Aristotelian concept of gravity.[55][b] They attributed the motion of objects to an impetus (akin to momentum), which varies according to velocity and mass;[55] Buridan was influenced in this by Ibn Sina's Book of Healing.[1] Buridan and the philosopher Albert of Saxony (c. 1320 – c. 1390) adopted Abu'l-Barakat's theory that the acceleration of a falling body is a result of its increasing impetus.[2] Influenced by Buridan, Albert developed a law of proportion regarding the relationship between the speed of an object in free fall and the time elapsed.[56] He also theorized that mountains and valleys are caused by erosion[c]—displacing the Earth's centre of gravity.[57][d]
Uniform and difform motion
[edit]The roots of Domingo de Soto's expression uniform difform motion [uniformly accelerated motion] lies in the Oxford Calculators terms "uniform" and "difform" motion:[59] "uniform motion" was used differently then than it would be by later writers, and might have referred both to constant speed and to motion in which all parts of a body are moving at equal speed. The Calculators did not illustrate the different types of motion with real-world examples.[59] John of Holland at the University of Prague, illustrated uniform motion with what would later be called uniform velocity, but also with a falling stone (all parts moving at the same speed), and with a sphere in uniform rotation. He did, however, make distinctions between different kinds of "uniform" motion. Difform motion was exemplified by walking at increasing speed.[59]
Mean speed theorem
[edit]Also in the 14th century, the Merton School developed the mean speed theorem; a uniformly accelerated body starting from rest travels the same distance as a body with uniform speed whose speed is half the final velocity of the accelerated body. The mean speed theorem was proved by Nicole Oresme (c. 1323 – 1382) and would be influential in later gravitational equations.[55] Written as a modern equation:
However, since small time intervals could not be measured, the relationship between time and distance was not so evident as the equation suggests. More generally; equations, which were not widely used until after Galileo's time, imply a clarity that was not there.
15th–17th centuries
[edit]Leonardo da Vinci
[edit]Leonardo da Vinci (1452–1519) made drawings recording the acceleration of falling objects.[60] He wrote that the "mother and origin of gravity" is energy. He describes two pairs of physical powers which stem from a metaphysical origin and have an effect on everything: abundance of force and motion, and gravity and resistance. He associates gravity with the 'cold' classical elements, water and earth, and calls its energy infinite.[61][e] In Codex Arundel, Leonardo recorded that if a water-pouring vase moves transversally (sideways), simulating the trajectory of a vertically falling object, it produces a right triangle with equal leg length, composed of falling material that forms the hypotenuse and the vase trajectory forming one of the legs.[63] On the hypotenuse, Leonardo noted the equivalence of the two orthogonal motions, one effected by gravity and the other proposed by the experimenter.[63]
Nicolaus Copernicus, Petrus Apianus
[edit]By 1514, Nicolaus Copernicus had written an outline of his heliocentric model, in which he stated that Earth's centre is the centre of both its rotation and the orbit of the Moon.[64][f] In 1533, German humanist Petrus Apianus described the exertion of gravity:[g]
Since it is apparent that in the descent [along the arc] there is more impediment acquired, it is clear that gravity is diminished on this account. But because this comes about by reason of the position of heavy bodies, let it be called a positional gravity [i.e. gravitas secundum situm][67]
Francesco Beato and Luca Ghini
[edit]By 1544, according to Benedetto Varchi, the experiments of at least two Italians, Francesco Beato, a Dominican philosopher at Pisa, and Luca Ghini, a physician and botanist from Bologna, had dispelled the Aristotelian claim that objects fall at speeds proportional to their weight.[68]
Domingo de Soto
[edit]In 1551, Domingo de Soto theorized that objects in free fall accelerate uniformly in his book Physicorum Aristotelis quaestiones.[69] This idea was subsequently explored in more detail by Galileo Galilei, who derived his kinematics from the 14th-century Merton College and Jean Buridan,[55] and possibly De Soto as well.[69]
Simon Stevin
[edit]In 1585, Flemish polymath Simon Stevin performed a demonstration for Jan Cornets de Groot, a local politician in the Dutch city of Delft.[70] Stevin dropped two lead balls from the Nieuwe Kerk in that city. From the sound of the impacts, Stevin deduced that the balls had fallen at the same speed. The result was published in 1586.[71][72]
Let us take (as ... Jan Cornets de Groot ... and I have done) two balls of lead, the one ten times larger and heavier than the other, and drop them together from a height of 30 feet on to a board or something on which they give a perceptible sound. Then it will be found that the lighter will not be ten times longer on its way than the heavier, but that they fall together on to the board so simultaneously that their two sounds seem to be one and the same. ... Therefore Aristotle ... is wrong.
— Simon Stevin, De Beghinselen der Weeghconst
Galileo Galilei
[edit]Between 1589 and 1592,[73] the Italian scientist Galileo Galilei (then professor of mathematics at the University of Pisa) is said to have dropped "unequal weights of the same material" from the Leaning Tower of Pisa to demonstrate that their time of descent was independent of their mass, according to a biography by Galileo's pupil Vincenzo Viviani, composed in 1654 and published in 1717.[74][75]: 19–21 [76][77] The basic premise had already been demonstrated by Italian experimenters a few decades earlier.
According to the story, Galileo discovered through this experiment that the objects fell with the same acceleration, proving his prediction true, while at the same time disproving Aristotle's theory of gravity (which states that objects fall at speed proportional to their mass). Though Viviani wrote that Galileo conducted "repeated experiments made from the height of the Leaning Tower of Pisa in the presence of other professors and all the students,"[74] most historians consider it to have been a thought experiment rather than a physical test.[78]Galileo successfully applied mathematics to the acceleration of falling objects,[79] correctly hypothesizing in a 1604 letter to Paolo Sarpi that the distance of a falling object is proportional to the square of the time elapsed.[80][h]
I have arrived at a proposition, ... namely, that spaces traversed in natural motion are in the squared proportion of the times.
— Galileo Galilei, Letter to Paolo Sarpi
Written with modern symbols: s ∝ t2
The result was published in Two New Sciences in 1638. In the same book, Galileo suggested that the slight variance of speed of falling objects of different mass was due to air resistance, and that objects would fall completely uniformly in a vacuum.[81] The relation of the distance of objects in free fall to the square of the time taken was confirmed by Italian Jesuits Grimaldi and Riccioli between 1640 and 1650. They also made a calculation of the gravity of Earth by recording the oscillations of a pendulum.[82]
Johannes Kepler
[edit]In his Astronomia nova (1609), Johannes Kepler proposed an attractive force of limited radius between any "kindred" bodies:
Gravity is a mutual corporeal disposition among kindred bodies to unite or join together; thus the earth attracts a stone much more than the stone seeks the earth. (The magnetic faculty is another example of this sort).... If two stones were set near one another in some place in the world outside the sphere of influence of a third kindred body, these stones, like two magnetic bodies, would come together in an intermediate place, each approaching the other by a space proportional to the bulk [moles] of the other....[83]
Evangelista Torricelli
[edit]A disciple of Galileo, Evangelista Torricelli reiterated Aristotle's model involving a gravitational centre, adding his view that a system can only be in equilibrium when the common centre itself is unable to fall.[66]
European Enlightenment
[edit]The relation of the distance of objects in free fall to the square of the time taken was confirmed by Francesco Maria Grimaldi and Giovanni Battista Riccioli between 1640 and 1650. They also made a calculation of the gravity of Earth constant by recording the oscillations of a pendulum.[84]
Mechanical explanations
[edit]In 1644, René Descartes proposed that no empty space can exist and that a continuum of matter causes every motion to be curvilinear. Thus, centrifugal force thrusts relatively light matter away from the central vortices of celestial bodies, lowering density locally and thereby creating centripetal pressure.[85][86] Using aspects of this theory, between 1669 and 1690, Christiaan Huygens designed a mathematical vortex model. In one of his proofs, he shows that the distance elapsed by an object dropped from a spinning wheel will increase proportionally to the square of the wheel's rotation time.[87] In 1671, Robert Hooke speculated that gravitation is the result of bodies emitting waves in the aether.[88][i] Nicolas Fatio de Duillier (1690) and Georges-Louis Le Sage (1748) proposed a corpuscular model using some sort of screening or shadowing mechanism. In 1784, Le Sage posited that gravity could be a result of the collision of atoms, and in the early 19th century, he expanded Daniel Bernoulli's theory of corpuscular pressure to the universe as a whole.[89] A similar model was later created by Hendrik Lorentz (1853–1928), who used electromagnetic radiation instead of corpuscles.
English mathematician Isaac Newton used Descartes' argument that curvilinear motion constrains inertia,[90] and in 1675, argued that aether streams attract all bodies to one another.[j] Newton (1717) and Leonhard Euler (1760) proposed a model in which the aether loses density near mass, leading to a net force acting on bodies.[citation needed] Further mechanical explanations of gravitation (including Le Sage's theory) were created between 1650 and 1900 to explain Newton's theory, but mechanistic models eventually fell out of favor because most of them lead to an unacceptable amount of drag (air resistance), which was not observed. Others violate the energy conservation law and are incompatible with modern thermodynamics.[91]
'Weight' before Newton
[edit]Before Newton, 'weight' had the double meaning 'amount' and 'heaviness'.[92]
What we now know as mass was until the time of Newton called "weight." ... A goldsmith believed that an ounce of gold was a quantity of gold. ... But the ancients believed that a beam balance also measured "heaviness" which they recognized through their muscular senses. ... Mass and its associated downward force were believed to be the same thing. Kepler formed a [distinct] concept of mass ("amount of matter" (copia materiae), but called it "weight" as did everyone at that time.
— K. M. Browne, The pre-Newtonian meaning of the word “weight”
Mass as distinct from weight
[edit]In 1686, Newton gave the concept of mass its name. In the first paragraph of Principia, Newton defined quantity of matter as "density and bulk conjunctly", and mass as quantity of matter.[93]
The quantity of matter is the measure of the same, arising from its density and bulk conjunctly. ... It is this quantity that I mean hereafter everywhere under the name of body or mass. And the same is known by the weight of each body; for it is proportional to the weight.
— Isaac Newton, Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, Definition I.
Newton's law of universal gravitation
[edit]In 1679, Robert Hooke wrote to Isaac Newton of his hypothesis concerning orbital motion, which partly depends on an inverse-square force.[94][k] In 1684, both Hooke and Newton told Edmond Halley that they had proven the inverse-square law of planetary motion, in January and August, respectively.[96] While Hooke refused to produce his proofs, Newton was prompted to compose De motu corporum in gyrum ('On the motion of bodies in an orbit'), in which he mathematically derives Kepler's laws of planetary motion.[96] In 1687, with Halley's support (and to Hooke's dismay), Newton published Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy), which hypothesizes the inverse-square law of universal gravitation.[96] In his own words:
I deduced that the forces which keep the planets in their orbs must be reciprocally as the squares of their distances from the centres about which they revolve; and thereby compared the force requisite to keep the moon in her orb with the force of gravity at the surface of the earth; and found them to answer pretty nearly.
Newton's original formula was:
where the symbol means "is proportional to". To make this into an equal-sided formula or equation, there needed to be a multiplying factor or constant that would give the correct force of gravity no matter the value of the masses or distance between them – the gravitational constant. Newton would need an accurate measure of this constant to prove his inverse-square law. Reasonably accurate measurements were not available in until the Cavendish experiment by Henry Cavendish in 1797.[97]
In Newton's theory[98] (rewritten using more modern mathematics) the density of mass generates a scalar field, the gravitational potential in joules per kilogram, by
Using the Nabla operator for the gradient and divergence (partial derivatives), this can be conveniently written as:
This scalar field governs the motion of a free-falling particle by:
At distance r from an isolated mass M, the scalar field is
The Principia sold out quickly, inspiring Newton to publish a second edition in 1713.[99][100] However the theory of gravity itself was not accepted quickly.
The theory of gravity faced two barriers. First scientists like Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz complained that it relied on action at a distance, that the mechanism of gravity was "invisible, intangible, and not mechanical".[101]: 339 [102]: 144 The French philosopher Voltaire countered these concerns, ultimately writing his own book to explain aspects of it to French readers in 1738, which helped to popularize Newton's theory.[103]
Second, detailed comparisons with astronomical data were not initially favorable. Among the most conspicuous issue was the so-called great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn. Comparisons of ancient astronomical observations to those of the early 1700s implied that the orbit of Saturn was increasing in diameter while that of Jupiter was decreasing. Ultimately this meant Saturn would exit the Solar System and Jupiter would collide with other planets or the Sun. The problem was tackled first by Leonhard Euler in 1748, then Joseph-Louis Lagrange in 1763, by Pierre-Simon Laplace in 1773. Each effort improved the mathematical treatment until the issue was resolved by Laplace in 1784 approximately 100 years after Newton's first publication on gravity. Laplace showed that the changes were periodic but with immensely long periods beyond any existing measurements.[104]: 144
Successes such the solution to the great inequality of Jupiter and Saturn mystery accumulated. In 1755, Prussian philosopher Immanuel Kant published a cosmological manuscript based on Newtonian principles, in which he develops an early version of the nebular hypothesis.[105] Edmond Halley proposed that similar looking objects appearing every 76 years was in fact a single comet. The appearance of the comet in 1759, now named after him, within a month of predictions based on Newton's gravity greatly improved scientific opinion of the theory.[106] Newton's theory enjoyed its greatest success when it was used to predict the existence of Neptune based on motions of Uranus that could not be accounted by the actions of the other planets. Calculations by John Couch Adams and Urbain Le Verrier both predicted the general position of the planet. In 1846, Le Verrier sent his position to Johann Gottfried Galle, asking him to verify it. The same night, Galle spotted Neptune near the position Le Verrier had predicted.[107]
Not every comparison was successful. By the end of the 19th century, Le Verrier showed that the orbit of Mercury could not be accounted for entirely under Newtonian gravity, and all searches for another perturbing body (such as a planet orbiting the Sun even closer than Mercury) were fruitless.[108] Even so, Newton's theory is thought to be exceptionally accurate in the limit of weak gravitational fields and low speeds.
At the end of the 19th century, many tried to combine Newton's force law with the established laws of electrodynamics (like those of Wilhelm Eduard Weber, Carl Friedrich Gauss, and Bernhard Riemann) to explain the anomalous perihelion precession of Mercury. In 1890, Maurice Lévy succeeded in doing so by combining the laws of Weber and Riemann, whereby the speed of gravity is equal to the speed of light. In another attempt, Paul Gerber (1898) succeeded in deriving the correct formula for the perihelion shift (which was identical to the formula later used by Albert Einstein). These hypotheses were rejected because of the outdated laws they were based on, being superseded by those of James Clerk Maxwell.[91]
Modern era
[edit]In 1900, Hendrik Lorentz tried to explain gravity on the basis of his ether theory and Maxwell's equations. He assumed, like Ottaviano Fabrizio Mossotti and Johann Karl Friedrich Zöllner, that the attraction of opposite charged particles is stronger than the repulsion of equal charged particles. The resulting net force is exactly what is known as universal gravitation, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. Lorentz calculated that the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.[109]
In the late 19th century, Lord Kelvin pondered the possibility of a theory of everything.[110] He proposed that every body pulsates, which might be an explanation of gravitation and electric charges. His ideas were largely mechanistic and required the existence of the aether, which the Michelson–Morley experiment failed to detect in 1887. This, combined with Mach's principle, led to gravitational models which feature action at a distance.
Albert Einstein developed his revolutionary theory of relativity in papers published in 1905 and 1915; these account for the perihelion precession of Mercury.[108] In 1914, Gunnar Nordström attempted to unify gravity and electromagnetism in his theory of five-dimensional gravitation.[l] General relativity was proven in 1919, when Arthur Eddington observed gravitational lensing around a solar eclipse, matching Einstein's equations. This resulted in Einstein's theory superseding Newtonian physics.[111] Thereafter, German mathematician Theodor Kaluza promoted the idea of general relativity with a fifth dimension, which in 1921 Swedish physicist Oskar Klein gave a physical interpretation of in a prototypical string theory, a possible model of quantum gravity and potential theory of everything.
Einstein's field equations include a cosmological constant to account for the alleged staticity of the universe. However, Edwin Hubble observed in 1929 that the universe appears to be expanding. By the 1930s, Paul Dirac developed the hypothesis that gravitation should slowly and steadily decrease over the course of the history of the universe.[112] Alan Guth and Alexei Starobinsky proposed in 1980 that cosmic inflation in the very early universe could have been driven by a negative pressure field, a concept later coined 'dark energy'—found in 2013 to have composed around 68.3% of the early universe.[113]
In 1922, Jacobus Kapteyn proposed the existence of dark matter, an unseen force that moves stars in galaxies at higher velocities than gravity alone accounts for. It was found in 2013 to have comprised 26.8% of the early universe.[113] Along with dark energy, dark matter is an outlier in Einstein's relativity, and an explanation for its apparent effects is a requirement for a successful theory of everything.
In 1957, Hermann Bondi proposed that negative gravitational mass (combined with negative inertial mass) would comply with the strong equivalence principle of general relativity and Newton's laws of motion. Bondi's proof yielded singularity-free solutions for the relativity equations.[114]
Early theories of gravity attempted to explain planetary orbits (Newton) and more complicated orbits (e.g. Lagrange). Then came unsuccessful attempts to combine gravity and either wave or corpuscular theories of gravity. The whole landscape of physics was changed with the discovery of Lorentz transformations, and this led to attempts to reconcile it with gravity. At the same time, experimental physicists started testing the foundations of gravity and relativity—Lorentz invariance, the gravitational deflection of light, the Eötvös experiment. These considerations led to and past the development of general relativity.
Einstein (1905–1912)
[edit]In 1905, Albert Einstein published a series of papers in which he established the special theory of relativity and the fact that mass and energy are equivalent. In 1907, in what he described as "the happiest thought of my life", Einstein realized that someone who is in free fall experiences no gravitational field. In other words, gravitation is exactly equivalent to acceleration.
Einstein's two-part publication in 1912[115][116] (and before in 1908) is really only important for historical reasons. By then he knew of the gravitational redshift and the deflection of light. He had realized that Lorentz transformations are not generally applicable, but retained them. The theory states that the speed of light is constant in free space but varies in the presence of matter. The theory was only expected to hold when the source of the gravitational field is stationary. It includes the principle of least action:
where is the Minkowski metric, and there is a summation from 1 to 4 over indices and .
Einstein and Grossmann[117] includes Riemannian geometry and tensor calculus.
The equations of electrodynamics exactly match those of general relativity. The equation
is not in general relativity. It expresses the stress–energy tensor as a function of the matter density.
Lorentz-invariant models (1905–1910)
[edit]Based on the principle of relativity, Henri Poincaré (1905, 1906), Hermann Minkowski (1908), and Arnold Sommerfeld (1910) tried to modify Newton's theory and to establish a Lorentz invariant gravitational law, in which the speed of gravity is that of light. As in Lorentz's model, the value for the perihelion advance of Mercury was much too low.[118]
Abraham (1912)
[edit]Meanwhile, Max Abraham developed an alternative model of gravity in which the speed of light depends on the gravitational field strength and so is variable almost everywhere. Abraham's 1914 review of gravitation models is said to be excellent, but his own model was poor.
Nordström (1912)
[edit]The first approach of Nordström (1912)[119] was to retain the Minkowski metric and a constant value of but to let mass depend on the gravitational field strength . Allowing this field strength to satisfy
where is rest mass energy and is the d'Alembertian,
where is the mass when gravitational potential vanishes and,
where is the four-velocity and the dot is a differential with respect to time.
The second approach of Nordström (1913)[120] is remembered as the first logically consistent relativistic field theory of gravitation ever formulated. (notation from Pais[121] not Nordström):
where is a scalar field,
This theory is Lorentz invariant, satisfies the conservation laws, correctly reduces to the Newtonian limit and satisfies the weak equivalence principle.
Einstein and Fokker (1914)
[edit]This theory[122] is Einstein's first treatment of gravitation in which general covariance is strictly obeyed. Writing:
they relate Einstein–Grossmann[117] to Nordström.[120] They also state:
That is, the trace of the stress energy tensor is proportional to the curvature of space.
Between 1911 and 1915, Einstein developed the idea that gravitation is equivalent to acceleration, initially stated as the equivalence principle, into his general theory of relativity, which fuses the three dimensions of space and the one dimension of time into the four-dimensional fabric of spacetime. However, it does not unify gravity with quanta—individual particles of energy, which Einstein himself had postulated the existence of in 1905.
General relativity
[edit]In general relativity, the effects of gravitation are ascribed to spacetime curvature instead of to a force. The starting point for general relativity is the equivalence principle, which equates free fall with inertial motion. The issue that this creates is that free-falling objects can accelerate with respect to each other. To deal with this difficulty, Einstein proposed that spacetime is curved by matter, and that free-falling objects are moving along locally straight paths in curved spacetime. More specifically, Einstein and David Hilbert discovered the field equations of general relativity, which relate the presence of matter and the curvature of spacetime. These field equations are a set of 10 simultaneous, non-linear, differential equations. The solutions of the field equations are the components of the metric tensor of spacetime, which describes its geometry. The geodesic paths of spacetime are calculated from the metric tensor.
Notable solutions of the Einstein field equations include:
- The Schwarzschild solution, which describes spacetime surrounding a spherically symmetrical non-rotating uncharged massive object. For objects with radii smaller than the Schwarzschild radius, this solution generates a black hole with a central singularity.
- The Reissner–Nordström solution, in which the central object has an electrical charge. For charges with a geometrized length less than the geometrized length of the mass of the object, this solution produces black holes with an event horizon surrounding a Cauchy horizon.
- The Kerr solution for rotating massive objects. This solution also produces black holes with multiple horizons.
- The cosmological Robertson–Walker solution (from 1922 and 1924), which predicts the expansion of the universe.[citation needed]
General relativity has enjoyed much success because its predictions (not called for by older theories of gravity) have been regularly confirmed. For example:
- General relativity accounts for the anomalous perihelion precession of Mercury.[108]
- Gravitational lensing was first confirmed in 1919, and has more recently been strongly confirmed through the use of a quasar which passes behind the Sun as seen from the Earth.
- The expansion of the universe (predicted by the Robertson–Walker metric) was confirmed by Edwin Hubble in 1929.
- The prediction that time runs slower at lower potentials has been confirmed by the Pound–Rebka experiment, the Hafele–Keating experiment, and the GPS.
- The time delay of light passing close to a massive object was first identified by Irwin Shapiro in 1964 in interplanetary spacecraft signals.
- Gravitational radiation has been indirectly confirmed through studies of binary pulsars such as PSR 1913+16.
- In 2015, the LIGO experiments directly detected gravitational radiation from two colliding black holes, making this the first direct observation of both gravitational waves and black holes.[123]
It is believed that neutron star mergers (since detected in 2017)[124] and black hole formation may also create detectable amounts of gravitational radiation.
Quantum gravity
[edit]Several decades after the discovery of general relativity, it was realized that it cannot be the complete theory of gravity because it is incompatible with quantum mechanics.[125] Later it was understood that it is possible to describe gravity in the framework of quantum field theory like the other fundamental forces. In this framework, the attractive force of gravity arises due to exchange of virtual gravitons, in the same way as the electromagnetic force arises from exchange of virtual photons.[126][127] This reproduces general relativity in the classical limit, but only at the linearized level and postulating that the conditions for the applicability of Ehrenfest theorem holds, which is not always the case. Moreover, this approach fails at short distances of the order of the Planck length.[125]
See also
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ The source of this quote is Al-Biruni's India (c. 1030).[42]
- ^ This was interpreted as deriving the weight of objects from the pressure of the air below them.[55]
- ^ Leonardo da Vinci tested this theory by observing trace fossils,[57] which he used to argue against the myth of a universal flood.[58]
- ^ Furthermore, he hypothesized that the planet is in equilibrium when its centre of gravity coincides with that of its mass.[57]
- ^ Leonardo did not publish his manuscripts and they had no direct influence on subsequent science.[62]
- ^ He accounted for these movements by explaining, "Rotation is natural to a sphere, and by that very act is its shape expressed."[65]
- ^ Physicist Pierre Duhem erroneously attributes this to Jordanus Nemorarius, whom he calls the "precursor of Leonardo". Leonardo alludes to Jordanus in his notebooks, but not to any of his theories.[66]
- ^ The distance traversed in successive equal intervals of time is calculated with a triangular model whose width (representing maximum velocity) increases by two for every equal section of height (representing time elapsed). This is in part anticipated by the Merton rule.[80]
- ^ James Challis repeated this assumption in 1869.
- ^ Bernhard Riemann made a similar argument in 1853.
- ^ Newton was almost certainly influenced by this correspondence to do his subsequent work on gravitation,[94] although he denied that Hooke had told him of the inverse-square force.[95]
- ^ In string theory, dimensions exceeding four allow for the existence of parallel realities—which along with the anthropic principle, help to explain the statistical near-impossibility of our fine-tuned universe.
References
[edit]Citations
[edit]- ^ a b c Sayili, Aydin (1987). "Ibn Sīnā and Buridan on the Motion of the Projectile". Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 500 (1): 477–482. Bibcode:1987NYASA.500..477S. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1987.tb37219.x. S2CID 84784804.
- ^ a b c Gutman, Oliver (2003). Pseudo-Avicenna, Liber Celi Et Mundi: A Critical Edition. Brill. p. 193. ISBN 90-04-13228-7.
- ^ Smith, Homer W. (1952). Man and His Gods. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. p. 144.
- ^ Patzia, Michael. "Anaxagoras (c.500—428 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Campbell, Gordon. "Empedocles (c. 492—432 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Preston, David (2020). "Empedocles' Big Break: Pre-Socratic Cosmology and The Big Bounce". Sapiens Ubique Civis. 1: 11–28. doi:10.14232/suc.2020.1.11-28. ISSN 2786-2984.
Empedocles also posits two opposing forces in an eternal tug-of-war as the energy which causes the roots to move about in the first place. These are 'Love' (also referred to as Aphrodite, Cypris, or Harmony) and 'Strife' (also referred to as Anger, Wrath, or Discord), the former named so for its unifying nature, the latter for its destructive. Under the influence of Love, the roots are 'glued' and 'fitted' together, while under Strife they are torn apart. To equate this to something more relatable, here we might think about the roles of gravity and dark energy in modern physical cosmology.
- ^ Furley, David (1987). The Greek Cosmologists: Volume 1, The Formation of the Atomic Theory and its Earliest Critics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 140–141. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511552540. ISBN 0-521-33328-8.
- ^ McKirahan, Richard D. (2011) [1994]. Philosophy Before Socrates (2nd ed.). Hackett. pp. 411–412. ISBN 978-1-60384-182-5.
- ^ a b "Aristotle's Theory of Free-Fall". Relativity of Gravity. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- ^ Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. JSTOR 90584.
- ^ a b Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. ISSN 2053-4477. S2CID 44193681.
- ^ "On the Heavens by Aristotle, Book 2, Part 14". classics.mit.edu. MIT. Retrieved 23 August 2023 – via The Internet Classics Archive.
- ^ Grant, Edward (1996). The foundations of modern science in the Middle Ages: their religious, institutional, and intellectual contexts. Cambridge University Press. pp. 60–61. ISBN 978-0-521-56137-2 – via the Internet Archive.
- ^ Pedersen, Olaf (1993). Early physics and astronomy: a historical introduction. Cambridge University Press. p. 130. ISBN 978-0-521-40340-5 – via the Internet Archive.
- ^ Carrier, Richard (2017). The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire. United States and Canada: Pitchstone. p. 333. ISBN 978-1-63431-107-6.
For example, in his lost books On Lightness and Heaviness and On Motion, Strato abandoned the doctrine of 'natural places' in exchange for a more mechanical view of why some objects rise and others fall
- ^ Fortenbaugh, William (2017). Strato of Lampsacus: Text, Translation and Discussion. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-48792-4.
If someone drops a rock [from] a finger's height above the ground, it certainly won't make a visible impact on the ground, but if someone drops it holding it a hundred feet or more, it will have a strong impact. And there is no other reason for that impact. Because it does not have greater weight, nor is it impelled by greater force; but it moves faster.
- ^ "Weight in Greek Atomism". Philosophia. 45: 85. 2015.
- ^ Laertius, Diogenes. "Letter of Epicurus to Herodotus, (61)". Attalus. Retrieved 26 February 2024.
- ^ Berryman, Sylvia (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), Ancient Atomism (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 11 February 2024
- ^ a b "Plutarch, Platonicae quaestiones, Question VIII, section 1". perseus.tufts.edu. Retrieved 27 August 2023.
- ^ Strabo. "Geography — III, 5, 9". penelope.uchicago.edu. University of Chicago. Retrieved 27 August 2023.
- ^ Neitz, Reviel; Noel, William (2011). The Archimedes Codex: Revealing The Secrets Of The World's Greatest Palimpsest. Hachette. ISBN 978-1-78022-198-4.
- ^ Tuplin, C. J.; Wolpert, Lewis (2002). Science and Mathematics in Ancient Greek Culture. Hachette. p. xi. ISBN 978-0-19-815248-4.
- ^ "The works of Archimedes". Cambridge University Press. 1897. p. 257.
Any solid lighter than a fluid will, if placed in the fluid, be so far immersed that the weight of the solid will be equal to the weight of the fluid displaced.
- ^ The works of Archimedes. Translated by Heath, T. L. Cambridge University Press. 1897. p. 254. Retrieved 13 November 2017.
- ^ Ceccarelli, Marco (2007). Distinguished Figures in Mechanism and Machine Science: Their Contributions and Legacies. Springer. p. 13. ISBN 978-1-4020-6366-4.
- ^ Sorabji, Richard, ed. (2014). Simplicius: On Aristotle On the Heavens 1.5-9. Translated by Hankinson, R. J. Bloomsbury. p. 87. ISBN 978-1-4725-0111-0.
- ^ Carrier, Richard (2017). The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire. Pitchstone. ISBN 978-1-63431-107-6.
Hipparchus rejected the Aristotlian physics of motion and followed Strato in embracing an early impetus theory
- ^ Leonard, William Ellery (ed.). "Lucretius, De Rerum Natura, BOOK II, line 216". Perseus Digital Library. Retrieved 20 August 2023 – via Tufts University.
- ^ Vitruvius, Marcus Pollio (1914). "VII". In Howard, Alfred A. (ed.). De Architectura libri decem [Ten Books on Architecture] (in Latin). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. p. 215.
- ^ For another English translation see:The architecture of M. Vitruvius Pollio. Vol. 2. 1791. p. 168.
- ^ Carrier, Richard (2017). The Scientist in the Early Roman Empire. Pitchstone. ISBN 978-1-63431-107-6.
Plutarch also attests to the existence of Roman philosophers and astronomers who rejected Aristotelian dynamics and were engaging sophisticated debates on the subject, even contemplating theories of inertia and universal gravitation
- ^ Taub, Liba Chaia (2008). Aetna and the Moon: Explaining Nature in Ancient Greece and Rome. Oregon State University Press. ISBN 978-0-87071-196-1.
- ^ Bakker, Frederik; Palmerino, Carla Rita (1 June 2020). "Motion to the Center or Motion to the Whole? Plutarch's Views on Gravity and Their Influence on Galileo". Isis. 111 (2): 217–238. doi:10.1086/709138. hdl:2066/219256. ISSN 0021-1753. S2CID 219925047.
- ^ Pliny the Elder (1893). The Natural History of Pliny. H. G. Bohn. p. 128. ISBN 978-0-598-91073-8.
- ^ Ptolemy (1940). "2". Tetrabiblos. Vol. 1. Translated by Robbins, Frank E. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- ^ "John Philoponus". eoht.info. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- ^ Pickover, Clifford (2008). Archimedes to Hawking: Laws of Science and the Great Minds Behind Them. Oxford University Press. p. 105. ISBN 978-0-19-979268-9.
- ^ Bose, Mainak Kumar (1988). Late classical India. A. Mukherjee & Company.[page needed]
- ^ Sen, Amartya (2005). The Argumentative Indian. Allen Lane. p. 29. ISBN 978-0-7139-9687-6.
- ^ Thurston, Hugh (1993). Early Astronomy. New York: Springer. ISBN 978-0-387-94107-3.[page needed]
- ^ a b Alberuni's India. Kegan Paul. p. 272. Retrieved 3 June 2014.
- ^ Kitāb al-Jawharatayn al-'atīqatayn al-mā'i'atayn min al-ṣafrā' wa-al-bayḍā': al-dhahab wa-al-fiḍḍah كتاب الجوهرتين العتيقتين المائعتين من الصفراء والبيضاء : الذهب والفضة (in Arabic). Cairo: Maṭba'at Dār al-Kutub wa-al-Wathā'iq al-Qawmīyah bi-al-Qāhirah. 2004. pp. 43–44, 87. OCLC 607846741.
- ^ Áryabhat́t́a; Bháskarácárya (1150) [505, 1150]. "Chapter III ─ Called Bhuvana-kośa or Cosmograghy". Súrya Siddhánta and Siddhánta Shiromańi (in Sanskrit). Translated by Deva Sástri, Bápú; Wilkinson, Lancelot. Calcutta: C. B. Lewis, Baptist Mission Press (published 1860). p. 113.
- ^ Bháskarácárya (1150). "ভুবনকোষ". Siddhánta Shiromańi: Goládhyáyah (PDF) (in Sanskrit). Calcutta.
- ^ Deparis, Vincent (2013), Souchay, Jean; Mathis, Stéphane; Tokieda, Tadashi (eds.), "Investigations of Tides from the Antiquity to Laplace", Tides in Astronomy and Astrophysics, vol. 861, Berlin: Springer, pp. 31–82, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-32961-6_2, ISBN 978-3-642-32960-9
- ^ McGinnis, Jon; Reisman, David C. (2007). Classical Arabic philosophy: an anthology of sources. Hackett. p. 174. ISBN 978-0-87220-871-1. Retrieved 16 June 2010.
- ^ Espinoza, Fernando (2005). "An analysis of the historical development of ideas about motion and its implications for teaching". Physics Education. 40 (2): 141. Bibcode:2005PhyEd..40..139E. doi:10.1088/0031-9120/40/2/002. S2CID 250809354.
- ^ Nasr, Seyyed Hossein; Mehdi Amin, Razavi (1996). The Islamic intellectual tradition in Persia. Routledge. p. 72. ISBN 978-0-7007-0314-2.
- ^ Espinoza, Fernando. "An Analysis of the Historical Development of Ideas About Motion and its Implications for Teaching". Physics Education. Vol. 40 (2).
- ^ Clagett, Marshall (1961). The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. Vol. 1. University of Wisconsin Press. p. 58 – via the Internet Archive.
- ^ Starr, S. Frederick (2015). Lost Enlightenment: Central Asia's Golden Age from the Arab Conquest to Tamerlane. Princeton University Press. p. 260. ISBN 978-0-691-16585-1.
- ^ Rozhanskaya, Mariam; Levinova, I. S. (1996). "Statics". In Rushdī, Rāshid (ed.). Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science. Vol. 2. Psychology Press. pp. 614–642. ISBN 978-0-415-12411-9.
Using a whole body of mathematical methods (not only those inherited from the antique theory of ratios and infinitesimal techniques, but also the methods of the contemporary algebra and fine calculation techniques), Muslim scientists raised statics to a new, higher level. The classical results of Archimedes in the theory of the centre of gravity were generalized and applied to three-dimensional bodies, the theory of ponderable lever was founded and the 'science of gravity' was created and later further developed in medieval Europe. The phenomena of statics were studied by using the dynamic approach so that two trends – statics and dynamics – turned out to be inter-related within a single science, mechanics. The combination of the dynamic approach with Archimedean hydrostatics gave birth to a direction in science which may be called medieval hydrodynamics. ... Numerous fine experimental methods were developed for determining the specific weight, which were based, in particular, on the theory of balances and weighing. The classical works of al-Biruni and al-Khazini can by right be considered as the beginning of the application of experimental methods in medieval science.
- ^ Pines, Shlomo (1970). "Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī, Hibat Allah". Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. pp. 26–28. ISBN 0-684-10114-9.
(cf. Abel B. Franco (October 2003). "Avempace, Projectile Motion, and Impetus Theory", Journal of the History of Ideas 64 (4), pp. 521–546 [528].) - ^ a b c d e Gillispie 1960, p. 41.
- ^ Drake, Stillman (1975). "Free fall from Albert of Saxony to Honoré Fabri". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A. 5 (4): 347–366. Bibcode:1975SHPSA...5..347D. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(75)90007-2. ISSN 0039-3681 – via Academia.edu.
- ^ a b c Knight, Kevin (2017). "Albert of Saxony". New Advent. Retrieved 10 July 2019.
- ^ Da Vinci, Leonardo (1971). Taylor, Pamela (ed.). The Notebooks of Leonardo da Vinci. New American Library. pp. 136–138, 142–148.
- ^ a b c Wallace 2004a, p. 386.
- ^ Ouellette, Jennifer (10 February 2023). "Leonardo noted link between gravity and acceleration centuries before Einstein". Ars Technica. Retrieved 11 February 2023.
- ^ Da Vinci, Leonardo (1971). Taylor, Pamela (ed.). The Notebooks of Leonardo da Vinci. New American Library. p. 124.
Force arises from dearth or abundance; it is the child of physical motion, and the grandchild of spiritual motion, and the mother and origin of gravity. Gravity is limited to the elements of water and earth; but his force is unlimited, and by it infinite worlds might be moved if instruments could be made by which the force be generated.
Force, with physical motion, and gravity, with resistance, are the four external powers on which all actions of mortals depend. - ^ Capra, Fritjof (2007). The Science of Leonardo. Doubleday. pp. 5–6. ISBN 978-0-385-51390-6.
- ^ a b Gharib, Morteza; Roh, Chris; Noca, Flavio (1 February 2023). "Leonardo da Vinci's Visualization of Gravity as a Form of Acceleration". Leonardo. 56: 21–27. doi:10.1162/leon_a_02322. S2CID 254299572. Retrieved 16 February 2023.
- ^ Durant, Will (2011) [1957]. The Story of Civilization: Volume VI – The Reformation. Simon & Schuster. p. 823. ISBN 978-1-4516-4763-1.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 27.
- ^ a b Ginzburg, Benjamin (September 1936). "Duhem and Jordanus Nemorarius". Isis. 25 (2). The University of Chicago Press: 341–362. doi:10.1086/347085. JSTOR 225373. S2CID 145152521.
- ^ Duhem, Pierre (2012). The Origins of Statics: The Sources of Physical Theory Volume 1. Translated by Leneaux, G. F.; Vagliente, V. N.; Wagener, G. H. Springer. p. xxiv. ISBN 9789401137300.
- ^ Wallace 2004b, p. 121.
- ^ a b Wallace, William A. (2018) [2004]. Domingo de Soto and the Early Galileo: Essays on Intellectual History. Abingdon, UK: Routledge. pp. 119, 121–122. ISBN 978-1-351-15959-3.
- ^ Icke, V. (2014). Gravity does not exist: A puzzle for the 21st century. Amsterdam University Press. p. 9. Bibcode:2014gdne.book.....I.
- ^ Drake, S (1978). Galileo at work: His scientific biography. University of Chicago Press. p. 20. ISBN 978-0-226-16226-3.
- ^ Stevin, S. (1955) [1586]. Dijksterhuis, E. J. (ed.). The Principal Works of Simon Stevin (PDF) (in Dutch and English). Vol. 1. C. V. Swets & Zeitlinger. pp. 509, 511.
- ^ Some contemporary sources speculate about the exact date; e.g. Rachel Hilliam gives 1591 (Galileo Galilei: Father of Modern Science, The Rosen Publishing Group, 2005, p. 101).
- ^ a b Vincenzo Viviani (1717), Racconto istorico della vita di Galileo Galilei, p. 606: [...dimostrando ciò con replicate esperienze, fatte dall'altezza del Campanile di Pisa con l'intervento delli altri lettori e filosofi e di tutta la scolaresca... [...Galileo showed this [all bodies, whatever their weights, fall with equal speeds] by repeated experiments made from the height of the Leaning Tower of Pisa in the presence of other professors and all the students...].
- ^ Drake, Stillman (2003). Galileo at Work: His Scientific Biography (Facsim. ed.). Mineola (N.Y.): Dover publ. ISBN 9780486495422.
- ^ "Sci Tech : Science history: setting the record straight". The Hindu. 30 June 2005. Archived from the original on 2 November 2005. Retrieved 5 May 2009.
- ^ Vincenzo Viviani on museo galileo
- ^ "El experimento más famoso de Galileo probablemente nunca tuvo lugar". The Conversation. 16 May 2019. Retrieved 17 May 2019.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 42.
- ^ a b Gillispie 1960, pp. 3–6.
- ^ Galilei, Galileo (2015). Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences. Translated by Crew, Henry. Eastford, CT: Martino Fine Books. p. 72. ISBN 978-1-61427-794-1.
- ^ J.L. Heilbron, Electricity in the 17th and 18th Centuries: A Study of Early Modern Physics (Berkeley: the University of California Press, 1979), 180.
- ^ Kepler, Johannes (2004). Selections from Kepler's Astronomia Nova. Translated by Donahue, William H. Santa Fe, NM: Green Lion. p. 1. ISBN 1-888009-28-4.
- ^ J.L. Heilbron, Electricity in the 17th and 18th Centuries: A Study of Early Modern Physics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), 180.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 93.
- ^ Descartes, René (1644). Principles of Philosophy.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 121.
- ^ Taylor, William Bower (1876). "Kinetic Theories of Gravitation". Smithsonian Report: 205–282.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 480.
- ^ Gillispie 1960, p. 120.
- ^ a b Zenneck, J. (1903). "Gravitation". Encyklopädie der Mathematischen Wissenschaften mit Einschluss ihrer Anwendungen (in German). Vol. 5. Leipzig. pp. 25–67. doi:10.1007/978-3-663-16016-8_2. ISBN 978-3-663-15445-7.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - ^ Browne, K. M. (2018). "The pre-Newtonian meaning of the word "weight"; a comment on "Kepler and the origins of pre-Newtonian mass" [Am. J. Phys. 85, 115–123 (2017)]". American Journal of Physics. 86 (6): 471–474. Bibcode:2018AmJPh..86..471B. doi:10.1119/1.5027490. S2CID 125953814.
- ^ Newton, I. (1729) [Original work published 1686]. The mathematical principles of natural philosophy. Translated by Motte, A. Printed for Benjamin Motte. pp. 1–2.
- ^ a b Cohen, I. Bernard; Smith, George Edwin (2002). The Cambridge Companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press. pp. 11–12, 96–97. ISBN 978-0-521-65696-2.
- ^ H. W. Turnbull (ed.), Correspondence of Isaac Newton, Vol. 2 (1676–1687), (Cambridge University Press, 1960), pp. 297–314, 431–448.
- ^ a b c Sagan, Carl; Druyan, Ann (1997). Comet. New York: Random House. pp. 52–58. ISBN 978-0-307-80105-0.
- ^ Poynting 1894
- ^ Newton, I. (1686). Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (in Latin).
- ^ The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 4, Cambridge University Press 1967, at pp. 519, n.2.
- ^ Westfall, Richard S. (1971), Force in Newton's Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth Century. New York: American Elsevier, p. 750.
- ^ Hesse, Mary B. (1955). "Action at a Distance in Classical Physics". Isis. 46 (4): 337–353. doi:10.1086/348429. ISSN 0021-1753. JSTOR 227576. S2CID 121166354.
- ^ Gillispie, Charles Coulston. The edge of objectivity: An essay in the history of scientific ideas. Princeton University Press, 2016.
- ^ Shank, J. B. (2009). "Voltaire". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Whittaker, Edmund T. (1989). A history of the theories of aether & electricity. 2: The Modern Theories 1900–1926 (Repr. ed.). New York: Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-26126-3.
- ^ Woolfson, M. M. (1993). "Solar System – its origin and evolution". Q. J. R. Astron. Soc. 34: 1–20. Bibcode:1993QJRAS..34....1W.
- ^ Hughes, D. W. (1987). "The history of Halley's Comet". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Mathematical and Physical Sciences. 323 (1572): 349–367. Bibcode:1987RSPTA.323..349H. doi:10.1098/rsta.1987.0091. ISSN 0080-4614. S2CID 123592786.
- ^ Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 1 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 177–178.
- ^ a b c Einstein, Albert (1916). "The Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity" (PDF). Annalen der Physik. 49 (7): 769–822. Bibcode:1916AnP...354..769E. doi:10.1002/andp.19163540702. Retrieved 3 September 2006.
- ^ Lorentz, H. A. (1900). "Considerations on Gravitation" (PDF). Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences (KNAW). 2: 559–574.
- ^ Thompson, Silvanus P. (2019). "Lord Kelvin". International Electrotechnical Commission. Archived from the original on 29 March 2019. Retrieved 16 October 2019.
- ^ Andrzej, Stasiak (2003). "Myths in science". EMBO Reports. 4 (3): 236. doi:10.1038/sj.embor.embor779. PMC 1315907.
- ^ Haber, Heinz (1967) [1965]. "Die Expansion der Erde" [The expansion of the Earth]. Unser blauer Planet [Our blue planet]. Rororo Sachbuch [Rororo nonfiction] (in German) (Rororo Taschenbuch Ausgabe [Rororo pocket edition] ed.). Reinbek: Rowohlt Verlag. p. 52. Bibcode:1967ubp..book.....H.
Der englische Physiker und Nobelpreisträger Dirac hat ... vor über dreißig Jahren die Vermutung begründet, dass sich das universelle Maß der Schwerkraft im Laufe der Geschichte des Universums außerordentlich langsam, aber stetig verringert." English: "The English physicist and Nobel laureate Dirac has ..., more than thirty years ago, substantiated the assumption that the universal strength of gravity decreases very slowly, but steadily over the course of the history of the universe.
- ^ a b "Big Bang's afterglow shows universe is 80 million years older than scientists first thought". The Washington Post. Archived from the original on 22 March 2013. Retrieved 22 March 2013.
- ^ Bondi, H. (1957). "Negative mass in general relativity". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 423–428. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..423B. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.29.423.
- ^ Einstein, Albert (1912). "Lichtgeschwindigkeit und Statik des Gravitationsfeldes". Annalen der Physik (in German). 38 (7): 355–369. Bibcode:1912AnP...343..355E. doi:10.1002/andp.19123430704.
- ^ Einstein, Albert (1912). "Zur Theorie des statischen Gravitationsfeldes". Annalen der Physik (in German). 38 (7): 443. Bibcode:1912AnP...343..443E. doi:10.1002/andp.19123430709.
- ^ a b Einstein, A. and Grossmann, M. (1913), Zeitschrift für Mathematik und Physik 62, 225
- ^ Walter, S. (2007). Renn, J. (ed.). "Breaking in the 4-vectors: the four-dimensional movement in gravitation, 1905–1910" (PDF). The Genesis of General Relativity. 3. Berlin: 193–252. Bibcode:2007ggr..conf..193W.
- ^ Nordström, G. (1912). "Relativitätsprinzip und Gravitation". Physikalische Zeitschrift (in German). 13: 1126.
- ^ a b Nordström, G. (1913). "Zur Theorie der Gravitation vom Standpunkt des Relativitätsprinzips". Annalen der Physik (in German). 42 (13): 533. Bibcode:1913AnP...347..533N. doi:10.1002/andp.19133471303.
- ^ Pais, Abraham (2005). Subtle is the Lord: The Science and Life of Albert Einstein. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-152402-8.
- ^ Einstein, Albert; Fokker, A. D. (1914). "Die Nordströmsche Gravitationstheorie vom Standpunkt des absoluten Differentkalküls". Annalen der Physik (in German). 44 (10): 321–328. Bibcode:1914AnP...349..321E. doi:10.1002/andp.19143491009.
- ^ Abbott, Benjamin P.; et al. (LIGO Scientific Collaboration and Virgo Collaboration) (2016). "Observation of Gravitational Waves from a Binary Black Hole Merger". Physical Review Letters. 116 (6): 061102. arXiv:1602.03837. Bibcode:2016PhRvL.116f1102A. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.116.061102. PMID 26918975. S2CID 124959784.
- "Observation of Gravitational Waves from a Binary Black Hole Merger" (PDF). LIGO Scientific Collaboration.
- ^ Abbott, B. P.; Abbott, R.; Abbott, T. D.; Acernese, F.; Ackley, K.; Adams, C.; Adams, T.; Addesso, P.; Adhikari, R. X.; Adya, V. B.; Affeldt, C.; Afrough, M.; Agarwal, B.; Agathos, M.; Agatsuma, K.; Aggarwal, N.; Aguiar, O. D.; Aiello, L.; Ain, A.; Ajith, P.; Allen, B.; Allen, G.; Allocca, A.; Altin, P. A.; Amato, A.; Ananyeva, A.; Anderson, S. B.; Anderson, W. G.; Angelova, S. V.; Antier, S. (2017). "Multi-messenger Observations of a Binary Neutron Star Merger". The Astrophysical Journal Letters. 848 (2): L12. arXiv:1710.05833. Bibcode:2017ApJ...848L..12A. doi:10.3847/2041-8213/aa91c9. S2CID 217162243.
- ^ a b Randall, Lisa (2005). Warped Passages: Unraveling the Universe's Hidden Dimensions. Ecco. ISBN 978-0-06-053108-9.
- ^ Feynman, Richard; Morinigo, F. B.; Wagner, W. G.; Hatfield, B. (1995). Feynman lectures on gravitation. Addison-Wesley. ISBN 978-0-201-62734-3.
- ^ Zee, A. (2003). Quantum Field Theory in a Nutshell. Princeton University Press.
Sources
[edit]- Gillispie, Charles Coulston (1960). The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-02350-6.
- Wallace, W. A. (2004a). "The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics". In Wallace, W. A. (ed.). Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history. Routledge. (Reprinted from "The enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and falling bodies in late medieval physics". (1968). Isis, 59(4), 384–401).
- Wallace, W. A. (2004b). "Domingo de Soto and the Iberian roots of Galileo's science". In Wallace, W. A. (ed.). Domingo de Soto and the early Galileo: Essays on intellectual history. Routledge. (Reprinted from White, K. (Ed.). (1997). Hispanic philosophy in the age of discovery. Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 29. Catholic University of America Press).